Hayek Two Essays

57
Two Hayek Essays – page 1 Two Essays by F.A. Hayek: “The Use of Knowledge in Society” & “Liberalism” Class Notes: Please read all of “The Use of Knowledge in Society” (1945) and only sections 1, 7, & 16 of “Liberalism” (1973), though the remainder of both the historical and systematic sections of the second essay will be most useful for those who read them. “The Use of Knowledge in Society”  by F.A. Hayek Hayek, F. A., 1899-1992. "The Use of Knowledge in Society" Edition:  American Economic  Review, XXXV, No. 4; September, 1945, pp. 519-30. First published: 1945.  I What is the problem we wish to solve when we try to construct a rational economic order? On certain familiar assumptions the answer is simple enough. If we possess all the relevant information, if we can start out from a given system of preferences, and if we command complete knowledge of available means, the problem

Transcript of Hayek Two Essays

Page 1: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 1/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 1

Two Essays by F.A. Hayek:

“The Use of Knowledge in Society” & “Liberalism” 

Class Notes: Please read all of “The Use of Knowledge in Society” (1945) and onlysections 1, 7, & 16 of “Liberalism” (1973), though the remainder of both the historical

and systematic sections of the second essay will be most useful for those who read them.

“The Use of Knowledge in Society” 

 by F.A. Hayek

Hayek, F. A.,  1899-1992. "The Use of Knowledge in Society"  Edition:  American Economic

 Review, XXXV, No. 4; September, 1945, pp. 519-30. First published: 1945. 

 I 

What is the problem we wish to solve when we try to construct a rational

economic order? On certain familiar assumptions the answer is simple enough. If we

possess all the relevant information, if we can start out from a given system of 

preferences, and if we command complete knowledge of available means, the problem

Page 2: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 2/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 2

which remains is purely one of logic. That is, the answer to the question of what is the

best use of the available means is implicit in our assumptions. The conditions which the

solution of this optimum problem must satisfy have been fully worked out and can be

stated best in mathematical form: put at their briefest, they are that the marginal rates of 

substitution between any two commodities or factors must be the same in all their

different uses.

This, however, is emphatically not the economic problem which society faces.

And the economic calculus which we have developed to solve this logical problem,

though an important step toward the solution of the economic problem of society, does

not yet provide an answer to it. The reason for this is that the "data" from which the

economic calculus starts are never for the whole society "given" to a single mind which

could work out the implications and can never be so given.

The peculiar character of the problem of a rational economic order is determined

precisely by the fact that the knowledge of the circumstances of which we must make use

never exists in concentrated or integrated form but solely as the dispersed bits of 

incomplete and frequently contradictory knowledge which all the separate individuals

possess. The economic problem of society is thus not merely a problem of how to

allocate "given" resources—if "given" is taken to mean given to a single mind which

deliberately solves the problem set by these "data." It is rather a problem of how to secure

the best use of resources known to any of the members of society, for ends whose relative

importance only these individuals know. Or, to put it briefly, it is a problem of the

utilization of knowledge which is not given to anyone in its totality.

Page 3: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 3/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 3

This character of the fundamental problem has, I am afraid, been obscured rather

than illuminated by many of the recent refinements of economic theory, particularly by

many of the uses made of mathematics. Though the problem with which I want primarily

to deal in this paper is the problem of a rational economic organization, I shall in its

course be led again and again to point to its close connections with certain

methodological questions. Many of the points I wish to make are indeed conclusions

toward which diverse paths of reasoning have unexpectedly converged. But, as I now see

these problems, this is no accident. It seems to me that many of the current disputes with

regard to both economic theory and economic policy have their common origin in a

misconception about the nature of the economic problem of society. This misconception

in turn is due to an erroneous transfer to social phenomena of the habits of thought we

have developed in dealing with the phenomena of nature.

 II 

In ordinary language we describe by the word "planning" the complex of interrelated

decisions about the allocation of our available resources. All economic activity is in this

sense planning; and in any society in which many people collaborate, this planning,

whoever does it, will in some measure have to be based on knowledge which, in the first

instance, is not given to the planner but to somebody else, which somehow will have to

be conveyed to the planner. The various ways in which the knowledge on which people

base their plans is communicated to them is the crucial problem for any theory explaining

Page 4: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 4/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 4

the economic process, and the problem of what is the best way of utilizing knowledge

initially dispersed among all the people is at least one of the main problems of economic

policy—or of designing an efficient economic system.

The answer to this question is closely connected with that other question which

arises here, that of who is to do the planning. It is about this question that all the dispute

about "economic planning" centers. This is not a dispute about whether planning is to be

done or not. It is a dispute as to whether planning is to be done centrally, by one authority

for the whole economic system, or is to be divided among many individuals. Planning in

the specific sense in which the term is used in contemporary controversy necessarily

means central planning—direction of the whole economic system according to one

unified plan. Competition, on the other hand, means decentralized planning by many

separate persons. The halfway house between the two, about which many people talk but

which few like when they see it, is the delegation of planning to organized industries, or,

in other words, monopoly.

Which of these systems is likely to be more efficient depends mainly on the

question under which of them we can expect that fuller use will be made of the existing

knowledge. And this, in turn, depends on whether we are more likely to succeed in

putting at the disposal of a single central authority all the knowledge which ought to be

used but which is initially dispersed among many different individuals, or in conveying to

the individuals such additional knowledge as they need in order to enable them to fit their

plans with those of others.

Page 5: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 5/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 5

 III 

It will at once be evident that on this point the position will be different with

respect to different kinds of knowledge; and the answer to our question will therefore

largely turn on the relative importance of the different kinds of knowledge; those more

likely to be at the disposal of particular individuals and those which we should with

greater confidence expect to find in the possession of an authority made up of suitably

chosen experts. If it is today so widely assumed that the latter will be in a better position,

this is because one kind of knowledge, namely, scientific knowledge, occupies now so

prominent a place in public imagination that we tend to forget that it is not the only kind

that is relevant. It may be admitted that, as far as scientific knowledge is concerned, a

body of suitably chosen experts may be in the best position to command all the best

knowledge available—though this is of course merely shifting the difficulty to the

problem of selecting the experts. What I wish to point out is that, even assuming that this

problem can be readily solved, it is only a small part of the wider problem.

Today it is almost heresy to suggest that scientific knowledge is not the sum of all

knowledge. But a little reflection will show that there is beyond question a body of very

important but unorganized knowledge which cannot possibly be called scientific in the

sense of knowledge of general rules: the knowledge of the particular circumstances of 

time and place. It is with respect to this that practically every individual has some

advantage over all others because he possesses unique information of which beneficial

use might be made, but of which use can be made only if the decisions depending on it

are left to him or are made with his active coöperation. We need to remember only how

much we have to learn in any occupation after we have completed our theoretical

Page 6: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 6/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 6

training, how big a part of our working life we spend learning particular jobs, and how

valuable an asset in all walks of life is knowledge of people, of local conditions, and of 

special circumstances. To know of and put to use a machine not fully employed, or

somebody's skill which could be better utilized, or to be aware of a surplus stock which

can be drawn upon during an interruption of supplies, is socially quite as useful as the

knowledge of better alternative techniques. And the shipper who earns his living from

using otherwise empty or half-filled journeys of tramp-steamers, or the estate agent

whose whole knowledge is almost exclusively one of temporary opportunities, or the

arbitrageur who gains from local differences of commodity prices, are all performing

eminently useful functions based on special knowledge of circumstances of the fleeting

moment not known to others.

It is a curious fact that this sort of knowledge should today be generally regarded

with a kind of contempt and that anyone who by such knowledge gains an advantage over

somebody better equipped with theoretical or technical knowledge is thought to have

acted almost disreputably. To gain an advantage from better knowledge of facilities of 

communication or transport is sometimes regarded as almost dishonest, although it is

quite as important that society make use of the best opportunities in this respect as in

using the latest scientific discoveries. This prejudice has in a considerable measure

affected the attitude toward commerce in general compared with that toward production.

Even economists who regard themselves as definitely immune to the crude materialist

fallacies of the past constantly commit the same mistake where activities directed toward

the acquisition of such practical knowledge are concerned—apparently because in their

scheme of things all such knowledge is supposed to be "given." The common idea now

Page 7: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 7/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 7

seems to be that all such knowledge should as a matter of course be readily at the

command of everybody, and the reproach of irrationality leveled against the existing

economic order is frequently based on the fact that it is not so available. This view

disregards the fact that the method by which such knowledge can be made as widely

available as possible is precisely the problem to which we have to find an answer.

 IV 

If it is fashionable today to minimize the importance of the knowledge of the

particular circumstances of time and place, this is closely connected with the smaller

importance which is now attached to change as such. Indeed, there are few points on

which the assumptions made (usually only implicitly) by the "planners" differ from those

of their opponents as much as with regard to the significance and frequency of changes

which will make substantial alterations of production plans necessary. Of course, if 

detailed economic plans could be laid down for fairly long periods in advance and then

closely adhered to, so that no further economic decisions of importance would be

required, the task of drawing up a comprehensive plan governing all economic activity

would be much less formidable.

It is, perhaps, worth stressing that economic problems arise always and only in

consequence of change. So long as things continue as before, or at least as they were

expected to, there arise no new problems requiring a decision, no need to form a new

plan. The belief that changes, or at least day-to-day adjustments, have become less

important in modern times implies the contention that economic problems also have

Page 8: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 8/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 8

become less important. This belief in the decreasing importance of change is, for that

reason, usually held by the same people who argue that the importance of economic

considerations has been driven into the background by the growing importance of 

technological knowledge.

Is it true that, with the elaborate apparatus of modern production, economic

decisions are required only at long intervals, as when a new factory is to be erected or a

new process to be introduced? Is it true that, once a plant has been built, the rest is all

more or less mechanical, determined by the character of the plant, and leaving little to be

changed in adapting to the ever-changing circumstances of the moment?

The fairly widespread belief in the affirmative is not, as far as I can ascertain,

borne out by the practical experience of the businessman. In a competitive industry at any

rate—and such an industry alone can serve as a test—the task of keeping cost from rising

requires constant struggle, absorbing a great part of the energy of the manager. How easy

it is for an inefficient manager to dissipate the differentials on which profitability rests,

and that it is possible, with the same technical facilities, to produce with a great variety of 

costs, are among the commonplaces of business experience which do not seem to be

equally familiar in the study of the economist. The very strength of the desire, constantly

voiced by producers and engineers, to be allowed to proceed untrammeled by

considerations of money costs, is eloquent testimony to the extent to which these factors

enter into their daily work.

