Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

download Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

of 41

Transcript of Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    1/41

    1

    Learning From Hegel What Philosophy is All About:For the Metaphysics of Reason and Against the Priority ofSemantics1

    Jim [email protected]

    DRAFT, PLEASE DO NOT CITE, comments welcome

    When it comes to Hegel, disagreement begins with even the most basic questions.

    Recent debates have focused specifically on so-called non-metaphysical

    interpretations, which raise the most basic question of all: what is Hegels philosophy

    about?

    And yet it is not as clear as it should be what of philosophical substance is at stake

    in these Hegel debates, if anything. For it is difficult state what is at issue in a manner

    that would be accepted by opposing sides. As Redding puts it, it is still not clear which

    issues dividing them are substantive and which are ultimately verbal.2 Certainly the

    opposing sides make characteristic claims. Metaphysical interpreters say that Hegels

    ambitious goalsfor example, to give an account of the absoluteclearly express

    metaphysical ambitions.3 Non-metaphysical interpreters argue that they have a trump

    card in a superior ability to make sense of Hegels aim of engaging philosophically with

    Kants critique of metaphysics, rather than merely assuming the viability of a project

    1I want to thank Michela Bordignon, Richard Boyd, Paul Hurley, Luca Illetterati, Daniel Mornier, Dean Moyar,

    Jamila Mascat, Federico Orsini, Peter Thielke and Paolo Vinci, the works in progress group of the Claremontphilosophy departments, and audiences at Universit degli Studi di Padova and Sapienza - Universit di Roma.

    2Ibid.

    3e.g. Beiser 2005, ch. 3.

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    2/41

    2

    which Kant has specifically argues is hopeless.4 But insofar as this disagreement is

    about whether Hegel pursues metaphysics, differences may simply spring from

    different uses of that term. True, non-metaphysical interpreters more specifically

    compare Hegels view with anti-realism, internal realism, or other rejections of

    metaphysical realism or realism.5 But philosophical disagreements about realism

    are a paradigm case of the lack of agreement between opponents on the issues at stake:

    anti-realists tend to see a dispute fundamentally in semantics concerning reference and

    the truth predicate, realists a dispute fundamentally in metaphysics or ontology

    concerning what exists.6 So if the Hegel debates concern whether Hegel is realist or

    anti-realist, then this is again cause to worry whether the sides are talking past one

    another. Further, some who once called their view non-metaphysical now argue thatthis label produces misunderstanding of the approach, and prefer the label post-

    Kantian,7 emphasizing Hegels engagement with Kant. But my view requires me to

    contest the implication of the new label. For I argue that my metaphysical approach is a

    better way to understand Hegels philosophical engagement with Kant. And so the

    debate seems drawn ever farther toward debate about labels, and away from philosophy.

    But I will argue here that there is a surprising kind of philosophical substance to

    the debates about Hegel. For they expose a crucial philosophical question whose import

    is otherwise easy to miss: the question of metaphilosophy. The question is, what is

    philosophy itself most fundamentally about? Or, what issues are most fundamental in

    philosophy?

    Thinking in terms of metaphilosophy, in this sense, we will be able characterize the

    debate in substantively philosophical terms that all parties should accept. What

    distinguishes non-metaphysical interpretations is that they see in Hegel a

    commitment to taking as fundamental the project of considering our cognition in order

    4E.g. Pippin 1989, 7.

    5See the citations below from Pippin 1989 on realism.

    6See e.g. Devitt 1991.

    7E.g. Pinkard 1999, 230.

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    3/41

    3

    to construct an account in epistemology of the possibility of knowledge and/or an

    account in semantics of the possibility of meaningful thought (section 1). This need not

    mean a renunciation of all involvement in metaphysics in any and all senses. But it does

    mean that the only legitimate metaphysics would be one that is shaped so as to avoid

    conflict with, and to play a role in or rest upon the more fundamental project in

    epistemology and/or semantics. If the emphasis is specifically on the fundamentality of

    accounting for the possibility of knowledge, then we could mark this priority by

    referring to an epistemology-first metaphilosophy. If the emphasis is rather on

    accounting for the possibility ofmeaningfulthought, cognition or experience, then we

    can call it a semantics-first metaphilosophy.8 Insofar as both take as prior

    consideration of our own cognition and its capacities, we could speak more generally of

    a cognition-first metaphilosophy. Insofar as the so-called non-metaphysical readings

    of Hegel ultimately will emphasize meaning, I will generally call them semantics-first

    interpretations of Hegel.

    But I reject all forms of epistemology- or semantics-first metaphilosophy. And I

    think that Hegel rejects them too. Articulating a substantial and successful alternative,

    however, requires care with the term metaphysics. Some people may begin by thinking

    that philosophy is fundamentally concerned with problems about meaningful thought

    about or knowledge of an independent world. They will then tend to take metaphysicsto assume that some things are absolutelyindependent of our perspective, and that we

    can know them; they will tend to take metaphysics to be inquiry into the absolutely

    perspective-independent. But we can think of metaphysics differently, and must if we

    are to understand Hegel (section 2). We need not think of what I call the metaphysics

    of perspective-independence. We should think instead in terms of what I call the

    metaphysics of reason. Metaphysical inquiry, in this sense, is not founded on any

    special notion of, or assumptions about, perspective-independence. It is founded instead

    on the basic notion of one thing being any kind ofreason for another, or because of

    another. For example, a monist metaphysics (in this sense) would hold that the whole of

    everything is the reason for the existence and natures of the parts; an atomist

    8It might be better to say that such accounts would be part of meta-semantics, but for the sake of concision I

    will use the term semantics.

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    4/41

    4

    metaphysics would hold the reverse. Perhaps inquiry into reasons, in this sense, is also

    what is meant when AristotlesMetaphysics specifies its concern with primary causes

    and principles. But my aim here is not just to compare, but to explain this kind of

    metaphysics and its lasting philosophical appeal in independently accessible terms.

    The Hegel debates, then, concern what issues are fundamental. Some say that

    Hegels fundamental project is to account for the possibility of knowledge and,

    especially, for the possibility of meaningful thought, where the only sense in which

    Hegel might be engaged in metaphysics would be one that flows from and is shaped by

    the more fundamental engagement with epistemology and semantics. My alternative is

    the reverse: Hegels project is fundamentally within the metaphysics of reason.

    But my opponents will still take themselves to have a trump card when it comes to

    making sense of Hegels philosophical engagement with Kants critique of metaphysics.Matching this trump card requires distinguishing two stands of Kants critique. One

    strand is an epistemology-first critique, arguing that philosophy must begin by

    considering our cognition and constructing an account of the conditions of the

    possibility of knowledge, which will then show our cognition to be unfit for the projects

    pursued by pre-Kantian metaphysicians. But Kants critique would be weaker if it

    merely attacked metaphysics from the foreign territory of epistemology. It is stronger

    insofar as there is another strand: Kant also attacks metaphysics from within, or argues

    that it contradicts itself from within. That is the argument of the Transcendental

    Dialectic, which makes clear that Kants most immediate interest and target is the

    metaphysics of reason, rather than the metaphysics of perspective-independence

    (section 3).

    I can then match my opponents trump card. They see Hegels basic project as

    carrying yet further Kants attempt to account for the conditions of the possibility of

    knowledge and meaningful cognition in the Transcendental Dialectic from the first

    Critique, putting this to a different and more radically anti-skeptical end. But I too read

    Hegel as carrying Kantian considerations yet further. I read Hegels basic project as

    carrying further Kants consideration of reason and metaphysics in the Transcendental

    Dialectic, putting this to a different and more metaphysically constructive end (section

    4).

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    5/41

    5

    Once the metaphysics of reason approach to Hegel is clear, and the trump card

    matched, the advantages are easy to see. For it is then easy to see that Hegel himself

    argues powerfully against the claim that philosophy must first or most fundamentally

    set aside metaphysics and consider instead cognition in order to construct of accounts of

    our cognitive capacities (section 5). Further, this is not bad news for attempts to relate

    Hegel to contemporary analytic philosophy; my approach does just as well establishing

    such relations. And, finally, Hegels metaphysics of reason can help us to better

    understand the philosophical issues themselves. Of course, there is no space here to

    definitively defend a comprehensive interpretation of Hegel, let alone a comprehensive

    metaphilosophy. But we can use these terms to better appreciate the underlying terrain

    on which wars in philosophy are still fought today. In that sense, we can learn

    something important from Hegel with respect to the question of what philosophy itselfis all about.

