Passmore-Treatment of Animals (JHI 36.2 [1975])

download Passmore-Treatment of Animals (JHI 36.2 [1975])

of 24

Transcript of Passmore-Treatment of Animals (JHI 36.2 [1975])

  • 8/10/2019 Passmore-Treatment of Animals (JHI 36.2 [1975])

    1/24

    THE TREATMENT

    OF ANIMALS1

    BY JOHNPASSMORE

    One restrictionon the absolutism

    of

    man's rule over Nature

    is now

    generally

    accepted:

    moral

    philosophers

    nd

    public

    opinion

    agree

    that

    it

    is

    morally mpermissible

    o be cruel

    to

    animals.

    And

    by

    this

    they

    mean

    not

    only

    that

    it is

    wrong

    to

    enjoy torturing

    animals-which

    few

    moralists

    would

    ever have

    wished

    explicitly

    o

    deny,

    however ittle

    em-

    phasis they

    might

    have

    placed

    on

    cruelty

    to animals

    in

    their

    moral

    teaching-but that it

    is

    wrongto cause them to sufferunnecessarily.

    "The

    Puritan,"

    Macaulay

    once

    wrote

    with

    condemnatory

    intent,

    "hated

    bear-baiting,

    ot because

    t

    gave

    pain

    to

    the

    bear,

    but because

    t

    gave

    pleasure

    to the

    spectators."2

    n other

    words,

    what

    they

    hated-

    and

    by

    no means

    perversely-was

    the

    enjoyment

    of animal

    suffering;

    o

    the

    mere fact that the bears

    sufferedas

    a

    consequence

    f humanaction

    they

    were

    ndifferent.

    That,

    on the

    whole,

    s

    the

    Christian radition.

    But

    now the situation has

    changed;

    not

    only cruelty-the

    enjoyment

    of

    animalsuffering-but callousness, ndifferenceo animalsuffering,not

    taking

    it

    into account

    in

    deciding

    how

    one

    ought

    to

    act,

    is

    morally

    condemned.3

    Controversies

    no

    doubt

    remain.

    But

    they

    now

    turn around he

    ques-

    tion what

    is

    to

    count

    as

    "making

    animals

    suffer

    unnecessarily,"

    whether,

    for

    example,

    vivisection

    or

    fox-hunting

    are,

    in these

    terms,

    morally

    ustifiable.By looking

    in

    some

    detail at

    the

    way

    in

    which the

    general

    moral

    principle

    hat

    it is

    wrong

    to

    act

    callously

    has

    gradually

    won acceptance,we can hope to see revealed,first, how reluctantly

    Western

    man has

    acceptedany

    restrictionwhatsoever

    on

    his

    supposed

    right

    to deal as

    he

    pleases

    with

    Nature

    and,

    secondly,

    how

    changes

    n

    his

    moral

    outlook

    have

    nevertheless ome

    about.

    The Old

    Testament did

    not

    leave

    men

    totally

    without

    guidance

    n

    their treatment

    of animals.

    The Hebrews

    were

    told,

    for

    example,

    not to

    "seethe

    a kid

    in his

    mother's

    milk"

    and

    not

    to "muzzle

    he ox when

    he

    treadeth out

    the corn."4

    But

    these

    somewhat outre

    prohibitions,

    as

    lAn occasional sentence in this paper also appears in my Man's Responsibility for

    Nature

    (London,

    1974).

    2Thomas

    Macaulay,

    History of

    England

    (London,

    1850),

    I,

    ch.

    2,

    161.

    3The distinction

    between

    cruelty

    and

    callousness,

    here

    suggested,

    does not conform

    to

    ordinary

    usage

    which includes

    under the head

    of

    "cruelty"

    both indifference

    to and

    enjoyment

    of

    suffering.

    In the

    argument

    that

    follows,

    this

    usage

    will

    sometimes be

    adopted.

    But

    at

    other

    points

    it

    leads

    to

    the

    confusion

    of

    issues,

    and I shall have to

    dis-

    tinguish,

    as

    I

    have

    just

    done,

    between

    enjoyment

    (cruelty)

    and

    indifference

    (callous-

    ness).

    4Exodus

    23:19;Deuteronomy

    25:4.

    195

  • 8/10/2019 Passmore-Treatment of Animals (JHI 36.2 [1975])

    2/24

    196

    JOHN

    PASSMORE

    Maimonides and

    Aquinas

    suspected

    and modern

    scholarship

    has

    confirmed,

    weredirected

    against

    heathen

    magical

    practices

    rather

    han

    againstcrueltyor callousnessas such.5As for the other familiarOld

    Testament

    prohibitions,

    hey

    sometimes

    rest

    on the fact

    that

    asses and

    oxen

    were a valuable

    orm

    of

    property, ust

    as

    when

    Luke

    reports

    Jesus

    as

    asking

    he Jews "Which

    of

    you

    shall

    have an assor an

    ox fallen

    nto a

    pit,

    and

    will not

    straightway

    ull

    him out on the Sabbath

    day?"

    he

    is

    not

    suggesting

    hat

    they

    will

    break

    the Sabbath

    o relieveanimal

    suffering,

    but that

    they

    willdo

    so to retrieve heir

    property.6

    n other cases

    they

    reflect

    a

    superstitious

    ear

    of

    shedding

    blood. So one

    must not

    exag-

    gerate, as some interpretershave been temptedto do, the degreeto

    which

    the Old

    Testament condemns

    callousness.

    Its

    total

    effect,

    however,

    is

    certainly

    not one of

    complete

    indifference

    to

    animal

    suffering.

    Paul, however,

    refuses

    o

    interpret iterallyany

    Biblical

    precepts

    re-

    lating

    to the

    treatment

    of

    animals.

    "Doth

    God,"

    he

    rhetorically

    asked,

    "take care

    of oxen?"When

    men are

    told not to muzzle

    he mouthof the

    ox, this,

    Paul

    is

    confident,

    s

    meant

    metaphorically,

    s a

    way

    of

    telling

    men that "he thatplowethshouldplowin hope."7Nor does Paul stand

    alone.

    In

    his

    commentary

    on Psalm

    104,

    Augustine

    after

    quoting

    with

    approval

    Paul's

    "Doth

    God

    take care

    of

    oxen?"carries

    his

    habit

    of alle-

    gorical

    interpretation

    o

    far as

    completely

    to.disguise

    he

    character

    of

    that

    psalm

    as a

    hymn

    to God's

    providentialgovernment

    of

    Nature.

    ("The

    earth,"

    for

    example,

    becomes

    n

    Augustine's

    nterpretation,

    the

    Church.")8

    The

    precept

    not to seethe

    a kid in

    its

    mother's

    milk

    Augus-

    tine understands

    as a

    prefiguring

    f

    Christ.9

    In

    short,

    God,

    as

    under-

    stood by Augustine,is quite unconcernedabout man's treatment of

    Nature;

    all God cares

    about

    s man's

    relation

    o

    God

    and

    his

    Church.

    Augustine

    was

    particularly

    concerned lest Christians

    should be

    tempted

    by

    the Manichaean

    doctrine hat

    it is

    wrong

    to

    kill

    and

    eat ani-

    mals.

    He

    had

    been a Manichaean

    himself

    and knew

    ts

    attractions.

    As

    is so

    often

    true of

    vegetarianism,

    Manichaean

    egetarianism

    estedon a

    complex

    religioussystem.

    The

    divine

    part

    of

    the

    world,

    so

    the Man-

    "Moses

    Maimonides,

    Guide

    of

    the

    Perplexed

    (Part

    III,

    ch.

    48)

    and the

    commentary

    by

    David Bourke

    and

    Arthur

    Littledale

    to their

    translation of

    Aquinas,

    Summa Theolo-

    giae,

    vol.

    29,

    The

    Old

    Law

    (la

    2ae,

    98-105),

    question

    102,

    article

    6,

    p.

    225.

    6Luke

    14:5.

    7I

    Corinthians 9:10-11.

    8Expositions

    on the

    Book

    of

    Psalms,

    trans.

    by

    members

    of the

    English

    Church

    (Ox-

    ford,

    1853),

    V,

    85.

    9Aurelii

    Augustini

    Opera,

    Pars V:

    Quaestiones

    in

    Heptateuchum,

    Liber

    Secundus,

    Quaest.

    Exodi, XC,

    23,

    19

    in

    Corpus

    Christianorum,

    XXXIII,

    114-15

    (Turnhout,

    1958).

    On the

    whole theme of Christian

    attitudes to

    animals: Edward

    Westermarck,

    Christianity and Morals ch. XIX, and C. W. Hume, The Status of Animals in the

    Christian

    Religion (London,

    1956).

  • 8/10/2019 Passmore-Treatment of Animals (JHI 36.2 [1975])

    3/24

    THE TREATMENT

    OF

    ANIMALS

    197

    ichaeans

    taught,

    was

    constantlybeing

    released

    from the soil.

    It

    enters

    thence

    into

    plants

    in

    virtue of the fact that

    they

    have

    their roots in the

    soil.10Animals eat the plants,butin the processdefilethe divine ngre-

    dients

    the

    plants

    contain-inevitably

    so,

    on Manichaean

    principles,

    since animalsare

    born

    as a result

    of the

    supremelydefiling

    act

    of

    sexual

    intercourse.

    Holy

    men,

    spiritualizedby

    prayer,

    celibacy,

    and

    fasting,

    can

    extract

    divinity

    n its

    pure

    form from

    plants

    whereas even their

    holiness

    couldnot

    abate

    the

    corruption

    nherent

    n animalbodies."

    In

    the course

    of

    attacking

    the Manichaeans

    Augustine

    was led

    to

    make a

    quite general

    point

    about

    man's treatment

    of animals.