One reason why economists are increasingly apt to forget about the constant small

changes which make up the whole economic picture is probably their growing

preoccupation with statistical aggregates, which show a very much greater stability than

Page 9: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 9/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 9

the movements of the detail. The comparative stability of the aggregates cannot,

however, be accounted for—as the statisticians occasionally seem to be inclined to do—

by the "law of large numbers" or the mutual compensation of random changes. The

number of elements with which we have to deal is not large enough for such accidental

forces to produce stability. The continuous flow of goods and services is maintained by

constant deliberate adjustments, by new dispositions made every day in the light of 

circumstances not known the day before, by B stepping in at once when A fails to deliver.

Even the large and highly mechanized plant keeps going largely because of an

environment upon which it can draw for all sorts of unexpected needs; tiles for its roof,

stationery for its forms, and all the thousand and one kinds of equipment in which it

cannot be self-contained and which the plans for the operation of the plant require to be

readily available in the market.

This is, perhaps, also the point where I should briefly mention the fact that the

sort of knowledge with which I have been concerned is knowledge of the kind which by

its nature cannot enter into statistics and therefore cannot be conveyed to any central

authority in statistical form. The statistics which such a central authority would have to

use would have to be arrived at precisely by abstracting from minor differences between

the things, by lumping together, as resources of one kind, items which differ as regards

location, quality, and other particulars, in a way which may be very significant for the

specific decision. It follows from this that central planning based on statistical

information by its nature cannot take direct account of these circumstances of time and

place and that the central planner will have to find some way or other in which the

decisions depending on them can be left to the "man on the spot."

Page 10: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 10/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 10

If we can agree that the economic problem of society is mainly one of rapid

adaptation to changes in the particular circumstances of time and place, it would seem to

follow that the ultimate decisions must be left to the people who are familiar with these

circumstances, who know directly of the relevant changes and of the resources

immediately available to meet them. We cannot expect that this problem will be solved

by first communicating all this knowledge to a central board which, after integrating all

knowledge, issues its orders. We must solve it by some form of decentralization. But this

answers only part of our problem. We need decentralization because only thus can we

insure that the knowledge of the particular circumstances of time and place will be

promptly used. But the "man on the spot" cannot decide solely on the basis of his limited

but intimate knowledge of the facts of his immediate surroundings. There still remains

the problem of communicating to him such further information as he needs to fit his

decisions into the whole pattern of changes of the larger economic system.

How much knowledge does he need to do so successfully? Which of the events

which happen beyond the horizon of his immediate knowledge are of relevance to his

immediate decision, and how much of them need he know?

There is hardly anything that happens anywhere in the world that might not have

an effect on the decision he ought to make. But he need not know of these events as such,

nor of all their effects. It does not matter for him why at the particular moment more

screws of one size than of another are wanted, why paper bags are more readily available

than canvas bags, or why skilled labor, or particular machine tools, have for the moment

Page 11: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 11/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 11

become more difficult to obtain. All that is significant for him is how much more or less

difficult to procure they have become compared with other things with which he is also

concerned, or how much more or less urgently wanted are the alternative things he

produces or uses. It is always a question of the relative importance of the particular things

with which he is concerned, and the causes which alter their relative importance are of no

interest to him beyond the effect on those concrete things of his own environment.

It is in this connection that what I have called the "economic calculus" proper

helps us, at least by analogy, to see how this problem can be solved, and in fact is being

solved, by the price system. Even the single controlling mind, in possession of all the data

for some small, self-contained economic system, would not—every time some small

adjustment in the allocation of resources had to be made—go explicitly through all the

relations between ends and means which might possibly be affected. It is indeed the great

contribution of the pure logic of choice that it has demonstrated conclusively that even

such a single mind could solve this kind of problem only by constructing and constantly

using rates of equivalence (or "values," or "marginal rates of substitution"), i.e., by

attaching to each kind of scarce resource a numerical index which cannot be derived from

any property possessed by that particular thing, but which reflects, or in which is

condensed, its significance in view of the whole means-end structure. In any small

change he will have to consider only these quantitative indices (or "values") in which all

the relevant information is concentrated; and, by adjusting the quantities one by one, he

can appropriately rearrange his dispositions without having to solve the whole puzzle ab

initio or without needing at any stage to survey it at once in all its ramifications.

Page 12: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 12/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 12

Fundamentally, in a system in which the knowledge of the relevant facts is

dispersed among many people, prices can act to coördinate the separate actions of 

different people in the same way as subjective values help the individual to coördinate the

parts of his plan. It is worth contemplating for a moment a very simple and commonplace

instance of the action of the price system to see what precisely it accomplishes. Assume

that somewhere in the world a new opportunity for the use of some raw material, say, tin,

has arisen, or that one of the sources of supply of tin has been eliminated. It does not

matter for our purpose—and it is very significant that it does not matter—which of these

two causes has made tin more scarce. All that the users of tin need to know is that some

of the tin they used to consume is now more profitably employed elsewhere and that, in

consequence, they must economize tin. There is no need for the great majority of them

even to know where the more urgent need has arisen, or in favor of what other needs they

ought to husband the supply. If only some of them know directly of the new demand, and

switch resources over to it, and if the people who are aware of the new gap thus created

in turn fill it from still other sources, the effect will rapidly spread throughout the whole

economic system and influence not only all the uses of tin but also those of its substitutes

and the substitutes of these substitutes, the supply of all the things made of tin, and their

substitutes, and so on; and all his without the great majority of those instrumental in

bringing about these substitutions knowing anything at all about the original cause of 

these changes. The whole acts as one market, not because any of its members survey the

whole field, but because their limited individual fields of vision sufficiently overlap so

that through many intermediaries the relevant information is communicated to all. The

mere fact that there is one price for any commodity—or rather that local prices are

Page 13: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 13/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 13

connected in a manner determined by the cost of transport, etc.—brings about the

solution which (it is just conceptually possible) might have been arrived at by one single

mind possessing all the information which is in fact dispersed among all the people

involved in the process.

VI 

We must look at the price system as such a mechanism for communicating

information if we want to understand its real function—a function which, of course, it

fulfils less perfectly as prices grow more rigid. (Even when quoted prices have become

quite rigid, however, the forces which would operate through changes in price still

operate to a considerable extent through changes in the other terms of the contract.) The

most significant fact about this system is the economy of knowledge with which it

operates, or how little the individual participants need to know in order to be able to take

the right action. In abbreviated form, by a kind of symbol, only the most essential

information is passed on and passed on only to those concerned. It is more than a

metaphor to describe the price system as a kind of machinery for registering change, or a

system of telecommunications which enables individual producers to watch merely the

movement of a few pointers, as an engineer might watch the hands of a few dials, in

order to adjust their activities to changes of which they may never know more than is

reflected in the price movement.

Of course, these adjustments are probably never "perfect" in the sense in which

the economist conceives of them in his equilibrium analysis. But I fear that our

theoretical habits of approaching the problem with the assumption of more or less perfect

Page 14: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 14/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 14

knowledge on the part of almost everyone has made us somewhat blind to the true

function of the price mechanism and led us to apply rather misleading standards in

 judging its efficiency. The marvel is that in a case like that of a scarcity of one raw

material, without an order being issued, without more than perhaps a handful of people

knowing the cause, tens of thousands of people whose identity could not be ascertained

by months of investigation, are made to use the material or its products more sparingly;

i.e., they move in the right direction. This is enough of a marvel even if, in a constantly

changing world, not all will hit it off so perfectly that their profit rates will always be

maintained at the same constant or "normal" level.

I have deliberately used the word "marvel" to shock the reader out of the

complacency with which we often take the working of this mechanism for granted. I am

convinced that if it were the result of deliberate human design, and if the people guided

by the price changes understood that their decisions have significance far beyond their

immediate aim, this mechanism would have been acclaimed as one of the greatest

triumphs of the human mind. Its misfortune is the double one that it is not the product of 

human design and that the people guided by it usually do not know why they are made to

do what they do. But those who clamor for "conscious direction"—and who cannot

believe that anything which has evolved without design (and even without our

understanding it) should solve problems which we should not be able to solve

consciously—should remember this: The problem is precisely how to extend the span of 

out utilization of resources beyond the span of the control of any one mind; and therefore,

how to dispense with the need of conscious control, and how to provide inducements

Page 15: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 15/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 15

which will make the individuals do the desirable things without anyone having to tell

them what to do.

The problem which we meet here is by no means peculiar to economics but arises

in connection with nearly all truly social phenomena, with language and with most of our

cultural inheritance, and constitutes really the central theoretical problem of all social

science. As Alfred Whitehead has said in another connection, "It is a profoundly

erroneous truism, repeated by all copy-books and by eminent people when they are

making speeches, that we should cultivate the habit of thinking what we are doing. The

precise opposite is the case. Civilization advances by extending the number of important

operations which we can perform without thinking about them." This is of profound

significance in the social field. We make constant use of formulas, symbols, and rules

whose meaning we do not understand and through the use of which we avail ourselves of 

the assistance of knowledge which individually we do not possess. We have developed

these practices and institutions by building upon habits and institutions which have

proved successful in their own sphere and which have in turn become the foundation of 

the civilization we have built up.

The price system is just one of those formations which man has learned to use

(though he is still very far from having learned to make the best use of it) after he had

stumbled upon it without understanding it. Through it not only a division of labor but also

a coördinated utilization of resources based on an equally divided knowledge has become

possible. The people who like to deride any suggestion that this may be so usually distort

the argument by insinuating that it asserts that by some miracle just that sort of system

has spontaneously grown up which is best suited to modern civilization. It is the other

Page 16: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 16/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 16

way round: man has been able to develop that division of labor on which our civilization

is based because he happened to stumble upon a method which made it possible. Had he

not done so, he might still have developed some other, altogether different, type of 

civilization, something like the "state" of the termite ants, or some other altogether

unimaginable type. All that we can say is that nobody has yet succeeded in designing an

alternative system in which certain features of the existing one can be preserved which

are dear even to those who most violently assail it—such as particularly the extent to

which the individual can choose his pursuits and consequently freely use his own

knowledge and skill.

VII 

It is in many ways fortunate that the dispute about the indispensability of the price

system for any rational calculation in a complex society is now no longer conducted

entirely between camps holding different political views. The thesis that without the price

system we could not preserve a society based on such extensive division of labor as ours

was greeted with a howl of derision when it was first advanced by von Mises twenty-five

years ago. Today the difficulties which some still find in accepting it are no longer

mainly political, and this makes for an atmosphere much more conducive to reasonable

discussion. When we find Leon Trotsky arguing that "economic accounting is

unthinkable without market relations"; when Professor Oscar Lange promises Professor

von Mises a statue in the marble halls of the future Central Planning Board; and when

Professor Abba P. Lerner rediscovers Adam Smith and emphasizes that the essential

utility of the price system consists in inducing the individual, while seeking his own

Page 17: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 17/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 17

interest, to do what is in the general interest, the differences can indeed no longer be

ascribed to political prejudice. The remaining dissent seems clearly to be due to purely

intellectual, and more particularly methodological, differences.

