Web viewThe method of agreement suggests that we identify the cause by looking at which food in...

38
NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro LOGIC LOGIC – DEFINITION, AND MORE Logic is the Study of the principles and concepts of good reasoning. This implies that there is a distinction between good and bad reasoning. Also, logicians, people who study logic, are not interested in HOW people reason, those are psychologists. Logicians are interested in the principles of reasoning. THE THREE “LAWS OF THOUGHT” Early Logicians defined logic as the “science of the laws of thought” and that there are three basic laws we must obey to think correctly: 1. The principle of identity: This asserts that if any statement is true, then it is true! 2. The principle of non-contradiction: This asserts that no statement can be both true and false. 3. The principle of excluded middle: this asserts that any statement is either true or false. 1

Transcript of Web viewThe method of agreement suggests that we identify the cause by looking at which food in...

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

LOGICLOGIC – DEFINITION, AND MORE

Logic is the Study of the principles and concepts of good reasoning.

This implies that there is a distinction between good and bad reasoning.

Also, logicians, people who study logic, are not interested in HOW people reason, those are psychologists. Logicians are interested in the principles of reasoning.

THE THREE “LAWS OF THOUGHT”

Early Logicians defined logic as the “science of the laws of thought” and that there are three basic laws we must obey to think correctly:

1. The principle of identity: This asserts that if any statement is true, then it is true!2. The principle of non-contradiction: This asserts that no statement can be both true and

false.3. The principle of excluded middle: this asserts that any statement is either true or false.

History of LogicAristotle (384-322 B.C.E.) invented logic. He used letters for terms, he created syllogistic logic, which studies arguments like these

All humans are mortal. = All H are M.

All Greeks are humans. = All G are H.

Therefore All Greeks are mortal. = All G re M.

This argument is valid because of its structure. So any argument with the same structure is valid.

1

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

Aristotle studied the logic of possibility and necessity.

Stoics continued Aristotle’s work and in the Medieval Period many thinkers developed ways to teach Aristotle’s system of logic. During the Enlightenment many philosophers would just agree that nothing significant was invented in logic after Aristotle. Leibniz (1646-1716), however, anticipated modern logic, proposing a concept of symbolic language, but his work was published after George Boole (1815-1864).

In 1879, Gottlob Frege (1848-1925) invented modern logic. He created more ways to express logic through symbols and operators. His project was to show that arithmetic is reducible to logic. Some sets, such as the set of all teacups, or of all cats are not members of themselves. The set of all teacups is not a teacup and the set of all cats is not a cat. Other sets, such as the set of all non-teacups, or the set of all abstract objects are members of themselves because the set of all non-teacups is a non-teacup and the set of all abstract objects is an abstract object. Now, consider the set of all sets that are not members of themselves “R.” If R is a member of itself, then by definition it must not be a member of itself. Similarly, if R is not a member of itself, then by definition it must be a member of itself. Frege’s life work was destroyed! This is known as the Russell’s Paradox. Russell and Whitehead developed a system that fixed this problem.

These new developments propelled logic forward to new territories that Aristotle would be impressed. Systems like truth tables were invented. Modern Logic was important in the development of computers. Also the most important aspect of logic is modal logic dealing with necessary and possible.

The distinction between analytic and synthetic judgments, and by that between a priori and a posteriori knowledge.

Analytic and Synthetic Judgments

Any sentence has a Subject and a Predicate.

A simple subject/predicate sentence can be either universal, “all bachelors are unmarried,” or particular, “this chalk is white” is Analytic if and only if the predicate concept is “contained in” the subject concept. 

To analyze something is to determine how it is constructed out of its constituent parts. An analysis of a concept is like a definition of the concept. For example, we might discover that something fits the concept bachelor if and only if it is an unmarried male person. In this case we can say that the concept bachelor contains such concept as being unmarried. So a judgment is analytic if analysis of the subject-concept reveals that it contains the predicate-concept.

A judgment is synthetic if and only if it is not analytic. Or, a judgment is synthetic just when the predicate concept is not contained in the subject concept. For example, “all bachelors are tall,” “the Sun will rise tomorrow,” or “the children are playing in the playground,” are synthetic judgments.

