Book Review PORTER the Origin of the Aesthetic Thought in Anc. Greece

download Book Review PORTER the Origin of the Aesthetic Thought in Anc. Greece

of 5

Transcript of Book Review PORTER the Origin of the Aesthetic Thought in Anc. Greece

  • 7/28/2019 Book Review PORTER the Origin of the Aesthetic Thought in Anc. Greece

    1/5

    1

    Bryn Mawr Classical Review 2012.01.11

    James I. Porter, The Origins of Aesthetic Thought in Ancient

    Greece: Matter, Sensation, and Experience. Cambridge, UK:

    Cambridge University Press, 2010. Pp. xvii, 607. ISBN

    9780521841801. $145.00.

    Reviewed by Anastasia-Erasmia Peponi, Stanford University

    ([email protected])

    For too long a time beauty was out of favor within Classical scholarship. Porters

    book heralds beautys return and newer ways of engaging with it. As the manner in

    which cultures perceive and discuss the beautiful (and allied concepts) is central to

    our understanding of their sensibilities, a renaissance of the aesthetic in Classics can

    lead to rich and vigorous debates. One, then, cannot but welcome this voluminous and

    thought-provoking piece of work, the importance of which lies both in the

    sustainability and the merits of its key-ideas and in its occasional rifts and fissures thatprovide room for further deliberation.

    Porters main argument revolves around the ways in which pre- and post-Platonic and

    Aristotelian Greek aesthetic thought apprehended the sensuous and the material, the

    two major fourth-century BCE philosophers being the ones who established a

    formalist and idealist aesthetics that eventually silenced alternative aesthetic

    approaches. By formalism Porter means any attention to the purity or ideality of

    form, structure, or design (principles which are thought to organize matter or

    material); and a kind of Platonism, which for present purposes may be defined as a

    repudiation of the senses. (p. 2; see also pp. 70-71). Matter, on the other hand,

    largely refers to the concrete materials that artifacts consist of, such as pigments inpainting or phonemes in verbal production. Reviving the neglected aspects of a Greek

    aesthetics of matter founded on sensuous apprehension is the major goal of the book.

    The Introduction is followed by four parts, the first three of which are multi-sectional,

    while the last one consists of a brief epilogue. Part One is foundational as it discusses

    the authors key theoretical assumptions. This includes his ideas about the

    controversial applicability to Greek antiquity of the concept of art as well as to the

    two opposed (according to him) aesthetic forces that permeate Greek aesthetic

    thought, formalism and materialism. Part Two expands on most of the above issues. It

    contains detailed discussions of fragments and testimonies referring mainly (but not

    exclusively) to fifth-century discourses about language and the arts, mostly verbal arts

    in their vocal and broadly musical aspects. Presocratic and, especially, Sophistic

    http://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/2012/index.html
  • 7/28/2019 Book Review PORTER the Origin of the Aesthetic Thought in Anc. Greece

    2/5

    2

    approaches have a central position here, while among the poets Pindar and especially

    Aristophanes are discussed in greater detail. The last section in this part, dedicated to

    visual experience, examines critical issues involving painted and sculpted artifacts

    with regard to tensions between aesthetic idealization and materiality. Part Three,briefer than the other two, focuses on explicit and implicit links connecting an

    aesthetic of matter, monumentalization, and the sublime, as these appear in poetic

    discourses, inscriptional practices, and in the critical heritage of Hellenistic debates.

    Modern approaches to literature, the arts, and the aesthetic as a whole punctuate

    Porters inquiry from the beginning to the end of the book.

    Porters venture, his focus on matter and sensation as decisive constituents of Greek

    aesthetic thought, is insightful and impressively wide-ranging and far-reaching. It

    sheds light on some of the issues that much-needed new theories and histories of

    Greek aesthetics should seriously take into account. Several of his views stand out--

    for instance, his general statements regarding the existence and importance of earlier(largely pre-philosophical) Greek aesthetic thought, which I cannot applaud loudly

    enough; his overall engagement with AristotlesPoetics; and many of his approaches

    to visual artifacts, a particularly sensitive one being his reading of a Nolan amphora

    attributed to the Berlin painter, depicting a young cithara player, with its embedded

    tensions between tactility and visuality.

    While the validity and the importance of Porters main argument are unquestionable,

    certain side effects of the fervor with which he defends it kept me skeptical several

    times. The question pending while reading the book is not whether materialist

    sensibilities put their mark on Greek aesthetics but whether they have been as

    predominant as the author emphatically claims (p. 15). This reluctance may increase

    in cases where one is faced with almost imperceptible transitions from the archaic and

    classical period to Hellenistic and later times. Attaching itself to this experience here,

    beauty (or aesthetic value under some other name) becomes a concrete thing, non-

    transferable, non-generalizable, non-universal: it is truly idiosyncratic (an idion) (p.