A recent statement by Professor Joseph Schumpeter in his Capitalism, Socialism,

and Democracy provides a clear illustration of one of the methodological differences

which I have in mind. Its author is pre-eminent among those economists who approach

economic phenomena in the light of a certain branch of positivism. To him these

phenomena accordingly appear as objectively given quantities of commodities impinging

directly upon each other, almost, it would seem, without any intervention of human

minds. Only against this background can I account for the following (to me startling)

pronouncement. Professor Schumpeter argues that the possibility of a rational calculation

in the absence of markets for the factors of production follows for the theorist "from the

elementary proposition that consumers in evaluating ('demanding') consumers' goods ipso

facto also evaluate the means of production which enter into the production of these

goods."*1

Taken literally, this statement is simply untrue. The consumers do nothing of the

kind. What Professor Schumpeter's "ipso facto" presumably means is that the valuation of 

the factors of production is implied in, or follows necessarily from, the valuation of 

consumers' goods. But this, too, is not correct. Implication is a logical relationship which

can be meaningfully asserted only of propositions simultaneously present to one and the

same mind. It is evident, however, that the values of the factors of production do not

depend solely on the valuation of the consumers' goods but also on the conditions of 

supply of the various factors of production. Only to a mind to which all these facts were

Page 18: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 18/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 18

simultaneously known would the answer necessarily follow from the facts given to it.

The practical problem, however, arises precisely because these facts are never so given to

a single mind, and because, in consequence, it is necessary that in the solution of the

problem knowledge should be used that is dispersed among many people.

The problem is thus in no way solved if we can show that all the facts, if they

were known to a single mind (as we hypothetically assume them to be given to the

observing economist), would uniquely determine the solution; instead we must show how

a solution is produced by the interactions of people each of whom possesses only partial

knowledge. To assume all the knowledge to be given to a single mind in the same manner

in which we assume it to be given to us as the explaining economists is to assume the

problem away and to disregard everything that is important and significant in the real

world.

That an economist of Professor Schumpeter's standing should thus have fallen

into a trap which the ambiguity of the term "datum" sets to the unwary can hardly be

explained as a simple error. It suggests rather that there is something fundamentally

wrong with an approach which habitually disregards an essential part of the phenomena

with which we have to deal: the unavoidable imperfection of man's knowledge and the

consequent need for a process by which knowledge is constantly communicated and

acquired. Any approach, such as that of much of mathematical economics with its

simultaneous equations, which in effect starts from the assumption that people's

knowledge corresponds with the objective facts of the situation, systematically leaves out

what is our main task to explain. I am far from denying that in our system equilibrium

analysis has a useful function to perform. But when it comes to the point where it

Page 19: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 19/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 19

misleads some of our leading thinkers into believing that the situation which it describes

has direct relevance to the solution of practical problems, it is high time that we

remember that it does not deal with the social process at all and that it is no more than a

useful preliminary to the study of the main problem.

Page 20: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 20/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 20

 Liberalism 

F. A. Hayek  

Written in 1973 for the Italian Enciclopedia del Novicento where the article appeared in an Italian translation. 

Reprinted as Chapter Nine of Hayek, F. A., New Studies in Philosophy, Politics, Economics and the History of Ideas, Routledge

& Keagan Paul, London and Henley, 1982 [1978], pp. 119-151 

INTRODUCTION 

§1. The different concepts of liberalism 

The term is now used with a variety of meanings which have little in common beyond

describing an openness to new ideas, including some which are directly opposed to those

which are originally designated by it during the nineteenth and the earlier parts of the

twentieth centuries. What will alone be considered here is that broad stream of political

ideals which during that period under the name of liberalism operated as one of the most

influential intellectual forces guiding developments in western and central Europe. This

movement derives, however, from two distinct sources, and the two traditions to which

they gave rise, though generally mixed to various degrees, coexisted only in an uneasy

partnership and must be clearly distinguished if the development of the liberal movement

is to be understood.

The one tradition, much older than the name 'liberalism', traces back to classical antiquity

and took its modern form during the late seventeenth and the eighteenth centuries as the

political doctrines of the English Whigs. It provided the model of political institutions

Page 21: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 21/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 21

which most of the European nineteenth-century liberalism followed. It was the individual

liberty which a 'government under the law' had secured to the citizens of Great Britain

which inspired the movement for liberty in the countries of the Continent in which

absolutism had destroyed most of the medieval liberties which had been largely preserved

in Britain. These institutions were, however, interpreted on the Continent in the light of a

philosophical tradition very different from the evolutionary conceptions predominant in

[119] Britain, namely of it rationalist or constructivistic view which demanded a

deliberate reconstruction of the whole of society in accordance with principles of reason.

This approach derived from the new rationalist philosophy developed above all by René

Descartes (but also by Thomas Hobbes in Britain) and gained its greatest influence in the

eighteenth century through the philosophers of the French Enlightenment. Voltaire and

J.-J. Rousseau were the two most influential figures of the intellectual movement that

culminated in the French Revolution and from which the Continental or constructivistic

type of liberalism derives. The core of this movement, unlike the British tradition, was

not so much a definite political doctrine as a general mental attitude, a demand for an

emancipation from all prejudice and all beliefs which could not be rationally justified,

and for an escape from the authority of 'priests and kings'. Its best expression is probably

B. de Spinoza's statement that 'he is a free man who lives according to the dictates of 

reason alone'.

These two strands of thought which provided the chief ingredients of what in the

nineteenth century came to be called liberalism were on a few essential postulates, such

as freedom of thought, of speech, and of the press, in sufficient agreement to create a

common opposition to conservative and authoritarian views and therefore to appear as

part of a common movement. Most of liberalism's adherents would also profess a belief 

in individual freedom of action and in some sort of equality of all men, but closer

examination shows that this agreement was in part only verbal since the key terms

'freedom' and 'equality' were used with somewhat different meanings. While to the older

British tradition the freedom of the individual in the sense of a protection by law against

all arbitrary coercion was the chief value, in the Continental tradition the demand for the

self-determination of each group concerning its form of government occupied the highest

Page 22: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 22/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 22

place. This led to an early association and almost identification of the Continental

movement with the movement for democracy, which is concerned with a different

problem from that which was the chief concern of the liberal tradition of the British type.

During the period of their formation these ideas, which in the nineteenth century came to

be known as liberalism, were not yet described by that name. The adjective 'liberal'

gradually assumed its political connotation during the later part of the eighteenth century

when it was used in such occasional phrases as when Adam Smith wrote of 'the liberal

plan of equality, liberty, and justice'. As the [120] name of a political movement

liberalism appears, however, only at the beginning of the next century, first when in 1812

it was used by the Spanish party of Liberales, and a little later when it was adopted as a

party name in France. In Britain it came to be so used only after the Whigs and theRadicals joined in a single party which from the early 1840s came to be known as the

Liberal Party. Since the Radicals were inspired largely by what we have described as the

Continental tradition, even the English Liberal Party at the time of its greatest influence

was based on a fusion of the two traditions mentioned.

In view of these facts it would be misleading to claim the term 'liberal' exclusively for

either of the two distinct traditions. They have occasionally been referred to as the

'English', 'classical' or 'evolutionary', and as the 'Continental' or 'constructivistic' types

respectively. In the following historical survey both types will be considered, but as only

the first has developed a definite political doctrine, the later systematic exposition will

have to concentrate on it.

It should be mentioned here that the USA never developed a liberal movement

comparable to that which affected most of Europe during the nineteenth century,

competing in Europe with the younger movements of nationalism and socialism and

reaching the height of its influence in the 1870s and thereafter slowly declining but still

determining the climate of public life until 1914. The reason for the absence of a similar

movement in the USA is mainly that the chief aspirations of European liberalism were

largely embodied in the institutions of the United States since their foundation, and partly

Page 23: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 23/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 23

that the development of political parties there was unfavourable to the growth of parties

based on ideologies. Indeed, what in Europe is or used to be called 'liberal' is in the USA

today with some justification called 'conservative'; while in recent times the term 'liberal'

has been used there to describe what in Europe would be called socialism. But of Europe

it is equally true that none of the political parties which use the designation 'liberal' now

adhere to the liberal principles of the nineteenth century.

HISTORICAL 

§2. The classical and medieval roots 

The basic principles from which the Old Whigs fashioned their evolutionary liberalism

have a long pre-history. The eighteenth-century [121] thinkers who formulated them were

indeed greatly assisted by ideas drawn from classical antiquity and by certain medieval

traditions which in England had not been extinguished by absolutism.

The first people who had clearly formulated the ideal of individual liberty were the

ancient Greeks and particularly the Athenians during the classical period of the fifth and

fourth centuries BC. The denial by some nineteenth-century writers that the ancient knew

individual liberty in the modern sense is clearly disproved by such episodes as when the

Athenian general at the moment of supreme danger during the Sicilian expedition

reminded the soldiers that they were fighting for a country which left them 'unfettered

discretion to live as they pleased'. Their conception of freedom was of freedom under the

law, or of a state of affairs in which, as the popular phrase ran, law was king. It found

expression, during the early classical periods, in the ideal of  isonomia or equality before

the law which, without using the old name, is still clearly described by Aristotle. This law

included a protection of the private domain of the citizen against the state which went so

far that even under the 'Thirty Tyrants' an Athenian citizen was wholly safe if he stayed at

home. Of Crete it is even reported (by Ephorus, quoted by Strabo) that, because liberty

was regarded as the state's highest good, the constitution secured 'property specifically to

Page 24: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 24/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 24

those who acquire it, whereas in a condition of slavery everything belongs to the rulers

and not to the ruled'. In Athens the powers of the popular assembly of changing the law

were strictly limited, though we find already the first instances of such an assembly

refusing to be restrained by established law from arbitrary action. These liberal ideals

were further developed, particularly by the Stoic philosophers who extended them

beyond the limits of the city state by their conception of a law of nature which limited the

powers of all government, and of the equality of all men before that law.

These Greek ideals of liberty were transmitted to the modems chiefly through the

writings of Roman authors. By far the most important of them, and probably the single

figure who more than any other inspired the revival of those ideas at the beginning of the

modern era was Marcus Tullius Cicero. But at least the historian Titus Livius and theemperor Marcus Aurelius must be included among the sources on which the sixteenth-

and seventeenth-century thinkers chiefly drew at the beginning of the modern

development of  [122] liberalism. Rome, in addition, gave at least. to the European

continent a highly individualist private law, centring on a very strict conception of private

property, a law, moreover, with which, until the codification under Justinian, legislation

had very little interfered and which was in consequence regarded more as a restriction on,

rather than as an exercise of, the powers of government.