2

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

A Priori and A Posteriori Knowledge:

Consider these two statements:

1. All bachelors are unmarried.2. Some bachelors are happy.

While we know both to be true, how we know differs.

A judgment is knowable a priori if and only if it can be justified independently of experience. A judgment is a posteriori if it cannot be known without recourse to experience. Arguably, the truths of mathematics (2 + 2 = 4) and logic (if George will go only if John will go, and George will go, then John will go) are a priori. We do not need empirical evidence in order to know that they are true.

Most judgments of particular fact, however, are a posteriori. I cannot know that a particular room is more than 10’ wide without some sort of experience, for example the experience of measuring the room with a tape measure.

Can we have synthetic a priori knowledge?

Immanuel Kant says yes.

Consider, for example, our knowledge that 7+5=12 and that the interior angles of any triangle add up to a straight line. These (and similar) truths of mathematics and geometry are synthetic judgments: the concept “the sum of the interior angles” is not contained in the concept of a triangle. Yet, clearly, such truths are known a priori, since they apply with strict and universal necessity to all of the objects of our experience, without having been derived from that experience itself.

In 1951, Willard Van Orman Quine published the essay “Two Dogmas of Empiricism” in which he argued that the analytic–synthetic distinction is untenable. The argument at bottom is that there are no “analytic” truths, but all truths involve an empirical aspect.

3

Analytic Synthetic

A Priori X ?A Posteriori X

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

Quine argues:

Analytic propositions – propositions grounded in meanings, independent of matters of fact.

Synthetic propositions – propositions grounded in fact.

The notion of an analytic proposition requires a notion of synonymy, but establishing synonymy inevitably leads to matters of fact – synthetic propositions.

What is knowledge?Is knowledge only what is true or rather what is useful? But is it what is useful always true? Take mathematics. We agree that it is a form of knowledge. But is 2+2=4 really knowledge or a tautology? What can 2+2=4 tell us about the world?

Religion: many have justified belief in claiming knowledge of the existence of a god. Others, in a similar way, have sound justification to claim that there isn’t any god.

Then to what extent is it possible for a given subject or entity to be known? One view is the objection that there is very little or no knowledge at all—skepticism. If you think you can clearly define knowledge, then you know not what knowledge is.

Before Galileo, earth was “known” to be at the center of the universe. Today we “know” better—but do we? What puts us in a better position? If knowledge is linked with truth, what is the best instrument with which to acquire truth? Is it science? Is it religion?

We saw the distinction between empiricism and rationalism. Which of the two views affords us knowledge?

Knowledge that, knowledge how: in epistemology in general, the kind of knowledge in which philosophers are interested is propositional knowledge, AKA “knowledge that.”

Example: The way in which we are able to see atoms is by using the “Scanning Tunneling Microscope” (STM). This type of microscope has an extremely sensitive “probe” with a very fine tip that, so to speak, feels the bumps caused by atoms. These “bumps” then are converted by a computer into a picture showing the individual atoms.

When the probe of the microscope is brought close to the surface of the sample, there is an interaction between the electron cloud and the tip of the probe. The question that follows is obvious:

4

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

What are those bumps, real atoms or images produced by a microscope that was built by its inventor to see those images?

Atoms are thousands of times smaller than the smallest visible light waves, but there is so much evidence for atoms, and the success of many theories depend on the fact that we know so much about atoms. Now, some philosophers may object that such devices as the STM are made appositely to see what we want to see? But others say that if atoms do not exist, then it would seem that our theories work accidentally!

Traditional Theory of knowledge: Many epistemologists hold the Justified True Belief (JTB) account of knowledge: the claim that knowledge can be conceptually analyzed as justified true belief.

A subject S knows that a proposition P is true if and only if:

1. P is true2. S believes that P is true, and3. S is justified in believing that P is true

Is Justified True Belief (JTB) knowledge? Consider these 3 scenarios:

I. Your roommate is watching TV in the kitchen. You’re in the bathroom preparing for work. You need to know the time and so you get out of the bathroom and see the time as it appears on the lower right corner of the TV set, which reads 2:15 P.M. You’re late for work. You get dressed quickly and zoom out. Now what you don’t know is that your friend was playing a tape. It just so happened that the time in the video precisely coincided with the real time. Now, do you know the time?