    1. Metaphilosophical Diagnosis of the Hegel Debates

    I begin by giving the so-called non-metaphysical story about Hegels engagement

    with Kant a sympathetic formulation, in order to see how it depends on semantics-

    first metaphilosophy. So imagine someonecall her SF for semantics-firsttelling

    the basic story in three steps:SF:First,pre-Kantian philosophers have discussed things they thought we could

    know about. It doesnt matter what thingscall them X. But Kant argues that they

    have all taken some X to be independent of our knowledge or cognition, something

    which can in turn explain the possibility of our knowledge and cognition, and

    something which sets the standard to which our knowledge and cognition is

    responsible. In other words, they take the standard to be a way of grasping of X in its

    independence of our point of viewsomething like a Gods eye view. This package of

    pre-critical views is called metaphysical realism or just realism.9

    9Here non-metaphysical interpreters of Hegel can follow non-metaphysical interpreters of Kant; see e.g.

    Allisons explanation of Kant as fundamentally gathering together all previous philosophy as realismcommitted to a theocentric model of knowledge, and rejecting it all (1983, 19ff.).

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    6/41

    6

    I should interject in my own voice that SF here uses the term realism to refer to a

    view about the explanation of the possibility of knowledge and its standard; it is not at

    base a claim about the existence of a world independent of us. I will continue to use it in

    SFs way, since I have no special need of any use of the term. She continues:

    SF: Second, Kant rejectsrealism in this sense, taking it to guarantee

    skepticism, because we could never know how things would look from a Gods eye

    view. Kants alternative is reflection on our own cognition, aiming to demonstrate that

    we fix from within a distinction between the subjective and the objectivenow in a

    sense of objective that is internal to our cognition, and opposed to a pre-critical sense

    of absolute independence from us. So Kants philosophy parallels 20th century

    rejections of metaphysical realism in favor of a kind of internal realism.

    I should interject again that I dont seek to defend this reading of Kant, but only totell this one kind of story about Kant and Hegel, which continues:

    SF: Third,Hegel argues that Kant should have gone farther. Kant should have

    taken his argument in epistemology, concerning the possibility of knowledge, and

    extended it more consistently also to semantics, concerning the possibility of

    meaningful thought. More specifically, Kant claims that we cannot have knowledge of

    things as they are in themselves. But just as Kant admits that we cannot explain the

    possibility of knowledge of such things supposed to be absolutely perspective-

    independent, Hegel argues that we cannot even explain the possibility of meaningful

    thought about them. To assume otherwise would be to retain a semantic version of the

    same realism rejected in epistemology. To complete the parallel with the above, the

    conclusion is that we can meaningfully refer to an objective world only insofar as we

    fix from within our cognition a distinction between the subjective and the objective

    again in a sense of objective that is internal rather than the pre-critical sense of

    absolute perspective-independence. So we must give up as meaningless claims about

    absolutely independent things in themselves, even Kants claims to be ignorant of

    them.

    That is the basic non-metaphysical story. Redding has a nice encapsulation of the

    idea that the Hegelian worry about Kant is that he should apply his epistemological

    points more completely to semantics:

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    7/41

    7

    Kants combination of conceivability but unknowability seems to take awaywith the one hand a quasi-divine epistemic take on the world the so-calledGods-eye view only to return something like a semantic version of it withthe other (2007, 222)

    McDowells version of Hegel's Idealism as Radicalization of Kant takes its departure

    (2001, 527) from Pippins work. And the crucial elements of recent versions generally do

    stem from PippinsHegels Idealism. The story there is as follows:

    RP:Hegels basic project focuses on meaning or intelligibility in the sense of

    considering the conditions of the possibility of any intelligible experience of an object.

    Hegels view is built around acceptance, specifically, of Kants claim about the

    spontaneity and reflexivity of any intelligible experience of an object (1989, 12). This

    key claim is a revolt against realism, in that the spontaneity of our cognition explains

    the possibility of intelligible experience, rather than the objects themselves. Realism

    generally supports skepticism, or realist skeptical doubts (e.g. p. 107).Even Kants

    own thing in itself skepticism (p. 6) retains and rests on a residual realism which

    should, more consistently, be eliminated. Hegel rejects all realism, undercutting realist

    skepticism, in an attempt to reach the conclusion that our own knowledge is second to

    no other intelligible standard, and so is absolute (p. 94).

    It is easy to see why some who tell this story are rethinking the non-metaphysical

    label. For the point is not that Hegel limits himself to only modest knowledge about our

    own cognition as opposed to knowledge of reality. Rather, in Hegels hands, Kantian

    reflection on the necessary conditions of meaning and knowledge yields knowledge of

    realityknowledge that is not in any intelligible respect limited or less than absolute.10

    So the idea is that Hegel is an anti-realist, but of a radically anti-skeptical variety. And

    ifmetaphysics just means inquiry into what there is, then the point is that Hegels

    philosophy comes to metaphysical conclusions in that sense.

    But, by the same token, this story has oriented its understanding of Hegel around a

    debate whose philosophical substance can be elusive. If all sides could agree about

    Hegels conclusions are metaphysical, depending on how that term is used, then there

    is a threat that the debate is merely verbal. Further, attempting to locate Hegel relative

    10Redding 2009, 7.

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    8/41

    8

    to disagreements about anti-realism, brings us to disagreements facing the same threat:

    Realists will argue that anti-realism simply must be a form of skepticism, social

    constructivism, or some other denial of objectivity. Anti-skeptical anti-realists will

    answer that this is a misunderstanding, because their view is anti-skeptical; they will

    counter-charge that realists conceive of objectivity in a manner that is incoherent.

    Realists will respond that they do not hold the incoherent conception attributed to them.

    Anti-realists will charge that realists assume an objectionable account of the truth

    predicate in semantics. Realists will respond that the debate is not about semantics but

    about what exists. Etc. Those of us not involved in the fray will naturally wonder

    whether there can be a substantive philosophical debate if the sides so entirely fail to

    agree about what is being debated.

    Fortunately, I need not try to clarify the opposing positions on the object level ofdebates about anti-realism. For my view is that it is a mistake to read Hegel as if his

    basic project were to take any stand in anything like a debate about anti-realism. For my

    purposes, the most important feature of the story above about Kant and Hegel is the

    dependence on a view at the meta-level, or a metaphilosophy. The dependence is clear if

    we examine the need to argue against an opponent, rather than just tell a story. It is

    clearest if we consider an especially modest sort of pre-critical metaphysiciancall him

    PCM. He might say:

    PCM:Look, no philosophy can explain everything. Everyone must take

    something for granted. I begin with our knowledge of ordinary things, like rocks and

    trees and their parts, and then I use this to address the metaphysical issues of interest

    to mefor example, the question of whether these objects have indivisible atomic parts.

    SF seems to think that I am thereby leaving unanswered some other question about the

    possibility of knowledge of such things, or the possibility of meaningfully thinking of

    them. But, if so, then these are questions that I have no interest in answering. Nor,

    since we clearly can meaningfully think about trees, and most will agree that we can

    know about them, do I have any need of an account of the conditions of the possibility

    of such meaning and knowledge.

    Now the non-metaphysical story about Kant and Hegel begins with the idea that

    wherever we find such metaphysics, without a prior Kantian reflection on cognition, we

    are essentially dealing with objectionably realist account of the possibility of

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    9/41

    9

    knowledge. But what could the argument be for this claim against modest PCM, who

    takes no interest in and does without any account of this topic at all? As far as I can see,

    there can be an argument here, but only on the basis of strong metaphilosophical claim

    that the consideration of our cognition and the problem of accounting for the possibility

    of knowledge is fundamental to philosophy in a way that makes it inescapable. SF, for

    example, might defend herself as follows:

    SF: Claims about any rocks or trees or any X presume the possibility of

    knowledge of X. So such claims always raise philosophical problems about the

    explanation of the possibility of this knowledge. If PCM thinks he can ignore those

    issues, he is mistaken. For he is implicitly committed to some explanation of knowledge

    of X. Further, such explanations can either be realist or anti-realist. But PCMs account

    includes no analysis of our own cognition, only discussions of the objects of knowledge,X. So he cannot account for the possibility of knowledge in an anti-realist manner, in

    terms of the features of our cognition, such as its spontaneity. So he is committed,

    know it or not, to the realist view that the objects of knowledge, X, explain the

    possibility of our having knowledge of them. But an explanans must be distinct from

    an explanandum, or there is no real explanation. So PCM implicitly takes X to be

    something independent of our cognition. And that means that PCM implicitly takes our

    knowledge to be explained by a standard that is independent of our perspective

    which is the realist view that will inevitably support skepticism, etc.

