Zimmermann - Criteria of Identity

download Zimmermann - Criteria of Identity

of 22

Transcript of Zimmermann - Criteria of Identity

  • 8/2/2019 Zimmermann - Criteria of Identity

    1/22

    DEAN W. ZIMMERMAN

    CRITERIA OF IDENTITY AND THE IDENTITY MYSTICS

    1. INTRODUCTION

    The centerpiece of this paper is the construction of a framework in which

    to state theses of mereological supervenience assertions about the de-

    pendence of wholes upon their parts. The project is given its point by

    the light it sheds upon two controversies over criteria of synchronic anddiachronic unity. Some philosophers (the Identity Mystics, as I shall call

    them) claim that, at least in the case of human beings, there is no reason to

    look for informative criteria of identity over time. I shall argue that, given

    certain highly plausible theses of mereological supervenience, if human

    beings are wholly material if, that is, they have no immaterial soul then

    this view is untenable. In the final section, I consider a problem that arises

    for those who suppose that criteria of synchronic and diachronic unity are,

    in a certain sense, intrinsic.

    2. THE ROLE OF CRITERIA OF IDENTITY

    I begin, however, with a brief description of the philosophical disputes that

    have given rise to the technical terminology of criteria of synchronic and

    diachronic unity or identity.

    It is relatively easy to say what a principle of synchronic unity is sup-

    posed to do: it tells us under what conditions a group of things go together

    to compose a whole in the case of spatially located objects, under what

    conditions a group of smaller things go to make up a spatially larger whole.

    Such principles will look something like this: a set of things S constitutes

    a whole of kind K if and only if . . . , where the ellipsis is to be filled in by

    some condition on the members ofS.

    Principles of diachronic unity tell us under what conditions a successionof things existing at different moments go together to compose a tempo-

    rally extended whole. But this way of putting things may already seem

    to presuppose what it should not: the doctrine of temporal parts, which

    Erkenntnis 48: 281301, 1998.

    1998 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.

  • 8/2/2019 Zimmermann - Criteria of Identity

    2/22

    282 DEAN W. ZIMMERMAN

    Figure 1. The ship of Theseus.

    says that just as spatially extended objects have different parts at different

    places, temporally extended objects have different parts at different times.

    Philosophers friendly to this doctrine will no doubt regard principles of

    diachronic and synchronic unity as precisely parallel in form; the rest of uswill disagree. But are there any successions of things existing at different

    moments that can be accepted by both the friends and enemies of temporal

    parts, and so used to state criteria of diachronic unity that are neutral with

    respect to the doctrine of temporal parts?

    After a thorough survey of alternative frameworks for giving criteria of

    diachronic identity, Harold Noonan concludes that such criteria are best

    taken as stating conditions necessary and sufficient for a series of events

    to constitute the history of a persisting thing. His idea can be applied to

    the Ship of Theseus, a ship kept continuously functioning over many years

    by gradual replacement of all the original boards. In situation (1) (see Fig-

    ure 1), the discarded boards become flotsam, never recovered; in situation

    (2), they are saved by an antiquarian and then finally reassembled to form

    the ship occupying the spatiotemporal path c; in (3), the boards are never

    replaced, so that Theseus ship becomes gradually unseaworthy, ceasing to

    be a ship long before the antiquarian puts his boards together.

    Noonan shows that the position of best candidate or closest contin-

    uer theorists comes to something like this: Consider all the events that oc-

    cur within the boundaries of some ship or other in situation (3) including

    those rather uneventful occurrences Cardinal Mercier dubbed unchanges,

    such as a certain boards retaining its location relative to the contours of the

    ship. If we think of events as exemplifications of properties or as property

    instances, then an event happening within some ships boundaries can be

    construed as the exemplification of an intrinsic property (of which morelater) by any aggregate of boards, and the holding of a relation of distance

    between any parts. All the events (that are instances of these event-types)

    going on within the boundaries of Theseus ship in situation (3) also occur

  • 8/2/2019 Zimmermann - Criteria of Identity

    3/22

    CRITERIA OF IDENTITY AND THE IDENTITY MYSTICS 283

    Figure 2. The fissioning simple.

    in situation (2). In the former, they constitute the history of a single ship; in

    the latter, they do not. The best candidate theorist can interpret the namesin the diagram as referring to series of events of this sort. Her thesis can

    then be put in this way: c and c are the same events; in situation (3) they

    go together with the events a to constitute the history of a single ship; in

    situation (2) they do not, but constitute instead the history of a ship that

    came into being for the first time when the antiquarian put his collection of

    planks together. The opponent of best candidate theories of identity holds

    that, given the precise similarity of the series of events a + c and a + c,

    the one constitutes the history of a single ship only if the other does.

    As Noonan realizes, controversies will sometimes arise over whether

    one has the same or different events in counterfactual situations. Con-

    sider the two circumstances depicted in Figure 2: situation (4) involves

    the fissioning of a simple particle; in situation (5), a process goes on that is

    intrinsically just like a + c in (4). The best candidate theorist would likely

    judge that c and c are distinct though qualitatively identical. The sub-

    strate of the c events is identical with the substrate of the a events; but the

    substrate of the c events is not identical with the substrate of the a events.

    On the assumption that no event could have had a different substrate than

    it actually had,1 the c and c events cannot be the same.2

    I assume that every event is the exemplification of a property; so contro-

    versies over event identity across possible worlds can be avoided altogether

    simply by stating criteria of unity in terms of the properties exemplified by

    objects at different times. Competing criteria of diachronic unity can then

    be given in terms of potential histories of objects, where the histories inquestion consist of collections of parts and potential parts taken at differ-

    ent times and paired with the properties and relations they exemplify or

    might have exemplified at those times. If fixing the intrinsic properties of

  • 8/2/2019 Zimmermann - Criteria of Identity

    4/22

    284 DEAN W. ZIMMERMAN

    and spatial relations among the parts in these collections is all it takes to

    settle whether such a series constitutes the history of a single persisting

    thing, then the criteria of diachronic unity are intrinsic; otherwise, not. It

    is this approach to criteria that will fall out of the theory of mereologicalsupervenience developed in the next section.