1. It is true that the time is 2:15.2. You believe that the time is 2:15, and,3. You are justified in believing that the time is 2:15.

5

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

LOGIC THE SCIENCE OF ARGUMENTS

Different sciences, like biology, mathematics, etc. study their respective subject matters. Logic studies arguments. Arguments are the subject matter of logic.

In logic, an argument is a piece of reasoning used to show or express or prove a point; that point, whatever it may be, is supported by sub-points, which are statements.

For example:

All humans are mortal. My logic prof. is human.

Therefore, my logic prof. is mortal.

This is a classic example of an argument. A point is expressed—namely, that logic prof. is mortal. This is called conclusion. The conclusion is supported by certain statements, All humans are mortal and my logic prof. is human.

ARGUMENT DEFINITION: An argument is a group of premises (at least one premise) in support of a conclusion.

OR

A group of statements, one of which is claimed to follow from the others.

PREMISE DEFINITION: A premise is a statement capable of being true or false. “Fetch me a bagel!” is not a premise. “Joe is my dog.” is a premise.

6

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

CONCLUSION DEFINITION: A conclusion is also a statement capable of being true or false; in addition, it is the main point of the argument, that is, the statement that is claimed to follow from other premises (statements).

HOW TO UNDERSTAND/RECOGNIZE AN ARGUMENT

To understand an argument you must first pick out the conclusion. To pick out the conclusion ask yourself, “What’s the main point? What does the speaker want to persuade me to believe?”

Also you can spot the conclusion as it is often preceded by certain clue words: Therefore, thus, it must be deduced that, so, consequently…

On the other hand, premises often begin with these words: Since, because, for, given that…

ARGUMENT FORM

Arguments are given by people in the form of a speech. We will study textbook examples of arguments to facilitate our discussion.

Also, the arguments I will present will have numbered premises. Conclusions will be differentiated by other premises with a straight line that separates them from premises, like this:

1. All flowers are plants. (Premise 1)2. All Roses are flowers. (Premise 2)_______________________________

3. Therefore, all roses are plants. (Conclusion)

Exercise: Argument form – Determine Arguments, put them in argument form

7

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

SUPPLYING MISSING PARTS – ENTHYMEMES

What’s missing?

An argument missing a premise, or a conclusion, is an enthymeme. Eg:

1. All chemists are scientists. 1. If you wake up late, you’ll miss your train.

2. So Joe is a scientist. OR 2. And as usual, you woke up late.

Exercise: Supply Missing Parts

DIAGRAMMING ARGUMENTS

Another technique to identify arguments is diagramming them. To diagram, read it through and then number each statement.

e.g.: Joe was promoted to VP; therefore, he will move to DC.

Number Like such:

(1) Joe was promoted to VP.(2) He will move to DC.

The above example is called “Single support” because the conclusion is directly supported by the premise.

Now draw an arrow from the statement to the conclusion:

(1)

|

(2) e.g.: If Joe is promoted to VP, he will move to DC. He was promoted; therefore, he will move to DC.

Number Like Such:

(1) If Joe is promoted to VP he will move to DC.(2) He was promoted.(3) Therefore he will move to DC.

8

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

In this case you have a “Joint Support” (if…then)

(1) + (2)

|

(3)

Let’s do it again…

e.g.: Cats make good pets because they are affectionate, they’re clean, they’re entertaining, and they do well in apartments.

(1) Cats make good pets...(2) They’re affectionate,(3) They’re clean,(4) They’re entertaining,(5) They do well in apartments.

This is an example of “Independent Support”

(2)(3) (4) (5)

|

(1)

One More Time…

e.g.: Cats make good pets because they are affectionate, they’re clean, they’re entertaining, and they do well in apartments. So if you want a good pet, you should get a cat.

(1) Cats make good pets...(2) They’re affectionate,(3) They’re clean,(4) They’re entertaining,(5) They do well in apartments.(6) If you want a good pet, you should get a cat.

This is an example of “Extended Argument”

9

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

(2) (3) (4) (5)

|

(1)

|

(6)

Last one and then you do it…

e.g.: Cats make good pets and cats make good anatomical subjects. Therefore, some good pets make good anatomical subjects. Since good anatomical subjects are in high demand in medical schools, it follows that some good pets are in high demand in medical schools.