    This is essentially an argument of the you are either with us or against us sort: no

    one can be neutral, because the issue is too important, and there are only two kinds of

    response. And SF will eventually turn this general line of argument against Kant as well.

    We could just as well imagine a modest Kantian, who claims ignorance of things in

    themselves. SF will have to argue that any such claim is committed to an account in

    semantics of the possibility of meaningful thought about things in themselves. And that

    any such semantics must be either realist or anti-realist. And that realism must be

    rejected in semantics too, undercutting realist skeptical doubts including thing in

    itself skepticism. So the arguments in what was once called non-metaphysical

    readings of Hegel must depend on the metaphilosophical commitment to the

    fundamentality or inescapability of issues about the possibility of knowledge and,

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    10/41

    10

    especially, meaning. And we can call this a priority of semantics or semantics-first

    approach to Hegel.

    Granted, there are any number of ways of developing a semantics-first approach

    that could be more balanced in other respects. Consider the quietist, Q, who argues for

    this view:

    Q: Constructive philosophy must be avoided altogether, because it will inevitably

    involve commitment to either a realist or anti-realist account of the possibility of

    knowledge and meaning, and neither is acceptable.

    True, this view gives priority to neither realism nor anti-realism. But the view is

    still driven by a priority claim at the meta-level: issues about knowledge and meaning

    are supposedly so fundamental that entanglement in one or another position on just

    those issues becomes inescapable for any constructive philosophy.Or consider the defender of a seemingly balanced semantics, BS, who will say this:

    BS:Hegel argues that, in order to account in semantics for the possibility of

    meaningful thought, we must recognize certain ontological commitments about what

    there is. So Hegel takes such ontology to be just as legitimate, for this reason, as

    semantics.

    But even if this results in a balance between semantics and ontology at the object-

    level, what is distinctive about the philosophy here is the way it is shaped by a priority-

    claim at the meta-level: ontology is legitimate only becauseand insofar as a kind of

    ontology can avoid conflict with an account in semantics of the possibility of meaning,

    and only because and insofar ontology shaped in this way can contribute to semantics. I

    will argue that Hegels project is quite the opposite: he takes a kind metaphysics as

    fundamental, discussing meaning and knowledge where these do not conflict with but

    are necessary to advance the fundamentally metaphysical project; for example,

    discussion of knowledge and meaning will be necessary in a metaphysical account of

    what we ourselves are and how we fit into the rest of realitynot in the sense of an

    account in epistemology of the conditions of the possibility of knowledge or meaning,

    but rather an account in metaphysics of the ways in which knowledge and meaning

    make us what we are.

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    11/41

    11

    2. Distinguishing the Metaphysics of Reason

    Different understandings of metaphysics will agree that it is an inquiry into

    something that is supposed to be privileged or prior, disagreeing on the relevant senses

    of priority or privilege. The most minimal understanding would take metaphysics to be

    inquiry into what existsor what is privileged merely insofar as it exists rather than not.

    Some might prefer to call that ontology, but it makes no difference here. More

    important is that those who look at philosophy through the epistemological lens of

    problems concerning the possibility of knowledge of a world independent of our

    perspective will tend to take metaphysics to be inquiry into whatever is privileged in

    the sense of being perspective-independent. If that is right, then to read as metaphysics

    any project of accounting for the absolute would be to read it as inquiry into

    something supposed to be absolutely perspective-independent. But it is crucial that this

    is only one way of understanding metaphysics; it is what I call the metaphysics of

    perspective-independence. We can distinguish the metaphysics of reason, which

    would be inquiry into whatever is privileged insofar as it is a reason for something else.

    Thinking in this way, a metaphysical account of the absolute would be a very different

    undertaking: inquiry into reasons that are most basic, fundamental or complete

    regardless of whether those most complete reasons are in any sense more independent

    of our perspective than anything else.To see what I mean by reasons, consider again this example of a recognizably

    metaphysical debate: Some monists will argue that the one whole of all reality is the

    reason why there are many parts and/or why the parts are as they are or do what they

    do. Some atomists will take the opposite view: atomic parts are the reason why there is a

    whole of everything, and why that the whole is as it is and does what it does.11 Perhaps

    others would develop and defend a sense in which the whole and parts can be the

    reasons for one another. But, in any case, note that the sense of reason here is not

    epistemic: the question is not whether we conclude that there are parts for the reason

    that we know there to be a whole, or vice versa. Further, the question here has nothing

    to do with whether the whole or the parts is more independent of our perspective. It is

    11Shaffer (2010) calls the former priority monism.

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    12/41

    12

    open to the monist, for example, to say that they are precisely equal in perspective-

    independence; the point is that the former is prior in a different sense: the whole is the

    reason why there are parts, and why they are as they are. So this inquiry need not

    presuppose any special conception of perspective-independence. This is a dispute within

    the metaphysics of reason.

    Further, this sort of debate can be of interest to almost anyone. Anti-realists who

    prefer a coherence theory of truth can take an interest in the question just as much as

    those who prefer a correspondence theory of truth, those who think there is nothing

    interesting to be said about the truth predicate, and those who just dont have a position

    concerning these options. The metaphysics of reason in itself is not built on any of these

    specific notions of truth, but by what it seeks the truth about: about what is a reason for

    what.12

    Similarly, imagine you hold the radically anti-skeptical form of anti-realism that

    some people see in Hegel, namely: we can have knowledge of the objective world in an

    internal sense; and we cannot even meaningfully or intelligibly engage with any

    competing accounts of objectivity as absolute or external perspective-independence. If

    you hold thatview, then it will make sense to ask you questions about the objective

    world you recognize, including the question: what is the reason for what in this objective

    world? And since your view is radically anti-skepticalyou have dismissed asunintelligible what you call realist skeptical doubts including Kants claim to ignorance

    of things in themselvesyou will not deny the possibility of knowledge in principle of

    such reasons in the objective world. So even the sort of anti-realism some see in Hegel

    would not preclude engagement with the metaphysics of reason.

    Perhaps some will think that metaphysics must always involve positing a

    supposedly higher realm, or ground beyondthat of finite persons. But if we think in

    terms of reasons, this need not be so. Questions about whether there is anything beyond

    us that is a reason why we exist and are as we are would then be metaphysical questions.

    Different answers would equally stake out different positions within metaphysics: yes

    12Whether Hegel uses some entirely distinct conception of truth is another matter; on my view, even his

    conception of truth will be driven by the metaphysics of reason, so that the truth of X will sometimes refer to akind of reason for X.

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    13/41

    13

    is the position that there is such a beyond, which I would call the metaphysics of the

    beyond; no is the equally metaphysical position that there is no such thing.

    Returning to Hegel, then, when I say that I prefer a metaphysical interpretation, I

    mean that Hegel most fundamentally pursues inquiry into what is a reason for what. I

    do notmean that Hegels basic goal is to address in any particular manner the question

    of how to account for the possibility of knowledge or meaningwhether realist, anti-

    realist, or whatever.

    To see Hegels engagement with the metaphysics of reason, consider the initial

    example the laws of nature. The natural sciences seek knowledge of what is and what is

    not a law of nature. But there is a philosophical question here too: what is it to be a law

    of nature? On a humean approach, a law will just be a regularity or a generalization

    stating a regularity. (It is a matter of debate whether Hume himself is a humean, in

    this sense.13) Anti-humeans hold that a law is something else, something which governs

    events, or something responsible for which regularities hold. Recent humeans have

    emphasized that theirs is a non-governing conception of laws (Beebee 2000). For if

    laws are just regularities, then they more summarize than govern events.

    Hegel clearly holds that the laws of nature are the reason for the events that fall

    under them, or that laws govern. Consider the Lectures on the History of Philosophy,

    explaining how an idea of Anaxagoras provides the basis for further progress inphilosophy:

    Anaxagoras was the first to enunciate the doctrine that understandinggenerally, or reason, governs the world The movement of the solar system isgoverned by unalterable laws; these laws are its reason. But neither the sun northe planets which revolve around it are conscious of them. It is man whoabstracts the laws from empirical reality and acquires knowledge of them. Anyidea of this kind, that there is reason in nature or that it is governed byunalterable universal laws, does not strike us as in any way strange (LPH12:23/34)

    And Hegel notes how philosophy builds on the basic idea about reason or governing.Plato builds on it, even while rejecting the way in which Anaxagoras sought reasons

    merely in Atmosphere, Ether, Water, and the like. Indeed, Hegel here treats

    13The debate about whether Hume has a regularity theory focuses more specifically on causality than laws; see

    Winkler (1991).