    But what exactly are intrinsic properties? Intrinsic properties are those

    that do not differ between qualitative duplicates; no matter how different

    the environments of qualitative duplicates, their intrinsic properties remain

    the same. As David Lewis points out, this is a pretty tight definitional

    circle. One can, it may be hoped, do better. Lewis, in discussions of the

    intrinsic and extrinsic, introduces the notions of loneliness and accom-

    paniment where an item is lonely just in case nothing exists beside

    itself and any proper parts it might have, and something is accompanied

    if and only if not lonely.3 Elsewhere, I have proposed this account of

    the intrinsic:4 First, define provisionally spatially and temporally intrinsic

    properties as those that do not imply either spatial or temporal accom-paniment, or spatial or temporal loneliness. Then introduce a notion of

    parthood for properties, and say that a property is completely intrinsic

    if and only if every part that is also a property is intrinsic by the pro-

    visional criterion. Intrinsic properties are those necessarily equivalent to

    completely intrinsic properties.

    3. MEREOLOGICAL SUPERVENIENCE AND CRITERIA OF UNITY

    It should now be more or less clear what criteria of synchronic and di-

    achronic unity look like, and what such things are supposed to do. I turn

    then to the notion of mereological supervenience the thesis that wholes

    are dependent upon their parts. For I think it is the conviction that mere-

    ological supervenience must be true that fuels the search for criteria of

    identity.

    Jaegwon Kim has suggested that mereological dependence the de-

    pendence of wholes on their parts is a species of supervenience: super-

    venience with multiple domains.5 I suggest that criteria of synchronic

    and diachronic unity are themselves supervenience theses. Principles of

    synchronic unity state that wholes of a certain sort supervene upon parts

    arranged in a certain way; principles of diachronic unity state that a per-

    sisting whole of a certain sort supervenes upon a series of collections of

    parts arranged in certain ways. I set up a schematic framework for mul-tiple domain supervenience, in which mereological dependence and its

    implications with respect to criteria of synchronic and diachronic unity

    will become clear.

  • 8/2/2019 Zimmermann - Criteria of Identity

    5/22

    CRITERIA OF IDENTITY AND THE IDENTITY MYSTICS 285

    Before diving into the details, Ill introduce a simple analogy to mo-

    tivate the theory on offer. The analogy comes from flip books: books

    with pictures in the lower or upper right-hand corner of each page, which

    produce a moving image when one riffles through the pages from front toback. Each little picture is, often enough, made out of a bunch of dots. The

    arrangement of dots on a given page determines what object or group of

    objects is depicted on that page; the series of all the arrangements of dots

    that appear on the pages determines what the object or objects depicted

    do over time whether one disappears or disintegrates, whether new ones

    appear, and so on. Given the same arrangements of dots appearing in the

    same order, the same objects must appear doing the same things.

    The thesis of mereological supervenience I shall articulate affirms that

    something analogous is true of wholes and their parts. The parts are the

    dots; if a class of wholes are made entirely of a given sort of part, then

    fixing how things are at a time on the level of the parts will determine

    how things are at that time on the level of wholes. Furthermore, fixing howthings are over time on the level of parts determines how things are during

    that time on the level of persisting wholes. The analogy with flip books

    will prove helpful both where it holds and where it fails.

    Let (D1) be the subvenient domain the collection of parts and po-

    tential parts in terms of which principles of synchronic and diachronic

    unity will be stated, the things that will have the subvenient properties

    upon which wholes will supervene. And let (D2) be the domain of wholes

    that can be made out of the members of (D1). Generally, (D1) and (D2)

    will be disjoint. The B-properties and relations or subvenient properties

    and relations constitute the supervenience base. The A-properties should

    include all properties of wholes which are thought to be determined by theproperties and arrangement of their parts. In order for there to be princi-

    ples of synchronic and diachronic unity, these will have to include sortal

    properties, like being an organism or being a cat.6

    If principles of synchronic and diachronic unity are intrinsic, then the

    supervenience base (the B-properties) need only include the intrinsic prop-

    erties of parts (including their causal dispositions, both active and passive)

    and the spatial relations holding among them. If, on the other hand, such

    principles are notintrinsic, more will be needed in the supervenience base:

    what Kim has called generalized relations will have to be added in

    particular, generalized spatial and spatiotemporal relations. For every spa-

    tial relation that holds between myself and something else of a certain

    kind (for instance, being two feet from, which holds between me and oneof my bookshelves), there is a generalized spatial relation I have, which

    is really the property of standing in that relation to something or other

  • 8/2/2019 Zimmermann - Criteria of Identity

    6/22

    286 DEAN W. ZIMMERMAN

    of that kind (in this case, being two feet from a bookshelf). The extrinsic

    determiners of identity that I shall consider countenancing are general-

    ized spatial relations to things having intrinsic properties appropriate to

    items in the domain of parts, or to events involving the exemplificationof such properties. So if the intrinsic property having positive charge is

    in the supervenience base, then the generalized relation being two feet

    from something having positive charge would also be in the supervenience

    base. Well call this way of enriching the supervenience base, admitting

    extrinsic determiners.

    First, I define a notion meant to capture something like the complete

    state of a collection of objects at a time complete, that is, with respect to

    subvenient properties and relations.

    F is a synchronic complete specification with respect to B =dfF is a property of sets which is such that, necessarily, for any

    sets S and S, S and S both have F iff there is a one-onefunction f from S (and its subsets) to S (and its subsets) such

    that, for any x and {y, z} in S, and any B-property P and B-

    relation R, x has P ifff x has P, and {y, z} is in the extension

    ofR ifff{y, z} is in the extension ofR.

    (D1)

    In a domain of flip-book dots, which vary only in color and location on

    the page, the notion of a synchronic complete specification for dots comes

    to this: a property of a set of dots on a single page that fixes their spatial

    relations and colors. Any two groups of dots with the same synchronic

    complete specification will include dots of the same colors arranged in the

    same way. Synchronic complete specifications F and F

    are structure-specific indiscernible just in case, necessarily, a set exemplifies the one if

    and only if it exemplifies the other.