(1) Cats make good pets,(2) Cats make good anatomical subjects,(3) Therefore some good pets make good anatomical subjects. (4) Since good anatomical subjects are in high demand in medical schools, it follows that(5) Some good pets are in high demand in medical schools.

(1) + (2)

|

(3) + (4)

|

(5)The above argument is also an extended argument: there is an argument within an argument. You see that (1) and (2) support conclusion (3). Then (3) is combined with (4) to support (5)

Exercises: Diagramming arguments

10

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

IN SEARCH FOR A GOOD ARGUMENT

What’s a good argument? Good arguments have

(A) A conclusion that follows from the premises and(B) The premises are true.

What does it mean to follow? 2 ways to follow: deductive validity or inductive strength.

DEDUCTION VS. INDUCTIONArguments can be deductive or inductive. A deductive argument can be valid or invalid; and a valid argument can be sound or unsound. An inductive argument can be weak or strong.

An argument is called DEDUCTIVE when its conclusion follows NECESSARILY—by logical necessity. Deductive arguments may be valid or invalid.

DEDUCTIVE + VALID

1. If I am eating I have food.2. I am eating.3. Therefore I have food.

Given premises 1 and 2, the conclusion, 3, is necessary. If you deny (3) you contradict yourself.

1. If it rains my car is wet.2. It rains.3. Therefore my car is wet.

11

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

1. People from France speak French2. Marc is from France.3. Therefore, he speaks French

1. All bachelors are males.2. Joe is a bachelor.3. Therefore he is a male.

1. A human fetus has a brainwave after 25 weeks.2. A human fetus with a brain wave is a person.3. Killing a person is morally wrong.4. Therefore, killing a fetus after 25 weeks is morally wrong.

1. All animals have teeth.2. Dogs are animals.3. Therefore, dogs have teeth.

Note that an argument may be deductively valid, yet have one or more false premises.Premise (1) is false because birds, and octopi, shrimp, etc. are not teethed animal. The second argument has a false premise and false conclusion:

1. The moon is made of marshmallow.2. Marshmallow is edible.3. Therefore, you can eat the moon.

12

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

Now, what is an INVALID argument? A deductive argument is INVALID when its conclusion does not follow at all.

DEDUCTIVE + INVALID

1. If it rains my car is wet.2. My car is wet.3. It follows that it rains.

1. Dogs have teeth.2. Dogs are animals.3. So, we must deduce that all animals have teeth.

1. If you are eating you have food.2. You have food. 3. Therefore you are eating!

1. All bachelors are males2. Joe is a male.3. It follows then that Joe is a bachelor.

1. All politicians are liars. 2. All used car salesmen are liars. 3. Therefore all politicians are used car salesmen.

13

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

1. All ants are insects.2. All mosquitoes are insects.3. Therefore, all ants are mosquitoes.

The above arguments are INVALID because their conclusions are not granted by the premises; or, they neither follow necessarily nor probably—they just don’t follow!

Next, deductive arguments can be sound or unsound.

DEDUCTIVE + VALID + SOUND

1. All humans are mortal.2. Nancy is human.3. Therefore, Nancy is mortal.

1. All us presidents are politicians2. Obama is a US president.3. Therefore Obama is a politician.

1. 5 is greater than 3.2. 3 is greater than 2.3. Therefore, 5 is greater than 2.

1. All physical objects occupy space.2. My book is a physical object.3. Therefore, my book occupies space.

14

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

1. Citytech is either in China or In Brooklyn.2. Citytech is not in China.3. Therefore, Citytech is in Brooklyn.

The foregoing arguments are DEDUCTIVE because their conclusions follow by logical necessity and not probably. Hence, they are VALID. Furthermore, they are SOUND because their premises are true.

DEDUCTIVE + VALID + UNSOUND

1. If January has 33 days, the 33rd is the last day.2. January has 33 days.3. Therefore, the 33rd is the last day.

1. All unicorns have wings.2. Juju is a unicorn.3. Therefore, Juju has wings.

1. All living things can fly.2. Women are living things.3. Therefore, women can fly.

1. All felines have six legs.2. Tigers are felines.3. Therefore, tigers have six legs.

Notice that the conclusion to these arguments is necessary. The premises are related: one leads to the other; GIVEN THE PREMISES, the conclusion follows from the premises necessarily and not probably. So, these are deductively valid arguments. But they are unsound because soundness requires true premises.