    "Christ

    Himself,"he writes,"showsthat to refrain romthe killingof animals

    and the

    destroying

    of

    plants

    is

    the

    height

    of

    superstition

    or,

    judging

    that there

    are

    no

    common

    rights

    between

    us

    and

    the

    beasts and

    trees,

    he

    sent the devils

    nto a

    herd

    of swineand

    with

    a cursewithered he tree

    on whichhe foundno fruit."

    "Surely,"

    Augustine

    continues,

    "the swine

    had

    not

    sinned,

    nor had the tree."

    Animals,

    that

    is,

    have

    no

    rights.

    Christ,

    who

    might

    simply

    have

    destroyed

    the

    possessing

    devils,

    chose

    rather to

    transfer them

    to swine

    in

    order

    to make

    that fact

    perfectly

    clearto men.At anotherpoint Augustine ells us that animalsuffering

    means little

    or

    nothing

    to human

    beings.

    "We can

    perceive by

    their

    cries,"

    he

    writes,

    "that animalsdie

    in

    pain, although

    we

    make little

    of

    this

    since the

    beast,

    lacking

    a rational

    soul,

    is not related

    to us

    by

    a

    common

    nature."12 ince beasts

    lack

    reason,

    that

    is,

    we

    need

    not con-

    cern ourselves

    with

    their

    sufferings.

    And

    this, too,

    is

    why

    they

    have no

    rights.

    The source of these

    Augustinian

    eachings

    s

    certainly

    not

    the Old

    Testament,according o whichanimalsandmensharea commonprin-

    ciple

    of

    life

    (nebesh).

    For the

    author of

    Ecclesiastes,

    indeed,

    "that

    which befalleth the sons of men befalleth

    beasts;

    even

    one

    thing

    be-

    falleth

    them;

    as

    the one

    dieth,

    so dieth the

    other;

    yea,

    they

    have

    all

    one

    breadth;

    so that a man hath no

    preeminence

    above a beast."13And

    if

    Ecclesiastes

    s a hard nut for

    orthodoxy

    o

    crack-it

    is

    nowhere

    quoted

    in

    the

    New

    Testament-there

    is

    nothing

    novel,

    from

    an Old

    Testament

    point

    of

    view,

    in its

    suggestion

    hat man and beast

    share "one

    breath,"

    ?1This iew-that the soil

    is

    the

    source of all

    goodness-persists

    in

    European

    and

    American

    thinking.

    Jefferson

    Notes

    on the State

    of

    Virginia,

    Query XIX)

    was con-

    vinced hat "thosewho labour

    n

    the earth

    are the chosen

    people

    of God."Or

    compare

    P. W.

    Foxburgh's

    The Natural

    Thing

    New

    York,

    1953):

    "The land

    is

    good,

    in

    fact

    good

    beyondquestion

    and

    t

    is

    good

    to live on the

    land

    andwork

    t"

    (24).

    The

    goodness

    of

    virgin

    oil is often

    taken

    for

    granted,

    with

    disastrous

    agricultural

    onsequences.

    "Augustine,

    The

    Catholicand

    Manichaean

    Waysof Life,

    trans.

    D. A.

    Gallagher

    and

    I.

    J.

    Gallagher

    Washington,

    966),

    ch.

    XV,

    91.

    21Ibid.,

    h.

    XVII,

    102and 105.

    3Ecclesiastes

    :19.

  • 8/10/2019 Passmore-Treatment of Animals (JHI 36.2 [1975])

    4/24

    198

    JOHN

    PASSMORE

    one

    soul,

    one

    principle

    of

    life.

    In the

    New

    Testament,

    too,

    all

    living

    things

    are

    represented

    s

    possessing

    a

    psyche.14

    We do

    not

    have

    to

    look

    far

    into Greek

    philosophy,

    however,

    o

    find

    the

    source

    of

    Augustine's

    eachings.

    TheStoics

    thought

    t obvious

    hat

    animals

    were

    devoid

    of

    reason.

    They

    were

    as

    confident

    as

    Paul

    that

    Providence

    cared

    nothing

    for

    animals,

    except

    as an indirect

    way

    of

    caring

    for

    men.

    And

    like

    Augustine,

    they

    were

    ready

    to

    conclude

    that

    animals,

    as

    lacking

    reason,

    must

    also lack

    rights.15

    From

    the

    society

    of

    rational

    beings,"

    so Pohlenz

    sums

    up

    the

    Stoic

    position,

    "animals

    are

    naturally

    excluded."

    "Against

    the

    Pythagoreans,"

    he

    goes

    on

    to

    pointout, "theStoicsvigorouslydefended heviewthatthere

    s no

    legal

    or moral

    tie of

    any

    kind

    between

    man

    and animal."16

    Even

    the

    most

    unorthodox

    of

    Stoics

    stood

    firm on

    this

    point,

    during

    the

    long

    five-

    hundred

    ear

    history

    of

    the Stoic

    school.

    Not all Christians

    were

    convinced,

    however,

    by

    the

    Stoic

    argument

    that

    since

    the

    beasts are

    irrational,

    men

    may

    treat

    them

    as

    they

    please.

    "Even to

    the

    unreasoning

    creatures,"

    wrote

    John

    Chrysostom

    n the

    fourth

    century,

    "[the

    saints]

    extend

    their

    gentleness."17

    lso

    a

    Greek-

    the Italian Fathers absorbedsomething of the inhumanitycharac-

    teristic of

    Rome-Basil

    the

    Great

    composed

    a

    prayer

    for

    animals:

    "And for

    these

    also,

    O

    Lord,

    the

    humble

    beasts,

    who

    bear

    with

    us

    the

    heat and

    burdenof

    the

    day,

    we

    beg

    thee to extend

    thy

    great

    kindness

    of

    heart,

    for thou

    hast

    promised

    o save

    both

    man

    and

    beast,

    and

    great

    is

    thy loving-kindness,

    O

    Master."18

    Note

    that Basil

    thinks of

    God

    as

    having"promised

    o

    save both

    man

    and beast."

    He

    relies,

    no

    doubt,

    on

    Paul's

    Epistle

    to

    the

    Romans,

    where

    Paul tells

    us

    that "the

    earnest

    ex-

    pectationof the creaturewaitethfor the manifestationof the sons of

    God."

    Paul's

    phrase

    "of

    the

    creature,"

    particularly

    when

    t

    is followed

    by

    the observation

    hat

    "the whole creation

    groaneth

    and

    travaileth

    n

    pain

    together

    until

    now,"

    does

    not

    suggest

    that

    it is

    only

    human

    beings

    who are

    waiting

    on God.19

    But,

    although

    Basil

    is

    by

    no

    means

    the sole

    exception,

    his

    passage

    has

    not

    normally

    been taken to

    imply

    that beast

    as well as man

    will be

    saved,

    as

    distinct from

    being

    "transfigured."

    That beasts are

    incapable

    of

    immortality,

    indeed,

    is

    often

    taken to

    follow fromtheverynatureof theirsouls.20

    4W. E.

    Lynch,

    "Soul,"

    in New Catholic

    Encyclopedia

    (New

    York,

    1967),

    XIII,

    449-50,

    sums

    up

    the Biblical

    situation.

    15Cf.

    E. V.

    Arnold,

    Roman

    Stoicism

    (London,

    1911),

    187,

    205,

    274.

    16Max

    Pohlenz,

    Die

    Stoa

    (G6ttingen,

    1948),

    137.

    17Homilies

    of

    St. John

    Chrysostom

    on

    the

    Epistle

    of

    St.

    Paul

    to

    the

    Romans,

    trans.

    by

    members

    of

    the

    English

    Church

    (Oxford,

    1861),

    Homily

    XXIX,

    471.

    "8Quoted

    A. W.

    Moss,

    Valiant

    Crusade

    (London,

    1961),

    5.

    "9Romans,

    8:19,

    22.

    Compare

    Karl

    Barth,

    Church

    Dogmatics,

    III,

    pt.

    IV,

    trans.

    G. W. Bromiley andT. F. Torrance (Edinburgh, 1961).

    20E.g.,

    Charles

    Journet,

    The

    Meaning of

    Evil,

    trans.

    M.

    Barry

    (London,

    1963),

    142,

    which

    lays

    it down

    that

    not even

    God

    can

    bring

    an

    animal

    back

    to life.

  • 8/10/2019 Passmore-Treatment of Animals (JHI 36.2 [1975])

    5/24

    THE

    TREATMENT OF

    ANIMALS

    199

    In

    the

    popular

    mediaeval

    tradition,

    as contrasted

    with

    official

    theology,

    there are

    many legends

    which

    associate

    saintliness and

    martyrdom

    with kindness o

    animals:even

    Jerome

    has

    his

    lion,

    to

    say

    nothing

    of Androcles.

    Vicious animals

    in

    that tradition

    were

    like

    the

    Gadarene

    wine,

    inhabited

    by

    demons.

    They

    might

    be

    brought

    o trial

    for their

    misdeedsand

    punished

    by

    the

    extremest

    of

    penalties-a

    form

    of

    distinction

    which,

    no

    doubt,

    they

    would

    willingly

    have

    foregone.

    Domesticated

    animals,

    n

    contrast,

    were the

    dwelling

    places

    of

    angels.

    The

    merely

    wild,

    but not

    the

    vicious,

    were

    spiritually

    uninhabited.

    Saintliness

    was

    demonstrated

    by

    a

    capacity

    to drivethe demons out of

    the

    vicious-as

    some

    of the

    biographers

    of

    Francis

    of Assissi

    report

    that

    he

    tamed the

    wolf

    of Gobbio-and

    ordinary

    human

    virtue

    in

    domesticating

    wild

    animals,

    hus

    making

    of

    them a

    fit

    residence or an-

    gels.

    Saint Francis

    s,

    of

    course,

    the

    most

    famous

    example

    of a Christian

    Nature-lover,

    alling

    upon

    birds

    as his sisters in an Umbria still

    not en-

    tirely

    Christianized ut of

    Nature-worship.21

    ut his

    case

    is

    anything

    but a clear one.

