William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

download William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

of 39

Transcript of William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    1/39

    William of Ockham (Occam, c.1280 c.1349)

    William of Ockham (1280/5-1347/9), also known as William Ockham or William of

    Occam, was a fourteenth-century English philosopher. Historically, Ockham has been

    cast as the outstanding opponent of Thomas Aquinas (1224-1274): Aquinas perfected

    the great medieval synthesis of faith and reason and was canonized by the Catholic

    Church; Ockham destroyed the synthesis and was condemned by the Catholic Church.

    Although it is true that Aquinas and Ockham disagreed on most issues, Aquinas had

    many other critics, and Ockham did not criticize Aquinas any more than he did others. It

    is fair enough, however, to say that Ockham was a major force of change at the end of

    the Middle Ages. He was a courageous man with an uncommonly sharp mind. His

    philosophy was radical in his day and continues to provide insight into current

    philosophical debates.

    The principle of simplicity is the central theme of Ockhams approach, so much so that

    this principle has come to be known as Ockhams Razor. Ockham uses the razor to

    eliminate unnecessary hypotheses. In metaphysics, Ockham champions nominalism, the

    view that universal essences, such as humanity or whiteness, are nothing more than

    concepts in the mind. He develops an Aristotelian ontology, admitting only individual

    substances and qualities. In epistemology, Ockham defends direct realist empiricism,

    according to which human beings perceive objects through intuitive cognition,

    without the help of any innate ideas. These perceptions give rise to all of our abstract

    concepts and provide knowledge of the world. In logic, Ockham presents a version of

    supposition theory to support his commitment to mental language. Supposition theory

    had various purposes in medieval logic, one of which was to explain how words bear

    meaning. Theologically, Ockham is a fideist, maintaining that belief in God is a matter of

    faith rather than knowledge. Against the mainstream, he insists that theology is not a

    science and rejects all the alleged proofs of the existence of God. Ockhams ethics is a

    http://www.iep.utm.edu/aquinashttp://www.iep.utm.edu/aquinas
  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    2/39

    divine command theory. In the Euthyphro dialogue, Plato (437-347 B.C.E.) poses the

    following question: Is something good because God wills it or does God will something

    because it is good? Although most philosophers affirm the latter, divine command

    theorists affirm the former. Ockhams divine command theory can be seen as a

    consequence of his metaphysical libertarianism. In political theory, Ockham advances

    the notion of rights, separation of church and state, and freedom of speech.

    Table of Contents

    1. Life and Works2. The Razor3. Metaphysics: Nominalism4. Epistemology

    1. Direct Realist Empiricism2. Intuitive Cognition

    5. Logic1. Mentalese2. Supposition Theory3. The Categories

    6. Theology1. Fideism

    1. Theology is Not a Science2. The Trinity is a Logical Contradiction3. There Is No Evidence of Purpose in the Natural World

    2. Against the Proofs of Gods Existence1. The Ontological Proof2. The Cosmological Proof

    7. Ethics

    http://www.iep.utm.edu/platohttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#H1http://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#H2http://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#H3http://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#H4http://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH4ahttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH4bhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#H5http://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH5ahttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH5bhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH5chttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#H6http://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH6ahttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH6aihttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH6aiihttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH6aiiihttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH6bhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH6bhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH6bihttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH6biihttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#H7http://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#H7http://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH6biihttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH6bihttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH6bhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH6aiiihttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH6aiihttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH6aihttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH6ahttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#H6http://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH5chttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH5bhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH5ahttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#H5http://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH4bhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH4ahttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#H4http://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#H3http://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#H2http://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#H1http://www.iep.utm.edu/plato
  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    3/39

    1. Divine Command Theory2. Metaphysical Libertarianism

    8. Political Theory1. Rights2. Separation of Church and State3. Freedom of Speech

    9. References and Further Reading1. Ockhams Works in Latin2. Ockhams Works in English Translation3. Books about Ockham

    1. Life and Works

    Very little biographical information about Ockham survives. There is a record of his

    ordination in the year 1306. From this, we infer that he was born between 1280 and

    1285, presumably in the small town of Ockham, twenty-five miles southwest of London,

    England. The medieval church in this town, All Saints, recently installed a stained glass

    window of Ockham because it is probably the church in which he grew up. Nevertheless,

    we know nothing of Ockhams childhood or family. Most likely, he spoke Middle English

    and wrote exclusively in Latin.