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    14/41

    14

    exceptionless laws of nature governing the motion of matter as a form of reason in the

    worldbut he will also argue that this is the leastcomplete or absolute form of reason.

    Still, for now I focus on the sense in which laws are at least one form: the laws are the

    reason for the rotation of the planets; and this is just to say that their movements are

    governed by laws. The point is not epistemicit is not that knowledge of laws is our

    reason for believing or concluding that the planets rotate. Rather, the laws are a form

    of governing or reason in nature. The same commitment is clear in Hegels rejection

    of empiricism at the beginning of theEncyclopedia, which formulates and rejects the

    approach I call humean, according to which universal notions, principles, and laws

    (38) signify nothing over and above alterations that follow one after the other, and

    objects that lie side by side (39).

    Those who favor humeanism about laws might try to argue that the very idea of alaw of nature being a reason, or governing, is so unclear as to be meaningless. But

    thinking in terms of Hegels interest in reasons of all forms reveals the objection as

    powerless. For both sides in this debate are equally addressing an issue within the

    metaphysics of reason: both sides have a position on what is a reason for what. The

    humeans accept one form of reason in the worldthey hold that what actually happens

    is the reasonwhy there are laws (if there are, because laws are just patterns or

    regularities in what happens). Some recent humeans say specifically that it is in virtue

    of what happens that there are laws;14 or, there is a form of ontological grounding

    of laws by what happens, or a reduction of laws to what happens.15 These are all

    proposed ways of understanding the sense in which what happens is supposed to be the

    reason for the laws. An anti-humean, like Hegel, simply holds the reverse: in cases

    where there are laws, like the rotation of the planets, the laws are the reason for those

    happenings. So both sides are talking about reason, but they see different sorts of

    reason-relation moving in opposite directions. Since both sides are talking about

    different forms of the same general notion, humeans cannot object that their opponents

    are too obscure.

    14Loewer 1996, 102.

    15Schaffer 2008, 83.

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    15/41

    15

    Granted, some today might wish to reject both sides in this debate, finding anti-

    humean talk of governing and humean talk of ontological grounding bothtoo

    obscureperhaps because neither is analyzable in terms of ordinary causality. But this

    objection too is weak, because it assumes that causality itself is unproblematic, or

    something not in need of more basic philosophical comprehension. It is however

    obvious that there is philosophical debate about what causality is. And the debate is

    similar to the debate about laws. There is, for example, a humean conception of

    causality: for x to cause y is just for Xs and Ys to be constantly conjoined throughout

    space and time. And there are anti-humeans about causality. And this is again a dispute

    about reason: humeans hold that what happens is the reason why there is causality;

    anti-humeans hold that, where there are causes, these are the reasons why things

    happen as they do.What we are discovering, as we step through these debates, is the fundamentality

    of the question of what is a reason for what. We need the basic and general notion of one

    thing being a reason for another in order to engage any of these debates. And so we

    should accept that notion as basic, and proceed to consider what specific forms of

    reason there really are, which directions they run in different cases, and how they relate

    to one another.

    Further, these philosophical debates about reasons cannot be directly resolved by

    the natural sciences. No matter which specific laws natural science might uncover, doing

    so will not itself answer the underlying question about what it is to be a law, or the form

    and direction of reason in terms of which lawhood is best understood. In addition, part

    of what is at issue here is how different natural sciences relate to one another: are they

    all seeking reasons in a similar sense, or in divergent senses? If divergent, then how do

    these different reasons relate? Part of the aim of answering these questions within the

    metaphysics of reasons is to rationally and systematically comprehend the natural

    sciences themselves, the specific sorts of reasons they seek, and their relations. So

    although the sciences seek forms specific of reason in the world, the metaphysics of

    reason is distinguished from them in that it seeks to understand those forms of reason

    and how they relate.

    Those who prefer a semantics-first metaphilosophy might see all such issues about

    laws, monism, causes, etc. as a series of technical issues in isolated or minor areas of

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    16/41

    16

    philosophyas merely issues in the philosophy of science, for example, peripheral to

    the core concerns of philosophy with perspective-independence, knowledge, and

    meaning. But my point here is just that there is an alternative way to look at it. When we

    think in terms of the metaphysics of reason, we see rather a surprising thread linking

    issues throughout metaphysics. Take the example of the humean views above: they all

    stem from a wonderfully clear and incredibly comprehensive humean metaphysicsall

    there is to reality, says the humean, is a series of disconnected events arranged in space

    and time; this arrangement is the reason for everything there isfor laws, causality,

    necessity, etc.it can all be explained in these same terms. As David Lewis formulates

    the form of humeanism so important in recent analytic metaphysics, it is the doctrine

    that all there is to the world is a vast mosaic of local matters of particular fact, just one

    little thing and then another (1986, ix).I think that Hegels basic aim is to defend a comparably comprehensive position

    within the metaphysics of reasonalbeit one that is about as far away as you can get in

    content and simplicity as compared to humeanism. The humean view finds the

    fundamental at the bottom: the reason for everything real is found at the bottom, with

    one little thing and then another. Hegels view will find the fundamental at the top,

    although in a surprising sense. This will mean that the example of Hegels anti-humean

    position on the lowest-level laws of nature is only an introductory example. Hegels view

    is notthat the unalterable laws of nature are absolutely fundamental to everything. The

    rotation of the solar system as an example of something governed by laws of nature. But

    this does not mean that Hegel sees everything as so governed. Hegel will argue that the

    behavior of living beings, for example, is teleological, and not governed by exceptionless

    laws.16 And Hegel will argue that the laws of nature are only a very limited, incomplete,

    or minimal form of reason for the events they govern; teleological reasons for the

    behavior of living beings will turn out to be a more complete form of reasoncloser to

    the absolute. And it is not life but rather Geistor spirit that will turn out to manifest

    the most complete or absolute form of reason of all. So the laws of nature will turn out to

    be relatively less important in Hegels philosophy, even if a good place to begin.

    16I argue that he has a compelling case in Kreines (2008).

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    17/41

    17

    This is to say that Hegel will consider many different accounts of what is a reason

    for what, in many different senses of a reason. This will include those metaphysicians

    who think about reason as Grund (ground), in a sense that Hegel thinks inadequate.

    Thus Hegel will complain about the way reason is generally understood by advocates of

    the Satz des Grundes or principle of sufficient reason (WL 446/6:82). But what Hegel

    thinks most important here are those aspects of Leibnizs use of the principle which

    direct us rather toward a more complete form of reason, which he calls here

    teleologicalground (teleologische Grund). Elsewhere Hegel uses Vernunft (reason)

    to speak of reasons in the world, as when he says of the movement of the solar system

    that the laws are its reason, or the Gesetze sind die Vernunft desselben (LPH

    12:23/34). And we will see that the term Vernunftestablishes an important connection

    to Kant. But these are in any case different ways of thinking about reasons. The forms ofindependence most important to Hegel, like what he calls Selbststndigkeit (self-

    subsistence), do not concern at base independence of our point of viewthey rather

    raise issues about whether something is an independent reason for itself; Hegel will

    argue that this is a standard by which teleological phenomena will be of greater interest

    in a metaphysics of reason than phenomena governed by exceptionless laws.

    3. Kants Transcendental Dialectic Critique of the Metaphysics of Reason

    I turn now to Kants critique of metaphysics in the Transcendental Dialectic of

    the first Critique, so that we can later understand Hegels response. The thread running

    throughout this section is Kants account of the faculty of reason (Vernunft). The basic

    idea here is that truth is too profligate to serve as any kind of guiding goal for theoretical

    or rational inquiry. For there are innumerable truths about any number of things, many

    of them trivial or of no special theoretical interestsuch as the exact number of cookies

    in each box of cookies, the exact distance in miles between the box and the Golden gate

    bridge, and which of these numbers is higher. The faculty of the understanding is

    capable of coming to true judgments about what is the case in the empirical world; but

    the understanding nonetheless requires guidance from some more discriminating norm

    or goal, and it is the faculty of reason that provides the guidance. Because reasons role

    is to guide, Kant must characterize reason in terms of an aim or end (Zweck) or even

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    18/41

    18

    an interest (Interesse). And one way of expressing the goal of reason is to say that we

    are interested, insofar as we are rational, in underlying grounds or conditions of all

    kinds, or in following a regress from the conditioned to its condition (A523/B521).