    Biographies y English

    animal-lovers,

    ften Protestant,

    naturallystress his fellowshipwith Nature; Roman Catholicbiogra-

    phers,

    n

    contrast,

    are intent

    on

    establishing

    his

    orthodoxy.22

    hey

    write

    with

    scorn of those

    who

    see

    in

    Francisa sentimental

    nature-lover,

    nly

    by

    an

    accident

    of

    time

    ineligible

    or the

    Presidency

    f

    the

    Royal

    Society

    for

    the Prevention

    of

    Cruelty

    to Animals.

    Nor

    is

    there

    any

    hope

    of set-

    tling

    such

    controversies

    by

    returning

    o

    primary

    sources;

    hose

    sources

    are

    for

    the

    most

    part

    deliberately

    designed

    o

    create

    a

    particular

    mage

    of Saint

    Francis,

    he

    image varying

    rom

    chronicler

    o

    chronicler.

    A fewfacts, however,seemto be relativelyuncontroversial.His at-

    titude

    to

    Nature-as

    given

    expression,

    or

    example,

    in his

    Canticle

    to

    the

    Sun-is

    very

    like

    that

    of the

    psalmist.

    When

    he

    "preaches

    o

    the

    birds"

    it

    is to

    exhort

    them

    to

    glorify

    God in

    the same

    spirit

    as

    the

    psalmist

    calls

    upon

    not

    only

    all

    living things

    but even "fire

    and

    hail;

    snow

    and

    vapors;

    stormy

    wind

    ulfilling

    his word" o

    praise

    he

    Lord,

    or

    as an

    old

    Englishhymn

    informs

    us,

    in a somewhatunfortunate

    meta-

    phor,

    that "even

    the

    worm

    bends

    his

    knee

    to God."

    "My

    sister

    birds,"

    Francis s saidto havepreached,"youowe much to God andyou must

    always

    and

    in

    everyplace give

    praise

    to

    him."23

    And

    his chronicler

    oes

    on to draw a

    moral

    n which he birds

    are

    compared

    o the friars

    "who,

    like the

    birds,

    owned

    nothing

    of their

    own

    in

    the world

    and

    entrusted

    21E.

    M.

    Almedigen,

    Francis

    of

    Assisi

    (London,

    1967),

    23.

    22Esp.

    Michael

    de

    la

    Bedoyere,

    Francis

    (London, 1962).

    23The Little

    Flowers

    of

    St.

    Francis,

    and

    other Franciscan

    Writings,

    trans.

    S.

    Hughes

    (New

    York,

    1964),

    78.

    The

    introduction

    should

    be read as

    illustrating

    how

    difficult it is to decide what Saint Francis did and taught; also J. R. H. Moorman, The

    Sources

    for

    the

    Life

    of

    St.

    Francis

    of

    Assisi

    (Manchester, 1940),

    in the 1966

    reprint

    with

    a new

    preface

    by

    Bishop

    Moorman.

  • 8/10/2019 Passmore-Treatment of Animals (JHI 36.2 [1975])

    6/24

    200

    JOHN

    PASSMORE

    their lives

    only

    to the

    providence

    f

    God."

    It

    was, indeed,

    o the

    friars,

    not

    to

    the

    birds,

    that Francis

    was

    preaching.

    Anthony

    of

    Padua,

    in a

    similarspirit,was to "preach

    o

    fish" as a means

    of

    rebuking

    eretics.

    Only

    once does the

    question

    of

    callousness

    arise

    in the

    biographies

    of Saint Francis

    written

    by

    his friendsor

    near-contemporaries

    ndthen

    it does so rather

    disconcertingly.

    One

    of

    the

    brethren,

    aken

    ill,

    told

    Saint Francis'

    disciple,

    Jonathan,

    he

    had a

    longing

    for

    pig's

    trotters.

    "In

    great

    fervor

    of

    spirit,"

    Jonathan

    cut

    a trotter

    off

    a

    living

    pig.

    Saint

    Francis rebuked

    him,

    but with

    no

    referencewhatsoever

    o his

    callous-

    ness. He

    urged

    him,

    only,

    to

    apologize

    o

    the owner

    of

    the

    pig

    for

    having

    damagedhisproperty.24

    The

    vogue

    of

    Saint Francis

    is

    a

    modern

    one;

    he

    was in no

    sense

    a

    well-known aint

    until

    after

    the

    appearance

    of Paul

    Sabatier's

    Life

    in

    1893.

    For Sabatierhe was that

    favorite

    nineteenth-century

    igure:

    an

    in-

    dividual

    n

    revolt

    against

    an institution.

    Subsequentapologists

    have

    found

    him useful as a

    living

    demonstration

    hat

    Christianity

    does not

    necessarily

    think of Nature

    as

    something

    to be dominated.

    But Saint

    Francis

    had,

    in this

    particularrespect,

    no immediate nfluence.

    And

    as

    thatstaunchhumanitarian, rancesCobbe,putsit:

    It

    is a

    very

    small

    matter that a

    Saint,

    six hundred

    years ago, sang

    with

    nightingales

    and fed

    wolves,

    if the monks of

    his own Orderand the

    priests

    of

    the

    Church

    whichhas canonised

    him,

    never

    warn

    their

    flocks that

    to torment

    God's

    creatures is

    even a venial

    sin,

    and

    when

    forced

    to notice barbarous

    cruelties

    o

    a

    brute,

    nvariably

    eply

    "Non

    e

    Cristiano,"

    s if all claims

    to

    com-

    passion

    were

    dismissed

    by

    that

    consideration.25

    In general terms, certainly, Christianity, ike Stoicism, has not

    thought

    of

    man as

    being

    bound

    by

    moral considerations

    n

    his

    dealings

    with

    animals.

    When

    n

    1772

    James

    Grangerpreached

    against

    cruelty

    o

    animals

    his

    sermon,

    he

    tells

    us,

    "gave

    almost universal

    disgust

    to

    two

    considerable

    congregations."

    "The

    mention

    of

    horses

    and

    dogs,"

    he

    continues,

    "was censured

    as

    a

    prostitution

    of the

    dignity

    of

    the

    pulpit."26

    The characteristicRoman Catholic

    teaching

    on

    man's treatment

    of

    animals derivesfrom Aquinas. Aquinasdraws a distinctionbetween

    affections

    of reason

    and

    affections

    of

    sentiment.

    At

    the level

    of

    reason,

    he

    says,

    it is

    a matter

    of

    indifference

    ow

    men

    behave

    owardsanimals.

    For God has

    given

    men

    complete

    dominionover them.

    In

    the

    words of

    the

    psalmist, praising

    God:

    "Thou

    madest

    him

    to

    have dominionover

    24Lifeof

    Brother

    Jonathan,

    Ch.

    I,

    in

    The Little

    Flowers,

    186-87.

    25Lifeof

    Frances

    Power

    Cobbe,

    by

    Herself

    (London,

    1894),

    II,

    ch.

    XVIII,

    174-75.

    2E.

    S. Turner,All Heaven in a Rage (London, 1964), 72-73.

  • 8/10/2019 Passmore-Treatment of Animals (JHI 36.2 [1975])

    7/24

    THE TREATMENT

    OF ANIMALS 201

    the works

    of

    thy

    hands;

    hou hast

    put

    all

    things

    under

    his

    feet."27

    This,

    according

    o

    Aquinas,

    s the

    sense

    in

    which"St.

    Paul

    says

    that God

    has

    no carefor oxen, since he does not judge a man on how he has acted

    with

    regard

    o

    oxen or

    other animals."28

    The

    situation

    at the level of the emotions

    is rather different.

    Ani-

    mals can

    feel

    pain;

    men can feel

    pity

    for their

    pain.

    And

    the

    man

    who

    often

    feels

    pity

    for

    suffering

    animals

    s

    more

    likely,

    so

    Aquinas

    ells

    us,

    to

    have

    compassion

    on

    his

    fellowman.

    It

    is in

    the

    light

    of

    this

    fact,

    he

    argues,

    that we

    ought

    to

    interpret

    what

    is

    often taken

    to

    be

    the

    most

    unambiguous

    Old

    Testament moral exhortation

    o

    man

    to care for

    his

    beasts: "a righteousmanregardeth he life of his beast: butthe tender

    mercies of the wicked are cruel."2

    Men,

    on

    Aquinas's

    view,

    are "of a

    piece"; they

    are

    compassionate

    both to

    men

    and to animals.

    So

    righteous

    men

    will in

    fact treat

    their

    beasts

    well. But

    only

    their com-

    passion

    or their

    cruelty

    to men

    is

    of

    any

    moral

    consequence; hey

    are

    not

    righteous

    because

    they

    treat their beasts well. The

    Jews,

    Aquinas

    goes

    on

    patronizingly

    o

    remark,

    were

    particularlygiven

    to

    cruelty.

    God, therefore,

    "exhorted

    hem

    in

    pity

    even to

    animals,

    by

    forbidding

    certainpracticessavoringof crueltyto them." The fact remainsthat

    there is

    nothing morally

    objectionable

    n

    cruelty

    to

    animals,

    as

    such,

    considered

    n

    isolation from

    the

    cruelty

    to men

    with which

    it

    is

    em-

    pirically

    associated. And

    "cruelty"

    includes both

    enjoyment

    of

    and

    indifference o their

    sufferings.

    He sums

    up

    his

    position

    thus:

    "If

    any

    passages

    of

    Holy Scripture

    seem

    to forbid

    us to

    be

    cruel

    to

    brute

    ani-

    mals,

    for

    instance

    to kill a bird

    with its

    young,

    that

    is

    either

    to remove

    men's

    thoughts

    from

    being

    cruel

    to

    other

    men,

    or lest

    throughbeing

    cruelto animalsone becomes cruelto other humanbeings,or because

    injury

    of an animal eads to

    the

    temporal

    hurt of

    man,

    eitherof

    the doer

    of

    the

    deed,

    or of

    another;

    or because of some

    signification...

