Effective Quantum Time Travel

download Effective Quantum Time Travel

of 8

Transcript of Effective Quantum Time Travel

  • 8/12/2019 Effective Quantum Time Travel

    1/8

    a r X i v : 0 9 0 2 . 4 8 9 8 v 1 [ q u a n t - p h ] 2 7 F e b 2 0 0 9

    Effective Quantum Time Travel

    George Svetlichny

    February 27, 2009

    Abstract

    The quantum teleportation protocol can be used to probabilisticallysimulate a quantum circuit with backward-in-time connections. This al-lows us to analyze some conceptual problems of time travel in the contextof physically realizable situations, to realize encrypted measurements of future states for which the decryption key becomes available only afterthe state is created, and to probabilistically realize a multistage quantumstate processing within the time needed to complete only one stage. Theprobabilistic nature of the process resolves any paradox.

    Consider that part of the teleportation protocol for qubits which makes nouse of classical communication, as shown in Fig. 1.

    M

    00

    AB

    Figure 1:

    Here 00 = 1 2 (| 0 | 0 + | 1 | 1 ) is the totally entangled 2-qubit state, part of the Bell basis xy = 1

    2(| x | y + ( 1)y | x + 1 | y + 1 ) where x, y are qubit

    indices, that is 0 or 1, and all sums are modulo 2. M is a measurement in abasis containing 00 , such as the Bell basis itself. The dotted lines representtwo classical bit of information which well ignore for the time being. There is a

    Departamento de Matem atica, Pontifcia Universidade Cat olica, Rio de Janeiro, [email protected] http://www.mat.puc-rio.br/ svetlich

    1

    http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1http://www.mat.puc-rio.br/~svetlichhttp://www.mat.puc-rio.br/~svetlichhttp://www.mat.puc-rio.br/~svetlichhttp://www.mat.puc-rio.br/~svetlichhttp://arxiv.org/abs/0902.4898v1
  • 8/12/2019 Effective Quantum Time Travel

    2/8

    fundamental identity in Hilbert space theory (I consider only nite dimensions):L(H 1 H 2 , H 3) L (H 1 , H 3 H 2 ) where by L(H , K) I denote the space of linearmaps from H to K and by H I denote the dual space to H , the space of bras.I identify H with H itself. Thus we can identify any entangled state =

    ci | i | i H K with a map F : H K by | ci | i | i ,a fact behind the many equivalences between states and channels mentionedin the literature. Likewise any bra of an entangled state = di i | i | (H K ) H K can be identied with a map G : H K

    by | di i | i | . Consider now those measurement incidents of M in which the state is projected onto the 00 subspace. This projector is| 00 00 | so the action of the bra of this projector can be considered as amap from H to H (the qubit Hilbert space) which is then transformed bythe ket 00 in the lower box again to an element of H. A simple calculationshows F 00 G 00 =

    12 I , so aside from an overall scalar the qubit at point B of

    the diagram is the same as at point A. When the measurement projects ontoanother Bell state, the qubit at point B is a unitary transform of the one atpoint A, and this fact makes deterministic teleportation work as then after the result of the measurement is known one can transform the qubit issuing from Bto be identical to the one entering A 1. What we have in the case of projectiononto 00 is effective time travel. After the fact of the measurement M takenplace there is no empirical way to falsify the statement that the qubit at A didtravel back in time to B, but this is not true time travel. By true time travel Imean one whose denial can be falsied by empirical evidence. One can howeverask if any of the supposed effects and benets of supposed true time travel dosomehow exist in this case. The surprising answer is yes, but obviously thosethat cannot lead to time travel paradoxes. In these cases, time travel is a reading of the situation which can otherwise be analyzed in usual quantum mechanical

    terms, but this reading makes these process conceptually easier to follow and soIll use this metaphor. Thus I will use expressions such as send back in timewithout the quotes, knowing I am dealing in the restricted context of this paper.I consider only multipartite qubit systems as extensions to higher dimensionswould be straightforward.

    When the measurement result of M is not projection onto 00 but ontoanother stated then the qubit at B is the F G 00 transform of the one atA. One can still describe this with a time travel metaphor in which time travelitself changes the input state to another one in a linear way. One then comesout in the past transformed from what one was upon entering the time machine.

    Consider now a qubit quantum circuit with one backward-in-time connectionas in Fig 2, which may be considered as part of a larger circuit with no otherbackward-in-time connections. If instead of making the connection we kept the

    output and input as such, we would have a multipartite unitary map. Whatthe circuit with the connection represents is then a partial trace of this mappreceded or followed (in this case) by a swap map (which is unitary) of the two

    1 I learned of this view of teleportation at the 2004 meeting of the International QuantumStructures Association in Denver during a talk by Bob Coecke. See arXiv:quant-ph/0402014.