    But Kant exposes difficulties by arguing that this last idea about conditions is not

    yet an adequate characterization of a guiding aim of the faculty of reason. In a way,

    conditions threaten to be still too profligate to guide. Imagine for example that we know

    of some X that is conditioned; if so, the faculty of reason will leave us unsatisfied and

    interested in the underlying condition. But what if the underlying condition, Y, is also

    something merely conditioned? Then the same dissatisfaction of reason will persist. So

    there are many conditions that do not in themselves satisfy reasons interest. Theoretical

    inquiry is concerned in conditions only insofar as we assume that, in finding conditions,

    we are making some progress toward knowledge of an underlying or unifyingcompletion in the series of conditions, or a complete reasonprogress toward what Kant

    calls the unconditioned. And so Kant argues that, if we find the condition for

    something, reason requires that the condition of its condition thereby has to be

    sought; thus:

    we see very well that the proper principle of reason in general (in its logicaluse) is to find the unconditioned for conditioned cognitions of theunderstanding, with which its unity will be completed. (A307/B364)

    Another way of putting this point is to say that reason seeks complete unity, or a unified

    underlying complete explanation. And this is the goal or norm by which reason provides

    the guidance needed by the understanding: the law of reason to seek unity is necessary,

    since without it we would have no reason, and without that, no coherent use of the

    understanding (A651/B679).

    It is worth noting an example crucial to the Transcendental Analytic, insofar as it

    is the topic of the Second Antinomy: the understanding might achieve knowledge of an

    object extended in space; reason will then take an interest in why it fills this volume of

    space, or the underlying conditions in the sense of the parts. Note that this isnotthe

    question of the epistemic reason how we know that or whether the object is extended.

    The question about underlying conditions (Bedingungen) here is a about why the object

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    19/41

    19

    fills that space.17 The idea of the unconditioned, then, is notany epistemic idea, such

    as the idea of something knowable with absolute certainty; to say that we seek

    knowledge of the unconditioned is not to say that we seek something under any

    particular epistemic description. Nor is it fundamentally the idea of something

    independent of our perspective, or the idea of something knowable only from a Gods-

    eye view. It is the idea of a complete reason why.

    But Kant is aiming to further argue that we cannot ever attain knowledge of

    anything unconditioned. Compare: I might be seeking a good espresso in Nevada, when

    it turns out that it is not possible to find a good espresso in Nevada; this is not to say

    that I am seeking something under the description ofthe unfindable. Similarly, Kant

    holds that we seek the aim of theoretical inquiry under the description ofthe

    unconditioned, or the complete reason whynot under the an epistemic description

    like the absolutely perspective-independent, or the knowable with absolute certainty,

    or how things appear from Gods point of view, etc. But it turns out, Kant will argue,

    that what we seek under the non-epistemic description is in fact unknowable for us, and

    would be knowable only for an intellect superior in kind. Thus Kant begins the A-preface

    to the Critiquewith the resulting tension between reasons interest and the limits of our

    knowledge:

    Human reason has the peculiar fate in one species of its cognitions that it isburdened with questions which it cannot dismiss, since they are given to it asproblems by the nature of reason itself, but which it also cannot answer, sincethey transcend every capacity of human reason

    Our attempts to answer these questions cannot be conclusive, and so we fall into endless

    controversies. And this is metaphysics: [t]he battlefield of these endless controversies is

    called metaphysics (Avii-viii). Note that metaphysics in this sense has nothing

    fundamentally to do with absolute perspective-independence, nor with any idea of a

    Gods-eye view. Metaphysics, in thissense is concerned fundamentally with the

    complete reasons for things, or the unconditioned. It is only on grounds of a further

    argument that our form of cognition cannot achieve knowledge of anything

    17Later, we will see that Hegel criticizes this approach, arguing that there are kinds of conditions which are no

    genuine sort of reason at all, so that an absolute form of reason need not involve being unconditioned.

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    20/41

    20

    unconditioned that the derivative result will follow: metaphysics amounts to an interest

    in something (the unconditioned) that is unknowable from our point of view.

    The resulting problem will be this: We seek insofar as we are rational or reasonable

    to reach conclusions concerning the unconditioned. But, on the face of it, our choices

    with respect to the existence of unconditioned grounds are that they exist or that they do

    not. And Kant argues that holding either view is unacceptable.

    Consider first the affirmation. Kant argues that we are naturally tempted by it.

    That is, we are naturally tempted to mistake the maxims or rules guiding reason for

    objective principles: In our reason there lie fundamental rules and maxims for its

    use, which look entirely like objective principles (A297/B353). So given reasons

    demand that we seek the unconditioned, we are tempted to affirm this further principle:

    there must always be unconditioned grounds for everything conditioned. This isessentially the principle of sufficient reason (PSR) of the early modern rationalists.

    The idea is that everything not a sufficient ground or reason of itselfeverything

    conditionedmust have an external sufficient or complete ground or reason, or an

    unconditioned ground. Rationalism, in the sense I will use it, is not fundamentally a

    position in epistemology. Rather, rationalism is any view in metaphysics that endorses a

    PSR and argues on that basis for the existence of God in this sense of a sufficient

    reason for everything.

    18

    But note that Spinoza is a paradigmatic rationalisthe employsthe PSR in arguing for his God atEthics IP11D. But of course his God is not something

    separate from the rest of reality, but the single substance that everything real is in.

    This is irrelevant to his status as a paradigmatic rationalist (in my sense here): he argues

    from a PSR to the existence of an unconditioned ground of everything, or God in that

    sense.

    Kants response to rationalism is subtle. On the one hand, the interest of our

    faculty of reason leaves us naturally tempted by rationalism. For example, consider the

    rationalist arguments for God, in the rationalist sense of that the concept of which

    contains within itself the Because to every Why? that which is in all ways sufficient

    18Compare Curley: Prospects for identifying a common rationalist programme are better in metaphysics. One

    doctrine Descartes, Spinoza and Leibniz did agree on was what Leibniz was to call the principle of sufficientreason (1995, 430).

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    21/41

    21

    as a condition. Kant holds that reason itself makes this rationalist argument tempting:

    this is even the natural course taken by every human reason (A584-5/B612-3). On the

    other hand, the Transcendental Dialectic argues that we must learn to avoid asserting

    theoretical knowledge of such rationalist conclusions.

    The problem with rationalism is supposed to be this: it must either contradict

    itself, or else come to depend on an untenable combination of epistemological claims.

    The threatened self-contradictions are developed in the first two Antinomies. The

    contradictions arise from a specifically rationalist line of argument, whose major

    premise is that there must be completion or sufficiency in a series of conditions: The

    entire antinomy of pure reason rests on this dialectical argument: If the conditioned is

    given, then the whole series of all conditions for it is also given; now objects of the

    senses are given as conditioned; consequently, etc.19 The problem arises specifically

    with respect to a regress of conditions in time (the first Antinomy) or space (the second).

    It is best, for the purpose of understanding Hegels response, to briefly sketch the

    second Antinomy.

    First, imagine accepting what I will call Assumption A: beginning with an object

    extended in space, there is an infinite regress to smaller parts. But a rationalist must

    insist that there is a sufficient reason why there can be any composition here at all. And

    the only way to find such a reason within the regresswould be to hold that there aresmallest, simplest parts which explain why there is anything here out of which things

    could be composed.20 So a rationalist looking for completeness within the regress must

    reject the Assumption A and instead endorse smallest spatial parts.

    Second, we can try Assumption not-A: there are such smallest parts in space. If

    they occupy some region of space, then the rationalist must insist that there is a

    sufficient reason why they occupy that region. Within the regress in space, the only

    thing that could provide such a reason would be smaller parts which, conjoined, occupy

    that region. So for any simple or indivisible part in space, the rationalist must hold that

    19A497/B525. In emphasizing this passage and my approach to the Transcendental Dialectic here, I am

    following Grier (2001).

    20By the assumption, there would be no simple part, thus nothing at all would be left over; consequently, no

    substance would be given (A434/B462).

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    22/41

    22

    there are underlying partswhich is a contradiction.21 And so the rationalist must

    reject the Assumption not-A, and hold instead that the regress to smaller parts extends

    infinitely down.

    But it is important that there is a popular way for the rationalist to escape

    contradiction. He can say that there is another optionunlike both smallest parts and

    infinite descent into compositionspecifically insofar as the sufficient reasons for things

    might be comprehensible and knowable only by a divine intellect. What God would be

    able to comprehend is how there could be an infinite regress of conditions,and then

    also, outside of the infinite regress, an underlying sufficient condition for all of them.