    246). This is a very attractive formulation. Soon, though, this idiosyncratic aesthetic

    experience is explained as the kind of attentiveness to material detail that ought to

    have lain behind the Democritean title On Euphonious and Harsh- Sounding Letters.

    This is further identified as the principle that later compelled Dionysius of

    Halicarnassus to write about the aesthetic value of phonemes and to focus on the

    material density of the elements (p. 247). An introductory statement about the effectof such aesthetic conceptions refers to both pre- and post-Platonic aesthetics.

    Two interrelated concerns may arise in such cases. First, I cannot recall many

    instances in Greek texts (from Homer to Philostratus, for instance) that represent at

    some length a non-parodic experience of art exhausting itself in or even highlighting

    the sensuous appreciation of matter while not also implicating a larger interpretive

    agenda. Such agendas, although sensitive to matter, are usually attached to broader

    notional and emotional parameters beyond matter itself and often present affinities

    with what Porter understands as formalism. Second, even if such attitudes became

    central to certain Alexandrian and post-Alexandrian sensibilities, one may be skeptical

    about their prevalence in earlier times, however valuable such tendencies might have

  • 7/28/2019 Book Review PORTER the Origin of the Aesthetic Thought in Anc. Greece

    3/5

    3

    been even then.

    On the contrary, significant early evidence points either in the direction of flexible

    models of thought whereby materialist and other-than-materialist aesthetics, instead ofopposing one another, morphed into one another; or it gestures toward the direction of

    vivid aesthetic concerns outside the realm of matter and sensation. For instance, the

    semantics ofkosmos, a key term in early Greek aesthetics, were flexible enough to

    encompass both material objects, such as a wide variety of ornaments, and more

    abstract notions of order and structure, such as that of poetic narrative. And regardless

    of ones interpretation of the much-contested lines in theHomeric Hymn to Apollo,

    where the chorus of the Deliades is praised for their exquisite performance, the praise

    touches not on the sensuous but on the mental (both emotional and intellectual)

    apparatus by way of which performers and audience bond. Although such an

    achievement would have been the result of diligent labor involving the material of a

    chorus voices and bodies, this passage attests to aesthetic preoccupations outside therealm of matter, such as the relationships that connect structural coherence, mimesis,

    and the conceptualization of selfhood.

    For a history of Greek aesthetic thought, then, with an emphasis on Greece in its

    earlier phases (p. 1), it is important to discuss the broader significance of such

    occurrences, which because of their considerable weight deserve more than just brief

    listing (p. 181). In fact, such instances may affect the way one explains the derailing

    (p. 10) moment of Plato in particular. For although Platos unfriendliness to the

    senses (e.g. p. 87) is a widely accepted fact, it is likely that his battle against other

    aesthetic discourses was hard precisely because it had to undo not just proclivities to

    matter and sensation but all-encompassing aesthetic modes of feeling, thinking and

    interpreting.

    To move on to later literary critics, to whom Porter refers throughout his book, sonic

    matter was indeed analyzed by them as a thoroughly sensuous quality. Yet scrupulous

    analyses of this type may sometimes lead to generalizations that can damage a

    listeners idiosyncratic delights. More importantly, whenever we do have full evidence

    from such traditions, it becomes clear that the critics sensuous indulgence is rarely

    pure, for it is usually embedded in a profoundly conceptual frame. Dionysius of

    Halicarnassus enviable close reading of Sisyphus labor in the Odyssey (Comp. 20),

    for instance, is founded on the principle that successful verbal art is primarilymimetic. This is apparent not only in his views on the relationship between mimesis

    and language, which are explicit in this case though latent elsewhere, but also in the

    philosophical genotype his vocabulary.

    An eclectic aesthetic sensibility, appreciative of structures not only as sensuous but

    also as notional wholes, is verifiable in the work of another master of literary

    criticism, whose empirical stance Porter considers typical of materialist

    aesthetics: Longinus (p. 247). The Longinian sublime, Porter submits, is never a

    matter of the whole. Unlike the Aristotelian idea of a (well)-composed plot, the

    materialist constructs synthetic unities that are themselves just further material

    wholesa sound or a (collective) impact on the senses (p. 248). Yet Longinusinterpretation of Sapphos masterpiece (31V) indicates that sensuousness may yield to

  • 7/28/2019 Book Review PORTER the Origin of the Aesthetic Thought in Anc. Greece

    4/5

    4

    notional apprehension (Subl.10). Even if one refuses to acknowledge an Aristotelian

    twist in Longinus emphasis on the combination of constituent elements (moria) in an

    organically unified whole (hen ti sma --cf. Poet. 1459a20:zon hen holon), one has

    to admit that the critics praise of Sappho for the way she picks the extreme symptomsof desire from real life (ek ts altheias) and binds them together (sundsai) is

    founded not on his sensuous apparatus but on his mental conception.