    The pursuit of principles of synchronic unity for complex objects is

    justified by the conviction that wholes are dependent upon their parts: Fix

    how things are at the level of parts, and youve fixed how things are on the

    level of wholes. This conviction can be turned into a more precise principle

    of synchronic supervenience:

    For every set S and S of members of (D1), and all worlds w1

    and w2, if S in w1 and S in w2 exemplify structure-specific

    indiscernible synchronic complete specifications, then Sconsti-

    tutes an object in w1 if and only ifS does in w2; and if eitherconstitutes an object, then there is an object constituted by S in

    w1 that is indiscernible with respect to A-properties from one

    constituted by S in w2.7

    (SS)

  • 8/2/2019 Zimmermann - Criteria of Identity

    7/22

    CRITERIA OF IDENTITY AND THE IDENTITY MYSTICS 287

    There are two ways of reading (SS): the B-properties that go into the

    complete specifications of the sets of parts may be restricted to intrinsic

    determiners, or expanded to include extrinsic ones as well. One might have

    doubts about the truth of (SS) on the intrinsic reading: In the domain ofdots, there are groups that wouldconstitute a picture of a cat without a tail,

    but for the presence of nearby dots that make them just part of a picture

    of a cat with a tail. Similarly, suppose the subvenient domain consists of

    living cells and the supervenient domain of mammals, like poor Tibbles

    the cat, who has just lost her tail in a very sudden accident.8 Couldnt there

    be sets of cells constituting just a part of a cat that are intrinsically just like

    the set of cells now constituting all of Tibbles? If so, cells arranged just like

    Tibbless could have failed to constitute a cat. Someone who accepts this

    reasoning must throw extrinsic determiners into the supervenience base as

    well. Then the difference between the external situations of the two sets of

    cells will make a difference in the generalized spatial relations exemplified

    by the cells.But whether (SS) be construed weakly (by including extrinsic determin-

    ers in the supervenience base) or strongly (by excluding them), it implies

    that there are principles of synchronic unity.9 For any particular kind K

    of object made of the parts in (D1), there will be a set G of synchronic

    complete specifications such that a set S from (D1) constitutes a whole of

    kind K if and only if it exemplifies one of the members of G. Granted, this

    set G will consist of infinitely many different complete specifications of

    arrangements of parts, at least in the case of complex objects made of more

    than just a few parts that can be arranged in more than just a few ways. But

    that doesnt prove that there is no hope of our seeing what the members

    ofG have in common; the difference between those types of arrangementswhich yield wholes and those that dont may be quite simple. In any case,

    if synchronic supervenience is true with respect to some domains of parts

    and wholes, then there are necessary connections between what goes on

    at the level of parts and what goes on at the level of wholes. Even if it

    should prove too hard for us to formulate precise necessary and sufficient

    conditions for the emergence of a whole out of parts, we should still hope

    to be able to find some sufficient conditions, and to see that some others

    are necessary. To deny that principles of synchronic unity exist for some

    domain of complex things is, by my lights, nearly incoherent. To deny such

    supervenience is to say that, although the complex things are made entirely

    out of things of some other kind, nonetheless everything could have been

    the same at the level of these parts and yet some of the complex things havefailed to exist. On this view, making a complex thing out of parts takes

    more than just putting the parts together in the right way; it even takes

  • 8/2/2019 Zimmermann - Criteria of Identity

    8/22

    288 DEAN W. ZIMMERMAN

    more (assuming the supervenience base to include extrinsic determiners)

    than making sure the parts are in the right sort of environment. What more

    could be asked for is beyond me.10

    Principles ofdiachronic unity follow from the supervenience of persist-ing wholes upon the histories of the parts that make them up at different

    times. Formulating a thesis of diachronic supervenience requires the no-

    tions of a B-micro-history, and of the B-micro-history exemplified by a

    particular object.

    T is a B-micro-history =df Tis an ordered series of ordered pairs

    B, t such that: (1) B is a synchronic complete specification,

    (2) t is a real number, and (3) one member of T is earlier than

    another iff its second member is lower than that of the other.

    (D2)

    The numerical member of these pairs will be used to measure, in minutes,

    the temporal distances between the parts of the micro-history. If the differ-

    ence between the numbers in two members of a micro-history is three, this

    signifies that, if the micro-history were exemplified, then the one with the

    lower number would occur three minutes before the one with the higher

    number where (D3), below, gives the relevant meaning of exemplifi-

    cation. In the realm of flip-book pictures, a micro-history is a series of

    possible ways for dots to be arranged on a page, with a page number

    attached to each arrangement. A series of sets of actual dots exemplifies

    such a micro-history only if each group of dots in the series exemplifies

    one of the arrangements, and the pages on which they appear come in

    the order specified. In the general case, exemplification of a micro-history

    comes to this:

    A series U of sets of members of (D1) exemplifies B-micro-

    history T =df . There is a one-one function f from U onto T

    such that: (1) for every pair Sand S of members U, S exempli-

    fies the first member off S, and S exemplifies the first member

    of f S; and (2) Ss exemplification of the first member of f S

    occurs n minutes earlier than Ss if and only if the second

    member off Ssubtracted from the second member off S = n.

    (D3)

    Diachronic supervenience is a matter of the exemplification of indis-

    cernible micro-histories having the same macro-results. Now in the case

    of dots, theres no need to ask questions about whether the dot on page

    three that is part of the cats tail is the same as some dot on page four. Eachdot is confined to its own page. But in the case of real wholes made out

    of real parts, this is a question that does matter. If God were to annihilate

    all the atoms in my body at noon, while an evil demon simultaneously

  • 8/2/2019 Zimmermann - Criteria of Identity

    9/22

    CRITERIA OF IDENTITY AND THE IDENTITY MYSTICS 289

    replaced them with duplicates arranged exactly as mine would have been,

    many would be inclined to say that I failed to survive the mishap. We

    want to be able to recognize the difference between the exemplification

    of my micro-history in this way (with the instantaneous replacement ofall the cells by new ones at some point) and an exemplification of the

    same micro-history in which the annihilation and creation doesnt occur.

    I shall say that exemplifications of micro-histories are structure-specific

    indiscernible only if parts that play a certain role in one exemplification

    of a micro-history have counterparts playing the same role in the other

    exemplification of the micro-history.