    For God need not follow a regress one step at a time; Leibniz holds that God could grasp

    even an infinite series all at once: there is always, underneath, a reason even if it is

    perfectly understood only by God, who alone goes through an infinite series in one act of

    the mind (Ariew and Garber, 303). Applying this escape strategy specifically to the

    regress in space, we get this view: insofar as complete reasons might be such as to be

    comprehended only by God, there could be an infinite regress of smaller parts in space,

    which also has a ground or reason from outside itself in the form of non-extended

    monads.22

    But Kant will respond that the rationalist escape route requires both affirming and

    denying oneself the possibility of knowledge of the same thing. It is not that Kant thinkswe are entirely unable to comprehend the idea of an intellect able to grasp immediately

    even an infinity of everythingthis is a central feature of what Kant calls intellectual

    intuition, which would grasp and present the object immediately and all at once

    (8:389). But if the rationalist speaks of sufficient reasons knowable only by such an

    intellect, superior in kind to our own, then Kant argues that the right conclusion is that

    we cannot know anything about themnot even whether there exists any such thing. Of

    course, there is a difference between knowing that something exists and knowing more

    about it; but Kant argues that if the latter requires divine knowledge, then there is no

    21the simple would be a substantial composite, which contradicts itself (A435/B463)

    22Or, similarly, Spinoza can take the analogous escape route, holding that there is an infinite regress within

    space and timeand then also add that the whole series is grounded insofar as it is in and so dependent onone substance or God.

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    23/41

    23

    principled reason why the former should not as well. For example, Kant complains that

    those who defend Leibnizian monads would have us be able to cognize things, thus

    intuit them, even without senses, consequently they would have it that we have a faculty

    of cognition entirely distinct from the human not merely in degree but even in intuition

    and kind, possessed by not by humans but beings that we cannot even say are

    possible, let alone how they are constituted (A277-8/B333-4).

    Note that this criticism need not rely on commitments from Kants specific claims

    about the limits of our cognition, its discursivity, etc. There is rather here an

    independent line of argument, which will offer supportfor Kants specific claims about

    our epistemic limitations. The point about rationalists is that theybox themselves into

    an untenable epistemic position: they can escape from the contradictions of the

    Antinomies only by claiming that reality is such as to be knowable only by a divinemind; but this involves claiming to know something while also claiming it is

    unknowable.

    Now to this point I have commented only on Kants critique ofrationalist

    metaphysics. But the Transcendental Dialectic is not just developing a worry about

    rationalist metaphysics; it is developing a worry about metaphysics more generally. It

    presents a problem that is supposed to affect everyone, not just the rationalist. The root

    of the problem is that we needthe faculty of reason, and its guidance by means of ideas

    of the unconditioned, if we are to pursue any theoretical inquiry at all, and even if there

    is to be any coherent use of the understanding (A651/B679). We cannot rationally

    hold that there are no unconditioned grounds while also trying to discover somewhich

    is to say, while still engaging in any theoretical inquiry at all. So the denial leads to the

    skeptical renunciation of the project of reason or theoretical inquiry, theeuthanasia of

    pure reason, or skeptical hopelessness (A407/B433-4).

    A quick way to get a glimpse of the point is to consider a famous scene in Molire:

    the character Argan is asked why opium interacts with us by putting us to sleep. And

    Argan responds, famously, that opium has a dormitive virtue or power. Of course, we

    now know better. We know what opium is made of, and why it does what it does. But

    consider the farthest point to which we have advanced in the regress of powers or

    dispositions. Say we find, at the limit of our current knowledge, particles X and Y, where

    Xs attract Ys. We might still ask why do Xs attract Ys? A contemporary Argan would

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    24/41

    24

    say: on account of their attractive power. But is it rational to take this answer for any

    sort ofconclusion?Kant would deny it. And he would explain his answer in this way:

    reason demands that we assume, at least for the sake of inquiry, that there is something

    more complete to be said in answer to the why-question. And reason demands that we

    inquire into what that more complete explanation might be. True, one could conceivably

    deny that there is anything more satisfying. But then one has no grounds left for saying

    that reason favors further inquiry over Argans self-satisfaction or utter lack of

    intellectual curiosity. And thatis skeptical hopelessness.

    While I think that there is more to say in defense of this last point, this will have to

    wait for another occasion. For our purposes, the important point is that Kants

    Dialectic aims to present a seemingly insoluble problem for everyone. We can affirm

    or deny rationalism, but thisleads reason into the temptation either to surrender itself to a skepticalhopelessness or else to assume the attitude of a dogmatic stubbornnessEither alternative is the death of a healthy philosophy though the former mightalso be called the euthanasia of pure reason. (A407/B433-4)

    Now Kant raises this problem in order to argue that there is one acceptable

    alternative, and only onesomething he thinks is new and radical. We must conclude

    that our own knowledge is fundamentally limited or restricted. More specifically, we

    must conclude that there are specific, principled limits of our knowledgelimits that

    will preclude knowledge of whether or not there is anything unconditioned, so that we

    can continue to be guided by ideas of the unconditioned without threat of the rationalist

    conclusion that we can know any such thing (thus precluding further theoretical

    inquiry) and without threat of the denial that there is any such thing (thus rendering

    further inquiry without reason of guidance). What compelling account of our knowledge

    would leave it limited in principle, in just this way? Kants answer is that our

    understanding is merely discursive, or dependent for content on intuitions from a

    receptive faculty of sensibility, and so also dependent on the a prioriforms of our

    sensibility: space and time. And in sensibility, i.e. in space and time, every condition to

    which we can attain in the exposition of given appearances is in turn conditioned

    (A508/B536). This account of our limitations gains support in this way: it provides a

    principled reason for denying knowledge of anything unconditioned, including

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    25/41

    25

    knowledge of whether or not there is anything unconditioned, thus explaining why the

    threat of the Antinomy does not justify complete skeptical hopelessness.

    Precisely this limitation of knowledge is what will allow Kant to hold that we can

    and must always assume, for the sake of inquiry, that there are unconditioned grounds

    and then seek them in inquiry.23 So reason demands that we pursue the unconditioned

    as an end, a goal; and reason provides perfectly legitimate regulative orguiding

    principles; but we must learn not to mistake this for knowledge of anything

    unconditioned. We can thereby at least make progress asymptotically (A663/B691) as

    Kant says at one point, toward the goal of reason that guides scientific inquiry. And thus

    Kant claims to avoid the skeptical hopelessness, or the euthanasia of pure reason,

    but without slipping back into the dogmatism of rationalist assertions.

    This line of argument for the limitation of our knowledge is clear to see in Kants

    own gloss of the argument of the Transcendental Dialectic. Kant says:

    That which necessarily drives us to go beyond the boundaries of experience andall appearances is the unconditioned, which reason necessarily and with everyright demands (Bxx)

    True, we cannot know that there really is anything unconditioned. But precisely because

    we still must conceive the unconditioned as a goal, we must conceive of it as

    unknowable, as present in things as things in themselves. Otherwise, the

    unconditioned cannot be thought at all without contradiction (Bxx). So the threat of

    contradiction concerning the unconditioned forces us to distinguish the objects of our

    knowledge from things as they are in themselves, and conclude that our knowledge is

    merely limited or restricted.

    It follows that there is a sense in which metaphysics is impossible for us. Recall

    that reason gives rise to endless controversies on the battlefield called

    metaphysics (Aviii). If reasonis responsible, then these are controversies about the

    unconditioned. The Dialectic arguments supports the conclusion that such metaphysicsis impossible for us: we cannot legitimately assert knowledge of any conclusion about

    this topic. But this is not to say we can or should forget these controversies: Kant says

    23On the need to assume, for the sake of inquiry, that there is something unconditioned, although we cannot

    have knowledge, see e.g. A307-8/B364.

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    26/41

    26

    just here that reason cannot dismiss(Avii) those metaphysical questions. He later says

    that we will always return to metaphysics as to a beloved from whom we have been

    estranged (A850/B878). True, some philosophers think that they have become

    indifferent to such metaphysics, but Kant sees them as unknowingly entangled in

    metaphysics: they always unavoidably fall back into metaphysical assertions, which

    they yet professed so much to despise (Ax). So the point is not that metaphysics stems

    from an optional or misguided interest in knowing things from a Gods eye point of

    view. It stems from a rational, legitimate, an ineliminable interest in the unconditioned

    or complete reasons; and we must keep in mind that inescapable interest, precisely in

    order to guard against mistakenly thinking that we can attain theoretical knowledge that

    would satisfy it.

