Happiness in the finite

28
Happiness in the finite * Subrato Banerjee Priyanka Kothari Abstract The idea that 'more is better' has retained its axiomatic stature in economics. Psychologists however, have contested this idea that too many choices translate to greater welfare, by pointing out that the cognitive costs of evaluating available choices against each other often take away from agent-satisfaction. We formalize this idea and apply the same in the context of markets with welfare implications that contradict the idea that competition maximizes surplus. We demonstrate that welfare is maximized with a strictly finite number of firms even when they are heterogeneous, thereby mimicking an monopolistic structure. An immediate implication for regulatory authorities is that maximizing welfare is not the same as maximizing competition. Keywords: welfare, market structure, choice JEL classifications: L11, L13, L15, D43, D91 * This paper has received valuable feedback from Prabal Roy Chowdhury, Arunava Sen, Amit Kumar Goyal, Lionel Page, Dipanwita Sarkar, Jayanta Sarkar, and Uwe Dulleck. New Generation Network Scholar, Queensland University of Technology, Gardens Point Campus, 2 George St, Brisbane City QLD 4000; and Honorary Fellow at the University of Melbourne (Australia India Institute). Email: [email protected] Senior Research Fellow, Indian Statistical Institute, 7 SJS Sansanwal Marg, New Delhi -110016. Email: [email protected] .

Transcript of Happiness in the finite

Page 1: Happiness in the finite

Happiness in the finite*

Subrato Banerjee† Priyanka Kothari‡

Abstract

The idea that 'more is better' has retained its axiomatic stature in economics. Psychologists

however, have contested this idea that too many choices translate to greater welfare, by pointing

out that the cognitive costs of evaluating available choices against each other often take away

from agent-satisfaction. We formalize this idea and apply the same in the context of markets with

welfare implications that contradict the idea that competition maximizes surplus. We

demonstrate that welfare is maximized with a strictly finite number of firms even when they are

heterogeneous, thereby mimicking an monopolistic structure. An immediate implication for

regulatory authorities is that maximizing welfare is not the same as maximizing competition.

Keywords: welfare, market structure, choice

JEL classifications: L11, L13, L15, D43, D91

*This paper has received valuable feedback from Prabal Roy Chowdhury, Arunava Sen, Amit Kumar Goyal, Lionel

Page, Dipanwita Sarkar, Jayanta Sarkar, and Uwe Dulleck. †New Generation Network Scholar, Queensland University of Technology, Gardens Point Campus, 2 George St,

Brisbane City QLD 4000; and Honorary Fellow at the University of Melbourne (Australia India Institute). Email:

[email protected] ‡Senior Research Fellow, Indian Statistical Institute, 7 SJS Sansanwal Marg, New Delhi -110016. Email:

[email protected].

Page 2: Happiness in the finite

1

1. Introduction

We re-examine one of the central and important results of welfare economics, that competition

maximizes welfare. We argue that the validity of this known result implicitly rests on the

assumption that consumers have infinite cognitive capacity. We show that in a real world of

consumers with limited cognition, a welfare-maximizing market has a strictly oligopolistic

structure. In the process, we introduce an elegant new approach to incorporate product-

heterogeneity in an oligopoly, that unifies the known attempts to that end in the industrial

organization literature (Eaton and Lipsey, 1989, Häckner, JET 2000. Tirole, 1988, Tremblay and

Tremblay, 2011).

We model decision-makers' cognitive limitations directly from the biology of the human brain

(Sapolsky, 2017; Eagleman 2015) and study the welfare implications of cognitively limited

agents in markets. This immediately relates to the limited mental bandwidth problem of

Mullainathan and Shafir, 2013. To the best of our knowledge, this is a first attempt at the

endeavor of uncovering the welfare implications of Mullainathan and Shafir's 'science in the

making'.

The idea that the availability of greater choices can only improve welfare, is embedded in

economic theory.1 The empirical truth that the Western world is flooded with choices, is

however, seen as the official dogma of the industrialized world by psychologists (Schwartz,

2004; Iyengar and Lepper, 2000). Specifically, what economists call variety is formally termed

as choice overload by psychologists.

1 The intuition is that any additional item in the choice basket will be consumed only if it enhances utility, otherwise

that additional choice will be redundant. Thus, additional choices can only be welfare improving ... even if the

number of choices is infinite.