The early moderns could draw also on a tradition of liberty under the law which had been

preserved through the Middle Ages and was extinguished on the Continent only at the

beginning of the modern era by the rise of absolute monarchy. As a modern historian (R.

W. Southern) describes it, the hatred of that which was governed, not by rule, but by will,

went very deep in the Middle Ages, and at no time was this hatred as powerful and

practical a force as in the latter half of the period.... Law was not the enemy of freedom:

on the contrary, the outline of liberty was traced by the bewildering variety of law which

was evolved during the period.... High and low alike sought liberty by insisting on

enlarging the number of rules under which they lived.

Page 25: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 25/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 25

This conception received a strong support from the belief in a law which existed apart

from and above government, a conception which on the Continent was conceived as a

law of nature but in England existed as the Common Law which was not the product of a

legislator but had emerged from a persistent search for impersonal justice. The formal

elaboration of these ideas was on the Continent carried on chiefly by the Schoolmen after

it had received its first great systematization, on foundations deriving from Aristotle, at

the hands of Thomas Aquinas; by the end of the sixteenth century it had been developed

by some of the Spanish Jesuit philosophers into a system of essentially liberal policy,

especially in the economic field, where they anticipated much that was revived only by

the Scottish philosophers of the eighteenth century.

Mention should finally also be made of some of the early developments in the city statesof the Italian Renaissance, especially Florence, and in Holland, on which the English

development in the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries could largely draw. [123] 

§3. The English Whig tradition 

It was in the course of the debates during the English Civil War and the Commonwealth

period that the ideas of the rule or supremacy of law became finally articulated which

after the 'Glorious Revolution' of 1688 became the leading principles of the Whig Partythat it brought to power. The classical formulations were supplied by John Locke's

Second Treatise on Civil Government (1689) which, however, in some respects provides

a still more rationalist interpretation of institutions than came to be characteristic of 

eighteenth century British thinkers. (A fuller account would also have to consider the

writings of Algernon Sidney and Gilbert Burnet as early expositors of the Whig doctrine.)

It was also during this period that that close association of the British liberal movement

and the predominantly non-conformist and Calvinist commercial and industrial classes

arose which remained characteristic of British liberalism until recent times. Whether this

merely meant that the same classes which developed a spirit of commercial enterprise

were also more receptive to Calvinist Protestantism, or whether these religious views led

more directly to liberal principles of politics, is a much discussed issue which cannot be

Page 26: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 26/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 26

further considered here. But the fact that the struggle between initially very intolerant

religious sects produced in the end principles of tolerance, and that the British liberal

movement remained closely connected with Calvinist Protestantism, is beyond doubt.

In the course of the eighteenth century the Whig doctrine of government limited by

general rules of law and of severe restrictions on the powers of the executive became

characteristic British doctrine. It was made known to the world at large chiefly through

Montesquieu's  Esprit des lois (1748) and the writings of other French authors, notably

Voltaire. In Britain the intellectual foundations were further developed chiefly by the

Scottish moral philosophers, above all David Hume and Adam Smith, as well as by some

of their English contemporaries and immediate successors. Hume not only laid in his

philosophical work the foundation of the liberal theory of law, but in his  History of  England  (1754-62) also provided an interpretation of' English history as the gradual

emergence of the Rule of Law which made the conception known far beyond the limits of 

Britain. Adam Smith's decisive contribution was the account of a selfgenerating order

which formed itself spontaneously if the individuals [124] were restrained by appropriate

rules of law. His  Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations marks

perhaps more than any other single work the beginning of the development of modern

liberalism. It made people understand that those restrictions on the powers of government

which had originated from sheer distrust of all arbitrary power had become the chief 

cause of Britain's economic prosperity.

The beginnings of a liberal movement in Britain were soon interrupted, however, by a

reaction against the French Revolution and a distrust of its admirers in England, who

endeavoured to import to England the ideas of Continental or constructivist liberalism.

The end of this early “English” development of liberalism is marked by the work of 

Edmund Burke who, after his brilliant restatement of the Whig doctrine in defence of the

American colonists, violently turned against the ideas of the French Revolution.

It was only after the end of the Napoleonic wars that the development based on the

doctrine of the Old Whigs and of Adam Smith was resumed. The further intellectual

Page 27: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 27/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 27

development was guided largely by a group of disciples of the Scottish moral

philosophers who gathered round the  Edinburgh Review, mostly economists in the

tradition of Adam Smith; the pure Whig doctrine was once more restated in a form which

widely affected Continental thinking by the historian T. B. Macaulay who for the

nineteenth century did what Hume in his historical work had done for the eighteenth.

Already, however, this development was paralleled by the rapid growth of a radical

movement of which the Benthamite 'Philosophical Radicals' became the leaders and

which traced back more to the Continental than to the British tradition. It was ultimately

from the fusion of these traditions that in the 1830s the political party arose which from

about 1842 came to be known as the Liberal Party, and for the rest of the century

remained the most important representative of the liberal movement in Europe.

Long before that, however, another decisive contribution had come from America. The

explicit formulation by the former British colonists, in a written constitution, of what they

understood to be the essentials of the British tradition of liberty, intended to limit the

powers of government, and especially the statement of the fundamental liberties in a Bill

of Rights, provided a model of political institutions which profoundly affected the

development of liberalism in Europe. Though the United States, just because their people

felt [125] that they had already embodied the safeguards of liberty ill their political

institutions, never developed it distinct liberal movement, for the Europeans they became

the dreamland of liberty and the example which inspired political aspirations as much as

English institutions had done during the eighteenth century.

§4. The development of Continental liberalism 

The radical ideas of the philosophers of the French Enlightenment, mainly in the form in

which they, had been applied to political problems by Turgot, Condorcet and the Abbé

Sieyès largely dominated progressive opinion in France and the adjoining countries of the

Continent during the Revolutionary and Napoleonic periods; but of a definite liberal

movement one can speak only after the Restoration. In France it reached its height during

the July Monarchy (1830-48), but after that period remained confined to a small élite. It

Page 28: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 28/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 28

was made up of several different strands of thought. An important attempt to systematize

and adapt to Continental conditions what he regarded as the British tradition was made by

Benj amin Constant, and was developed further during the I 830s and 1840s by a group

known as the 'doctrinaires' under the leadership of F. P. G. Guizot. Their programme,

known as 'guarantism', was essentially a doctrine of constitutional limitations of 

government. For this constitutional doctrine which made up the most important part of 

the Continental liberal movement of the first half of the nineteenth century, the

constitution of 1831 of the newly created Belgian state served as an important model. To

this tradition, largely deriving from Britain, also belonged the perhaps most important

French liberal thinker, Alexis de Tocqueville.

The feature, however, which greatly distinguished the type of liberalism predominant onthe Continent from the British one was from the beginning what is best described as its

free-thinking aspect, which expressed itself in a strong anti-clerical, anti-religious and

generally anti-traditionalist attitude. Not only in France, but also in the other Roman

Catholic parts of Europe, the continuous conflict with the church of Rome became indeed

so characteristic of liberalism that to many people it appeared as its primary

characteristic, particularly after, in the second half of the century, the church took ill) the

struggle against 'modernism' and therefore against most demands for liberal reform.

During the first half of the century, up to the revolutions of 1848, [126] the liberal

movement in France, as well its in most of the rest of' western and central Europe, had

also been much more closely allied with the democratic movement than was the case with

British liberalism. It was indeed largely displaced by it and by the new socialist

movement during the second half of the century. Except for a short period around the

middle of the century, when the movement for free trade rallied the liberal groups,

liberalism did not again play an important role in the political development of France, nor

after 1848 did French thinkers make any important contributions to its doctrine.

A somewhat more important role was played by the liberal movement in Germany, and a

more distinct development did take place during the first three-quarters of the nineteenth

Page 29: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 29/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 29

century. Though greatly influenced by the ideas derived from Britain and France, these

were transformed by ideas of the three greatest and earliest of the German liberals, the

philosopher Immanuel Kant, the scholar and statesman Wilhelm von Humboldt, and the

poet Friedrich Schiller. Kant had provided a theory on lines similar to those of David

Hume, centred on the concepts of law as the protection of individual freedom and of the

Rule of Law (or the Rechtsstaat, as it came to be known in Germany); Humboldt had in

an early work On the Sphere and Duties of Government (1792) developed the picture of a

state wholly confined to the maintenance of law and order - a book of which only a small

part was published at the time, but which, when it was finally published (and translated

into English) in 1854, exercised wide influence not only in Germany but also on such

diverse thinkers as J. S. Mill in England and E. Laboulaye in France. The poet Schiller,

finally, probably did more than any other single person to make the whole educated

public in Germany familiar with the ideal of personal liberty.

There was an early beginning towards a liberal policy in Prussia during the reforms of 

Freiherr vom Stein, but it was followed by another period of reaction after the end of the

Napoleonic wars. Only in the 1830s did a general liberal movement begin to develop,

which from the beginning, however, as was also true in Italy, was closely associated with

a nationalist movement aiming at the unification of the country. In general, German

liberalism was mainly a constitutionalist movement which in north Germany was

somewhat more guided by the British example, while in the south the French model was

more influential. This found expression chiefly in a [127] different attitude towards the

problem of limiting the discretionary powers of government which in the north produced

a fairly strict conception of the Rule of Law (or the Rechtsstaat), while in the south it was

guided more by the French interpretation of the Separation of Powers that stressed the

independence of the administration from the ordinary courts. In the south, however, and

especially in Baden and Wurttemberg, there developed a more active group of liberal

theorists around the Staatslexicon of C. von Rotteck and C. T. WeIcker, which in the

period before the revolution of 1848 became the main centre of German liberal thought.

The failure of that revolution brought another short period of reaction, but in the 186os

and early 1870s it seemed for a time as if Germany, too, were rapidly moving towards a

Page 30: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 30/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 30

liberal order. It was during this period that the constitutional and legal reforms intended

definitely to establish the  Rechtsstaat  were brought to completion. The middle of the

1870s must probably be regarded as the time when the liberal movement in Europe had

gained its greatest influence and its easternmost expansion. With the German return to

protection in 1878, and the new social policies initiated by Bismarck at about the same

time, the reversal of the movement began. The liberal party which had flourished for little

more than a dozen years rapidly declined.

Both in Germany and in Italy the decline of the liberal movement set in when it lost its

association with the movement for national unification, and the achieved unity directed

attention to the strengthening of the new states, and when, moreover, the beginnings of a

labour movement deprived liberalism of the position of the 'advanced' party which untilthen the politically active part of the working class had supported.