15

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

INDUCTIONOn the other hand, INDUCTIVE arguments work differently. The conclusion to an inductive argument can be strong or weak, depending on the circumstances, but never 100% true or 100% false. There are 3 kinds of inductive arguments: Inductive Generalizations, Arguments From Analogy, and Causal Arguments.

INDUCTIVE GENERALIZATION

To move from a sample to a general conclusion about a population.

1. This desk is brown.2. That desk is brown.3. Therefore, all desks are brown

1. The last ten times I played poker I won $.2. I’m playing poker tonight.3. Therefore I’ll win $.

1. The last ten times I played poker I won $.2. I’m playing poker tonight.3. Therefore I will not win $.

NOTICE THAT EVEN IF I DENY THE CONCLUSION, UNLIKE IN DEDUCTIVE ARGUMENTS, THE CONCLUSION IS STILL POSSIBLE!

1. 90 % of Citytech students are females.2. Therefore, the first person I’ll run into in the hallway is a female.

16

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

1. There are 20 cards in the deck and that includes 13 aces.2. I need to draw an ace to win.3. Therefore, I’ll win.

1. There are 1000 marbles in a jar.2. I take one and it’s red.3. Therefore they’re all red.

INDUCTIVE STRENGTH

1. There are 1000 marbles in a jar.2. I take 980 and they’re red.3. Therefore they’re all red

1. I’ve seen things fall to the ground when dropped many times.2. I’m about to drop this object.3. Therefore, it will fall to the ground.

ARGUMENTS FROM ANALOGY

Comparing two or more things in order to support a conclusion about one of them.

1. I read a book by Stephen King and it was very entertaining.2. I also watched a movie based on one of his books and was entertaining.3. Therefore his latest book must be entertaining as well.

1. Any mechanism like a watch is the product of intelligence.2. The universe is a complex mechanism.3. Therefore, the universe is also the product of intelligence.

17

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

1. The state is like family.2. You must respect family.3. Therefore, you must respect the state.

1. No one is obligated to donate his or her kidney to a person who needs one to live.2. Therefore, no woman should be under the obligation to donate the use of her womb to the

fetus who needs to live.

1. A and B are both spherical, yellow, waxy, small and light.2. A is sweet.3. So, probably B is sweet as well.

CAUSAL ARGUMENT

Arguments that rely on the concept of causality.

Causal Arguments contain causal statements as either a premise or the conclusion. Causal statements say that A is the cause of B and B is caused by A.

Sufficient VS Necessary Condition.

Oxygen is necessary for combustion, but not sufficient.

It is not always clear what the cause is.

In November 2003, a man resisting arrest died shortly after being beaten into submission by police officers in Cincinnati, Ohio. The struggle, you might say, is the primary “Cause” of his death. But what is really the cause? That is, what made him die? Lack of oxygen, damage of brain?

Another example: Persons who leave school before the age of 16 are 5 times more likely than university graduates to die from heart attack. And the death rate within one year of a heart attack is 3.5% for college graduate and 20% for those with fewer than 8 years of formal schooling. What is really the cause? Poor education is certainly part of it.

Increased stress causes increased risk of heart attack.

Drinking alcohol during pregnancy cause birth defects.

Smoking causes cancer.

Eating heavy food causes stomachache.

Jogging cause my side pain.

18

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

The conflict over slavery caused the Civil War.

TYPES OF CAUSAL ARGUMENTS

Causal Prediction:

Given a causal statement, we can predict what will happen:

1. Reduction in swelling causes relief of pain.2. The swelling in my arm is diminishing.3. Therefore, relief of pain will occur.

Causal Explanation:

Given a causal statement, we can explain how two events are related.

1. Reduction in swelling causes relief of pain.2. There is relief of pain.3. Therefore, the swelling in my arm has gone down.

Causal Prescription:

This is an argument asserting how something is to be achieved. Given a causal statement, we know that if we want to achieve a certain result we need to bring about the cause.