Page 3: Happiness in the finite

2

If we accept that utility is derived not only from final consumption but also from the process of

determining what to consume (called respectively as 'outcome satisfaction' and 'process

satisfaction' - see Reutskaja and Hogarth, 2009), then the cognitively-taxing process of

evaluating too many choices against each other may very well take away from satisfaction. On

the aggregate, therefore, welfare will reduce beyond the number of products where the

consumers' love for variety and the crunch/pressure/tax on cognitive capacity balance each other

out. Thus, we show that a finite variety of products, and therefore a finite number of producers,

is consistent with welfare maximization.2 Additionally, firms benefit from reduced competition -

thus, the additions to both consumers' and producers' surplus contribute to welfare maximization.

From economic theory we know that it is sufficient for a consumer to be able to make pair-wise

comparisons in order to arrive at the complete preference ordering between a certain number n of

commodities/bundles. The number of such pair-wise comparisons increases at a much higher rate

than n itself (specifically it is n(n - 1)/2). The cognitive costs of comparison therefore, increase

according to the number of possible comparisons rather than just on the basis of the number of

options. Even binary (n = 2) choices that involve only one (= n(n - 1)/2) possible comparison

(between the two available alternatives) could be mentally taxing in some cases. For example, a

diabetic who decides whether or not to consume the cake in front of him, experiences an internal

conflict. The amygdala (or the 'reptilian brain' governing individual instincts) gives in to the

temptation of immediate (tasty) benefits from consumption, but the pre-fontal cortex (PFC

hereafter, also the most recently evolved part of the brain that is broadly responsible for

reasoning), interferes with this instinct by making the individual aware of the threat of future

health-related costs. This 'tug of war' between the two brains consumes a sufficient amount of

2 The exact finite number will, among other things, depend on the nature and the strength of the cognitive costs of

comparison.

Page 4: Happiness in the finite

3

energy, leaving the agent mentally exhausted at the end of this decision-making process

(Sapolsky, 2017). Even if the amygdala wins, the still-active PFC takes away from the utility

from immediate consumption.

For a sufficiently large number of available choices, Schwartz (2004) provides two (additional)

psychological channels through which, decision-making becomes costly (in utility terms). First,

there is an automatic upward revision of expectations from the very availability of too many

alternatives. More specifically, it is easy to imagine that a better choice was possible whenever

one is made. The psychological comparison (between the choice made and the imagined

alternative) that follows, reduces the utility from the choice made. Second, if a bad choice is

made, then the blame is on the 'world' when the alternatives to choose from are very few (in the

extreme case with n = 1, the decision-maker can reason to himself that he could do nothing about

what was available), but there is an element of self-blame when there are too many alternatives

to choose from. Further, if the consumable in question is durable, then the memory of this self-

blame is triggered (in the hippocampus - the region responsible for memory storage) every time

the good is used, which further reduces utility. Therefore, in addition to the biological cognitive

costs of making a choice between too many alternatives, there are additional psychological costs

that take away from utility.

The comparison of too many alternatives directly translates to the processing of too much

information. The human brain has evolved to avoid the time-costs of too much processing and

focuses on only a subset of information that is deemed most important at any given point of time

(Sapolsky, 2017). This is the reason why one may forget his wallet when in a hurry to make it to

an important meeting. The mind creates a tunnel of focus on the key objective at hand (in this

case, to reach the meeting on time) and all the mental bandwidth is used up to think about

Page 5: Happiness in the finite

4

booking a cab, organizing the meeting briefs, and so on. Therefore, even basic (and often

important) things that remain out of the tunnel (in this case, remembering to carry wallet) are

immediately ignored by the brain — the sense of urgency created in the limited time leads an

agent to subliminally economize on his brain capacity (Mullainathan and Shafir, 2013). Since

cognition is a scarce resource, in order to facilitate quicker decision making when desirable, any

agent's actions are frequently dependent on the information that his senses can immediately

access (Sapolsky, 2017 and Eagleman, 2015). This information frequently translates to focal or

reference points, thereby explaining why the decoy effect works in marketing (Ariely, 2008), or

why economic agents are frequently present-biased (see Camerer, 2003; Bardsley et al 2009;

Frey and Stutzer, 2007), or why they rely on expert opinion (Smith, 2007; Beattie et al, 1994), or

even why they can be nudged to achieve greater levels of welfare (Thaler and Sunstein, 2008)

with an external influence on their choice architecture. In a nutshell, limited cognition against too

many alternatives has well-established empirical consequences, and is therefore worthy of a

theoretical examination from a welfare perspective.