    Us exemplification of B-micro-history T is structure-specific

    indiscernible from Us exemplification of B-micro-history

    T =df (1) U exemplifies T and U exemplifies T; and (2)

    there is a one-one function f from members ofU onto members

    ofU which is such that, for every pair of members S1 and S2 ofU, S1 and S2 exemplify synchronic complete specifications P1

    and P2 in T if and only if: (a) f S1 and f S2 exemplify a Q1 and

    Q2 in T that are structure-specific indiscernible from P1 and

    P2; (b) ift1 and t2 are the numbers paired with P1 and P2 in T,

    and t3 and t4 are the numbers paired with Q1 and Q2 in T, then

    t1 > t2 if and only ift3 > t4, and t1 t2 = t3 t4; and (c) if an

    individual x or pair y and z in S1 and S2 exemplify properties

    or relations in the supervenience base when S1 exemplifies P1

    and when S2 exemplifies P2, then there must be an individual

    t, or pair u and v, in both f S1 and f S2 exemplifying the same

    properties or relations when Q

    1

    and Q

    2

    are exemplified.

    (D4)

    Clause (2a) insures that each exemplification of a synchronic complete

    specification by a member of U gets matched up with a corresponding

    exemplification of an indiscernible synchronic complete specification by

    a member of U. Clause (2b) insures that these exemplifications of syn-

    chronic complete specifications come in the same temporal order, sepa-

    rated by the same temporal distances. Clause (2c) insures that parts in

    the subvenient domain that persist from one part of the micro-history to

    another are paired with corresponding persisting parts in the other micro-

    history.

    Now it is obvious that when two series of dots are arranged in the

    same ways on pages that are bound together in the same order, flippingone of the resulting books will reveal a cat chasing a mouse if and only if

    flipping the other book would do the same. Something analogous is true

    for any domain of wholes made out of parts. When there are indiscernible

  • 8/2/2019 Zimmermann - Criteria of Identity

    10/22

    290 DEAN W. ZIMMERMAN

    exemplifications of micro-histories, the one can be the history of a single

    supervening object if and only if the other is; and the supervening ob-

    jects must be indiscernible with respect to kind and other A-properties. So

    some micro-histories will be paired with supervening objects. The relevantpairing relation and notion of indiscernibility of A-histories are these:

    Us exemplification of B-micro-history T constitutes the his-

    tory of a single object x =df U exemplifies T; and, for all

    times t during Us exemplification of T, x exists at t iff x is

    constituted at t by some member of U which then exemplifies

    some element of T.

    (D5)

    x and y have the same A-history during t and t =df there is

    a series of A-properties S such that: (a) x exemplifies every

    member of S during t, and y exemplifies every member of S

    during t; (2) a property is in Sif it is an A-property exemplified

    by x during t or by y during t; (3) for every pair P and Q in S,x exemplifies P n minutes before Q during t iffy exemplifies

    P n minutes before Q during t.

    (D6)

    The diachronic supervenience of wholes on parts can now be stated:

    For all series U and U consisting of sets of the members of

    (D1), and all worlds w1 and w2, if Us exemplification of B-

    micro-history T is structure-specific indiscernible from Us

    exemplification of B-micro-history T, then (1) Us exempli-

    fication of T un w1 constitutes the history of a single object

    iffUs exemplification ofT does in w2; and (2) if either ex-

    emplification constitutes the history of a single object, then, forevery object x constituted by Us exemplification of T,11 x has

    the same A-history during the time of this exemplification as

    some object y constituted by Us exemplification ofT during

    the time of the latter exemplification.

    (DS)

    The existence of diachronic criteria of unity follows from (DS). For

    any kind of supervenient whole K that can be made out of the parts in the

    subvenient domain, there is a set L ofB-micro-histories which includes all

    and only the B-micro-histories that are the histories of a K. By (DS), none

    of these could have been exemplified without being the history of a K. So

    it is a necessary and sufficient condition for a given B-micro-history to be

    the history of a K that it belong to the set L. This, I shall argue, constitutesan informative criterion of diachronic unity for Ks.

    In what sense, and under what conditions will the set L of micro-

    histories serve as an informative criterion of diachronic unity for Ks? For

  • 8/2/2019 Zimmermann - Criteria of Identity

    11/22

    CRITERIA OF IDENTITY AND THE IDENTITY MYSTICS 291

    one thing, there should be no Ks in the subvenient domain. But even in

    some cases where there are no Ks in the realm of parts, the resulting

    criterion may be less informative than one would like. Suppose, for in-

    stance, that there were infinitely divisible Aristotelian matter, every chunkcomposed of smaller bits of the same stuff. And suppose the domain of

    supervening wholes contains all and only the hunks of this stuff that weigh

    more than one kilogram, and the subvenient domain all and only the hunks

    that weigh one kilogram or less. Now I suppose there will be something

    informative about the criterion implied by the version of (DS) resulting in

    this case. For instance, a kind of mereological essentialism would probably

    be true of this stuff: a more-than-one-kilogram mass of it cannot survive

    the gain or loss of any smaller-than-one-kilogram parts; and as long as

    you have all the same smaller-than-one-kilogram parts, you have the same

    larger-than-one-kilogram whole. But the supervenient and subvenient do-

    mains in this case are such obviously trivial restrictions on a single broader,

    naturally occurring kind, that the information gleaned from the criteriondoes not seem worth much.

    More is learned if the subvenient kind is very different from the super-

    venient kind, with associated persistence conditions different from those

    of the supervening wholes. If criteria for ships can be given in terms of

    the histories of planks, criteria for cells in terms of the histories of organic

    molecules, criteria for organisms in terms of the histories of cells, and so

    on, then there will be, it seems to me, importantly informative criteria of

    diachronic unity. In general, the more dissimilar the subvenient and su-

    pervenient domains, the more informative the criteria that follow from the

    thesis of mereological supervenience.

    If properties like being a part ofthis

    ship and relations like being partof the same persisting ship as were allowed into the supervenience base of

    a thesis of mereological supervenience for ships, there would be no assur-

    ance whatsoever that informative criteria of diachronic unity would follow.

    But since the supervenience base is restricted to just intrinsic properties of

    parts and their relations to other such parts, there should be no danger of

    uninformativeness resulting from the impurity of the ideology employed

    in the statement of mereological supervenience.

    Here is the most serious objection to the whole enterprise of deriving

    criteria of diachronic unity from mereological supervenience: What has

    been proven to follow from (DS) is just the existence of a set of micro-

    histories that coincides with all the possible careers of supervening objects.