    ."30

    These conclusions are

    supposed

    to

    follow from

    the

    fact

    that rational

    creatureshavethe

    right

    to

    govern

    rrationalnature.

    This

    interpretation

    f the

    moral

    situationwas to have

    a

    long

    life.

    In

    the

    eighteenth

    century

    Hogarth's engravings

    The

    Stages of

    Cruelty

    produced

    a considerable

    ffect;

    they

    purported

    o

    show,

    somewhat

    n

    the mannerof his now better-knownRake's Progress,how crueltyto

    animals

    develops

    into

    cruelty

    to man.

    In

    his lectures

    on

    ethics,

    Kant

    used these

    engravings

    as

    a text on

    which o

    hang

    his

    Aquinas-like

    iews

    about man's treatment

    of Nature.

    The Leibnizian

    Baumgarten,

    so

    Kant tells

    us,

    had

    maintained hat

    we have dutiesboth

    towardsanimals

    27Psalms

    8:6.

    28Summa

    Theologiae,

    Vol.

    29,

    la

    2ae

    102, 6,

    p.

    225.

    9Proverbs

    12:10.

    30Summa

    contra gentiles, Bk. III, ch. CXIII.

  • 8/10/2019 Passmore-Treatment of Animals (JHI 36.2 [1975])

    8/24

    202

    JOHN

    PASSMORE

    and towardsbeautiful

    andscapes.31

    his

    Kantdenies.

    Animals,

    he

    says,

    "are

    not

    self-consciousand

    are there

    merely

    as

    a

    meansto an

    end,"

    the

    end

    being

    man. What

    Baumgarten

    hinks of as duties

    to animalsare in

    fact

    "indirect

    duties

    towards

    humanity."

    n

    so far as

    the actionsof ani-

    mals

    are

    analogous

    o

    human

    actions,

    e.g.,

    in so far as

    we

    can

    think of

    an

    animal,

    ike a

    servant,

    as

    doing

    service o

    us,

    we

    have

    duties

    relating

    to

    them.

    But

    this

    is

    only

    because

    "thus we cultivate he

    corresponding

    duties towards human

    beings."

    If,

    for

    example,

    a man shoots a

    dog,

    although

    t

    has served

    him

    well,

    because t

    is

    getting

    old,

    "he does not

    fail in

    his

    duty

    to the

    dog,

    for

    the

    dog

    cannot

    udge."

    Nevertheless,

    "his

    act is inhumanand damagesin himself that humanitywhichit is his

    duty

    to show towards mankind."

    Anyone

    who

    is cruel or callous

    in

    regard

    to animal

    suffering,

    so Kant

    suggests,

    will

    become

    cruel

    or

    callous

    n

    his

    dealings

    with

    mankind;

    nversely,

    "tender

    eelings

    owards

    dumbanimals

    develop

    humane

    eelings

    owards

    mankind."

    In

    his

    last

    published

    work,

    his

    Metaphysics

    of

    Morals,

    Kant in-

    cludes

    compassion

    to

    animals

    among

    a man's

    duties to

    himself

    rather

    than his

    duties

    to

    others.

    But even

    if

    Kant's modification

    f his

    original

    viewmay bear witnessto a degreeof uneasiness, hegeneral ine of his

    argument

    is

    unaffected.

    "Intimately

    opposed

    to

    man's

    duty

    to

    himself,"

    Kant

    writes,

    "is a

    savage

    and at

    the same

    time

    cruel

    treatmentof

    that

    part

    of creationwhich

    s

    living,

    hough

    acking

    reason

    [animals]."

    "For

    thus,"

    he

    goes

    on,

    "is

    compassion

    for

    their

    suffering

    dulled

    n

    man,

    and

    thereby

    a natural

    predisposition

    ery

    serviceable

    o

    morality

    in

    one's

    relations

    with

    other

    men

    is weakenedand

    gradually

    obliterated."

    Kant was

    anything

    but a

    callous man:

    he is

    ready

    o main-

    tain that "physicalexperiments nvolving xcruciatingpainfor animals

    and conducted

    merely

    for the sake

    of

    speculative

    nquiry

    when

    the end

    might

    also be

    achieved

    without

    such

    experiments)

    are

    to

    be ab-

    horred."32

    ut he

    cannot see how

    men

    can be said

    to

    have a

    duty

    to

    ani-

    mals as

    distinct from a

    duty

    relating

    to or

    concerning

    animals;

    he has

    somehow

    to

    convert

    it

    either

    into a

    duty

    to

    other

    men

    or

    a

    duty

    to

    ourselves.

    For

    a rational

    ethics,

    as

    distinct

    from

    religion,

    here can

    be,

    on Kant's

    view,

    no such

    thing

    as a

    duty

    to

    God-the

    only

    other

    hypothesishe mighthaveentertained.)

    The

    generalizations

    n which Kant's

    argumentdepends

    are more

    8"Kant,

    Lectures

    on

    Ethics,

    trans.

    L.

    Infield

    (London,

    1930),

    239-40.

    I

    have

    not

    been able to trace the

    reference

    in

    Baumgarten.

    In

    his

    lectures,

    Kant

    is

    commenting,

    for the most

    part,

    on

    Baumgarten's

    Ethica

    Philosophica.

    In

    ?398

    of

    that

    work

    Baumgarten lays

    it

    down that brutal men should be avoided.

    But Kant's

    reference

    is

    to

    a much more

    developed

    view.

    "Metaphysics of

    Morals,

    Pt.

    II;

    The

    Metaphysical

    Principles

    of

    Virtue

    (1797),

    Ele-

    ments of

    Ethics,

    Pt.

    I, ?17,

    trans. J.

    Ellington

    and W. Wick

    (Indianapolis,

    1964),

    106.

  • 8/10/2019 Passmore-Treatment of Animals (JHI 36.2 [1975])

    9/24

    THE TREATMENT

    OF ANIMALS 203

    than

    dubious-tyrants

    from Nero to

    Himmler

    have

    been

    notoriously

    devotedto animals.

    It is

    a matter

    of common

    observation,

    ndeed,

    hat

    kindness o animals s often substituted or kindness o humanbeings.

    Whether

    he inverse

    also

    holds,

    whether hose who are

    cruel to

    animals

    are also cruel

    to human

    beings

    t is more

    difficult

    o

    say.

    There

    s

    cer-

    tainly

    no

    difficulty,

    at

    least,

    in

    conceiving

    a

    situation

    n

    which

    cruelty

    to

    man and

    cruelty

    to

    animals are

    completely

    dissociated:Kant

    would

    have

    us believe hat underthese circumstances

    here would be

    nothing

    wrong

    n

    cruelty

    o

    animals.

    Newman's

    conclusionson

    cruelty

    to

    animals-sufficiently

    authori-

    tative in the Roman Catholic Churchto be quoted at length in the

    Catholic

    Encyclopedia-belong

    to

    this

    same Stoic tradition:

    We

    have

    no duties owards

    hebrute

    reation;

    here s

    no

    relation f

    justice

    between

    hemandus. Of course

    we

    are

    bound ot to

    treat hem

    ll,

    for

    cruelty

    is

    an

    offence

    gainst

    hat

    holy

    Law

    which

    urMaker

    aswritten n our

    hearts,

    and s

    displeasing

    o Him.

    But

    they

    can claim

    nothing

    t our

    hands;

    ntoour

    hands

    they

    are

    absolutely

    delivered.

    We

    may

    use

    them,

    we

    may destroy

    them

    at

    our

    pleasure,

    not our

    wanton

    pleasure,

    but still for our own

    ends,

    for our

    own benefitor satisfaction,providedwe cangivea rationalaccountof whatwe

    do.33

    Men,

    in

    other

    words,

    can deal

    with animalsas

    they

    like,

    providedonly

    that

    they

    have

    a

    good

    reason

    for

    doing

    so: the

    suffering

    f

    animals

    does

    not count as a

    countervailing

    eason.

    They

    ought

    not to

    enjoy

    mal-

    treating

    hem,

    but indifference

    o their

    suffering-callousness-is

    not

    a

    sin.

    Although

    t

    wouldbe

    wrong,

    or

    example,

    o make

    of

    cruelty

    to ani-

    mals a

    sport,

    it is

    morally

    unimportant

    f animals

    suffer

    ncidentally

    o

    our

    sport. Bullfighting,

    n this

    view,

    is therefore

    permissible

    and so is

    coursing.

    If

    what Newmancalled

    "wanton"

    pleasure

    n the

    sufferings

    f

    animals

    is

    forbidden,

    his is

    only

    as a

    consequence

    of the fact that

    all

    wanton

    pleasures

    are

    morally mpermissible.

    Behind his attitude

    to animals ies a

    theology,

    a

    theology bitterly

    opposed

    to

    any

    form of

    naturalism,

    determined

    o insist that between

    man and beast there

    lies an absolute barrier.

    (Consider

    he

    everyday

    use

    of

    the words

    "brutes,""beasts,"

    and even

    "animal.")

    So,

    asked

    to

    permit

    the

    setting

    up

    of a

    Society

    for the Prevention

    f

    Cruelty

    o Ani-

    mals,

    Pope

    Pius

    IX

    replied

    hat "a

    society

    for such

    a

    purpose

    could

    not

    be sanctioned

    n

    Rome."

    The

    principle

    o which

    his

    reply appealed

    was

    the familiar

    Stoic

    one that "man owed

    duties to

    his

    fellow

    men;

    but he

    owed

    no

    duties

    to the lower animals."34

    33J.H.

    Newman,

    Sermons Preached

    on Various

    Occasions,

    2nd

    ed.