Regulatory authorities frequently try to increase welfare by promoting competition to counter the

market power possessed by monopolies. This gives any consumer, a sense of freedom of choice

accompanied with autonomy, thereby making the experience of shopping in the presence of

variety very pleasant. So long as the individual evaluation of each variety is costless, more

choices can only increase welfare (if not leave the same unaltered). Therefore, any regulation

that promotes variety in choices is expected to be welfare enhancing. We argue that this

traditional view of welfare only holds when consumers have infinite cognitive capacity to arrive

at the best decisions, after meticulously comparing all the available alternatives.

Page 6: Happiness in the finite

5

Section 2 presents our multi-agent model and establishes the presently known welfare results. In

section 3, we incorporate the cognitive costs of decision making in our framework, and establish

new welfare results. In section 4,we demonstrate the robustness of our results with the

introduction of product-heterogeneity, and we conclude with section 5.

2. The model

To begin with, we assume that there are k identical utility-maximizing (and perfectly rational)

consumers, and n identical profit maximizing firms who engage in Cournot competition. Our

choice of Cournot competition is simply based on the flexibility to look at the extreme cases of

monopoly (n = 1) and competitive (n = ∞) scenarios and show the established welfare

implications of each. This also requires us for now, to assume perfect product homogeneity so

that our results are immediately comparable (and consistent) with the known welfare

implications of perfect competition.

2.1. The consumers' problem

We are interested in the market for a given commodity, the quantity (consumed) of which is

represented by x. Each identical consumer must decide how to allocate his/her given income M,

between x units of this commodity and y units of all other goods. The price for the latter is

normalized to unity. We assume that utility U has a quasi-linear specification and is specifically

additive in the functional components of x and y. The representative consumer faces the

following (simple) utility maximization problem:

Page 7: Happiness in the finite

6

with the latter being the budget constraint: px + y = M , where p is the price of the commodity of

interest, and therefore, px is the total expenditure on the commodity. We look at a quadratic

specification in x (with a > 0 and b > 0) particularly for two reasons. First, quadratic expressions

can uniquely approximate any other well behaved utility specification remarkably well.3 Second,

and more importantly, we naturally arrive at a linear demand curve to keep things tractable when

we progressively introduce complications in sections 3 (consumers with limited cognition) and 4

(dropping the assumption of strict product homogeneity).

The solution to (1) involves the substitution of y from the budget constraint into the objective

function and equating the derivative (of U w.r.t. x) to zero.4 This gives us the following

(individual) demand curve for our representative consumer.

Finally, the aggregate market demand for k consumers (X = kx*) is attained from the horizontal

summation of k identical individual demand curves. Thus, the market demand X is given by:

with A = (ak/2b), and B =(k/2b).

We now invert the above and write the inverse demand curve as

3 For example, the function f(x) = ln(ax + b) can be approximated remarkably well by the quadratic expression g(x)

= (-a2/8b

2)x

2 +(3a/4b)x + [ln(2) +ln(b) - (5/8]) in the vicinity of x = b/a. Additionally see Small (2007) and Ball

(2003) for beautiful discussions on quadratic functions and approximations. 4 Note that U = ax - bx

2 + (M - px), after substitution. Maximization is guaranteed from the global concavity of U.

Page 8: Happiness in the finite

7

with α = (A/B), and β = (1/B). This is the demand curve faced by our n identical profit-

maximizing firms. We now turn to the supply-side of our story.

2.2. The producers' problem

Just like X represents the total market demand, we define the total market supply as ,

where qi is the quantity produced and supplied by Firm i (i ϵ {1, ... , n}). Using the fact that

market supply Q will exactly equal market demand X in the equilibrium, so that the market

clearing condition (X = Q) can be incorporated in the inverse demand function (2) as

The profit function of a typical firm i is given by πi = (p - c)qi. Assuming zero costs (c = 0) in

the interest of simplicity, the problem of Firm i is to maximize its own profit shown below.5

This leads us to the first order condition α - βQ - βqi = 0. Finally, we use symmetry (our firms

are identical) and use qi = (Q/n) to get

5 Even with zero costs, we will be dealing with exceedingly complex expressions in Sections 3 and 4. The results

presented here easily extend to general (upward sloping or constant) cost structures.