1. Reduction in swelling causes relief of pain.2. Therefore, if relief of pain is desired, reduce the swelling.

Causal Conclusion:

This type of argument provides evidence for concluding that one event causes another.

1. Whenever swelling is reduced, pain is relieved.2. Therefore, reduction in swelling causes relief of pain.

19

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

Mill’s MethodsJohn Stewart Mill (1806 – 1873) describes 5 methods for identifying causes and effects: METHODS OF AGREEMENT, DIFFERENCE, CONCOMITANT VARIATION, RESIDUE, and the joint method of AGREEMENT AND DIFFERENCE.

1. THE METHOD OF AGREEMENT

This method tells us to look at antecedent circumstances. The cause of an event is that antecedent circumstance common to all cases in which that event occurs.

Explanation: Suppose 3 friends eat at the same restaurant and an hour later they get sick. The method of agreement suggests that we identify the cause by looking at which food in common was eaten among the three:

Denise ate salad, potatoes, apple pie, tea. DID NOT GET SICK

Amy ate bananas, salad, apple pie, coffee. GOT SICK

Beth ate bananas, apple pie, cola. GOT SICK

Ellen ate spinach, fries, cola. DID NOT GET SICK

Clara ate bananas, beans, coffee. GOT SICK

Following the method of agreement, we focus on those who got sick and see for a common element.

Notice that Amy, Beth, and Clara all got sick and ate bananas. So, it is reasonable to conclude that bananas are at least a causal factor in producing the illness.

You can see that this method is not very reliable. What if nothing is in common?

2. THE METHOD OF DIFFERENCE

According to this method we can find out the cause of an event by looking at the antecedent event that is present when something occurs and we compare to those events that lack that antecedent event.

Explanation: Suppose you touch the TV antenna and the image gets clear. If you don’t touch the antenna the image is blurry. So by comparison, we infer that touching the antenna is the cause of clear images. Also, if you made the same soup with the same ingredients many times and then added a new ingredient, you infer that the cause of, say, a bitter taste is the new ingredient.

3. THE METHOD OF CONCOMITANT VARIATION

Things and people exhibit variation, they change. Often we observe that such variations are in concomitance with variations in other circumstances:

20

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

Explanation: If a variation in a certain event E coincide with another variation in phenomenon P, then it is probable that E and P are causally related.

~ The more you exercise the stronger you get.

~ The higher the humidity, the longer it takes for my clothes to dry.

4. THE METHOD OF RESIDUE

This method suggest that to know the cause of a certain phenomenon we need to subtract causes that are known from previous induction, and the residue of a certain phenomenon is the effect of the remaining antecedent.

Explanation: Suppose we investigate the increased incidence of AIDS in a community. Suppose we already know that the AIDS virus is transmitted through exchange of body fluids. All the cases observed in the antecedent circumstances were contaminated needles, unsafe sex, and blood transfusions. We have established that contamination is causal in 65% of cases, unsafe sex 25%. So, we infer that the remaining cases, the residue, are caused by blood transfusions.

5. THE JOINT METHOD (AGREEMENT + DIFFERENCE)

Every time I visit your house, your cat is there and I start sneezing. But when you visit me, and your cat is not here, I do not sneeze. So, by combining the methods of agreement and difference, I conclude that I am allergic to your cat. (By agreement I know that whenever your cat is present allergic reaction occurs. By difference, I know that whenever your cat is not present, allergic reaction does not occur.

Exercises: Identify Types of Arguments p. 219

21

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

Logical FallaciesOne type of invalid argument is called a Logical Fallacy. These arguments are instances of bad or poor reasoning. The conclusion of a logical fallacy either does not depend on the truth of the premises at all or the conclusion only follows very weakly from the premises. Fallacies can be formal or informal. A formal fallacy is an error in logic that can be seen in the argument’s form without requiring an understanding of the argument’s content. For example, see if you can spot the logical error in this argument:

E.g. 1:

1. If I own a Ferrari, I am rich.2. I am rich.______________________3. Therefore, I own a Ferrari.

E.g. 2:

1. People who are allergic to peanuts won’t eat peanuts.2. Mike won’t eat peanuts._______________________________________________3. Therefore, Mike is allergic to peanuts.