    (London, 1858),

    Sermon

    VI,

    106-07.

    3"Lifeof Frances Power Cobbe, by

    Herself

    (London, 1894), II,

    ch.

    XVIII,

    171-72.

    Cardinal

    Manning

    was more

    sympathetic:

    man,

    he

    thought,

    had

    a

    duty

    to God

    to be

  • 8/10/2019 Passmore-Treatment of Animals (JHI 36.2 [1975])

    10/24

    204

    JOHN

    PASSMORE

    Neither

    Aquinas

    nor

    Kant

    nor

    Newman

    denied,however,

    hat ani-

    mals could suffer:Descartes

    and Malebranche

    houghtdifferently.

    t

    is

    impossible, hey argued, o be cruel to animals,sinceanimalsareinca-

    pable

    of

    feeling.They

    lack

    not

    only-as

    Aquinas

    had

    followedAristotle

    in

    arguing-a

    rationalsoul but even that sensitive oul

    whichboth Aris-

    totle and

    Aquinas

    had allowed

    them. To

    suppose

    that animals could

    feel would

    be to

    suggest

    that there could

    be

    pain

    and

    suffering

    where

    there has

    been

    no

    sin.

    For

    animalsdid not eat

    of the

    ForbiddenTree.

    "Being

    nnocent,"

    Malebranche

    writes,

    "if

    they

    were

    capable

    of

    feeling,

    the

    effect would be that

    under

    the

    government

    of an

    infinitely ust

    and

    all-powerfulGod an innocent creature would sufferpain, which is a

    penalty,

    and

    the

    punishment

    of some

    sin."3

    The

    only

    possible

    con-

    clusion,

    appearances

    o the

    contrary

    notwithstanding,

    s that animals

    cannot

    feel.

    "They

    eat without

    pleasure,"

    Malebranche herefore ells

    us,

    "they cry

    without

    sorrow...,

    they

    desire

    nothing,

    they

    fear

    nothing,

    they

    know

    nothing."36

    The

    Stoic

    Chrysippus,

    t is

    worth

    noting,

    had also

    suggested

    hat animalsdo not feel

    but

    only

    "as

    it

    were"

    feel.)37

    What

    we hear

    as

    a

    cry

    of

    pain

    s

    of

    no more

    significance

    han the

    creaking of a machine. An organ, the CartesianRouhault argues,

    makes more noise

    when

    I

    play

    it than

    an animal

    when

    t cries

    out,

    yet

    we

    do not

    ascribe

    eelings

    o the

    organ.38

    These

    teachings,

    it

    should

    be

    observed,

    were more

    than

    metaphysical

    speculations.

    They

    had a direct effect

    on seventeenth-

    century

    behavioras

    manifested,

    or

    example,

    n the

    popularity

    f

    public

    vivisections,

    not

    as

    an

    aid

    to scientific

    discovery

    but

    simply

    as

    a tech-

    nical

    display. "They

    administered

    beatings

    to

    dogs

    with

    perfect

    indifference,"o La Fontaine,a contemporaryobserver, ells us, "and

    made

    fun of

    those who

    pitied

    the creaturesas

    if

    they

    had felt

    pain....

    They

    nailed

    poor

    animals

    up

    on boards

    by

    their four

    paws

    to

    vivisect

    them and see the

    circulationof

    the

    blood whichwas a

    great

    subject

    of

    conversation."39

    kind to

    the

    animals

    God had

    created.

    Nowadays,

    indeed,

    there is in

    Great Britain

    a

    Catholic

    Study

    Circle for Animal

    Welfare-with its

    own

    journal,

    The

    Ark,

    founded

    in

    1932.

    (Within

    the

    Anglo-American

    Roman Catholic

    Church, too,

    there are Animal

    Blessing Services.) Even more strikingly in the United States, what was once The Na-

    tional Catholic

    Society for

    Animal

    Welfare

    has

    significantly

    renamed itself

    Society

    for

    Animal

    Rights,

    although

    this still

    does not

    go quite

    as far as the

    name of

    the

    parallel

    In-

    dian

    Society,

    Animal Citizens.

    3Recherche

    de

    la

    Verite,

    IV,

    XI, ?11,

    in

    Oeuvres

    Completes,

    ed. G.

    Rodin-Lewis,

    II,

    104.

    36Ibid., VI, II, VII,

    394;

    also

    C.

    A.

    Sainte-Beuve,

    Le Port

    Royal,

    3rd. ed.

    (Paris,

    1867),

    Bk.

    2,

    ch.

    16,

    316-17.

    37Pohlenz,

    Die

    Stoa,

    147.

    38Entretiens

    ur

    laphilosophie,

    II,

    157.

    39Quoted(no source given) in Loren Eiseley, The Firmament of Time (New York,

    1962).

    28-29.

  • 8/10/2019 Passmore-Treatment of Animals (JHI 36.2 [1975])

    11/24

    THE TREATMENT OF

    ANIMALS

    205

    The

    theological

    problem

    Descartes and

    Malebranche

    professed

    to

    have solvedwas

    quite

    a

    seriousone: to account

    for

    the

    sufferings

    f ani-

    mals

    on

    the

    supposition

    hat the world s

    governedby

    a benevolentand

    omnipotent

    God.

    Augustine

    had

    sought

    to solve

    it

    by arguing

    hat there

    was a lesson for

    men

    n

    animal

    suffering.

    He

    condemned

    hose

    "carping

    critics" who

    "try

    to

    shake

    the

    faith

    of those less

    instructed

    on

    the

    problem

    of

    pain

    and

    hardships

    also

    suffered

    by

    animals"-animals

    which

    had

    not been

    implicated

    n

    Adam's

    fall. The

    solution,

    according

    to

    Augustine,

    s

    that

    only through

    heirobservation

    f

    animal

    suffering,

    suffering

    which is

    "a

    conscious

    struggle

    against

    disintegration

    and

    dissolution,"

    an men be made

    sufficiently

    ware

    hat animals

    possess

    a

    longing

    for

    unity,

    a

    longing

    he

    tells

    us,

    whichcould

    only

    have been

    im-

    planted

    n

    them

    by

    "the

    supreme,

    sublime,

    and

    unspeakable

    unity

    of

    their

    Creator."40

    Animal

    suffering,

    n

    other

    words,

    is a

    chapter

    n the

    book

    of

    nature.

    Less

    sophisticated

    heologians

    were more

    ready

    to

    adopt

    the

    al-

    ternative view

    that animal

    suffering

    was after

    all a

    consequence

    of

    Adam's

    sin;

    that sin threw he entireuniverse

    nto confusion-as

    indeed

    Paulseems to suggestwhenhewritesthat "thewholecreationgroaneth

    and travaileth

    n

    pain

    together

    until now."41

    But there

    s

    something

    in-

    gularly

    repellent

    n

    the idea

    of a God

    who wouldcause

    animals o suffer

    either so that

    theologians

    could

    supply

    another

    reason

    for

    believing

    hat

    animalsare his creationor because

    Adam had

    disobeyed

    him. It was

    in

    many ways

    a

    theologically

    easier

    solution

    to

    suppose,

    however

    im-

    plausibly,

    hat animalsdo not

    in fact suffer

    at all.

    Indeed,

    a

    contempo-

    rary

    Roman Catholic moral

    philosopher,

    Dom

    Trethowan,

    is

    still

    readyto suggestthat the apparent ufferingof, for example,cats can

    only

    be

    explained

    on the

    supposition

    hat "a cat

    is so

    arranged

    hat

    if

    you

    pull

    ts

    tail,

    a

    noise comes

    from

    the other end."42

    One of his

    co-religionists,Jacques

    Maritain,

    adopts,

    however,

    a

    very

    differentattitude.

    He

    specifically

    rejects

    the

    Aquinas-Kant

    view

    that men

    ought

    not to be cruel

    to

    animals

    only

    because

    "cruelty

    towards animals

    developsfeelings

    and

    habits of

    insensitivity

    r sadism

    which vitiate one's

    personality

    and menace

    others." This

    is

    in

    spite

    of

    his agreeingwith Kant andtheStoics that animalsarenot moralagents

    and

    have,

    in

    consequence,

    neither

    duties

    nor

    rights.

    Nonetheless,

    he

    says,

    we have duties

    toward

    them;

    for all

    that,

    they

    have

    no duties

    toward

    us. Animals are

    "foreshadowings

    f human

    persons";

    n virtue

    of that

    fact,

    they

    have a

    foreshadowing,

    lthoughonly

    a

    foreshadowing,

    4?Augustine,

    The Free

    Choice

    of

    the Will

    (Washington,

    1968),

    trans.

    F. P. Russell in

    The Fathers

    of

    the

    Church,

    LIX,

    227.

    4Romans

    8:22.

    42Trethowan,

    An

    Essay

    in Christian

    Philosophy,

    41;

    also 92.

  • 8/10/2019 Passmore-Treatment of Animals (JHI 36.2 [1975])

    12/24

    206

    JOHN PASSMORE

    of

    rights.

    Our

    duties towards

    them,

    however,

    are real.43Thisview has

    behind

    t, too,

    a

    long

    if

    very

    broken

    tradition.

    The Romans carried

    cruelty to animalsto new depthsof barbarity.Only very gradually,

    indeed,

    did

    they

    impose

    limitationson

    a

    man's

    treatmentof his children

    or

    a

    citizen's

    of

    foreigners.

    As

    for

    slaves,

    the Christian

    Emperor

    Justin-

    ian's

    codification

    of Roman Law

    lays

    it down that "slaves cannot

    be

    outraged

    themselves"

    although

    a master can

    be

    outraged

    through

    his

    slave.