Page 9: Happiness in the finite

8

Which is the standard n-firm Cournot outcome. We now come to a discussion of total utility

received by k consumers and n firms in the following subsection.

2.3. Welfare implications

Using (5), we can immediately work out individual profits (π* = p

*q

*) and the total producers'

surplus (nπ* = np

*q

*) as follows:

Finally, replacing α and β above by (A/B) and (1/B) respectively, and replacing A and B in turn,

by (ak/2b), and (k/2b) respectively (i.e. working back the transformations introduced in

subsection 2.1.), we re-write the (market and individual) quantities, the price, and the total

producers' surplus above as:

We now use the market clearing condition to replace Q* by X, (so that Q

*/k = X/k), to work out

individual consumption as follows:

To explain this equilibrium with an example, suppose eighty units of output are produced and

traded in a market comprising twenty consumers and five producers so that k = 20 and n = 5,

with X = Q = 80, then, each consumer must consume four units and each producer must produce

Page 10: Happiness in the finite

9

(and sell) sixteen units, so that x* = 4, and q

* = 16. The equilibrium level of utility for each

consumer is given by

Now, we replace

in the above expression to get

Finally, we sum up the individual utilities for k consumers, and add to that, the total profits of the

firms to define the total surplus S(n) = kU* + nπ

* (which is our measure of total welfare) as

follows:

which in turn, can be further simplified (after accounting for the fact that kp*x

* = nπ

*, i.e. what

consumers pay to producers is the latter's earning, and thus gets cancelled out from the last two

terms above) to:

It is immediately clear that welfare increases with more firms, since S(n + 1) - S(n) is always

positive as shown below:

Page 11: Happiness in the finite

10

Thus, it always benefits to accommodate more and more firms, thereby encouraging the

competitive removal of barriers to entry. Welfare in this world, has a maximum possible value of

ka2/4b (with an infinitely large number n of firms), and our model structure is consistent with the

established welfare results. We now introduce cognitive costs in our model while retaining the

current feature of product-homogeneity.

3. Markets with consumers of limited cognition

We now introduce bounds on perfect reasoning (i.e. perfect cognition is not costless) in a

manner, systematically different from those discussed in Spiegler (2011).6 More specifically we

model a (cognitive/biological and psychological) 'cost' of deciding what choice to make, the

basis for which has already been presented in the introductory section.

It may well be argued that if products are indeed homogeneous, then there is no reason for

consumers to 'choose between' what different firms make available in the market. In other words,

the consumers can simply buy the product without incurring any psychological/biological costs

(for example, without having to worry about comparing what they have bought against what they

have not, since the products are homogeneous). Therefore, with homogeneous products, the need

for comparison may not arise (thereby associating welfare maximization with the perfectly

competitive result as in the previous section). It is here, however, where we stress on a realism

that we intend to capture in our model. In the real world, consumers learn about the homogeneity

between two or more brands (even if there is any) only after they have already incurred the

cognitive cost of comparison. In other words, people need to first compare two things even to

6 More specifically, we distinguish Spiegler's (2011) bounded rational agents from our agents of limited cognition. It

is the former that implies the latter, and the latter does not systematically rule out rationality.

Page 12: Happiness in the finite

11

realise that they are indeed identical. Therefore, the cognitive costs of comparison (and therefore

deciding what to buy) are not necessarily lost even when agents deal with (comparing two or

more) homogeneous products. If anything, it is much easier to rank two items when one is

distinctly (and significantly) better than the other. Things become difficult (i.e. more cognitive

resources are required) when one has to choose between two very similar items (e.g. choosing

between two very similar jobs). The second reason why we want to incorporate cognitive costs

here is that we want our welfare results to be directly comparable with those in the previous

section (with homogeneous products). In any case, we will drop the assumption of product

homogeneity in the next section. The last reason why we incorporate cognitive costs here is

because we will use some of the results established here in the key derivations of the next

section.