    4. Hegels Non-Rationalist, Post-Kantian Metaphysics of Reason

    When we turn back to Hegel, we now have a choice. We need not read Hegel as if

    his basic goal were to defend one or another approach to explaining the possibility of

    knowledge and or meaning. So we need not take the basic orienting question to be

    whether Hegel is more of a realist or anti-realist about that matter. We can instead read

    Hegel as interested fundamentally in the issues raised by Kants Transcendental

    Dialectic critique of the metaphysics of reason. So the basic orienting question would behow Hegels view relates to the options Kant distinguishes there: the rationalist

    affirmation of the existence of unconditioned grounds, the denial of the same which

    Kant labels skeptical hopelessness, and Kants limitation of our knowledge. Does Hegel

    go for one of these options, or develop some other response to thissame set of issues?

    This orienting question makes it easy to see that traditional metaphysical readings,

    although not always explicit about it, tend to portray Hegel as holding a version of

    precisely the metaphysical rationalism targeted by Kant. For they portray Hegel as

    arguing on the basis of an assumption that everything must be completely explicable, so

    that there must be some complete reason for everything; such readings often take Hegel

    as accepting Spinozas claim that the whole of everything is a ground of everything, and

    then modifying Spinozas account of that whole. But that would be to say that Hegel

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    27/41

    27

    merely assumes a principle that Kant has argued against, rather than engaging

    philosophically with Kants critique of metaphysics.

    My aim here is to show how the a metaphysics of reason approach makes possible

    an alternative readingone which Hegel is not arguing for a return to specific

    metaphysical view specifically attacked by Kant. The idea is that Hegel follows Kants

    rejections of various basic options: Hegel agrees that problems concerning complete or

    absolute reasons are inescapable, so philosophers cannot claim to be indifferent to

    them; Hegel agrees in rejecting rationalism, or the claim that complete or absolute

    reasons would be something unconditioned, and that there must really be something

    unconditioned; Hegel also agrees that rejection of the existence of any sort of complete

    or absolute reasons would be an unacceptable form of skeptical hopelesness. But all

    this agreement does not mean that Hegel accepts Kants limitation of our knowledge anddenial of the possibility of our reaching conclusions in metaphysics. Rather, Hegel

    argues that Kant sees only these options because he views the matter in part from the

    perspective of the aimso important to earlier section of the first Critiqueof defending

    the faculty of the understanding. So Hegel will argue that, if we begin with Kants own

    account of reason, and re-work philosophy from this perspective, then we can build a

    new kind of metaphysicsone that finds a new way to avoid both rationalism and yet

    also skeptical hopelessness. In particular, Hegel will argue that complete or absolute

    reasons should not be understood as the sort of unconditioned grounds which

    rationalists think are real, and which Kant thinks are legitimately of interest to reason.

    Once we better understand completeness or absoluteness of reasons, we will be able to

    legitimately assert knowledge of them, without asserting rationalism.

    To see the break between Hegel and rationalism, consider Hegels account of law-

    governed natural phenomena, as for example in theLogic discussion of natural kinds of

    things that are linked by exceptionless lawswhich Hegel calls Chemism, emphasizing

    that he is not just talking about chemistry but lawfully interacting kinds of any sort.24

    Here Hegel argues that the nature of such a lawfully interacting thing is such that it

    cannot be comprehended except in relation to others. As Hegel says, a chemical object

    24WL 6:429/727.

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    28/41

    28

    is not comprehensible from itself alone, and the being of one is the being of the other

    (WL 6:430/728). What is it to be some law-governed X? It is to react in a specific

    manners with Ys, etc. And, further, to be Y will be to interact in characteristic ways with

    Zs and Xs. Etc. So the being of things of such kinds will depend ona whole

    interconnected network of kinds and laws within which that are a part, or the network

    within which they are nodes. For law-governed stuff, the determinateness of anything

    in particular is just one moment of a larger whole or Begriffof the whole: it is the

    concrete moment of the individual concept (Begriff) of the whole, which conceptis the

    universal essence, the real kind(Gattung) of the particular object (WL 6:430/728).

    The philosophical pressure towards this kind of metaphysical holism has often

    been noted in more recent metaphysics, even while holism is often resisted. For

    example, take Russell:There are many possible ways of turning some things hitherto regarded asreal into mere laws concerning the other things. Obviously there must be alimit to this process, or else all the things in the world will merely be eachother's washing (1927, 325)

    And Chalmers aims to resist the same holism: this would lead, he says, to a

    strangely insubstantial view of the physical world (1996, 153).

    In Chalmers and Russell, the aim of finding more substance in things pushes in the

    general direction of the view that physical reality is, in itself, mental or somehow akin to

    the mental. Chalmers reads Russell as attracted to the view that the intrinsic properties

    of the physical are themselves a variety of phenomenal property. And Chalmers

    considers protophenomenal properties (1996, 154). Kant reads Leibnizians as arguing

    in a similar manner: if there must be non-relational inner features of things, then what

    can I think of as inner accidents except for those which my inner sense offers me? -

    namely that which is either itself thinking or which is analogous to one (A265-6/B321-

    2). A more monistic form of rationalism would seek to dispel the seeming lack of

    substance by finding an unconditioned ground in the whole of all such interconnected

    kindswe could also take the whole to be a mind or something similar.

    But none of these is Hegels view. Hegels view is that, when we look to grasp a law-

    governed thing, it gets lost in relations, lost in a regress of dependence; it becomes

    something else than it is empirically, confuses cognition (Phn 3:190/149). Hegels

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    29/41

    29

    view is that lawfully governed things really are strangely insubstantial (as Chalmers

    puts it). Another way to put the point is to say that, when we look to lawful things, we

    find only the slightest ofreasons for what they do at all. True, the laws are the reason

    why things do what they do. But the laws are as they are on account of the relational

    natures of such things. Which is to say that the natures of things are as they are on

    account of the laws, and the laws on account of the natures, and so on. The regress into

    relationality results in surprisingly insubstantial reasons.

    Hegels anti-rationalist view is clearest where he discusses the weakness or

    powerlessness (Ohnmacht)(e.g. PN 248) or a degree of unreason (Unvernunft)

    (e.g. PN 250) in nature. Lowest-level law-governed things are weak insofar as they lack

    a complete or sufficient reason for why they do what they do. They falsify the PSR that is

    definitive of rationalism. And the point is not that we tend to mistakenly take lawfulnature to be weak or unreasonable because we tend to overlook some hidden inner side,

    like hidden mental grounds in physical particles or in the whole of everything. Rather,

    lawful nature really isthis weakness, or really this degree of unreason. For example, the

    lack of complete reason is a kind of contingency in the law-governed kinds or forms:

    In the sphere of nature contingency and determination from without has itsright, and this contingency is at its greatest in the realm of concrete individualforms, which however, as products of nature, are concrete only in an immediatemanner This is the powerlessness of nature. (PN250)

    Hegel will later argue that in some cases, there is a remedy for this lack of

    substance and reason. In particular, some of the sum total of all the lawfully interacting

    stuff finds itself part of different living beingslions, tigers, trees, and you and I. When

    we look to these higher-level beings, we find some of the substance that had gone

    missing in lower-level lawful nature. Take a tiger, for example. Why does the tiger have

    these sharp claws and the corresponding capacities to catch and kill rabbits? Here we do

    not get lost in a regress of dependence. The answer is not that rabbits have a

    disposition to be caught, and so on. For the tiger has these parts and capacities on

    account ofsomething about the tiger itself: an account of the intrinsic end or goal of

    self-preservation. As Hegel says, the living thing is articulated purposefully; all its

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    30/41

    30

    members serve only as means to the one end of self-preservation.25 This intrinsic end

    orZweck is supposed to allow the nature of an organism to be manifest in the

    determinate way that it relates to the environment, yet without its nature merely

    dissolving into relations with others. An organism is the real end orZweck itself it

    preserves itself in the relation to an other (Phn 156). This is supposed to make life a

    more complete form of reason, specifically as compared to lawfully governed lower-level

    things. Or, alternatively, a living being is more substantialprecisely in the sense that

    lawfully interacting things are strangely insubstantial.

    What is really surprising here is that a living being will be more substantial, in the

    above sense, than even the lower-level law-governed stuff of which it is composed. This

    can seem surprising when judged from the perspective of what Kant calls the

    understanding, from which we expect that if X supports Y, then X had better be more

    solid than Y in order to hold it up, as it were. But Hegel is arguing that matters are

    different once judged simply from the perspective of the interest in reasons, or the

    reasons why things do what they do. A tiger, for example, could not exist without the

    existence of the underlying stuff of which it is composed. But there is also a sense in

    which the natures of the underlying stuff are a matter of indifference when it comes to

    what it does. The tigers claw, for example, could have had the same capacities and yet

    be realized in a variety of different underlying stuff.Note, then, how Hegels conception of a complete or absolute reason comes apart

    from Kants conception of the unconditioned: an organism is, in a sense,conditionedby

    or dependent on the stuff of which it is composed. But insofar as this is a conditioning

    by something indifferent, this is no limitation of its status as a reason for its own

    behavior. We can mark this distinction with terms drawn from Hegel: dependence on an

    indifferent base26 makes no difference to the completeness of a form of reason. So to

    manifest a complete or absolute form of reason need not mean depending on nothing

    it need not mean being unconditioned in this sense. And, since a complete form of

    25(VPA 13:193/1:145)

    26For Hegels use of the term indifferent base, see for example the above discussion, from Chemism, of WL

    6:430/728. I am coining the term principle of activity to contrast with this.