    Not

    surprisingly

    t takes a

    very

    similarview

    aboutoxen.44

    The

    Greeks, however,

    had

    generally

    opposed

    cruelty

    to

    animals:

    "do

    not

    be cruel

    to animals" s said to

    have been one of

    three moral

    preceptsof Eleusis,45 ndPlutarchwas no exception.Especially n his

    early

    writings,

    he

    attacks

    that

    sharp

    contrastbetween

    man and animals

    which had been

    typical

    of the Stoics.

    He sets out to

    show,

    relying

    for

    this

    purpose

    on a

    long

    series

    of

    popular

    fables,

    that animals

    are

    quite

    capable

    of

    reasoning.46

    f

    considerably

    more interest

    s

    his

    attempt

    to

    cope

    with a

    somewhat

    special,

    and

    very

    relevant,

    argument

    which de-

    rives,

    he tells

    us,

    from Stoic sources. There

    could be no such

    thing

    as

    justice,

    this

    argument

    runs,

    if beasts

    partake

    of reason.

    For

    men are

    then"necessarilyunjust f theydo not sparethem";yet if theydo, "life

    becomes

    impracticable

    and

    impossible."

    In

    short,

    "we shall be

    living

    the

    life of

    beasts

    once we

    give up

    the

    use of beasts"-no civilized

    pur-

    suit,

    no

    "refinementof

    living"

    could survive.47

    Civilized

    man,

    so the

    Stoic

    argument

    concludes,

    simply

    cannot

    afford

    to

    allow that animals

    are

    rational.

    Plutarch

    suggests

    a

    reply

    to this line

    of

    argument,

    a

    reply

    which

    dates

    back,

    so he

    tells

    us,

    to

    Pythagoras.

    There s no

    injustice,

    he

    says,

    in punishingand slayingsuch animals as are vicious,"anti-socialand

    merely injurious."

    Nor

    is

    there

    any injustice

    n

    taming

    those

    animals

    which end

    themselvesto

    domestication,

    "making

    hem our

    helpers

    n

    the tasks for

    which

    they

    are fitted

    by

    nature,"

    trainingdogs

    as sen-

    tinels,

    or

    keeping

    herds of

    goats

    and

    sheep

    to be milkedand shorn.

    For

    men, too,

    are

    punished

    or

    put

    to death

    if

    they

    are

    viciousand

    men, too,

    are trained

    for

    particular

    asks,

    for which

    they

    are

    by

    nature suited.

    Only

    in two

    respects

    do men need

    to

    alter

    their conduct

    f

    they

    are

    to

    43Maritain,

    Neuf

    lecons sur les notions

    premieres

    de

    la

    philosophie

    morale

    (Paris,

    1951),

    as

    trans.

    in

    Charles

    Journet,

    The

    Meaning of

    Evil,

    trans. Michael

    Barry

    (London,

    1963),

    138-39. Journet

    follows Maritain on this

    point.

    "Institutes

    ofJustinian,

    trans. J.

    B.

    Moyle,

    5th ed.

    (London,

    1913),

    169-70.

    45So

    Porphyry says, quoting

    from

    Mermippus,

    citing

    Xenocrates.

    The

    precepts

    can

    be traced

    back,

    he also

    alleges,

    to

    Triptolemus

    (On

    Abstinence

    IV,

    22).

    46Plutarch,

    The

    Cleverness

    of

    Animals

    in

    Moralia,

    ?961,

    trans.

    W.

    Helmbold,

    Loeb

    Classical

    Library,

    335.

    On Plutarch and other classical writers:

    George

    Boas,

    "Theriophily,"Dictionary of the History of Ideas (1973), IV, 384-88.

    47Ibid.,

    ?6,963-64,

    p.

    347.

  • 8/10/2019 Passmore-Treatment of Animals (JHI 36.2 [1975])

    13/24

    THE TREATMENT OF

    ANIMALS

    207

    deal

    justly

    with animals:

    hey

    should

    give up slaughtering

    hem for the

    table

    and

    they

    should

    give

    up

    those varieties

    of

    sport

    which

    involve

    crueltyto, or the deathof, animals."ForI thinksportshouldbejoyful

    and between

    playmates

    who are

    merry

    on both sides."48Thus

    it is

    possible

    to

    reconcile

    being

    just

    to animals and

    sustaining

    civilization.

    For

    civilizationdoes

    not

    depend,

    Plutarch s

    confident,

    either on the

    eating

    of

    meat or

    on

    blood

    sports.

    (Later

    n

    life,

    Plutarch

    was

    to

    excuse

    meat-eating

    on the

    ground

    that it "has become

    a sort of unnatural

    second

    nature," i.e.,

    a fixed

    custom

    which it would

    be

    impossible

    to

    overthrow,

    although

    he still

    thought

    t

    best to

    do without

    t.)49

    Plutarch's arguments were taken over by the neo-Platonist

    Porphyry.

    Animals,

    he

    agrees

    with

    Plutarch,

    "are

    not

    entirely

    alienated

    from our nature."

    They participate

    n

    reason,

    even

    if to an inferior

    degree.

    It

    is therefore

    quite

    wrong

    to hunt or

    to

    eat

    them,

    or

    at

    least

    it

    is

    wrong

    for

    such

    men as

    aspire

    o

    perfection

    o do

    so,

    the

    only

    class of

    man

    in

    whom

    Porphyry

    was interested.

    But

    Porphyry

    went

    even further

    than Plutarch. "He who

    does not confine harmless conduct

    to men

    alone,"

    he

    writes,

    "but extends

    it

    to other

    animals,

    most

    closely ap-

    proachesto divinityand if it werepossible to extend it to plants, he

    would

    preserve

    this

    image

    in

    a

    still

    greaterdegree."50

    A

    typical

    ascetic,

    he was

    quite

    unimpressed y

    the Stoic

    argument

    hat the refinements

    f

    civilization

    depend

    on our

    dealing

    autocratically

    with

    animals

    and

    plants.

    So much

    the

    worse

    for refinements

    Like

    Genesis,

    Porphyry

    tells us

    that men

    in their

    perfected

    state

    would eat

    nothing

    but

    the

    fruits which

    plants

    bear

    in

    numbers

    beyond

    theirneed to

    reproduce.

    This

    s

    at

    least

    a

    gastronomic

    mprovement

    n

    the bill of farepermittedby theprophetsof SamuelButler'sErewhon.

    They

    restrictthe

    diet

    of the

    righteous

    o

    rotting

    fruit and

    decaying

    cab-

    bage-leaves.)51

    e

    adopts

    a rather different

    approach

    o the Stoic

    ar-

    gument

    that

    any

    attempt

    on

    man's

    part

    to be

    just

    to

    the

    beasts would

    reduce

    him to their

    evel.

    Justice,

    he

    says,

    is

    "nothing

    more

    than

    a

    phi-

    lanthropy";

    t

    consists

    in

    "abstaining

    rom

    injury

    to

    anything

    which

    is not

    noxious":

    that is

    why

    men

    can

    properly

    eat

    superfluous

    ruit,

    shear

    sheep,

    and take theirmilk.52

    It is illuminatingo observe heusewhichhas beenmade n modern

    times

    of

    Porphyrean

    eaching.

    In 1792

    the

    Platonist

    Thomas

    Taylor

    published

    a work

    entitled

    A

    Vindication

    f

    the

    Rights of

    Brutes

    which

    48Ibid.,

    ?7,964-65,

    pp.

    353-55.

    49De Tuenda

    Sanitate

    Praecepta,

    XVIII,

    in

    Plutarch's

    Moralia,

    trans.

    F. C.

    Bab-

    bitt, II,

    265.

    500n

    Abstinence,

    VI,

    27.

    I have followed

    the translation

    in

    Westermarck.

    "5Erewhon,ch. XXVII.

    "5De

    Abstinentia,

    3, 26,

    trans.

    Thomas

    Taylor

    (1823),

    127.

  • 8/10/2019 Passmore-Treatment of Animals (JHI 36.2 [1975])

    14/24

  • 8/10/2019 Passmore-Treatment of Animals (JHI 36.2 [1975])

    15/24

    THE

    TREATMENT

    OF ANIMALS

    209

    restrained

    by

    what

    he

    significantly

    alls "the

    cautious,

    ealous

    virtueof

    justice."

    The

    same is

    true,

    he

    argues,

    of

    their

    dealings

    with

    uncivilized

    peoplesandwithwomen;women andthebarbarians,ikeanimals, ack

    sufficient

    power

    to

    compel

    men to

    compromise

    with

    them.

    The fact

    remains that

    "we should be bound

    by

    the laws of

    humanity

    to

    give

    gentle

    usage

    to these

    creatures."55

    But

    it

    was not

    only

    the

    skeptics

    who were

    beginning

    to think

    differently

    about man's

    relationships

    o the

    animals.

    Rather

    surpris-

    ingly,

    Hume's teacher Hutcheson had been

    prepared

    o

    suppose

    that

    animalswere

    capable

    of

    virtue,

    f

    only

    virtue

    of

    a

    primitive

    kind,

    of

    the

    sort children analsopossess.56Othermoralphilosophers id notgo so

    far

    as

    this in

    their

    criticism

    of

    the

    Stoics,

    but

    even

    such

    Stoic-influenced

    moralistsas

    WilliamWollastonwere

    prepared

    o

    grant

    that men

    ought

    to take

    the

    happiness

    of

    animals nto account

    when

    hey

    act

    "in

    propor-

    tion to their

    several

    degrees

    of

    apprehension."57

    nd

    Wollaston's

    fellow-rationalist,

    ohn

    Balguy,

    while

    rejecting

    Hutcheson's

    view

    that

    animals

    are themselves

    capable

    of

    virtue,

    nonetheless

    s

    confident hat

    "brutes,

    as

    they

    are

    capable

    of

    being

    treated

    by

    us either

    mercifully

    or

    cruelly,maybe theobjectseitherof virtueorvice."58

    Poets and

    novelists,

    as well as

    moral

    philosophers,

    id

    something

    o

    prepare

    he

    way

    for

    a

    new attitude o

    animals,

    as indeed o Nature as a

    whole.