To model the cost M(n) of comparing n brands, we propose an idea that is roughly similar to the

notion of polynomial time-complexity in the field of computer science. Since the consumer has a

task of (pair-wise) comparing n 'brands' (to completely specify the ordering required by

economic theory), the information size (in the computing nomenclature) is n. Since the task of

pair-wise comparison involves 'choice within choices' (i.e. a choice between any two items

within/out of n available choices), the complexity of M must necessarily rule out an involution

(i.e. M(M(n)) = M○M(n) must have a strictly greater complexity than M(n) itself). Finally, we

recognize that a naturally minimum degree of polynomial that must necessarily rule out an

involution, is two (see Small, 2007).7 Since, the combinatorial number C(n, 2) = n(n - 1)/2 is

naturally a degree-two polynomial in n, we choose M(n) = µC(n, 2) as the simplest specification

that captures the cognitive (Mullainathan and Shafir, 2013), biological (Sapolsky, 2017; and

7 Simply put, the degree-n polynomial P(x) =

, can only be an involution if n = 1 (for example, P(x) = a -

x). For n > 1, P(P(x)) will necessarily be of a higher degree/complexity.

Page 13: Happiness in the finite

12

Eagleman, 2015) and psychological (Schwartz, 2004) costs of evaluating and comparing n

objects (with µ > 0, which can be thought of as the degree or measure of cognitive paralysis of

an agent). This composite cost of processing n 'information items' is also sufficiently in line with

economic theory that in general requires costs to be increasing and convex. We now look at the

modified consumers' and producers' problems in the subsection that follows.

3.1. Agent behaviour in the market

We borrow from psychology that the cognitive costs involving too many choices, take away

from the utility from consumption in the following modified specification of the representative

consumer's problem.8

The solution to the above problem gives us the exact demand structure and market outcomes of

the previous section specified from equations (2) to (7). With this additional negative utility

component though, the welfare conditions change. We turn to this now.

3.2. Analysis of welfare

The equilibrium utility level for our representative consumer is now given as follows

8 Minssky (1986) gives compelling argument that support the structure of the cognitive cost that we propose.

Page 14: Happiness in the finite

13

Just as in the previous section, the total utility of k consumers and the total producers' surplus

amounts to S(n) = kU* + nπ

*, and results in the following specification (after some steps).

The steps to arrive at the above expression are deferred to the Appendix. It is clear that

It is therefore, easily seen that the combined costs of cognition for k consumers must eventually

outweigh the welfare benefits of competition. We conclude that social welfare must necessarily

be at a positive maximum at a finite value of n, which in turn, will depend on the value of µ. We

now progressively examine the restrictions on µ for a given number of firms n, such that the

entry of the next firm (i.e. the (n + 1)th

firm) is necessarily welfare improving. More specifically,

we see (after a few complex algebraic steps deferred to the Appendix) that

Thus, S(n + 1) - S(n) > 0 means that the cognitive costs should be lower than a critical value.

More precisely, µ should not exceed a2(2n + 3)/4bn(n + 1)

2(n + 2)

2. This means that the latter

should be a strict lower bound for µ for maximum welfare to be attained with exactly n firms.

Thus, we have the following result.

Proposition 1: If exactly n firms maximize social welfare, then it must be the case that µ is at

least a2(2n + 3)/4bn(n + 1)

2(n + 2)

2.

Proof: Trivial. It follows directly from (13).

Page 15: Happiness in the finite

14

In Figure 1, we plot the socially most desirable number of firms against these lower bounds on µ

after normalizing a2/b = 100 and fixing k = M = 10.

0

1

2

3

4

5

6

7

8

9

0 0.2 0.4 0.6 0.8 1

Wel

fare

max

imiz

ing n

Lower bound on µ

Figure 1: Socially desirable number of firms against

the measure of cognitive paralysis µ

Figure 1 shows that as µ increases beyond each given critical bound, the number of firms that

maximize welfare progressively diminishes. Indeed, in Figure 2, we see that welfare is

maximized for a strictly finite value of n, for carefully chosen values of µ between the critical

bounds. The panels (a), (b), (c) and (d) show how S(n) is maximized at n = 3, 4, 5 and 6

respectively for different values of µ (0.20, 0.10, 0.05 and 0.02 in that order).

We now come to the final result of this section.

Proposition 2: If consumers have infinite cognitive capacity (µ = 0), then welfare is the

maximum with an infinite number of firms.

Proof: Trivial. It follows directly from the previous section where µ is indeed zero.

Page 16: Happiness in the finite

15

The importance of the above proposition becomes clear here where we have discussed cognitive

costs of comparison. Since there is no variety (i.e. all the products in this market are homogenous

- an assumption that we will relax in the next section), the fact that utility is strictly increasing in

n, gives an insight into the consumers' implicit love for the flexibility to choose his optimal

consumption amount from any of the n available firms. This is because U is strictly dependent on

the amount (x) of consumption of the commodity in question, and there is no a priori reason for

U to be strictly increasing in n as well. The latter just happens to be a consequence of

equilibrium. We bring in variety in the section that follows.