    But, for any even mildly complex domain of wholes, there will be infinitelymany such micro-histories. The condition, having a micro-history that

    is a member of L might be, for all we know, impossibly complicated

  • 8/2/2019 Zimmermann - Criteria of Identity

    12/22

    292 DEAN W. ZIMMERMAN

    for human beings to grasp in its details. So we have no assurance that a

    criterion that follows from mereological supervenience could in any sense

    inform us of anything.

    The contention here is that the members ofL might be such a heteroge-neous bunch, with so little in common, that there is nothing more we can

    say about them than that they happen to be just the set of micro-histories

    upon which the wholes in question supervene. I maintain that, at least in

    the case of the sorts of familiar, complex material objects that most interest

    us, a defeatist attitude towards our ability to grasp what these histories have

    in common is highly suspect. Consider, for example, what this would mean

    in the case of the supervenience of cats upon the histories of smallish bits

    of cat-hair, cat-flesh, and cat-bone. What if these histories had too little in

    common for us to make useful generalizations about them? Then wouldnt

    they also have too little in common for us to be able to have reasonable

    convictions concerning when we have or do not have the same cat?

    I take it that our evidence for sameness of cat comes from observingcats observing how cat-hair changes color only gradually, how cats grow

    only gradually, how changes in look or behavior tend to be retained, etc.

    And indiscernible histories of feline flesh and hair will be indiscernible

    with respect to the observations of these sorts that they make possible; so

    there couldnt be indiscernible micro-histories the one of which provided

    more evidence for the persistence of a cat than the other. Furthermore, our

    sensitivity to the observations that justify belief in cat persistence is not

    a wholly subrational process we dont have bare intuitions about cat

    identities that bypass the evidence of our senses, that are not grounded in

    the awareness of similarities and differences with respect to hair-coloring,

    behavior, size, shape, and arrangements of feline bodily parts. These sim-ilarities and differences are not only completely determined by the micro-

    histories of feline flesh and hair; knowing about them is simply a matter of

    knowing about the micro-history, knowing that there are bits of cat flesh

    and hair arranged thus and so, and that these bits at one time are suitably

    related to similar collections of bits at later times.

    Could there be a merely contingent connection, perhaps in the form of

    a brute but non-necessary law of nature, connecting micro-histories of cat

    parts with facts about persisting cats? I doubt it. For one thing, there would

    be no way to tell the difference between a world in which the law holds and

    one in which it does not. The micro-histories determine all the observable

    facts, so no observable differences between such worlds could appear. And

    just try imagining what would be involved in the failure of cat-persistenceto supervene upon micro-histories of feline flesh, blood, and bone. Tibbles

    survives the routine loss of a single hair, say, in our world; none the worse

  • 8/2/2019 Zimmermann - Criteria of Identity

    13/22

    CRITERIA OF IDENTITY AND THE IDENTITY MYSTICS 293

    for wear, she wanders on, and grows a new one. But, in some other world

    a world in which there are no changes in the laws governing the behavior

    of feline cells, for weve included causal powers of parts in the superve-

    nience base, she loses the hair, and poof, shes gone. Of course, nothingelse happens differently; a cat (a different one) wanders on, growing its

    new hair, digesting the same mouse that Tibbles ate moments before, etc.

    Unless removal of the hair had resulted in something substantially different

    in the nonactual world such as the loss of something like a kitty-soul

    this is too wild to countenance as a possibility. If a cat, or any other thing,

    is just a whole made out of suitably arranged cells, then the micro-histories

    of these cells determine the histories of wholes with a force stronger than

    mere nomic necessity.

    4. OBJECTIONS FROM THE IDENTITY MYSTICS

    There are important new voices being raised against criteria of diachronic

    unity for human beings.12 One wonders how they would respond to all this.

    The old guard objectors to criteria, such as Chisholm and Swinburne,13

    reason as follows: there are no informative criteria of identity for persons;

    there would be if persons were large material objects the size of living

    human bodies; therefore a person is not a living human body. But the new

    opponents of criteria for persons, including Trenton Merricks and E. J.

    Lowe, do not accept this reasoning. They ask: Why could there not be

    large-scale physical objects six-foot-tall, 150 pound objects, for instance

    that lack informative criteria of identity? Their answer: No reason at all.

    How might Lowe and Merricks try to resist my argument? I say com-

    plex objects made out of parts supervene upon them, are dependent upon

    them. And this requires criteria of unity that can be given in terms of those

    parts. Lowe might respond by simply denying that persons need supervene

    on, say, molecules or cells, since on his view14 persons have neither

    molecules nor cells nor anything else as parts. A person like myself is a

    material object, in that I have material properties like being six feet tall and

    weighing 150 pounds. But I am unlike the human organism here, and the

    mass of stuff that makes it up, in that I have no parts.

    Theres a familiar objection to views according to which one material

    object can constitute a distinct one: Since each is just like the other with

    respect to locally manifest properties, each is 150 pounds if either is. But

    then lifting both should be like lifting 300 pounds. But it isnt.15This objection is not as devastating as I once thought.16 Heres the

    problem with it. Take anything with parts that add up to 150 pounds; when

    you lift it, you lift something that weighs 150 pounds (the object itself) and

  • 8/2/2019 Zimmermann - Criteria of Identity

    14/22

    294 DEAN W. ZIMMERMAN

    something that weighs 100 pounds (its bottom two-thirds) and something

    that weighs 50 pounds (its top one-third); so why doesnt that take 300-

    pounds-worth of effort? Answer: because the extra things lifted were

    just parts of the whole. So in figuring how much work it will take to lifta given collection of objects, one must never add the weight of one to the

    weight of another if the one is part of the other. There are a number of

    principles that will insure this doesnt happen. For instance, if all the parts

    in a set are constituted, ultimately, of atomic parts, one can simply say:

    Add the weights of all the smallest parts of anything in the set. Or, if

    theres one member that has every other member as a part, say: Weigh

    only the biggest member. Now, in the normal case of coincident objects

    say, a 150-pound hunk of clay and the 150-pound statue made from it

    following such principles gives the right results. Since every part of the

    clay is a part of the statue (or at least is constituted entirely of parts of the

    statue), you shouldnt add the weight of any hunk of clay to the reading of

    150 pounds that results from weighing the statue alone.Notice, however, what happens when we accuse Lowe of countenanc-

    ing distinct objects with weights that dont add up. Applying the dont

    count common parts principle for figuring weights doesnt help. Since the

    150-pound person doesnt have any proper parts, a fortiori it has no part

    (proper or improper) of the coincident hunk of matter or human organism

    as a proper part. Could it have the organism as a whole as an improperpart?