    In

    As

    You

    Like

    It

    not

    only

    "the

    melancholy

    acques"

    but,

    much

    more

    significantly

    even

    the

    aristocratic exiles

    display

    an

    unexpected

    degree

    of

    sensibility

    to

    the

    sufferings

    of

    a

    woundeddeer.59Sterne's

    somewhat mawkish

    apostrophe

    o

    a

    donkey

    and

    Cowper's

    poem,

    The

    Task,

    are well known

    eighteenth-centuryxamples

    of the

    new

    tendency.

    The "sentimentalist"movement as a whole, like Romanticism ater,

    encouraged

    men to

    reflect on

    their

    relations

    to

    animals

    as well

    as

    to

    their

    fellowman.

    ndeed,

    t

    sometimes

    emphasized

    he formerat the

    ex-

    pense

    of the latter.

    But these were

    observations

    in

    passing,

    straws

    in the

    wind,

    or

    perhaps

    not even so

    much,

    the

    personal

    reactions

    of

    men

    of

    unusual

    sensibility.

    The

    fact

    remains,

    as

    we

    have

    already

    een,

    that the

    preacher

    John

    Granger

    aroused

    hostility

    and

    ridiculewhenhe

    preached

    n

    1772

    againstcruelty

    to animals.And as late as

    1798,

    Thomas

    Young began

    his

    Essay

    on

    Humanity

    to Animals

    by

    expressing

    he fear that he had

    exposed

    himself

    to

    ridicule

    by

    writing

    a book on such a

    topic.

    Yet

    55Enquiryconcerning

    the

    Principles of

    Morals,

    Sect.

    III,

    Pt.

    I;

    ed.

    Selby-Bigge,

    ?145,

    152.

    "5Francis

    Hutcheson,

    An

    Inquiry

    into

    the

    Original of

    our Ideas

    of Beauty

    and

    Virtue,

    Treatise

    11,

    4th

    edition

    London,

    1738),

    Section

    7,

    ?3.

    57Wollaston,

    he

    Religionof

    NatureDelineated

    London,

    1724),

    Section

    2,

    ?10.

    58Balguy,The Foundation of Moral Goodness (London, 1728), Pt. I, ?3.

    5eAs

    You Like

    It,

    Act

    II,

    Sc.

    I.

  • 8/10/2019 Passmore-Treatment of Animals (JHI 36.2 [1975])

    16/24

    210

    JOHNPASSMORE

    Henry

    Primatt

    had

    already,

    n

    1776,

    published

    his

    Dissertation

    on the

    Duty

    of

    Mercy

    and Sin

    of Cruelty

    to

    Animals

    and

    the

    century

    that

    followed was to witnessa long series of books on man's treatmentof

    the animals.

    Both Primatt

    and

    Young,

    it will be

    observed,

    plead

    for

    "humanity"

    o

    animals;

    Primattdescribes

    mercy

    as a

    duty

    and

    cruelty

    as a sin.

    The belief

    still

    widely

    prevailed,

    t must

    be

    remembered,

    hat

    large

    segments

    of

    mankind

    were,

    as Aristotle had

    maintained,

    born to be

    slaves.60"From

    the

    hour

    of

    their

    birth,

    some

    are

    markedout

    for

    sub-

    jection,

    others for

    rule....

    Some men are

    by

    nature

    free,

    and others

    slaves, and ... for these latter slavery is both expedient and right."

    From our

    present point

    of

    view,

    significantly,

    Aristotle

    compared

    he

    natural

    slave to tame animals

    which,

    he was

    convinced

    "have

    a

    better

    nature

    than

    wild."

    Not

    until

    1792did

    Wilberforce

    persuade

    he British

    House of Commonsto

    agree

    to the

    gradual

    abolition

    of the slave

    trade;

    not until

    1811 was

    slave-trading

    a

    felony.

    In

    America

    Delaware

    abolished

    slavery

    as

    early

    as

    1776,

    but

    it was

    not

    abolished in the

    United States

    as

    a whole until 1865.

    And

    in

    the widerworld

    t

    lingered

    on, perhapsstill lingerson, well into the twentiethcentury.Not only

    slaves

    but

    primitivepeoples,

    too,

    were

    commonly thought

    of as

    lying

    beyond

    the bounds

    of

    morality,

    as

    Calibans.

    As

    late

    as

    the

    mid-nine-

    teenth

    century,

    the

    aboriginal

    inhabitants of Tasmania were de-

    liberately

    wiped

    out.

    So

    long

    as callousness towards

    the

    sufferings

    of slaves

    and abo-

    rigines

    was

    not

    morally

    condemned,

    t was

    unlikely

    that

    callousness

    towards

    animalswouldbe

    seriouslyregarded.

    ndeed

    o

    insist

    on

    men's

    moral responsibilityowardsslaves and barbarianst was sometimes

    thoughtnecessary,

    as it was

    by

    Herder,

    to draw

    a

    sharp

    distinctionbe-

    tween the treatment

    proper

    to

    man and

    the

    treatment

    even

    of

    such

    higher

    animals

    as

    apes.

    "O

    man,

    honor

    thyself,"

    Herder

    writes,

    "neither he

    pongo

    nor

    the

    gibbon

    s

    thy

    brother;

    he American

    and the

    Negro

    are;

    these

    therefore hou

    shouldnot

    oppress,

    or

    murder,

    or

    steal

    from;

    for

    they

    are men like

    thee;

    with

    the

    ape

    thou

    canst

    not enter

    into

    fraternity."61

    lsewhere,

    however,

    Herderdraws attention

    o the close

    relationshipbetween men and, at least, domesticatedbeasts. "It is

    generally

    known,"

    he

    writes,

    "that all animals

    subservient

    o the

    pur-

    poses

    of

    man

    are more

    useful,

    in

    proportion

    o the

    humanity

    of

    the

    treatment

    they

    receive."62

    Note

    that

    it

    is

    the

    usefulness of kindness

    6?Politics

    1.5,

    1254a-1255a,

    rans.

    B. Jowett

    in

    The

    Works

    of

    Aristotle,

    ed. W. D.

    Ross,

    Vol.

    X

    (Oxford,

    1921).

    "'Herder,

    Reflections

    Ideen),

    Pt.

    I,

    Bk.

    7,

    ch.

    1,

    trans. T.

    O.

    Churchill

    London,

    1800).Bya "pongo" he translatorprobably,f wrongly,meantanorangutan.

    62lbid.,

    Bk.

    8,

    ch. 3.

  • 8/10/2019 Passmore-Treatment of Animals (JHI 36.2 [1975])

    17/24

    THE

    TREATMENT

    OF ANIMALS

    211

    which

    is

    here

    emphasized:

    here is

    no

    suggestion

    that

    animals have

    rights. Nineteenth-century

    writers,

    in

    contrast,

    tended to

    emphasize

    not so

    much

    the

    inhumanity

    f

    slavery

    or

    cruelty

    as

    the

    violence

    t

    does

    to

    rights-the

    typical

    reactions

    of a

    politically-conscious

    ge.

    As

    so

    often,

    the Benthamites ould

    oin

    handswith

    the

    evangelicals.

    "The French have

    already

    discovered,"

    Bentham

    wrote,

    "that

    the

    blackness

    of the skin is no

    reason

    why

    a

    human

    being

    should be

    abandoned

    withoutredressto

    the

    caprice

    of a

    tormentor.

    It

    may

    come

    one

    day

    to be

    recognised

    hat

    the

    numberof

    legs

    ... or the termination

    of

    the

    os

    sacrum

    are

    reasons

    equally

    insufficient

    or

    abandoning

    a

    sensitivebeingto the sameplight."63Observe he transition romslave

    to animal. Bentham'sUtilitarianism ooks not to the

    rationality

    of the

    agent

    or

    the

    patient,

    n

    the

    Stoic

    manner,

    but to

    the

    effect

    of

    the

    agent's

    actions on

    all sentient

    beings,

    who are from this

    point

    of

    view

    to

    be ac-

    counted

    equal.

    If

    all

    pain

    is

    evil,

    as

    Bentham

    hought,

    then the

    pain

    of

    animals-assuming

    only

    that

    they

    can feel

    pain-ought

    not

    to

    be

    ignored

    n man's moral

    decisions.

    The

    pains

    of animals

    might

    be

    less,

    as

    not

    including

    he

    pains

    of

    anticipation,

    han

    the

    pains

    felt

    by

    man,

    but

    that is no reason for not takingthem into account."Thequestion s

    not,"

    so

    Bentham

    argues,

    "Can

    they

    reason?"

    nor

    "Can

    they

    talk?"

    but "Can

    they

    suffer?"

    So

    whereasPlutarch and

    Porphyry hought

    t

    necessary

    to

    begin

    their case

    against treating

    animals

    merely

    as chat-

    tels

    by

    arguing

    hat

    animalshave a share

    n

    reason,

    for

    Bentham

    t

    is

    ir-

    relevant

    whether or not

    they

    are

    rational and to what

    degree.

    It is

    enough

    hat

    they

    are

    capable

    of

    suffering.

    In

    his

    later

    writings,

    however,

    Benthamreverted

    o

    something

    more

    like the Aquinas-Kantposition. The Traites edited by Dumont

    condemn

    cruelty

    to animals

    only-if

    Dumont

    can

    be trusted-on

    the

    ground

    that

    it can

    give

    rise

    to

    indifference

    o

    human

    suffering.

    n his

    Constitutional

    Code,

    Bentham's

    mphasis

    s

    not on

    suffering

    but

    on

    the

    alleged

    act,

    made

    secondary

    n

    the

    Principles,

    hat mature

    quadrupeds

    are more moral

    and more

    intelligent

    han

    young

    bipeds.