280

290

300

310

320

330

340

0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9

Wel

fare

= S

(n)

Number of firms = n

2(a): Maximum welfare at S(3)

when µ = 0.20

280

290

300

310

320

330

340

0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9

Wel

fare

= S

(n)

Number of firms = n

2(b): Maximum welfare at S(4)

when µ = 0.10

280

290

300

310

320

330

340

350

0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9

Wel

fare

= S

(n)

Number of firms = n

2(c): Maximum welfare at S(5) when

µ = 0.05

280

290

300

310

320

330

340

350

0 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9

Wel

fare

= S

(n)

Number of firms = n

2(d): Maximum welfare at S(6)

when µ = 0.02

Figure 2: Finite number of firms maximize welfare

Finally, before concluding this section we present one final result that we intend to use in the

section that immediately follows.

Theorem 1: The consumption component of utility is strictly positive in equilibrium. It is also

strictly increasing in consumption x.

Page 17: Happiness in the finite

16

Proof: We use the above equilibrium condition above and observe that

which gives us bx* < a, or a - bx

* > 0, which on multiplying by x

*, further gives us ax

* - b(x

*)2 >

0, thereby completing the proof. The latter part of the theorem follows directly from recognizing

that x* < a/2b.

4. Markets with finitely cognitive consumers who value variety

It may be argued that cognitive costs of undertaking a consumption decision only make sense

when there is variety in choice. To the extent that consumers actually love variety (i.e. they get a

positive utility just from the fact that there is variety), the welfare results established in the

previous section are expected to weaken. In this section we examine to what extent consumers

invite more and more variety, before eventually succumbing to the cognitive costs of evaluating

them to make their consumption decisions. Since such consumers must necessarily undertake

buying in a heterogeneous-product market, we model the latter first to then back out a utility

specification that is consistent with the established demand structure. It is clear that a demand

curve that captures a love for variety must necessarily come from a utility specification that

incorporates the same. We now come to the formulation of our heterogeneous-product market.

4.1. The heterogeneous-product market

Page 18: Happiness in the finite

17

Our model of the 'market with variety' unifies many key features that are well-established in

various known models of industrial organization theory (for a detailed discussion on each of the

following features, see the models covered in Tirole, 1988; Carlton and Perloff, 2000; and

Spiegler, 2011).

(a) Demand is relatively inelastic with product differentiation.

(b) Product-differentiation leads to market-power.

(c) Market-power dilutes with greater competition and more product homogeneity.

(d) Superior quality products are priced higher.

The final point brings about a realism that we want to capture. In keeping with a market with a

unique price, we capture this fundamental empirical reality in an indirect way by recognizing

that any given quantity of a higher brand is worth a greater quantity of a lesser brand. In other

words, a given amount of money either buys more of an inferior quality or less of a superior

quality.

A key feature of Cournot competition, is a unique price for all the players. We retain this feature

of a unique equilibrium price p but replace the quantity variable q (of the previous sections) by q'

= γq, for some quality parameter γ (≥ 1), so that for any two firms, i and j, with exogenous

quality parameters γi and γj, the equilibrium price p of γiqi will be the same as that of γjqj. Now,

since γiqi and γjqj have the same value and are therefore worth the same price, γi > γj implies that,

qj < qi. For example, if one can buy two shirts of 'brand j' (qj = 2) for the amount (p) that it takes

to buy just one shirt of 'brand i' (qi = 1), then it must be the case that the latter brand is of a

superior quality since clearly γi = 2γj > γj (which follows from γiqi = γjqj and qj = 2qi > qi). We

Page 19: Happiness in the finite

18

have shown that, for any given price, one can only afford a lesser quantity of a greater quality (or

'brand'). Thus, the parameter γ for each firm can be thought of the 'rate at which a given quantity

q, of a product has been embellished to charge a higher price'. We therefore call the quality

parameter 'γ' as the rate of product-embellishment. We use the following reduced-form demand

specification that captures this heterogeneity of brands.

The above demand specification, apart from immediately satisfying feature (a), also implicitly

makes a simplifying assumption that each firm produces and sells a unique brand. We will later

show that features (b), (c), and (d), will be a consequence of the market equilibrium. We now

turn to the producers' problem.