    Then the organism would be its sole part. But the organism is not simple; so

    this seems ruled out, by the transitivity of part. Could the simple person

    be a part (proper or improper) of the organism? Not an improper part, for

    the reasons just mentioned. And suppose you insist that it is a proper part of

    the organism. Well, the organism then consists of all the cells, molecules,and so on, plus this extra part, the person. Ignore that extra part for a

    moment, and whats left of the organism still weighs 150 pounds. So the

    remainder reached by subtracting the person from the whole (a remainder

    which sure looks like a living human organism so far as I can see, there is

    no independent motivation for saying that the organism has a simple person

    as a part), plus the person (which has no part in common with it), should

    still weigh 300 pounds. It follows from Lowes view, then, that there really

    are two wholly distinct objects here, a person and a living human organism,

    each weighing 150 pounds but sharing no parts in common. The fact that

    both can be lifted so easily constitutes an empirical refutation of his theory.

    If, then, persons are to be material objects coincident with these gross

    physical bodies, they had better have some physical parts. And this takesus to Trenton Merrickss view: although human persons are wholes made

    entirely of living cells, nonetheless there are no informative criteria of

  • 8/2/2019 Zimmermann - Criteria of Identity

    15/22

    CRITERIA OF IDENTITY AND THE IDENTITY MYSTICS 295

    diachronic unity for persons. This implies that (DS) is false for the do-

    mains of persons and living cells that is, human beings do not supervene

    mereologically upon their cells.

    But recall what this would mean: there are indiscernible micro-historiestelling precisely the same stories about cells, one of which is the history

    of a single human being, the other not. Now if extrinsic determiners were

    excluded from the supervenience base, one could imagine cases that might

    fit this bill. Remember Tibbles and her tail: there might be indiscernible

    micro-histories involving feline cells, the one of which is the history of a

    cat that loses her tail, the other of which is not a history of a whole cat

    at all rather, it is partly the history of a whole cat, but also partly the

    history of a proper part of a cat (all of Tibbles but her tail). Supposing

    we buy this possibility, we should allow generalized spatial relations in

    the supervenience base. But once extrinsic determiners are let in, denying

    diachronic supervenience of persons on their cells becomes truly heroic. It

    amounts to the claim that everything could have been the same with respectto all the histories of human cells everywhere (recall that there is now no

    limit to the range of spatial relations to other cells that can be generalized

    and included in the supervenience base), and yet there be some persons

    missing from the world, or some extra ones appearing. How could human

    beings be made completely out of cells, yet float free in this way from

    their parts? If certain kinds of wholes are made entirely out of certain kinds

    of parts, then worlds that are globally indiscernible with respect to what

    goes on at the level of these parts had better be globally indiscernible with

    respect to what goes on at the level of wholes. To claim that its possible for

    there to have been differences in when and where persons are constituted

    by cells even if everything had been the same at the level of cells is topromulgate a kind of identity mysticism. Persons are material objects,

    but they can come loose from their parts, can pass from one set of parts to

    another like shadows.

    5. INTRINSIC CRITERIA OF UNITY?

    Accepting the moral drawn from the case of Tibbles, above, leads one

    very naturally to conclude that no interesting kind of whole supervenes

    synchronically upon just the intrinsic properties of and spatial relations

    among objects in the domain of parts. Sortal properties for complex objects

    appear to be extrinsically sensitive in the following sense:

  • 8/2/2019 Zimmermann - Criteria of Identity

    16/22

    296 DEAN W. ZIMMERMAN

    Being a C is extrinsically sensitive =df being a C is possibly

    such that there is an object x which: (1) is a C, and (2) has a

    proper part y that is not a C but is constituted by some set S of

    members of (D1) that is possibly such that: (a) it will constitutex, (b) x will be a C, and (c) S will exemplify a set-theoretic

    complete specification (extrinsic determiners excluded) that is

    indiscernible from the one it exemplifies while constituting the

    proper part y.

    (D7)

    An extrinsically sensitive C is one that a thing can lack just in virtue of

    being a proper part of a C; and a set could constitute a part of some x that

    is a C at t, and then come to constitute x itself at t, and be intrinsically

    just the same at t and t.

    If causation does not propagate instantaneously, then any criterion of

    synchronic unity that appeals in an essential way to causal relations is in

    danger of being extrinsically sensitive. Let x be Tibbles with a tail, andS be the set of all Tibbless cells except for those in her tail. Consider

    the synchronic complete specification S exemplifies now (absent extrinsic

    determiners). Given that causal influence takes a finite time to be felt,

    couldnt the cells in the tail have been annihilated or have jumped away by

    some freak of quantum mechanics, leaving S, for the moment, intrinsically

    just as it is? If so, then, unless we want to say that S constitutes a cat even

    now (with the tail still attached), we must admit that being a cat does not

    supervene upon intrinsic determiners alone the criterion of synchronic

    unity for cats must include extrinsic determiners as well.

    A natural response to this argument is to balk at the alleged possibility

    described: it is impossible for there to be a set of cells intrinsically just like

    S is now, but without a tail (or at least a part of a tail) attached. But arent

    all of the particles that make up the tail-cells at some distance from the

    particles that make up the cells in S? If so, it would seem that there must

    be a time-lag, however small, during which the particles in the tail-cells

    could be gone but before which their absence would not be registered by

    any intrinsic changes in S.

    Are there ways in which this conclusion could be avoided? One could

    insist that the instant the cells in question cease to be parts of the cat,

    something changes somewhere in the cells that remain. This will require

    either instantaneous causation at a distance, or that some parts of the tail

    cells are coincident with some parts of some members ofS. I take it that the

    latter is preferable. But can there really be parts of one cell coincident withparts of another? If they share some parts in common, this is possible as

    two homes may share a common wall. The members of the supervenience

    base can, however, be chosen in such a way that none shares parts with

  • 8/2/2019 Zimmermann - Criteria of Identity

    17/22

    CRITERIA OF IDENTITY AND THE IDENTITY MYSTICS 297

    any other. This may require arbitrary stipulation about where one cell ends

    and another begins, but that shouldnt effect the truth of the supervenience

    thesis.