§5. Classical British liberalism 

Throughout the greater part of the nineteenth century the European country which

seemed nearest to a realization of the liberal principles was Great Britain. There most of 

them appeared to be accepted not only by a powerful Liberal Party but by the majority of 

the population, and even the Conservatives often became the instrument of theachievement of liberal reforms. The great events after which Britain could appear to the

rest of Europe as the representative model of a liberal order were the Catholic

emancipation of 1829, the Reform Act of 1832, and the repeal of the corn laws by the

Conservative, Sir [128] Robert Peel, in 1846. Since by then the chief demands of 

liberalism concerning internal policy were satisfied, agitation concentrated on the

establishment of free trade. The movement initiated by the Merchants' Petition of 1820,

and carried on from 1836 to 1846 by the Anti-Corn-Law League, was developed

particularly by a group of radicals who, under the leadership of Richard Cobden and John

Bright, took a somewhat more extreme laissez faire position than would have been

required by the liberal principles of Adam Smith and the classical economists following

him. Their predominant free trade position was combined with a strong anti-imperialist,

Page 31: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 31/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 31

anti interventionist and anti-militarist attitude and an aversion to a expansion of 

governmental powers; the increase of public expenditure was regarded by them as

mainly due to undesirable interventions in overseas affairs. Their opposition was directed

chiefly against the expansion of the powers of central government, and most

improvements were expected from autonomous efforts either of local government or of 

voluntary organizations. 'Peace, Retrenchment and Reform' became the liberal

watchword of this period, with 'reform' referring more to the abolition of old abuses and

privilege than the extension of democracy, with which the movement became more

closely associated only at the time of the Second Reform Act of 1867. The movement had

reached its climax with the Cobden Treaty with France of 186o, a commercial treaty

which led to the establishment of free trade in Britain and a widespread expectation that

free trade would soon universally prevail. At that time there

emerged also in Britain, as the leading figure of the liberal movement W. E. Gladstone

who, first as Chancellor of the Exchequer and the as liberal Prime Minister, came to be

widely regarded as the living embodiment of liberal principles, especially, after

Palmerston death in 1865, with regard to foreign policy, with John Bright as hi chief 

associate. With him also the old association of British liberalism with strong moral and

religious views revived.

In the intellectual sphere during the second half of the nineteenth century the basic

principles of liberalism were intensively discussed In the philosopher Herbert Spencer an

extreme advocacy of a individualist minimum state, similar to the position of W. von

Humboldt, found an effective expounder. But John Stuart Mill in his celebrated book On

 Liberty (1859), directed his criticism chiefly against the tyranny of opinion rather than the

actions of government and by his advocacy of distributive justice and a general

sympathetic [129] attitude towards  socialist aspirations in some of' his other works,

prepared the gradual transition of' a large part of' the liberal intellectuals to a moderate

socialism. This tendency was noticeably strengthened by the influence of the philosopher

T. H. Green who stressed the positive functions of the state against the predominantly

negative conception of liberty of the older liberals.

Page 32: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 32/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 32

But though the last quarter of the nineteenth century saw already much internal criticism

of liberal doctrines within the liberal camp and though the Liberal Party was beginning to

lose support to the new labour movement, the predominance of liberal ideas in Great

Britain lasted well into the twentieth century and succeeded in defeating a revival of 

protectionist demands, though the Liberal Party could not avoid a progressive infiltration

by interventionist and imperialist elements. Perhaps the government of H. Campbell

Bannerman (1904) should be regarded as the last liberal government of the old type,

while under his successor, H. H. Asquith, new experiments in social policy were

undertaken which were only doubtfully compatible with the older liberal principles. But

on the whole it can be said that the liberal era of British policy lasted until the outbreak of 

the First World War, and that the dominating influence of liberal ideas in Britain was

terminated only by the effects of this war.

§6. The decline of liberalism 

Though some of the elder European statesmen and other leaders in practical affairs after

the First World War were still guided by an essentially liberal outlook, and attempts were

made at first to restore the political and economic institutions of the pre-war period,

several factors brought it about that the influence of liberalism steadily declined until the

Second World War. The most important was that socialism, particularly in the opinion of 

a large part of the intellectuals, had replaced liberalism as the progressive movement.

Political discussion was thus carried on mainly between socialists and conservatives, both

supporting increasing activities of the state, though with different aims. The economic

difficulties, unemployment and unstable currencies, seemed to demand much more

economic control by government and led to a revival of protectionism and other

nationalistic policies. A rapid growth of the bureaucratic apparatus of government and the

acquisition of far-reaching discretionary powers by it was the consequence. These

tendencies, already strong during [130] the first post-war decade, became even more

marked during the Great Depression following the US crash of 1929. The final

abandonment of the gold standard and the return to protection by Great Britain in 1931

seemed to mark the definite end of a free world economy. The rise of dictatorial or

Page 33: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 33/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 33

totalitarian régimes in large parts of Europe not only extinguished the weak liberal groups

which had remained in the countries immediately affected, but the threat of war which it

produced led even in Western Europe to an increasing government dominance over

economic affairs and a tendency towards national self-sufficiency.

After the end of the Second World War there occurred once more a temporary revival of 

liberal ideas, due partly to a new awareness of the oppressive character of all kinds of 

totalitarian régimes, and partly to the recognition that the obstacles to international trade

which had grown up during the inter-war period had been largely responsible for the

economic depression. The representative achievement was the General Agreement on

Tariffs and Trade (GATT) of 1948, but the attempts to create a larger economic unit such

as the Common Market and EFTA also ostensibly aimed in the same direction. Yet themost remarkable event which seemed to promise a return to liberal economic principles

was the extraordinary economic recovery of the defeated Germany which, on the

initiative of Ludwig Erhard, 'had explicitly committed herself to what was called a 'social

market economy', and as a result soon outstripped the victorious nations in prosperity.

These events ushered in an unprecedented period of great prosperity which for a time

made it seem probable that an essentially liberal economic régime might again durably

establish itself in western and central Europe. In the intellectual sphere, too, the period

brought renewed efforts to restate and improve the principles of liberal politics. But the

endeavours to prolong the prosperity and to secure full employment by means of the

expansion of money and credit, in the end created a world-wide inflationary development

to which employment so adjusted itself that inflation could not be discontinued without

producing extensive unemployment. Yet a functioning market economy cannot be

maintained under accelerating inflation, if for no other reason than because governments

will soon feel constrained to combat the effects of inflation by the control of prices and

wages. Inflation has always and everywhere led to a directed economy, and it is only too

likely that the commitment to an inflationary policy [131] will mean the destruction of 

the market economy and the transition to a centrally directed totalitarian economic and

political system.

Page 34: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 34/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 34

At present the defenders of the classical liberal position have again shrunk to very small

numbers, chiefly economists. And the name 'liberal' is coming to be used, even in

Europe, as has for some time been true of the USA, as a name for essentially socialist

aspirations, because, in the words of J. A. Schumpeter, 'as a supreme but unintended

compliment, the enemies of the system of private enterprise have thought it wise to

appropriate the label'.

SYSTEMATIC

§7. The liberal conception of freedom

Since only the 'British' or evolutionary type of liberalism has developed a definite

political programme, an attempt at a systematic exposition of the principles of liberalismwill have to concentrate on it, and the views of the 'Continental' or constructivistic type

win be mentioned only occasionally by way of contrast. This fact also demands the

rejection of another distinction frequently drawn on the Continent, but inapplicable to the

British type, that between political and economic liberalism (elaborated especially by the

Italian philosopher, Benedetto Croce, as the distinction between liberalismo and

liberismo). For the British tradition the two are inseparable because the basic principle of 

the limitation of the coercive powers of government to the enforcement of general rules

of just conduct deprives government of the power of directing or controlling the

economic activities of the individuals, while the conferment of such powers gives

government essentially arbitrary and discretionary power which cannot but restrict even

the freedom in the choice of individual aims which all liberals want to secure. Freedom

under the law implies economic freedom, while economic control, as the control of the

means for all purposes, makes a restriction of all freedom possible.

It is in this connection that the apparent agreement of the different kinds of 

liberalism on the demand for freedom of the individual, and the respect for the individual

personality which this implies, conceals an important difference. During the heyday of 

liberalism this concept of freedom had a fairly definite meaning: it meant primarily that

the free person was not subject to arbitrary coercion. But for [132] man living in society

protection against such coercion required a restraint on all men, depriving them of the

Page 35: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 35/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 35

possibility of coercing others. Freedom for all could be achieved only if, in the celebrated

formula of Immanuel Kant, the freedom of each did not extend further than was

compatible with an equal freedom for all others. The liberal conception of freedom was

therefore necessarily one of freedom under a law which limited the freedom of each so as

to secure the same freedom for all. It meant not what was sometimes described as the

'natural freedom' of an isolated individual, but the freedom possible in society and

restricted by such rules as were necessary to protect the freedom of others. Liberalism in

this respect is to be sharply distinguished from anarchism. It recognizes that if all are to

be as free as possible, coercion cannot be entirely eliminated, but only reduced to that

minimum which is necessary to prevent individuals or groups from arbitrarily coercing

others. It was a freedom within a domain circumscribed by known rules which made it

possible for the individual to avoid being coerced so long as he kept within these limits.

This freedom could also be assured only to those capable of obeying the rules

intended to secure it. Only the adult and sane, presumed to be fully responsible for their

actions, were regarded as fully entitled to that freedom, while various degrees of tutelage

were regarded as appropriate in the case of children and persons not in full possession of 

their mental faculties. And by infringement of the rules intended to secure the same

liberty for all, a person might as penalty forfeit that exemption from coercion which those

who obeyed them enjoyed.

This freedom thus conferred on all judged responsible for their actions also held

them responsible for their own fate: while the protection of the law was to assist all in the

pursuit of their aims, government was not supposed to guarantee to the individuals

particular results of their efforts. To enable the individual to use his knowledge and

abilities in the pursuit of his self ‑chosen aims was regarded both as the greatest benefit

government could secure to all, as well as the best way of inducing these individuals to

make the greatest contribution to the welfare of others. To bring forth the best efforts for

which an individual was enabled by his particular circumstances and capabilities, of 

which no authority could know, was thought to be the chief advantage which the freedom

of each would confer on all others. [133]

Page 36: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 36/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 36

The liberal conception of freedom has often been described as a merely negative

conception, and rightly so. Like peace and justice, it refers to the absence of an evil, to a

condition opening opportunities but not assuring particular benefits; though it was

expected to enhance the probability that the means needed for the purposes pursued by

the different individuals would be available. The liberal demand for freedom is thus a

demand for the removal of all manmade obstacles to individual efforts, not a claim that

the community or the state should supply particular goods. It does not preclude such

collective action where it seems necessary, or at least a more effective way for securing

certain services, but regards this as a matter of expediency and as such limited by the

basic principle of equal freedom under the law. The decline of liberal doctrine, beginning

in the 1870s, is closely connected with a re‑interpreta tion of freedom as the command

over, and usually the provision by the state of, the means of achieving a great variety of 

particular ends.