4.2. The heterogeneous producers' problem

We retain the 'zero production-costs' assumption, so that Firm i solves the following problem:

We define for simplicity, , so that

, and the profit function can be written

below as follows:

Page 20: Happiness in the finite

19

It is clear that since for each firm i, γi is a strictly exogenous quality parameter, and is

strictly linear in , maximising with respect to in (15) is the same as maximising with

respect to in (16). The latter in turn is the same as maximizing with respect to

. Thus,

the problem reduces to

Thus, each firm must choose as a best response to other firms' augmented q'. This problem is

in fact, identical to the producers' problem discussed in Section 2 with the only difference being

that has been replaced by . Finally, since this problem is symmetric in

, we can simply

borrow the equilibrium results of Section 2 after suitably replacing by . The market

equilibrium is described as under:

Clearly, the greater the , the lesser will be the for the given equilibrium price. We now use

these above equilibrium results to back out the representative consumer's utility specification.

4.3. The variety-loving consumers' problem

We are in the process of constructing an equilibrium where market demand X = kx* and market

supply

balance each other out in the equilibrium. We use this

market clearing condition to back out the optimal x*.

Page 21: Happiness in the finite

20

Now from equation (17), we know that in equilibrium,

, we get

where, is the average rate of product embellishment. In particular, is the harmonic average

defined as under.

It is clear that in our framework, the higher this average quality, the higher will be the price, and

therefore the equilibrium consumption will be lower. In order to work out the exact utility

specification that is compatible with the demand function that yields the above equilibrium

conditions, let us consider the following utility maximization problem for our typical consumer:

Note that the above problem is identical to the original problem (1), only with the exception that

x in the original problem (1) is replaced by here. If the consumer values quality, he must pay

for the same (as shown in the budget constraint). Now, just like in the previous problem (more

specifically Theorem 1), so long as < a/2b, (the consumption component of) utility is strictly

concave and strictly increasing in both x and . Further, if we explicitly replace by

, then

Page 22: Happiness in the finite

21

it is clear that (the consumption component of) utility remains strictly increasing in n, thereby

implicitly capturing the love for variety.

The solution to problem (19) gives us the following market demand function:

where, A = ak/2b , and B = k/2b . Thus, the inverse demand function is

Finally, in order to work out the 'correct' values of α and β, we just equate the optimal

equilibrium demand and supply values of x* to each other.

Finally, recognizing that, p* = α/(n + 1), and suitably comparing coefficients, we get α = a and β

= 2b/k. This can be readily verified from the following (which is arrived at, by multiplying both

sides of the above equation by ).

Thus, the consumers' optimal choice of quantity is given by:

Interestingly, it can also be shown that at this optimal quantity, each consumer also chooses

optimal . The proof for this is deferred to the Appendix. Thus, in this section, we show through

Page 23: Happiness in the finite

22

the consumer's problem that our demand function must necessarily stem/originate from and be

implicit in a utility function that captures a love for variety. Indeed large variety is captured by

large n. We finally come to the implications on welfare.

4.4. A discussion on welfare

Before we begin, we re-write (17) after replacing α by a, and β by 2b/k as below.

In order to work out welfare in the heterogeneous market SH(n), we first evaluate the producers’

surplus as follows:

We now work out U* below

We multiply the above by k to obtain kU* and add the same to the expression for total producers’

surplus in (22) to get the total surplus SH(n) as below

Which, on further simplification gives us

Page 24: Happiness in the finite

23

Now, on comparing the above with the expression for S(n) in (12), we immediately see that

This can be interpreted as the ‘deadweight loss’ from the introduction of product-heterogeneity.

Firms get a certain degree of market power due to product differentiation and as a result charge

higher prices for lower quantities because they know that consumers value quality and are

willing to pay for it. On the whole, therefore, there is a welfare loss form this imperfection.

Clearly, this deadweight loss vanishes if each firm has γi = 1 (in which case, there is no

heterogeneity), or when the number of firms is infinitely large.

It is clear that since our representative consumer of this section values variety, the critical values

that the costs of cognition must exceed (for a finite socially optimal n) should be higher in

comparison to the previous section. We formally state this in the following theorem.

Theorem 2: The costs of cognition must be higher for the variety loving consumer for any given

welfare maximizing (finite) number of firms.