    I am inclined to accept all this, but to insist that criteria of synchronicunity are intrinsic nonetheless. But then what sorts of complex wholes

    could there be what kinds of complex things are not extrinsically sensi-

    tive? In order that a kind C not be extrinsically sensitive, no C can contain

    smaller parts that could come to constitute it without changing intrinsically.

    So ifx is a C, then any set of parts of x that either does constitute or could

    constitute a Cmust be such that the C they do or would constitute would be

    distinct from x. In other words, something very much like mereological es-

    sentialism must be true for things of kind C. This does not bother me, since

    I think there are independent reasons to be a mereological essentialist. Let

    me briefly recount them:

    Whenever there is a question concerning whether a certain collection

    of objects composes a whole, there is also a question concerning whethera certain mass of mattercomposes a whole the mass of matter composed

    of all the bits of stuff that constitute the members of the collection. This

    mass of matter is itself physical, and (according to me) itself a whole not

    a collection or plurality. By my lights, then, whenever one asks, Do the

    members of S compose a whole?, the answer is always Yes because

    theres bound to be a mass of matter that is identical with the sum of the

    members of S. Whats more, masses of matter arent like cats and ships;

    theyre not sensitive to extrinsic factors; they dont cease to be when scat-

    tered, or when other things are attached to them or detached from them. So

    whether or not the members ofS compose something does not depend on

    relations to things outside the group; in fact, it doesnt even depend uponrelations (other than mere coexistence) to things inside the group.

    Now if the members of S compose a whole distinct from the mass of

    matter, then there would be two physical objects, of different kinds but

    otherwise exactly alike, in the same place at the same time. But thats

    impossible. So the only object thats really there, or even could be there,

    is just the mass of matter. Collections of objects only compose masses of

    matter; so, naturally, all principles of synchronic unity are intrinsic.

    There are at least two spots where this train slows down enough for

    almost everyone but me to jump off. The first is at the point where I say

    that, for every collection of objects, there is a mass of matter that is the

    sum of those objects. I have defended this thesis at great length elsewhere,

    and with such relentlessness of detail as to put off almost everyone whohas tried to work out my argument (always a good defensive strategy). 17

    But heres the bare bones of my reasoning:

  • 8/2/2019 Zimmermann - Criteria of Identity

    18/22

    298 DEAN W. ZIMMERMAN

    A mass of matter is simply the kind of thing that we refer to by mass

    terms preceded by the or an unstressed some as in, He gave me some

    water, which I mixed with the water from Heraclitus tub. A leading fea-

    ture of masses is their mereological rigidity: we are unwilling to allow thatI still have precisely the same water he gave me if Ive spilled even a few

    drops; although I may still have mostof the water he gave me. Now some

    philosophers want to say were picking out pluralities, not wholes, when

    we talk in this way of some water or the copper in the statue; but I say this

    couldnt be so, at least not in general. Heres why: Aristotelian theories of

    matter are, if false, only contingently false; there could have been, perhaps

    even are, what Aristotle called homeomerous substances homogeneous

    stuffs that dont break down into simple atoms, but are instead of the same

    kind through and through. An artifact or organism made out of some such

    stuff-kind K would be constituted by a mass of matter that could not be

    identified with a plurality of smallest K-parts. Nor would it be safe to pick

    a set of parts of some arbitrary size and use those as ersatz-atoms. Afterall, these ersatz-atoms, to do duty for the mass of K, cannot survive the

    gain or loss of any parts. But, since the grid used to select the ersatz-atoms

    was chosen arbitrarily, it turns out that any portion of K you pick is in fact

    a whole that cannot gain or lose parts.

    Solving metaphysical problems of constitution requires that one take

    into account the possibility of Aristotelian stuff-kinds. It would be absurdly

    parochial to rest content with the reflection that the heaps of matter of

    which we are constituted do not appear to be homeomerous, and so can

    be treated as sets of atoms. Couldnt things have turned out differently

    for us? Or, if not precisely for us (perhaps we are necessarily constituted

    by electrons and quarks, themselves necessarily indivisible), at least forbeings just like us in every way that matters? And so I plump for a theory of

    masses that treats all the most fundamental material stuff-kinds as physical

    wholes, not collections of atoms.

    The second point at which many philosophers would jump off is at the

    rejection of coincident entities. I say there cant be, in the same place at

    the same time, both a human being that can gain or lose parts and a mass

    of matter that cannot. The friends of temporal parts say both can be there

    because, really, theres just one thing filling that place a single temporal

    part shared between four-dimensional objects that diverge before and after

    the time in question. The human being and the stuff she is now made of

    overlap for a tiny stretch of space-time, like intersecting roads with a single

    square of pavement in common. Others who, like me, reject temporal partsare nonetheless friends of coincident objects; there can be two physical

    wholes here with differing persistence conditions, but weighing the same

  • 8/2/2019 Zimmermann - Criteria of Identity

    19/22

    CRITERIA OF IDENTITY AND THE IDENTITY MYSTICS 299

    amount and sharing, at some level, all the same parts. This sort of brute

    difference between intrinsically indiscernible physical things is, I fear, be-

    yond my comprehension. So I see no choice but to stay on the train until the

    last stop: The only true principles of synchronic unity are ones that yieldmasses of matter. Garden variety objects that ostensibly gain and lose parts

    over time must be logical constructions out of masses, or processes passing

    through various parcels of stuff in something like the way a hurricane is

    a process that passes through many different tracts of air and water.

    There are many who would reject this argument for mereological es-

    sentialism but insist that criteria of synchronic unity are intrinsic. 18 What

    motivates their commitment? One factor is probably this: Once extrinsic

    determiners are allowed to play a role in criteria of synchronic unity, there

    would seem to be no way to exclude them from criteria of diachronic

    unity, and thus no principled way to resist best candidate theories of

    identity. I suspect that anyone who rejects both the doctrine of temporal

    parts and best candidate theories of identity will be forced inexorablytowards mereological essentialism. But I do not pretend to have shown

    this here.