    2

  • 8/12/2019 Effective Quantum Time Travel

    3/8

    V

    W

    Figure 2:

    Hilbert spaces involved. We are thus led to consider the situation represented

    by Fig. 3 with U unitary and where the loop is a qubit Hilbert space, and

    U

    Figure 3:

    the other lines represent the tensor product of all the other qubit spaces in thecircuit. The loop is a quantum mechanical analog of a closed time-like curve(CTC). We now modify this gure by the scheme of Fig. 1 as displayed in Fig.4. Each time the measurement projects onto 00 , the arrangement in Fig. 4acts, up to an overall scalar multiple, exactly as Fig. 3. For the sake of greaterclarity I present an algebraic proof of this fact. Let U bqap be the matrix of U where input indices are lower and output upper. Indices p and q refer to thequbit Hilbert space in the computation basis. The partial trace is U bpap usingthe summation convention that repeated indices are summed over. For Fig. 4the Bell state 00 corresponds to a matrix rs and a projection on this stateto a matrix ij rs . So Fig. 4 is U biap ij rs jq . Now in the computationbasis, rs = 1 2

    rs and ij = 1 2 ij so Fig. 4 is precisely 12 U

    bpap rs and so

    aside from the factor 1 / 2 and the disjoint state rs

    one has precisely the partialtrace. We are still not making use of the classical information obtained by themeasurement. The usual teleportation scheme is a particular case of this whereU is the swap map. The partial trace of the swap map is I and one can use theclassical information to achieve an identity transform, up to a factor of 12 , foreach of the possible measurement outcomes.

    3

  • 8/12/2019 Effective Quantum Time Travel

    4/8

    U

    M

    (00)

    Figure 4:

    An instructive example of the above construct is when U is the CNOT gate,whose action is | x | y | x | x + y . The modied partial trace of this is givenby Fig. 5.

    M

    00

    Figure 5:

    The partial trace of the CNOT gate is twice the orthogonal projection onto| 0 . The modied partial trace with M a Bell basis measurement is actuallya projective measurement in the computation basis. Assume the state on thecontrol line is = | 0 + | 1 , then after the creation of 00 and before the gateacts, the state is 00 . After the gate acts the state is | 0 00 + | 1 10 .

    So in the subsequent measurement projections onto the Bell states 01 and11 never occur and the two that do occur correspond to projecting onto| 0 or | 1 respectively with probabilities according to projective measurementin the computation basis. The partial trace of CNOT has been consideredan analog of a paradoxal time-travel situation [1] where an object goes backin time and changes its state in a contradictory way. Thus in the case the

    4

  • 8/12/2019 Effective Quantum Time Travel

    5/8

    control qubit is | 1 , if the state | 1 leaves the gate on the right and loops backin time, then upon arriving at the gate it must change and leave as | 0 , acontradiction. This contradiction manifests itself formally by the fact that thepartial trace, being twice the orthogonal projection onto | 0 , annihilates | 1 . Of course one cannot physically annihilate a state, an operator annihilating a stateis physically realized only in the company of others, such as in a POVM, wherethe transformed state is given by another operator acting on the original. Thisis what happens in the modied partial trace. If we dramatically call | 1 aliveand | 0 dead, then with | 1 at the control, the gate kills but also resurrects.The only state that can loop around consistently is the Schr odinger cat state| 1 + | 0 2 . This is similar to xed-point versions of consistent time travel [2]. Of course in a partial trace, its not a particular state that loops around, but a whole(no matter which) orthonormal basis; this is what computing a trace means.Nevertheless, such traces do constitute metaphors for CTCs and analyzing themas such provides a few insights into what time means in quantum situations.Consider a hapless physicist who has to traverse the loop of the partial traceof CNOT. Leaving the gate alive he has to, logically, be leaving it dead andvice versa. How does Fig. 5 resolve the paradox? Assume the control state is = | 0 + | 1 as above. If the exit state on the control line is | 0 , this can beconstrued that the gate operated with | 0 on the control and also that time travelsucceeded as the measurement projects onto 00 . The gate mercifully does notkill the traveler. If the exit state on the control line is | 1 this can be construedthat the gate operated with | 1 at the control. The measurement projectedonto the 10 Bell state. The composition F 00 G10 acts by | x 12 | x + 1so time travel itself kills our physicist but the gate mercifully resurrects him.No paradox here and there couldnt be one as Fig. 5 is a physically realizableconstruct. Deutch in Ref. [ 1] had to appeal to density matrices to resolve time

    travel paradoxes as contradictions remained with individual states. This doesnot happen in our case.Of course the above is a narrative and should not be simply accepted as a

    description of a physical process. All philosophically or scientically motivateddiscussions of time travel have been likewise narratives as the time travel process,or time machine, is necessarily merely hypothesized to have certain propertiesnot being able to refer to physically realizable situations. This type of narrativeis at best a meta-theoretic discussion, for instance exploring the question as towhether the existence of supposed true time travel is consistent with presentphysical laws or do these need to be modied to admit it. In our narrativesneither the claim nor the denial of time travel can be empirically falsied. Thisnon-falsiability makes both the claim and the denial non-scientic assertions.On the other hand our narrative takes place in the context of a physically

    realizable process and so cannot lead to any contradiction. We thus have asource of time travel narratives in which all paradoxes are resolved and this hasinteresting philosophical and scientic implications.