§8. The liberal conception of law

The meaning of the liberal conception of liberty under the law, or of absence of 

arbitrary coercion, turns on the sense which in this context is given to 'law' and 'arbitrary.

It is partly due to differences in the uses of these expressions that within the liberal

tradition there exists a conflict between those for whom, as for John Locke, freedom

could exist only under the law ('for who could be free when every other man's humour

could domineer over Him?') while to many of the Continental liberals and to Jeremy

Bentham, as the latter expressed it, 'every law is an evil for every law is an infraction of 

liberty.'

It is of course true that law can be used to destroy liberty. But not every product

of legislation is a law in the sense in which John Locke or David Hume or Adam Smith

or Immanuel Kant or the later English Whigs regarded law as a safeguard of freedom.

What they had in mind when they spoke of law as the indispensable safeguard of freedom

were only those rules of just conduct which constitute the private and criminal law, but

not every command issued by the legislative authority. To qualify as law, in the sense in

Page 37: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 37/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 37

which it was used in the British liberal tradition to describe the conditions of freedom, the

rules enforced by government had to possess certain attributes which a law like the

English Common Law of necessity possessed, but which the products of legislation need

not [134] possess: they must be general rules of individual conduct, applicable to all alike

in an unknown number of future instances, defining the protected domain of the

individuals, and therefore essentially of the nature of prohibitions rather than of specific

commands. They are therefore also inseparable from the institution of several property. It

was within the limits determined by these rules of just conduct that the individual was

supposed to be free to use his own knowledge and skills in the pursuit of his own

purposes in any manner which seemed appropriate to him.

The coercive powers of government were thus supposed to be limited to the

enforcement of those rules of just conduct. This, except to an extreme wing of the liberal

tradition, did not preclude that government should not render also other services to the

citizens. It meant only that, whatever other services government might be called upon to

provide, it could for such purposes use only the resources placed at its disposal, but could

not coerce the private citizen; or, in other words, the person and the property of the

citizen could not be used by government as a means for the achievement of its particular

purposes. In this sense an act of the duly authorized legislature might be as arbitrary as an

act of an autocrat, indeed any command or prohibition directed to particular persons or

groups, and not following from a rule of universal applicability, would be regarded as

arbitrary. What thus makes an act of coercion arbitrary, in the sense in which the term is

used in the old liberal tradition, is that it serves a particular end of government, is

determined by a specific act of will and not by a universal rule needed for the

maintenance of that selfgenerating overall order of actions, which is served by all the

other enforced rules of just conduct.

§9. Law and the spontaneous order of actions

The importance which liberal theory attached to the rules of just conduct is based

on the insight that they are an essential condition for the maintenance of a

Page 38: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 38/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 38

self ‑generating or spontaneous order of the actions of the different individuals and

groups, each of which pursues his own ends on the basis of his own knowledge. At least

the great founders of liberal theory in the eighteenth century, David Hume and Adam

Smith, did not assume a natural harmony of interests, but rather contended that the

divergent interests of the different individuals could be reconciled by the observance of 

appropriate rules of conduct; or, as their contemporary, Josiah Tucker, expressed it, [135]

that 'the universal mover in human nature, self ‑love, may receive such a direction ... as

to promote the public interest by those efforts it shall make towards pursuing its own'.

Those eighteenth century writers were indeed as much philosophers of law as students of 

the economic order, and their conception of law and their theory of the market

mechanism are closely connected. They understood that only the recognition of certain

principles of law, chiefly the institution of several property and the enforcement of 

contracts, would secure such a mutual adjustment of the plans of action of the separate

individuals that all might have a good chance of carrying out the plans of action which

they had formed. It was, as later economic theory brought out more clearly, this mutual

adjustment of individual plans which enabled people to serve each other while using their

different knowledge and skills in the service of their own ends.

The function of the rules of conduct was thus not to organize the individual efforts

for particular agreed purposes, but to secure an overall order of actions within which each

should be able to benefit as much as possible from the efforts of others in the pursuit of 

his own ends. The rules conducive to the formation of such a spontaneous order were

regarded as the product of long experimentation in the past. And though they were

regarded as capable of improvement, it was thought that such improvement must proceed

slowly and step by step as new experience showed it to be desirable.

Page 39: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 39/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 39

The great advantage of such a self ‑generating order was thought to be, not only

that it left the individuals free to pursue their own purposes, whether these were egotistic

or altruistic. It was also that it made possible the utilization of the widely dispersed

knowledge of particular circumstances of time and place which exists only as the

knowledge of those different individuals, and could in no possible way be possessed by

some single directing authority. It is this utilization of more knowledge of particular facts

than would be possible under any system of central direction of economic activity, that

brings about as large an aggregate product of society as can be brought about by any

known means.

But while leaving the formation of such an order to the spontaneous forces of the

market, operating under the restraint of appropriate rules of law, secures a more

comprehensive order and a more complete adaptation to the particular circumstances, it

also means that the particular contents of this order will not be subject to [136] deliberate

control but are left largely to accident. The framework of rules of law, and all the various

special institutions which serve the formation of the market order can determine only its

general or abstract character, but not its specific effects on particular individuals or

groups. Though its justification consists in it increasing the chances of all, and in making

the position of each in a large measure dependent on his own efforts, it still leaves the

outcome for each individual and group dependent‑also on unforeseen circumstances

which neither they nor anybody else can control. Since Adam Smith the process by which

the shares of the individuals are determined in a market economy has therefore often been

likened to a game in which the results for each depend partly on his skill and effort and

partly on chance. The individuals have reason to agree to play this game because it makes

the pool from which the individual shares are drawn larger than it can be made by any

other method. But at the same time it makes the share of each individual subject to all

kinds of accidents and certainly does not secure that it always corresponds to the

subjective merits or to the esteem by others of the individual efforts.

Page 40: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 40/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 40

Before considering further the problems of the liberal conception of justice which

this raises, it is necessary to consider certain constitutional principles in which the liberal

conception of law came to be embodied.

§10. Natural rights, the separation on powers, and sovereignty

The basic liberal principle of limiting coercion to the enforcement of general rules

of just conduct has rarely been stated in this explicit form, but has usually found

expression in two conceptions characteristic of liberal constitutionalism, that of 

indefeasible or natural rights of the individual (also described as fundamental rights or

rights of man) and that of the separation of powers. As the French Declaration of the

Rights of Man and of the Citizen Of 1789, at the same time the most concise and the

most influential statement of liberal principles, expressed it: 'Any society in which rights

are not securely guaranteed, and the separation of powers is not determined, has no

constitution.'

The idea of specially guaranteeing certain fundamental rights, such as 'liberty,

property, security and resistance to oppression', and, more specifically, such freedoms as

those of opinion, of speech, of assembly, of the press, which make their appearance first

in the [137] course of the American revolution, is, however, only an application of the

general liberal principle to certain rights which were thought to be particularly important

and, being confined to enumerated rights, does not go as far as the general principle. That

they are merely particular applications of the general principle appears from the fact that

none of these basic rights is treated as an absolute right, but that they all extend only so

far as they are not limited by general laws. Yet, since according to the most general

Page 41: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 41/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 41

liberal principle all coercive action of government is to be limited to the enforcement of 

such general rules, all the basic rights listed in any of the catalogues or bills of protected

rights, and many others never embodied in such documents, would be secured by a single

clause stating that general principle. As is true of economic freedom, all the other

freedoms would be secured if the activities of the individuals could not be limited by

specific prohibitions (or the requirement of specific permissions) but only by general

rules equally applicable to all.

The principle of the separation of powers in its original sense also is an

application of the same general principle, but only in so far as in the distinction between

the three powers of legislation, jurisdiction and administration the term 'law' is

understood, as it undoubtedly was by the early propounders of the principle, in the

narrow sense of general rules of just conduct. So long as the legislature could pass only

laws in this narrow sense, the courts could only order (and the executive only apply)

coercion in order to secure obedience to such general rules. This, however, would be true

only in so far as the power of the legislature was confined to laying down such laws in

the strict sense (as in the opinion of John Locke it ought to be), but not if the legislature

could give to the executive any orders it thought fit, and if any action of the executive

authorized in this manner was regarded as legitimate. Where the representative assembly,

called the legislature, has become, as it has in all modern states, the supreme

governmental authority which directs the action of the executive on particular matters,

and the separation of powers merely means that the executive must not do anything not

so authorized, this does not secure that the liberty of the individual is restricted only by

laws in the strict sense in which liberal theory used the term.

Page 42: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 42/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 42

The limitation of the powers of the legislature that was implicit in the original

conception of the separation of powers also implies a [138] rejection of the idea of any

unlimited or sovereign power or at least of any authority of organized power to do what it

likes. The refusal to recognize such a sovereign power, very clear in John Locke and

again and again recurring in later liberal doctrine, is one of the chief points where it

clashes with the now predominant conceptions of legal positivism. It denies the logical

necessity of the derivation of all legitimate power from a single sovereign source, or any

organized 'will', on the ground that such a limitation of all organized power may be

brought about by a general state of opinion which refuses allegiance to any power (or

organized will) which takes action of a kind which this general opinion does not

authorize. It believes that even a force such as general opinion, though not capable of 

formulating specific acts of will, may yet limit the legitimate power of all organs of 

government to actions possessing certain general attributes.

§11. Liberalism and justice

Closely connected with the liberal conception of law is the liberal conception of 

 justice. It is different from that now widely held in two important respects: it is founded

on a belief in the possibility of discovering objective rules of just conduct independent of 

particular interests; and it concerns itself only with the justice of human conduct, or the

rules governing it, and not with the particular results of such conduct on the position of 

the different individuals or groups. Especially in contrast to socialism it may be said that

liberalism is concerned with commutative justice and not with what is called distributive

or now more frequently 'social' justice.

The belief in the existence of rules of just conduct which can be discovered but

not arbitrarily created rests on the fact that the great majority of such rules will at all

times be unquestioningly accepted, and that any doubt about the justice of a particular

Page 43: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 43/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 43

rule must be resolved within the context of this body of generally accepted rules, in such

a manner that the rule to be accepted will be compatible with the rest: that is, it must

serve the formation of the same kind of abstract order of actions which all the other rules

of just conduct serve, and must not conflict with the requirements of any one of these

rules. The test of the justice of any particular rules is thus whether its universal

application is possible because it proves to be consistent with all the other accepted rules.