    I

    do not know

    why

    Bentham

    changed

    his

    mind.

    But

    perhaps

    he

    boggled,

    and

    not

    un-

    naturally,

    at the conclusion

    hat to determinewhether

    an

    act

    is

    right

    we

    ought to take into consideration ts consequencesfor every sentient

    being.64

    The

    evangelical-Benthamite

    rusadehas

    been

    largely

    successful.

    In

    Great Britain

    he

    law has

    extended ts

    protection

    irst

    (1822)

    to horses

    63lntroduction

    to

    the

    Principles of

    Morals

    and

    Legislation,

    written

    1780,

    published

    1789,

    ed.

    J.

    H.

    Burns and

    H. L.

    A. Hart

    (London,

    1970),

    ch.

    XVII,

    ?IV,

    note b.

    In

    some

    other editions the

    chapter

    number is XIX.

    64For

    details

    of the

    change:

    David

    Baumgardt,

    Bentham and

    the Ethics

    of

    Today

    (Princeton,

    1952),

    338,

    362.

  • 8/10/2019 Passmore-Treatment of Animals (JHI 36.2 [1975])

    18/24

    212 JOHN PASSMORE

    and

    cattle,

    excepting

    only

    bulls,

    and

    eventually,

    although slowly,

    to

    other animals.65

    t is

    sometimes

    argued-as by

    H.

    S. Salt

    in

    his

    Animal'sRights(1892)-that this is all thatis needed o show that ani-

    mals have

    rights:

    o

    say

    that

    they

    have

    rights

    s

    just

    to

    say

    that

    they

    are

    protected by

    law.

    Yet trees

    may

    also be

    protected

    by

    law,

    as

    in

    Na-

    tional

    Parks;

    t

    would be

    very

    odd to conclude hat

    they

    have

    rights.

    If

    we think

    of

    a

    "right"

    as

    a

    demand

    which,

    f

    it

    is

    made,

    s

    backed

    by

    law

    or common

    practice,

    then animals

    have no

    rights;

    hey

    make no claims.

    Nor

    (in

    this

    respect

    they

    are

    unlike

    nfants)

    can someoneelse

    demand,

    let

    us

    say,

    free

    pasturage

    for

    the rest of its life as

    compensation

    or

    damagesincurred n an accident. Its owner,no doubt, can claim for

    damages

    in

    such a

    case,

    but he does

    not

    hold the

    damages

    n

    trust

    for

    the

    horse;

    he

    is, indeed,

    at

    perfect

    iberty

    o shoot

    it.

    What has

    happened

    over the

    last

    century

    and a half in the West is

    not that

    animals have been

    given

    more

    power,

    more

    freedom,

    or

    anything

    else which

    might

    be accountedas

    a

    right.

    Rather,

    men have

    lost

    rights:

    hey

    no

    longer

    have the same

    power

    over

    animals,

    they

    can

    no

    longer

    treat them as

    they

    choose.

    This is characteristicof a

    moral

    change; t followsfrom the fact that, in Hart'swords,"moralrules m-

    pose

    obligations

    and withdrawcertain

    areas of conduct from

    the

    free

    option

    of

    the

    individual o do

    as he likes."66

    But

    that men have lost

    rights

    over them

    does

    nothing

    o convertanimals nto bearersof

    rights,

    any

    more than we

    give

    rights

    to

    a river

    by

    withdrawing

    omebody's

    right

    o

    pollute

    t.

    Disputing

    Salt's

    conclusions,

    D. G. Ritchie has

    argued,

    n

    my

    view

    correctly,

    that animals

    cannot have

    rights,

    "not

    being

    members of

    human society."67We sometimes now meet with the suggestion,

    however,

    that animals

    do

    in

    fact

    form,

    with

    men,

    a

    single

    community.

    Indeed,

    the American

    ecologist,

    Aldo

    Leopold,

    has

    gone

    furtherthan

    this:

    "When

    we see land as a

    community

    o

    which

    we

    belong,

    we

    may

    begin

    to

    use

    it with love and

    respect."68

    As

    a final

    absurdity,

    t is

    worth

    noting,

    Thomas

    Taylor's

    Vindication

    of

    the

    Rights of

    Beasts

    had

    looked forwardto

    a time when "even the

    most

    contemptible

    clod

    of

    earth"

    would

    be

    thought

    of

    as

    having

    rights.

    He was better

    as

    a

    prophet

    than as anironist.)

    Ecologically,

    no

    doubt,

    men form a

    community

    with

    plants,

    ani-

    mals, soil,

    in the sense that a

    particular ife-cycle

    may

    involve

    two,

    three,

    or even

    all four of them.

    From the

    point

    of view of a

    virus-if I

    may

    be

    permitted

    his

    way

    of

    talking-men

    are

    hosts

    in

    which

    hey

    can

    65Fordetails of

    this crusade:

    E.

    S.

    Turner,

    Heaven

    in

    a

    Rage

    (London,

    1964).

    66H.

    L.

    A.

    Hart,

    The

    Concept of

    Law

    (Oxford,

    1961),

    7.

    67D.

    G.

    Ritchie,

    Natural

    Rights (London, 1894),

    107.

    68Leopold,

    A

    Sand

    County

    Almanac

    (New

    York,

    1970),

    Foreword,

    xviii.

  • 8/10/2019 Passmore-Treatment of Animals (JHI 36.2 [1975])

    19/24

    THE

    TREATMENT

    OF

    ANIMALS

    213

    develop,

    hosts

    which,

    regrettably,

    ometimesdie before

    the virus

    has a

    chance to

    pass

    on to other hosts. But if it is

    essential to a

    community

    that the membersof it have common interestsand recognizemutual

    obligations

    then

    men,

    plants,

    animals,

    and

    soil

    do not form a com-

    munity.

    Viruses and men do

    not

    recognize

    mutual

    obligations,

    nor

    do

    they

    have common interests.

    In

    the

    only

    sense

    in

    which

    belonging

    o

    a

    community

    generates

    ethical

    obligation, hey

    do not

    belong

    o

    the same

    community.

    And it

    can

    only

    create confusion o

    suppose

    that

    they

    do,

    or

    ought

    to.

    Spinoza

    was

    right

    n

    saying

    that

    "excepting

    man

    we

    do

    not

    know

    of

    anything n nature in whose mind we can take pleasure,or anything

    with whichwe can unite

    ourselves

    by way

    of

    friendship."

    A

    dog

    cannot

    be "a

    man's best friend"

    unless this is

    just

    a

    way

    of

    saying

    hat the man

    has no friends.At

    best,

    to

    adopt

    Maritain's

    phrase,

    his relation

    with

    the

    dog

    is

    a

    "fore-shadowing"

    f

    friendship.

    A

    man

    can,

    of

    course,

    take

    pleasure

    n

    a

    dog's feelings,

    he can be

    pleased

    hat his

    dog

    is

    happy,

    and

    he

    can take

    pleasure,

    oo,

    in his

    dog's

    intelligence.

    But

    he cannot "share

    his mind"

    with

    the

    dog,

    if

    only

    because

    he

    dog,

    unlike

    man,

    has

    no

    con-

    cern for thefuture.It doesnot follow,as Spinozaalso thought,that we

    are

    free to

    destroy

    everything

    xcept

    human

    beings

    "or

    to

    adapt

    it to

    our

    service

    n

    any way

    whatever,"

    hat to have

    scruples

    on this

    point

    is

    a

    sign

    of

    "empty superstition

    and womanish tenderness."69

    here

    is

    nothing

    "womanish"

    or

    "superstitious"

    about

    condemning ruelty

    to

    animals,

    even if it

    is

    not difficult o

    think of attitudes o animals

    which

    are both

    "womanish" n their

    coddling

    and

    "superstitious"

    n

    that

    they

    try

    to

    treat a

    dog

    as

    if,

    let

    us

    say,

    it

    were

    a

    person

    n a

    poodle's

    skin.

    At the same time, the reference o dogs remindsus that domesti-

    cated animals

    may

    in a sense form

    part

    of a

    community

    as

    wild

    animals

    do not. Or at least this is true

    of

    societies

    in which a domesticated

    animal

    belongs

    to

    a

    particular family,

    which tends to treat

    it

    as

    a

    "honorary

    human

    being,"referring

    o

    it,

    as one

    sign

    of

    this

    attitude,

    as

    "he" or

    "she,"

    not

    as

    "it." Its wants are

    respected,

    and its ownersfeel

    some sense

    of

    obligation

    o

    it,

    perhaps

    o the

    degree

    that

    they

    will

    not

    migrate

    to another

    country,

    or take

    a

    long

    holiday,

    if this

    means

    deserting t. Such a feelingof obligation,however, s onlyjustifiableon

    the

    assumption

    hat to desert one's

    pets

    is

    a

    form

    of

    cruelty

    and that

    cruelty

    is

    morally wrong.

    Otherwise t can

    properly

    be

    condemned,

    n

    Spinoza's

    manner,

    as

    superstitious.

    It is

    sometimes

    supposed

    hat

    compassion

    o animals

    s a

    duty;

    as

    we have

    already

    seen,

    Kant

    gets

    into some

    difficulty

    n

    trying

    to deter-

    mine to whom it is our

    duty.

    But,

    as

    Hart has

    pointed

    out,

    there is

    somethingvery

    odd

    in

    describing ompassion

    as a

    duty,

    as if a manwho

    69Ethics,

    Pt.

    IV,

    Prop.

    37,

    Note

    1.

  • 8/10/2019 Passmore-Treatment of Animals (JHI 36.2 [1975])

    20/24

    214

    JOHN

    PASSMORE

    is cruelto animals s

    guilty only

    of a

    dereliction

    of

    duty.70

    t

    is far more

    natural

    to

    describe

    compassion

    as

    good

    and

    cruelty

    to animals as

    morally wrong. It can still be granted, o