    NOTES

    I have benefited from the criticisms and questions of my commentator and members

    of the audience in Innsbruck, and also from very detailed comments on an early draft

    from Trenton Merricks and Loretta Torrago. The paper was also read at Purdue University,

    where Franklin Mason, Martin Curd, and others provided some very helpful criticisms and

    suggestions.1

    I defend this assumption in Zimmerman (1997b).2 Compare Noonan (1989, 161162).3 Lewis (1983).4 See Appendix 1 of Zimmerman (1997a) and Langton et al. (1997).5 Cf. Kim (1993b). The scheme developed in this section is foreshadowed in Zimmerman

    (1997a).6 Would any animal physically indiscernible from an ordinary cat still be a cat, even if

    it were not generated from ordinary cat DNA? Some say no its not a cat unless its

    a descendent of ordinary earthly cats. But it could mate with ordinary cats, and produce

    cat-like offspring. Surely the animal would have the same persistence conditions as ordi-

    nary cats. So, I would argue, there must be some persistence-condition-determining sortal

    property that such a creature would share with ordinary cats.7 I do not say if either constitutes an object, then the object constituted by S in w1 is

    indiscernible with respect to A-properties from the one constituted by S

    in w2, since Ido not want to alienate the friends of coincident objects at least not at this point. A similar

    complication appears in (DS).

    I am indebted to Franklin Mason for pointing out that earlier versions of (SS) and (DS)

    presupposed that there are no coincident objects differing in sortal and other properties.

  • 8/2/2019 Zimmermann - Criteria of Identity

    20/22

    300 DEAN W. ZIMMERMAN

    8 Poor Tibbles wandered into a philosophical laboratory by accident back in the sixties.

    Peter Geach was chief investigator. For an account of the incident, cf. Wiggins (1968).9 My strategy here should be compared with Kims (1993c) for proving, in the case of

    single-domain supervenience, that supervening properties are equivalent to disjunctions of

    maximal B-properties (the strongest consistent properties constructible from propertiesin the supervenience base).10 Artifacts might be thought to represent a counterexample to this claim; couldnt there

    be a block of marble just like the David, related in the same ways to other bits of marble

    as the David, but not a statue? I take this failure of supervenience as just another reason to

    think that artifacts and artworks are fictions, logical constructions out of objects and times.

    Consider the ease with which a piece of driftwood or a urinal may be turned into a piece

    of art. How could such a change really represent a difference in the number of objects

    there are? And arent all artworks and artifacts on a continuum with such frivolous cases

    of creation?11 I leave open the possibility that more than one object be constituted by Us exemplifi-

    cation of T; there is no need, at this point, to presuppose the falsity of a metaphysics of

    coincident objects.12

    Cf. Merricks (1998), Lowe (1996, ch. 2), Lowe (1989, 121137), Oderberg (1993), andMackenzie (1983) 161174). There is considerable skepticism about the availability of

    informative criteria of identity in Mavrodes (1977) and Quinn (1978).13 Swinburne concludes that the only live possibility, then, is that persons are (or at least

    have) an immaterial part; while Chisholm, in some moods at least, wants to leave open the

    more bizarre possibility that persons are tiny physical particles. See Swinburne (1997) and

    Chisholm (1989).14 See Lowe (1996, ch. 2).15 Cf. Zimmerman (1995a, 8593) and (1995b).16 Thanks to Peter van Inwagen and Peter Simons for making me see this.17 Cf. Zimmerman (1995a).18 Compare, e.g., van Inwagen (1990, 1213).

    REFERENCES

    Chisholm, R. M.: 1989, On Metaphysics, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, pp.

    2541 and 11928.

    Kim, J.: 1993a, Supervenience and Mind: Selected Philosophical Essays, Cambridge

    University Press, Cambridge.

    Kim, J.: 1993b, Supervenience for Multiple Domains, reprinted in Kim (1993a), pp. 109

    30.

    Kim, J.: 1993c, Concepts of Supervenience, reprinted in Kim (1993a), pp. 5378.

    Langton, R. and Lewis, D.: 1998, Defining Intrinsic , Philosophy and Phenomenolog-

    ical Research 58, 33345.

    Lowe, E. J.: 1996, Subjects of Experience, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Lowe, E. J.: 1989, Kinds of Being, Basil Blackwell, Oxford.Mackenzie, P. T.: 1983, Personal Identity and the Imagination, Philosophy 58, 16174.

    Mavrodes, G. I.: 1977, The Life Everlasting and the Bodily Criterion of Identity, Nos

    11, 2739.

    Merricks, T.: 1998, There are no Criteria of Identity Over Time, Nos 32, 10624.

  • 8/2/2019 Zimmermann - Criteria of Identity

    21/22

    CRITERIA OF IDENTITY AND THE IDENTITY MYSTICS 301

    Noonan, H.: 1989, Personal Identity, Routledge, London.

    Oderberg, D. S.: 1993, The Metaphysics of Identity Over Time, St. Martins Press, New

    York.

    Quinn, P. L.: 1978, Personal Identity, Bodily Continuity and Resurrection, International

    Journal for Philosophy of Religion 9, 10113.Swinburne, R.: 1997, The Evolution of the Soul, revised ed., Clarendon Press, Oxford, pp.

    14560.

    Van Inwagen, P.: 1990, Material Beings, Cornell University Press, Ithaca, New York.

    Wiggins, D.: 1968, On Being in the Same Place at the Same Time, Philosophical Review

    77, 905.

    Zimmerman, D. W.: 1995a, Theories of Masses and Problems of Constitution, The

    Philosophical Review 104, 53110.

    Zimmerman, D. W.: 1995b, Ist ein Krper-Austausch mglich? Kommentar zu Peter van

    Inwagen, in J. Brandl, A. Hieke, and P. Simons (eds.) Metaphysik Neue Zugnge zu

    alten Fragen, Academia Verlag, St. Augustin, pp. 26568.

    Zimmerman, D. W.: 1997a, Immanent Causation, Nos supplementary volume (Philo-

    sophical Perspectives, Vol. 11: Mind, Causation, and World), pp. 43371.

    Zimmerman, D. W.: 1997b, Chisholm and the Essences of Events, in L. E. Hahn (ed.),

    The Philosophy of Roderick M. Chisholm, Open Court, La Salle, Illinois, pp. 73100.

    Department of Philosophy

    University of Notre Dame

    Notre Dame, IN 46556

    USA

    E-mail: [email protected]

  • 8/2/2019 Zimmermann - Criteria of Identity

    22/22