Proof: Trivial. On comparing the values of SH(n + 1) and SH(n)¸it is clear that welfare is

maximized at exactly n firms (i.e. the (n + 1)th firm can only reduce welfare) when

Which strictly exceeds the critical value for the consumer who does not necessarily value variety.

Page 25: Happiness in the finite

24

We show these corresponding lower bounds on µ against the welfare maximizing n, in Figure 3

(analogous to Figure 1 of the previous section) below.

The above figure assumes the previously used values of a2/b = 100 and k = M = 10, in addition

to our choice of = 10. We immediately see that this curve is only marginally to the left of that

in Figure 1, implying higher costs of cognition for a given value of welfare maximizing n. In

Figure 4 (analogous to Figure 2), we choose values of µ equal to 0.50, 0.20, 0.07, and 0.02 in

panels (a), (b), (c), and (d) respectively, where welfare is maximized (again respectively) at n =

3, 4, 5 and 6.

We immediately see that the shape and structure of S(n) against n is remarkably the same as it is

in the case of the previous section. Each curve however, sits on a strictly lower value in

comparison to Figure 2 because of the associated deadweight loss, the magnitude of which

increases with n in each case.

Page 26: Happiness in the finite

25

5. Conclusion

In this paper we have suggested a general theoretical approach to incorporate the cognitive cost

faced by consumers (as they have limited cognitive ability) in market structure. We consider

both heterogeneous and homogeneous products. We show that in presence of cognitive cost and

love for variety welfare is maximised with finite number of firms. This also suggests that policy

makers should think of both the aspects, as increasing competition need not be the best way to

increase welfare, especially if consumers find variety as choice overload.

Page 27: Happiness in the finite

26

References

Ariely D. 2008. Predictably irrational: The hidden forces that shape our decisions. Harper Collins

Publisher: New York.

Ball KM. 2003. Strange curves, counting rabbits, and other mathematical explorations. Princeton

University Press: NJ

Beattie J, Baron J, Hershey J C, Spranca M (1994). Determinants of decision attitude. Journal of

Behavioral Decision Making 7:129-44

Camerer CF. 2003. Behavioral game theory: Experiments in strategic interaction. Princeton

University Press: NJ

Carlton DW, Perloff JM. 2000. Modern industrial organization, (Third ed). Addison-Wesley:

Reading, MA.

Eaton BC, Lipsey RG. 1989. Product differentiation. In Handbook of Industrial Organization Vol

1, ed. Richard Schmalensee and Robert Willig. North-Holland, ch 12: 723- 70.

Eagleman D. 2015. The brain: The story of you (A companion to the PBS series). Penguin

Random House: New York, NY.

Häckner J. 2000. A note on price and quantity competition in differentiated oligopolies. Journal

of Economic Theory, 93(2): 233-239.

Iyengar SS, Lepper MR. 2000. When choice is demotivating: Can one desire too much of a good

thing? Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 79: 995–1006.

Minsky M. 1986. The society of mind. Simon and Schuster, New York.

Mullainathan S, Shafir E. 2013. Scarcity: Why having too little means so much. Henry-Holt:

New York, NY.

Reutskaja E, Hogarth R M. (2009). Satisfaction in choice as a function of the number of

alternatives: When “goods satiate”. Psychology and Marketing, 26(3): 197-203.

Sapolsky RM. 2017. Behave: The biology of humans at our best and worst. Penguin: New York.

Schwartz B. 2004. The paradox of choice - Why more is less. Harper Collins: New York.

Page 28: Happiness in the finite

27

Scitovsky T. 1976. The joyless economy. Oxford University Press: New York.

Shapiro C. 1989. Theories of oligopoly behavior. In Handbook of Industrial Organization Vol 1,

ed. Richard Schmalensee and Robert Willig. North-Holland, ch 6: 330-414.

Small CG. 2007. Functional equations and how to solve them. Springer: New York, NY.

Spiegler R. 2011. Bounded rationality and industrial organization. Oxford University Press:

Madison Av, NY.

Timmermans D. 1993. The impact of task complexity on information use in multi-attribute

decision making. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making 6(2):95-111.

Tirole J. 1988. The Theory of industrial organization. M.I.T. Press: Cambridge, MA.

Tremblay CH, Tremblay VJ. 2011. The Cournot-Bertrand model and the degree of product

differentiation. Economics Letters, 111: 233-235.

Why too many choice is stressing us out. The Guardian. October 21, 2015.