    This is not to deny the importance of Longinus interest in matter but to counter the

    impression that a reader of Porters book sometimes gets of an almost monolithic

    aesthetic materialism in antiquity. Enlightened critical approaches to visual or verbal

    artifacts in antiquity, both before and after Plato and Aristotle, seemed to possess a

    flexible aesthetic attitude hard to label as either materialist or formalist and not

    dissimilar to that of a perceptive theoretician of art nowadays. The latter would know

    that taking delight in Vermeers adept brushwork, when contemplating the miniscule

    surface of the famous pearl earring, can co-exist with ones reflection upon the Dutchmasters almost mathematical struggle with the representation of the ideal.

    Overall, there is no question that Porters emphasis on the material and the sensuous

    can bring excellent creative energies to the area of Greek aesthetics. But it will be to

    the benefit of both aesthetics and cultural studies if such energies push even further,

    toward untrodden paths. For if the aesthetic resides primarily in matter and sensation,

    as Porter insists, perhaps a student of ancient aesthetics should engage principally

    with representations of, and meditations upon, the materialist senses par excellence

    smell, touch, and taste in Greek culture. This thorny issue, of course, brings out the

    theoretical circularity of modern preconceptions: if the domain of the aesthetic is art

    (within the perpetually questionable boundaries of which Porter largely confines

    himself, despite clear attempts to push beyond) then indeed smell, taste, and touch can

    only be the secondary synaesthetic components of the aural and visual, as the author

    who is sensitive to this issueknows. To allow for a substantial materialist aesthetics

    founded on these senses one has to conceive of the aesthetic as expanding beyond the

    realm of art. Such an understanding requires more than just annexing additional fields

    of aesthetic inquiry, for it is a driving principle that affects ones whole system of

    thought. Nevertheless, even such an expansion would not be enough in this case.

    Kant, for instance, who himself touched very lightly upon art, would push out of the

    beautiful and toward the direction of the agreeable any condition that could

    challenge disinterested apprehension--which is precisely what these senses do.

    In other words, if some of the newer approaches to Greek aesthetics are willing to

    shatter aesthetic norms for materialitys sake, why not break the norms once and for

    all and allow the senses that have always been chased away from the aesthetic to come

    forth and revolutionize the field? This may entail a fuller reassessment of several

    theoretical assumptions or perhaps lead to a refreshing tumult.

    Comment on

    this review in

    the BMCRblog

    http://www.bmcreview.org/2012/01/20120111.htmlhttp://www.bmcreview.org/2012/01/20120111.htmlhttp://www.bmcreview.org/2012/01/20120111.htmlhttp://www.bmcreview.org/2012/01/20120111.html
  • 7/28/2019 Book Review PORTER the Origin of the Aesthetic Thought in Anc. Greece

    5/5

    5

    Read Latest

    Index

    for

    2012

    Change

    Greek

    Display

    Archives

    Books

    Available

    for Review

    BMCR

    Home

    Bryn Mawr

    Classical

    Commentaries

    BMCR, Bryn Mawr College, 101 N. Merion Ave., Bryn Mawr, PA 19010

    HTML generated at 22:35:24, Sunday, 08 January 2012

    x

    http://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/recent.htmlhttp://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/2012/index.htmlhttp://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/2012/index.htmlhttp://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/2012/index.htmlhttp://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/cgi-bin/change_Greek.pl?url=http://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/2012/2012-01-11.htmlhttp://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/cgi-bin/change_Greek.pl?url=http://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/2012/2012-01-11.htmlhttp://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/cgi-bin/change_Greek.pl?url=http://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/2012/2012-01-11.htmlhttp://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/archive.htmlhttp://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/booksavailable.htmlhttp://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/booksavailable.htmlhttp://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/booksavailable.htmlhttp://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/http://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/http://www.brynmawr.edu/classics/commentaries.htmlhttp://www.brynmawr.edu/classics/commentaries.htmlhttp://www.brynmawr.edu/classics/commentaries.htmlhttp://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/recent.htmlhttp://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/2012/index.htmlhttp://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/2012/index.htmlhttp://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/2012/index.htmlhttp://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/2012/index.htmlhttp://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/cgi-bin/change_Greek.pl?url=http://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/2012/2012-01-11.htmlhttp://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/cgi-bin/change_Greek.pl?url=http://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/2012/2012-01-11.htmlhttp://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/cgi-bin/change_Greek.pl?url=http://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/2012/2012-01-11.htmlhttp://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/archive.htmlhttp://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/booksavailable.htmlhttp://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/booksavailable.htmlhttp://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/booksavailable.htmlhttp://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/http://bmcr.brynmawr.edu/http://www.brynmawr.edu/classics/commentaries.htmlhttp://www.brynmawr.edu/classics/commentaries.htmlhttp://www.brynmawr.edu/classics/commentaries.html