The error here is to jump to the conclusion without carefully considering the premises. That is to say, in e.g. 1, if we accept premises 1 and 2 as true, it does not follow at all that I own a Ferrari. And in e.g. 2, perhaps Mike just does not like the taste of peanuts.

On the other hand, informal fallacies occur for reasons other than structural, and thus require examination of the argument’s content.

Here are some examples:

Appeal to Authority

Fallacious appeal to authority is when you back up your reasoning by the assertion(s) of someone who is not relevantly qualified or is biased.

22

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

Examples:

~ According to my classmate, philosophy is stupid. So I don’t waste my time on it!

~ Professor Alvaro is one of the most important philosophers of this century. I have that on the authority of his mother!

~ Bill: “I believe that abortion is morally permissible. Women should have a right to their bodies.Jane: “I disagree completely. Dr. John Spin says that abortion is always immoral, regardless of the situation. He has to be right because he is a respected expert in his field.”Bill: “Never heard of him. Who is he?”Jane: “He’s the guy who won the Nobel Prize in physics for his work on cold fusion.”Bill: “I see. Does he have any expertise in morality?Jane: “I don’t know. But he is a famous physicist, so I believe him.”

Appeal to the People

If you suggest too strongly that someone’s claim or argument is correct simply because it’s what most or everyone believes, you commit this fallacy.

Example:

~ Eating meat is morally permissible. Look how many people eat meat.

~ People have believed in God for millennia. I don’t see how so many people could be wrong. Therefore, God exists.

Appeal to Force

This is an argument based upon a threat to persuade you into accepting a conclusion.

Example:

~ Ladies and gentlemen of the jury, if you do not convict this person, you may be this killer’s next victim.

Appeal to Pity.

This is an appeal to your emotion. One who commits this fallacy wants you to accept a conclusion out of pity.

Example:

23

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

~ It is true that this man committed a crime; however, consider this: he never knew his father, his mother died, he has been poor for his whole life…therefore, you should acquit him.

Appeal to Ignorance

This is an argument in which it is claimed that the conclusion is true (or false) because there is no evidence of the contrary.

Example:

~ I have examined all the arguments for the existence of God and found them all invalid. Therefore, there is no God.

~ Scientists have not proven that ghosts do not exist. Therefore they exist.

Ad Hominem

You must give objective reasons for your views. Sometimes people get frustrated and attack another person. Often, people attack their opponents rather than their arguments. There are 3 common variations of ad hominem: abusive, circumstantial, and “you too!”

Examples of abusive:

~ My doctor told me I should lose some weight. But why should I listen to him? He’s fat!

~ Professor Alvaro told us about the theory of evolution. But he neglected to tell us that he’s a Godless atheist! Therefore, professor Alvaro cannot speak the truth.

~ (Suppose you argue for the moral superiority of suicide for terminally ill patients.) I say to you that I disagree because life is sacred. You respond “You disagree because you are a religious bigot, and religious people are nuts.”

Examples of circumstantial:

~ The auto industry lobbyists have been arguing that tax reform is unnecessary. Just remember that it is in their interest to argue that way because it benefits the auto industry if there is no tax reform!

~ I am not surprised that your mechanic suggests a complete engine overhaul. Do you know how much money he makes from that?

~ I am not surprised you suggested that I join a gym. You are a personal trainer, right? More money for you, huh?

24

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

Examples of “you too!”

~ You argue that eating meat is immoral. But you too used to eat meat. So why should I listen to you?

~ A: Smoking causes all sorts of problems, not to mention it causes cancer. So, do not ever start, kid.

B: You should talk! You smoke!

False Cause

This is committed when the arguer concludes that one event causes another without giving good evidence for their causal connection.

Example:

~ Last night I had an argument with Frank and I wished him dead. This morning they found him dead in his apartment. God, if only I hadn’t thought that! I killed him!

Slippery Slope

Suppose someone claims that a first step (in a chain of causes and effects, or a chain of reasoning) will probably lead to a second step that in turn will probably lead to another step and so on until a final step ends in trouble. If the likelihood of the trouble occurring is exaggerated, the slippery slope fallacy is present.

Example:

~ We should oppose same sex marriage because if we allow it then eventually people would demand to marry animals.