It is often alleged that this belief of liberalism in a justice independent of 

particular interests depends on a conception of a law of nature [139] that has been

conclusively rejected by modern thought. Yet it can be represented as dependent on a

belief in a law of nature only in a very special sense of this term, a sense in which it is by

no means true that it has been effectively refuted by legal positivism. It is undeniable that

the attacks of legal positivism have done much to discredit this essential part of the

traditional liberal creed. Liberal theory is indeed in conflict with legal positivism with

regard to the latter's assertion that all law is or must be the product of the (essentially

arbitrary) will of a legislator. Yet once the general principle of a self ‑maintaining order

based on several property and the rules of contract is accepted, there will, within the

system of generally accepted rules, be required particular answers to specific questions‑ 

made necessary by the rationale of the whole system and the appropriate answers to such

questions will have to be discovered rather than arbitrarily invented. It is from this fact

that the legitimate conception springs that particular rules rather than others will be

required by 'the nature of the case'.

The ideal of distributive justice has frequently attracted liberal thinkers, and has

become probably one of the main factors which led so many of them from liberalism to

socialism. The reason why it must be rejected by consistent liberals is the double one that

Page 44: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 44/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 44

there exist no recognized or discoverable general principles of distributive justice, and

that, even if such principles could be agreed upon, they could not be put into effect in a

society whose productivity rests on the individuals being free to use their own knowledge

and abilities for their own purposes. The assurance of particular benefits to particular

people as rewards corresponding to their merits or needs, however assessed, requires a

kind of order of society altogether different from that spontaneous order which will form

itself if individuals are restrained only by general rules of just conduct. It requires an

order of the kind (best described as an organization) in which the individuals are made to

serve a common unitary hierarchy of ends, and required to do what is needed in the light

of an authoritative plan of action. While a spontaneous order in this sense does not serve

any single order of needs, but merely provides the best opportunities for the pursuit of a

great variety of individual needs, an organization presupposes that all its members serve

the same system of ends. And the kind of comprehensive single organization of the whole

of society, which would be necessary in order to secure that each gets what some

authority thinks he deserves, must produce [140] a society in which each must also do

what the same authority prescribes.

§12. Liberalism and equality

Liberalism merely demands that so far as the state determines the conditions

under which the individuals act it must do so according to the same formal rules for all. It

is opposed to all legal privilege, to any conferment by government of specific advantages

on some which it does not offer to all. But since, without the power of specific coercion,

government can control only a small part of the conditions which determine the prospects

of the different individuals, and these individuals are necessarily very different, both in

their individual abilities and knowledge as well as in the particular (physical and social)

environment in which they find themselves, equal treatment under the same general laws

must result in very different positions of the different persons; while in order to make the

position or the opportunities of the different persons equal, it would be necessary that

government treat them differently. Liberalism, in other words, merely demands that the

Page 45: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 45/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 45

procedure, or the rules of the game, by which the relative positions of the different

individuals are determined, be just (or at least not unjust), but not that the particular

results of this process for the different individuals be just; because these results, in a

society of free men, will always depend also on the actions of the individuals themselves

and on numerous other circumstances which nobody can in their entirety determine or

foresee.

In the heyday of classical liberalism, this demand was commonly expressed by

the requirement that all careers should be open to talents, or more vaguely and inexactly

as 'equality of opportunity'. But this meant in effect only that those obstacles to the rise to

higher positions should be removed which were the effect of legal discriminations

between persons. It did not mean that thereby the chances of the different individuals

could be made the same. Not only their different individual capacities, but above all the

inevitable differences of their individual environments, and in particular the family in

which they grew up, would still make their prospects very different. For this reason the

idea that has proved so attractive to most liberals, that only an order in which the initial

chances of all individuals are the same at the start, can be regarded as just, is incapable of 

realization in a free society; it would require a deliberate [141] manipulation of the

environment in which all the different individuals worked which would be wholly

irreconcilable with the ideal of a freedom in which the individuals can use their own

knowledge and skill to shape this environment.

But though there are strict limits to the degree of material equality which can be

achieved by liberal methods, the struggle for formal equality, i.e. against all

discrimination based on social origin, nationality, race, creed, sex, etc., remained one of 

the strongest characteristics of the liberal tradition. Though it did not believe that it was

possible to avoid great differences in material positions, it hoped to remove their sting by

a progressive increase of vertical mobility. The chief instrument by which this was to be

secured was the provision (where necessary out of public funds) of a universal system of 

education which would at least place all the young at the foot of the ladder on which they

would then be able to rise in accordance with their abilities. It was thus by the provision

of certain services to those not yet able to provide for themselves that many liberals

Page 46: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 46/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 46

endeavoured at least to reduce the social barriers which tied individuals to the class into

which they were born.

More doubtfully compatible with the liberal conception of equality is another

measure which also gained wide support in liberal circles, namely the use of progressive

taxation as a means to effect a redistribution of income in favour of the poorer classes.

Since no criterion can be found by which such progression can be made to correspond to

a rule which may be said to be the same for all, or which would limit the degree of extra

burden on the more wealthy, it would seem that a generally progressive taxation is in

conflict with the principle of equality before the law and it was in general so regarded by

liberals in the nineteenth century.

§13. Liberalism and democracy

By the insistence on a law which is the same for all, and the con- sequent

opposition to all legal privilege, liberalism came to be closely associated with the

movement for democracy. In the struggle for consti-tutional government in the nineteenth

century, the liberal and the democratic movements indeed were often indistinguishable.

Yet in the course of time the consequence of the fact that the two doctrines were in the

last resort concerned with different issues became more and more apparent. Liberalism is

concerned with the functions of government and particularly with the limitation of all its

powers. [142]

Democracy is concerned with the question of who is to direct government.

Liberalism requires that all power, and therefore also that of the majority, be limited.

Democracy came to regard current majority opinion as the only criterion of the

legitimacy of the powers of government. The difference between the two principles

stands out most clearly if we consider their opposites: with democracy it is authoritarian

government; with liberalism it is totalitarianism. Neither of the two systems necessarily

Page 47: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 47/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 47

excludes the opposite of the other: a democracy may well wield totalitarian powers, and it

is at least conceivable that an authoritarian government might act on liberal principles.

Liberalism is thus incompatible with unlimited democracy, just as it is

incompatible with all other forms of unlimited government. It presupposes the limitation

of the powers even of the representatives of the majority by requiring a commitment to

principles either explicitly laid down in a constitution or accepted by general opinion so

as to effectively confine legislation.

Thus, though the consistent application of liberal principles leads to democracy,

democracy will preserve liberalism only if, and so long as, the majority refrains from

using its powers to confer on its supporters special advantages which cannot be similarly

offered to all citizens. This might be achieved in a representative assembly whose powers

were confined to passing laws in the sense of general rules of just conduct, on which

agreement among a majority is likely to exist. But it is most unlikely in an assembly

which habitually directs the specific measures of government. In such a representative

assembly, which combines true legislative with governmental powers, and which is

therefore in the exercise of the latter not limited by rules that it cannot alter, the majority

is not likely to be based on true agreement on principles, but will probably consist of 

coalitions of various organized interests which will mutually concede to each other

special advantages. Where, as is almost inevitable in a representative body with unlimited

powers, decisions are arrived at by a bartering of special benefits to the different groups,

and where the formation of a majority capable of governing depends on such bartering, it

is indeed almost inconceivable that these powers will be used only in the true general

interests.

Page 48: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 48/57

Page 49: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 49/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 49

The general growth of wealth and the new aspirations whose satisfaction were

made possible by it have since led to an enormous growth of those service activities, and

have made necessary a much more clear‑cut attitude towards them than classical

liberalism ever took. There can be no doubt that there are many such services, known to

the economists as 'public goods', which are highly desirable but cannot be provided by

the market mechanism, because if they arc provided they will benefit everybody and

cannot be confined to those who are willing to pay for them. From the elementary tasks

of the protection against crime or the prevention of the spreading of contagious diseases

and other health services, to the great variety of problems which the large urban

agglomerations [144] raise most acutely, the required services can only be provided if the

means to defray their costs are raised by taxation. This means that, if these services are to

be provided at all, at least their finance, if not necessarily also their operation must be

placed in the hands of agencies which have the power of taxation. This need not mean

that government is given the exclusive right to render these services, and the liberal will

wish that the possibility be left open that when ways of providing such services by

private enterprise are discovered, this can be done. He will also retain the traditional

preference that those services should so far as possible be provided by local rather than

central authorities and be paid for by local taxation, since in this manner at least some

connection between those who benefit and those who pay for a particular service will be

preserved. But beyond this liberalism has developed scarcely any definite principles to

guide policy in this wide field of ever increasing importance.

The failure to apply the general principles of liberalism to the new problems

showed itself in the course of the development of the modern Welfare State. Though it

should have been possible to achieve many of its aims within a liberal framework, this

would have required a slow experimental process; yet the desire to achieve them by the

most immediately effective path led everywhere to the abandonment of liberal principles.

Page 50: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 50/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 50

While it should have been possible, in particular, to provide most of the services of social

insurance by the development of an institution for true competitive insurance, and while

even a minimum income assured to all might have been created within a liberal

framework, the decision to make the whole field of social insurance a government

monopoly, and to turn the whole apparatus erected for that purpose into a great

machinery for the redistribution of incomes, led to a progressive growth of the

government controlled sector of the economy and to a steady dwindling of the part of the

economy in which liberal principles still prevail.

§15. Positive tasks of liberal legislation

Traditional liberal doctrine, however, not only failed to cope adequately with new

problems, but also never developed a sufficiently clear programme for the development

of a legal framework designed to preserve an effective market order. If the free enterprise

system is to work beneficially, it is not sufficient that the laws satisfy the negative criteria

sketched earlier. It is also necessary that their [145] positive content be such as to make

the market mechanism operate satisfactorily. This requires in particular rules which

favour the preservation of competition and restrain, so far as possible, the development of 

monopolistic positions. These problems were somewhat neglected by nineteenth‑century

liberal doctrine and were examined systematically only more recently by some of the

'neoliberal' groups.

It is probable, however, that in the field of enterprise monopoly would never have

become a serious problem if government had not assisted its development by tariffs,

certain features of the law of corporations and of the law of industrial patents. It is an

open question whether, beyond giving the legal framework such a character that it will

favour competition, specific measures to combat monopoly are necessary or desirable. If 

they are, the ancient common law prohibition of conspiracies in restraint of trade might

Page 51: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 51/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 51

have provided a foundation for such a development which, however, remained long

unused. Only comparatively lately, beginning with the Sherman Act of 189o in the USA,

and in Europe mostly only after the Second World War, were attempts made at a

deliberate antitrust and anti‑cartel legislation which, because of the discretionary powers

which they usually conferred on administrative agencies, were not wholly reconcilable

with classical liberal ideals.

The field, however, in which the failure to apply liberal principles led to

developments which increasingly impeded the functioning of the market order, is that of 

the monopoly of organized labour or of the trade unions. Classical liberalism had

supported the demands of the workers for 'freedom of association', and perhaps for this

reason later failed effectively to oppose the development of labour unions into institutions

privileged by law to use coercion in a manner not permitted to anybody else. It is this

position of the labour unions which has made the market mechanism for the

determination of wages largely inoperative, and it is more than doubtful whether a market

economy can be preserved if the competitive determination of prices is not also applied to

wages. The question whether the market order will continue to exist or whether it will be

replaced by a centrally planned economic system may well depend on whether it will

prove possible in some manner to restore a competitive labour market.