    2 One may also want to admit | 1 | 0 since going around the loop it changes only byphase, but this is inconsistent with the action of the gate as a vector transformer and not aray transformer.

    5

  • 8/12/2019 Effective Quantum Time Travel

    6/8

  • 8/12/2019 Effective Quantum Time Travel

    7/8

    locations the result of measurement M 0 today can be considered a legitimatemeasurement of tomorrows state AB . Of course this is a probabilistic situation;if we perform a large run of say N measurements today with the correspondingrun of pairs of measurements tomorrow, only a fraction of the measurementstoday can be considered legitimate measurements of tomorrows state, thosethat result tomorrow in projection onto 00 in both measurements. We havetoday thus probabilistic information about tomorrow. This in itself is not atall unusual. I could write down today all the possible outcomes of tomorrowslottery drawing, one of these is correct with known probability, and I will onlyknow tomorrow which one this is when the lottery is drawn. Todays informationis useless. The quantum mechanical situation goes beyond this. This is mostreadily seen when all three measurements in Fig. 6 are measurements in theBell basis. One has for any Bell state xy that, up to an overall phase, G xy =G 00 xy where the xy are appropriately labeled unitary (and hermitian)

    sigma matrices with 00 the identity 3

    . Thus whenever a measurement tomorrowprojects onto xy , the qubit arriving today is transformed by xy . Thus in allcases the state measured today is xy uv AB . The probability of projectingthis state onto a Bell state wz is the same as projecting AB onto xy uv wz which is another Bell state w z . Thus reassigning todays outcomeof projection onto wz to a projection onto w z , which we can do tomorrow,we once again have a legitimate measurement of AB . The N measurementsof todays run is thus a ciphertext of a run of measurements of tomorrowsstate. The N pairs of tomorrows measurements is the key necessary to deciphertodays results. This is different from the lottery case. Todays measurement areuseless by themselves (just as in the lottery case) since they are encrypted, buttomorrows measurements are also useless by themselves since they are localmeasurements from which one cannot deduce the run of joint measurements.

    This splitting of information between today and tomorrow is made possible byquantum entanglement and does not seem to have a classical counterpart.One may feel there is a paradox here as one could between today and to-

    morrow, after all the N measurements today are performed, change ones mindabout what state to create tomorrow. How is it that todays measurementsstill form a legitimate run of measurements of tomorrows state? What changesis the key needed to decipher. This is similar to the situation of receiving atext consisting of a random sequence of letters and punctuation marks, like onethat can be created by a one-time pad. For such a ciphertext, any text of thesame length could be the plaintext. Receiving different keys, one reads differentplaintexts. For this to work classically, the sender of the key needs to know theciphertext, in the quantum case, the key is generated without such knowledge.

    Instead of the measurement M 0 in Fig. 6, one can place a unitary gate.

    This allows us to probabilistically subject tomorrows state to a unitary trans-formation today. But then we can go on, and instead of subjecting the outcomeof this gate to another one tomorrow, perform this subsequent transformation

    3 Specically 10 = x , 01 = y , and 11 = z where the right-hand sides are theconventionally named sigma matrices.

    7

  • 8/12/2019 Effective Quantum Time Travel

    8/8

    also today. Thus any nte sequence of unitary transformations to be performedtomorrow, the day after tomorrow, the day after that, and so on, can all beprobabilistically performed today, and tomorrow one can nd out if the en-deavor succeeded. There may be some practical advantage to this, even payingthe price of probability. Each transformation is performed on freshly createdstates, possibly thus lessening effects of decoherence. Whether one can alsouse the instances of tomorrows measurements not projecting onto 00 to someadvantage, as in the joint measurement case, has not been investigated.

    One can wonder if the above described processes occur in nature. At rstthought this could only occur in complex highly organized system. Biologicalsystems, especially neurobiological ones, come to mind, but this is pure specu-lation.

    This research received partial nancial support from the Conselho Nacionalde Desenvolvimento Cientco e Tecnol ogico (CNPq), and the Funda cao de Am-paro a Pesquisa do Estado do Rio de Janeiro (FAPERJ).

    Acknowledgements

    This research received partial nancial support from the Conselho Nacional deDesenvolvimento Cientco e Tecnol ogico (CNPq), and the Funda cao de Amparoa Pesquisa do Estado do Rio de Janeiro (FAPERJ).

    References

    [1] D. Deutsch, Phys. Rev. D. 44 , 3197 (1991).

    [2] D. Kutach, Phil. Sci. 70 , 1098 (2003).

    [3] D. Deutsch, Scientic American, March 1994, pp. 68-74.

    8