Either/Or/Black-or-White/False Dichotomy

Example:

~ Well, it’s time for a decision. Either you contribute $10 to our environmental fund, or you are on the side of environmental destruction?

~ Either you drove here or you walk. So if you didn’t walk, you must have driven.

~ Either we enforce death penalty or we find convicted murderers back out on the streets. We cannot have murderers out on the streets. Therefore, we must enforce the death penalty.

25

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

A VERY IMPORTANT POINT TO REMEMBER: Informal logical fallacies are not exclusive of inductive arguments. The above examples are deductively valid arguments. Being valid, the fallacy is not structural; it is not formal. Rather, it stems from a false premise—the premise that there are only two options. But if there are more than two options, then the fallacy is a false dichotomy.

If I say to you, “Either you’re alive or you are dead. You are not dead. Therefore, you are alive.” This is not a false dichotomy because there is no other option.

Equivocation

This fallacy occurs when the conclusion of an argument rests upon the equivocal use of a word or phrase, typically used in two different senses.

Example:

~ If God is love and love is blind, and Stevie Wonder is blind. Then Stevie Wonder is God!

~ The doctor told me I need amino acids. But acids corrode your stomach. So I am not eating amino acids.

~ All feathers are light. Whatever is light cannot be dark. Therefore, feathers cannot be dark.

~ Logic is the study of arguments. My parents argue a lot. Therefore, I can learn logic by listening to my parents argue.

Hasty Generalization

This occurs when a generalization is made on the basis of an unrepresentative sample.

Example:

~ Last night I went to a town called Butte Creek and everywhere I went I saw children. So the inhabitants of that town are all children.

Composition

This is due to fallacious reasoning about the relationship between a whole and its parts.

Example:

~ Each member of the orchestra is excellent; therefore the orchestra is excellent.

26

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

~ Drinking this glass of whiskey cannot harm me, so how can drinking harm me?

~ Every brick of that house is relatively light. Therefore, the house must be light.

Division

The fallacy of division is the opposite of that of composition.

Example:

~ The union voted to strike. Therefore, each member voted to strike.

~ Humans are the only animals capable of philosophical thinking. Therefore, every human being is capable of philosophical thinking.

False Analogy

An argument from analogy draws a conclusion about something on the basis of an analogy with some other thing. But sometimes the analogy is not relevant enough or false.

Example:

~ Teaching teenagers to stay away from drinking by getting them drunk is like teaching gun safety by playing Russian roulette.

~ To say humans are immortal is like saying a car can run forever.

~ If complicated mechanisms require a maker, then the universe must have a maker as well.

Begging the Question

A form of circular reasoning in which a conclusion is derived from premises that presuppose the conclusion.

Example:

~ “Killing a human being is morally wrong. But a fetus is not a human being, so it is not wrong to kill a fetus.”

~ A student argues: “You can’t give me a C.  I’m an A student!”

27

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

~ Whatever is less dense than water will float, because such objects won’t sink in.

~ The Bible asserts that God exists. The Bible is the truth revealed by God. Therefore, God exists.

Straw Man

Your reasoning contains the straw man fallacy whenever you misinterpret the position of your opponent and then proceed to attack the easily refuted position (the straw man) believing you have undermined the opponent’s actual position.

Example:

~ The theory of evolution says that man comes from monkeys. But how come monkeys don’t give birth to human babies? The theory of evolution is absurd!

The Red Herring

This is a fallacy in which attention is deliberately moved away from the issue under discussion.

Example:

~ A: “What we do to animals is morally appalling.”

B: “But what about children starving in the world. That’s a real problem. And where would you get your proteins if all went vegan. And what would happen to the economy…”

Inconsistency

This occurs when one argues from inconsistent premises.

Example:

~ Parents are the sole authority on the education of their children. But the state is to ensure a quality and equal education for all children. That’s why we give teachers the authority to determine educational goals.

~ I’m completely against violence for any reason, and I would punch anybody in the face who is in favor of violence.

~ I love animals, you know. You can call me an animal lover! But let’s order now: “I will take the T-bone steak for main course and veal tartar as an appetizer, please.”

28

NYC COLLEGE OF TECHNOLOGY Intro to Philosophy PHIL 2101 Prof. Carlo Alvaro

29