The effects of these developments show themselves already in the manner in

which they have influenced government action in the [146] second main field in which it

is generally believed that a functioning market order requires positive government action:

the provision of a stable monetary system. While classical liberalism assumed that the

gold standard provided an automatic mechanism for the regulation of the supply of 

money and credit which would be adequate to secure a functioning market order, the

Page 52: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 52/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 52

historical developments have in fact produced a credit structure which has become to a

high degree dependent on the deliberate regulation by a central authority. This control,

which for some time had been placed in the hands of independent central banks, has in

recent times been in effect transferred to governments, largely because budgetary policy

has been made one of the chief instruments of monetary control. Governments have thus

become responsible for determining one of the essential conditions on which the working

of the market mechanism depends.

In this position governments in all Western countries have been forced, in order to

secure adequate employment at the wages driven up by trade union action, to pursue an

inflationary policy which makes monetary demand rise faster than the supply of goods.

They have been driven by this into an accelerating inflation which in turn they feel bound

to counteract by direct controls of prices that threaten to make the market mechanism

increasingly inoperative. This seems now to become the way in which, as already

indicated in the historical section, the market order which is the foundation of a liberal

system will be progressively destroyed.

§16. Intellectual and material freedom

The political doctrines of liberalism on which this exposition has concentrated

will appear to many who regard themselves as liberals as not the whole or even the most

important part of their creed. As has already been indicated, the term 'liberal' has often,

and particularly in recent times, been used in a sense in which it describes primarily a

general attitude of mind rather than specific views about the proper functions of 

government. It is therefore appropriate in conclusion to return to the relation between

those more general foundations of all liberal thought and the legal and economic

doctrines in order to show that the latter are the necessary result of the consistent

Page 53: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 53/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 53

application of the ideas which led to the demand for intellectual freedom on which all the

different strands of liberalism agree. [147]

The central belief from which all liberal postulates may be said to spring is that

more successful solutions of the problems of society are to be expected if we do not rely

on the application of anyone's given knowledge, but encourage the interpersonal process

of the exchange of opinion from which better knowledge can be expected to emerge. It is

the discussion and mutual criticism of men's different opinions derived from different

experiences which was assumed to facilitate the discovery of truth, or at least the best

approximation to truth which could be achieved. Freedom for individual opinion was

demanded precisely because every individual was regarded as fallible, and the discovery

of the best knowledge was expected only from that continuous testing of all beliefs which

free discussion secured. Or, to put this differently, it was not so much from the power of 

individual reason (which the genuine liberals distrusted), as from the results of the

interpersonal process of discussion and criticism, that a progressive advance towards the

truth was expected. Even the growth of individual reason and knowledge is regarded as

possible only in so ‑far as the individual is part of this process.

That the advance of knowledge, or progress, which intellectual freedom secured,

and the consequent increased power of men to achieve their aims, was eminently

desirable, was one of the unquestioned presuppositions of the liberal creed. It is

sometimes alleged, not quite justly, that its stress was entirely on material progress.

Though it is true that it expected the solution of most problems from the advance of 

scientific and technological knowledge, it combined with this a somewhat uncritical,

though probably empirically justified, belief that freedom would also bring progress in

the moral sphere; it seems at least true that during periods of advancing civilization moral

views often came to be more widely accepted which in earlier periods had been only

imperfectly or partially recognized. (It is perhaps more doubtful whether the rapid

intellectual advance that freedom produced also led to a growth of aesthetic

susceptibilities; but liberal doctrine never claimed any influence in this respect.)

All the arguments in support of intellectual freedom also apply, however, to the

case for the freedom of doing things, or freedom of action. The varied experiences which

Page 54: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 54/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 54

lead to the differences of opinion from which intellectual growth originates are in turn the

result of the different actions taken by different people in different circumstances. As in

the intellectual so in the material sphere, [148] competition is the most effective

discovery procedure which will lead to the finding of better ways for the pursuit of 

human aims. Only when a great many different ways of doing things can be tried will

there exist such a variety of individual experience, knowledge and skills, that a

continuous selection of the most successful will lead to steady improvement. As action is

the main source of the individual knowledge on which the social process of the advance

of knowledge is based, the case for the freedom of action is as strong as the case for

freedom of opinion. And in a modern society based on the division of labour and the

market, most of the new forms of action arise in the economic field.

There is, however, yet another reason why freedom of action, especially in the

economic field that is so often represented as being of minor importance, is in fact as

important as the freedom of the mind. If it is the mind which chooses the ends of human

action, their realization depends on the availability of the required means, and any

economic control which gives power over the means also gives power over the ends.

There can be no freedom of the press if the instruments of printing are under the control

of government, no freedom of assembly if the needed rooms are so controlled, no

freedom of movement if the means of transport are a government monopoly, etc. This is

the reason why governmental direction of all economic activity, often undertaken in the

vain hope of providing more ample means for all purposes, has invariably brought severe

restrictions of the ends which the individuals can pursue. It is probably the most

significant lesson of the political developments of the twentieth century that control of 

the material part of life has given government, in what we have learnt to call totalitarian

systems, far‑reaching powers over the intellectual life. It is the multiplicity of different

and independent agencies prepared to supply the means which enables us to choose the

ends which we will pursue.

Page 55: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 55/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 55

BIBLIOGRAPHY (For “Liberalism”) 

The best accounts of the liberal movement will be found in some of the histories of the

major European countries during the nineteenth century, such as 9. Halévy,  Histoire du

 peuple anglais au XIX siécle, 6 vols, Paris, 1912-32, trans. as History of the

 English People, London, 1926, etc.; and F. Schnabel,  Deutsche Geschichte im

 Neunzehnten Jahrhundert, vol. 11, Freiburg, 1933. The fullest survey of the

development of the ideals of liberalism is [149] G. de. Ruggiero, Storia dos liberalismo

europea, Bari 1925 trans. by R. G. Collingwood as The History of European Liberalism,

Oxford 1927, which contains an extensive bibliography to which reference must be made

for all the works of an earlier date, including the classical works of the founders of 

modern liberalism. The following list gives in chronological order the more importantworks of later date dealing with the history of liberal ideas and movements and the

present state of liberal doctrine.

Martin, B. Kingsley, 1926, French Liberal Thought in the Eighteenth Century, London;

new ed. 1954

Mises, L. von, 1927, Liberalismus, Jena. Croce, B., 1931, Etica e Politica, Bari.

Laski, H., 193 1, The Rise of European Liberalism, London.

Pohlenz, M., 1935, Die griechische Freiheit, Heidelberg; trans. as The Idea of Freedom

in Greek Life and Thought, Dordrecht, 1963

Lippmann, W., 1937,  An Inquiry into the Principles of the Good Society, Boston andLondon.

Sabine, G. H., 1937, A History of Political Theory, New York.

McIlwain, C. H., 1939, Constitutionalism and the Changing World, New York.

Hallowell, J. H., 1943, The Decline of Liberalism as an Ideology, Berkeley, Calif.

Slesser, H., 1943,  A History of the Liberal Party, London. Roepke, W., 1944, Civitas

 Humana, Zurich.

Diez del Corral, L., 1945, El Liberalismo doctrinario, Madrid.

Popper, K. R., 1945, The Open Society and Its Enemies, London.

Rustow, A., 1945, Das Versagen des Wirtschaftsliberalismus als religionssoziologisches

Problem, Zurich.

Page 56: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 56/57

Two Hayek Essays – page 56

Federici, F., 1946, Der deutsche Liberalismus, Zurich

Watkins, F., 1948, The Political Tradition of the West, Cambridge, Mass. Wormuth, F.

D., 1949, The Origin of Modern Constitutionalism, New York. Polanyi, M., 1 95 1, The

 Logic of Liberty, London.

Eucken, W., 1952, Grundsatze der Wirtschaftspolitik, Tubingen.

Robbins, L. C., 1952, The Theory of Economic Policy in English Classical Political

 Economy, London.

Talmon, J. L., 1952, The Origins of Totalitarian Democracy, London. Cranston, M.,1953, Freedom, London.

Lubtow, U. von, 1953,  Blute und Verfall der romischen Freiheit, Berlin. Neill, T. P.,1953, Rise and Decline of Liberalism, Milwaukee, Wis.

Thomas, R. H., 1953,  Liberalism, Nationalism and the German Intellectuals, Chester

Springs, Pa.

Mayer-Maly, T., 1954, 'Rechtsgeschichte der Freiheitsidee in Antike und Mittelalter',

Osterreichische Zeitschrift fur offentliches Recht, N.F.V1.

Hartz, L., 1955, The Liberal Tradition in America, New York.

[150] 

Bullock, A., and Shock, M., 1956, The Liberal Traditionf rom Fox to Keynes, London.

Wirszubski, C., 1956,  Libertas as a Political Ideal at Rome, Cambridge. Feuer, L. S.,

1958, Spinoza and the Rise of Liberalism, Boston.

Grifò G., 1958, 'Su alcuni aspetti della. libertà in Roma',  Archivoi Giuridico 'Filippo

Serafini', 6 serie XXIII.

Grampp, W. D., 1960, The Manchester School of Economics, Stanford, Calif. Hayek, F.A., 1960 The Constitution of Liberty, London and Chicago.

Friedmann, M., 1962, Capitalism and Freedom, Chicago.

Macpherson, C. B., 1962, The Political Theory of Possessive Individualism: Hobbes to

 Locke, Oxford.

Girvetz, H. K., 1963, The Evolution of Liberalism, New York.

Page 57: Hayek Two Essays

7/31/2019 Hayek Two Essays

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/hayek-two-essays 57/57

Schapiro, J. S., 1963, Condorcet and the Rise of Liberalism, New York.

Wheeler, 1963, The Rise and Fall of Liberal Democracy, Santa Barbara, Calif.

Grampp, W. D., 1965, Economic Liberalism, New York.

Bohm, F., 1966, 'Privatrechtsgesellschaft und Marktwirtschaft', in Ordo, XVII.

Lucas, J. R., 1966 Principles of Politics, Oxford.

Vincent, John, 1966, The Formation of the Liberal Party 1857-1868, London. Selinger,

M., 1968, The Liberal Politics of John Locke, London.

Cumming, R. D., 1971,  Human Nature and History, a Study of the Development of 

 Liberal Thought, Chicago.

Douglas, R., 1971, The History of the Liberal Party 1890-1970 London.

Hamer, D. A., 1972, Liberal Politics in the Age of Gladstone and Rosebery, Oxford.

[151]