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    31/41

    31

    reason might depend in that way on something else, clearly a complete form of reason

    need not be something on which everything else dependsit need not be some form of

    the rationalists God. To be a complete or absolute form of reason is rather to be

    something that does what it does on the basis of what we might call a complete and

    internal principle of activity.27

    Now organic life is supposed to be close to an absolute reason, in this sense, but

    not the most complete form. Although there is no space to even sketch the argument

    here, it is worth noting how Hegel puts the point in terms drawn from Kant: idea, in

    Kant, refers to a conception of something of interest to the faculty of reason; so Kants

    view is that the idea is always a conception of something unconditioned. Hegels view

    is that life (even if not unconditioned) is a form of the idea, is more satisfying to

    reason, although only a partial or incomplete form: the idea is firstly life (WL

    6:468/760). But Hegel will argue that an absolutely complete intrinsic principle of

    activity is realized only in the case of our own kind, or what Hegel callsGeistor spirit.

    This is why Hegel will call Geistthe absolute: the absolute is spiritthis is the

    supreme definition of the absolute (PG 384). Comparing life and spirit, then, the

    former retains a smaller degree of the unreason of nature, and only the latter is a

    complete or absolute form of reason, insofar as it is internally self-determining, or free

    in this sense:The highest level to which nature attains is life; but this, as only a natural modeof the idea, is at the mercy of the unreason of externality whereas in everyexpression ofGeistthere is contained the moment of free, universal self-relation. (PN 248An)

    We can know the absolute, in this sensewe can have absolute knowledgein that we

    can know something with an absolutely intrinsic principle of activity, something that

    realizes a complete form of reason: we can know and comprehend spirit. This need not

    mean that there is a complete reason for everything. Nor need it mean that we can know

    everythingfor there are many things without a sufficient reason, which are not

    absolute. For example, if basic physical particles lack any complete or absolute reason

    27See for example Hegels use of the term principle of activity in discussing Aristotles view of life (e.g. VGP

    19:174).

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    32/41

    32

    for what they do, then knowledge of the absolute need not be any kind of complete

    knowledge explaining the location and movement of every physical particle. Knowledge

    of the absolute is knowledge of something with an absolutely internal principle of

    activityknowledge of spirit.

    The resulting metaphysics holds that reality has a hierarchical organization of

    levels.28 Everything is composed of lower-level stuff, in which is found the most

    incomplete form of reason. Some of that stuff makes up living beings, whose behavior

    has more complete reason, or is more completely explicable. And some living beings

    have capacities of knowing (especially important will be the capacity to know

    themselves) and meaning, and behave in correspondingly distinct ways, because they

    are of the kind Geist, and it is here that we are supposed to find a complete form of

    reason.

    Why doesnt Hegels view, insofar as it is neither rationalist nor Kants own denial

    of knowledge, lead to the skeptical hopelessness Kant fears? First of all, Hegels view is

    that rational inquiry does not and need not seek knowledge of the absolutely

    unconditioned. For it need not have any interest in merely indifferent grounds. Rather,

    rational inquiry seeks knowledge of the internal principles of things. Such inquiry can be

    satisfied to increasingly greater degrees on the higher levels of reality. And even within

    lawful nature inquiry can make a sort of progress insofar as we discover at least adistant, imperfect echo of the sort of independent principle of activity found on the

    higher levels. For example, the whole network of kinds and laws within lawful nature is

    a distant but imperfect echo of the sorts of biological wholes we find on higher levels. It

    is comparable to, but not yet for itself that totality of self-determination (WL

    6:434/731-2). So we can have some success in explaining nature insofar as we can find

    more distant approximations of the idea throughout nature, even if these

    approximations are in truth other than the idea. In Hegels terms, nature is the idea in

    the form of otherness (247).

    28For example, in introducing the PN, Hegel says that there are different orders of kinds, a hierarchical

    structure of reality: the orders not only serve to give us a general view, but form a hierarchy (Stufenleiter) ofnature itself (PN 246Zu 9:20/10).

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    33/41

    33

    We can put the final combination of claims in this way: (i) Life approximates, but

    onlyGeistor spirit completely realizes, a complete independent principle of activity, or a

    complete manifestation of freedom and the idea. (ii) Metaphysically speaking,

    nature does not depend on Geist, but Geistdoes depend on the nature in which it is

    embodiedit presupposes nature. However, this is just dependence on an indifferent

    basis, in the sense discussed above, so it is no limitation of the status ofGeistas a

    complete form of reason, or as a manifestation of the idea. And (iii) speaking now

    epistemologically, there is a kind of dependence of nature on Geist. In particular, the

    explicability of nature depends on Geist: we seek to explain nature insofar as we find

    there a distant trace of the kind of self-determining system or complete reason that is

    fully realized only in the case of spiritso spirit finds, in this sense, traces of itself in

    nature, we find the world to be ourworld, in this sense. I will insert numbers for thesepoints to note how Hegel wraps them all together:

    (i) As Geistis free, its manifestation is to (iii) set forth Nature as itsworld; butbecause it is reflection, it, in thus setting forth its world, at the same time (ii)presupposes the world as a nature independently existing. (iii) In theintellectual sphere to reveal is thus to create a world as its being a being inwhich the mind procures the affirmation and (i) truth of its freedom. (384)

    In this way metaphysics can deal with the problems Kant uncovers in the Dialectic.

    True, the Second Antinomy shows that rationalists cannot accept there being only

    compositionality all the way down; rationalists similarly could not accept the idea that

    lawful nature is only relationality all the way down or around. But Hegel shows how to

    construct a metaphysics that breaks with rationalism on this point, accepting an anti-

    rationalist view, while avoiding the skeptically hopeless denial of the existence of

    complete or absolute reason. The key is to argue that Kant and the rationalists

    misunderstand what a complete form of reason would be: to be a complete form of

    reason need not involve being a ground of everything, nor being unconditioned; a

    complete form of reason would be rather something with an intrinsic principle ofactivity of its own. Thus Hegel can argue that there is an absolute form of reason

    Geistwithout arguing that this is the sort of metaphysical ground of everything

    envisaged by the rationalists. And Hegel can argue that we can know this absolute,

    without having to somehow know everything or any supposedly complete explanation of

    everything.

  • 7/31/2019 Last Kreines Metaphilosophy

    34/41

    34

    5. For the Metaphysics of Reason and Against Semantics-first Metaphilosophy

    I have argued that there is an alternative to non-metaphysical, or semantics-

    first interpretations of Hegel, which differ on matters philosophical rather than merely

    verbal. Semantics-first interpreters sometimes argue that they have a trump card in that

    they can best make sense of Hegels aim of engaging philosophically with Kants critique

    of metaphysics; but my alternative can match this card, once sufficient attention is paid

    to the Transcendental Dialectic. And once it is clear that there is a viable alternative,

    we can easily see some advantages of this metaphysics of reason approach.

    To sneak up on the more complex issues concerning Kant, it is helpful to start with

    Hegels response to empiricist critiques of metaphysics. Empiricists will attack by

    arguing that metaphysicians illegitimately take for granted the possibility of knowledge

    in metaphysics. The attack is based on an epistemology-first metaphilosophy: it argues

    that other projects in philosophy are subject to doubts about the possibility of

    accounting for knowledge on such domains. But Hegel has a powerful response:

    empiricists are in no position to complain that others merely take for granted knowledge

    on a favored domain, because precisely in such attacks empiricists do the same: the

    truth of the empirical, the truth of feeling and intuition is taken as basic (39An). The

    skeptical worry that we should doubt any kind of knowledge that is supposedly basic

    might be worrying for metaphysics, but only if it is equally worrying for empiricism aswell.Ifwe are to take such epistemological worries as fundamental, then the only

    principled or philosophical position, Hegel argues here, would be the more total

    skepticism of the ancient skeptics.

    Further, Hegel argues that empiricists do not provide any alternative to

    metaphysics. Just as Kant takes indifferentists to al