    Because Ockham joined the Franciscan order (known as the Order of the Friars Minor or

    OFM), he would have received his early education at a Franciscan house. From there, he

    pursued a degree in theology at Oxford University. He never completed it, however,

    because in 1323 he was summoned to the papal court, which had been moved from

    Rome to Avignon, to answer to charges of heresy.

    Ockham remained in Avignon under a loose form of house arrest for four years while

    the papacy carried out its investigation. Through this ordeal Ockham became convinced

    http://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH7ahttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH7bhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#H8http://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH8ahttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH8bhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH8chttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#H9http://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH9ahttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH9ahttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH9bhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH9bhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH9chttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH9chttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH9bhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH9ahttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#H9http://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH8chttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH8bhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH8ahttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#H8http://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH7bhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/ockham/#SH7a
  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    4/39

    that the papacy was corrupt and finally decided to flee with some other Franciscans on

    trial there. On May 26, 1328 they escaped in the night on stolen horses to the court of

    Louis of Bavaria, a would-be emperor, who had his own reasons for opposing the Pope.

    They were all ex-communicated and hunted down but never captured.

    After a brief and unsuccessful campaign in Italy, Louis and his entourage settled in

    Munich. Ockham spent the rest of his days there as a political activist, writing treatises

    against the papacy. Ockham died sometime between 1347 and 1349, unreconciled with

    the Catholic Church. Because he never returned to his academic career, Ockham

    acquired the nickname Venerable Inceptoran inceptor being one who is on the

    point of earning a degree. Ockhams other nickname is the More than Subtle Doctor

    because he was thought to have surpassed the Franciscan philosopher John Duns Scotus

    (1265/6-1308), who was known as the Subtle Doctor.

    Methodologically, Ockham fits comfortably within the analytic philosophical tradition.

    He considers himself a devoted follower of Aristotle (384-322 B.C.E.), whom he calls

    The Philosopher, though most Aristotle scholars would find many of his

    interpretations dubious. Ockham may simply have a unique understanding of Aristotle

    or he may be using Aristotle as cover for developing views he knew would be

    threatening to the status quo.

    Aside from Aristotle, the French Franciscan philosopher Peter John Olivi (1248 1298)

    was the single most important influence on Ockham. Olivi is an extremely original

    thinker, pioneering direct realism, nominalism, metaphysical libertarianism, and many

    of the same political views that Ockham defends later in his career. One notable

    difference between the two, however, is that, while Ockham loves Aristotle, Olivi hates

    him. Ockham never acknowledges Olivi because Olivi was condemned as a heretic.

    http://www.iep.utm.edu/aristotlhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/aristotl
  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    5/39

    Ockham published several philosophical works before losing official status as an

    academic. The first was his Commentary on the Sentences of Peter Lombard, a standard

    requirement for medieval theology students. The philosopher and archbishop Peter

    Lombard (11001160/4) composed a book of opinions (sententia) for and against

    various controversial claims. By commenting on this book, students would learn the art

    of argumentation while at the same time developing their own views. As a student,

    Ockham also wrote several commentaries on the works of Aristotle. In addition, he

    engaged in public debates, the proceedings of which were published under the titles

    Disputed Questions and Quodlibetal Questionsquodlibet meaning whatever you

    like. Ockhams opus magnum, however, is his Suma Logicae, in which he lays out the

    fundamentals of his logic and its accompanying metaphysics. We do not know exactly

    when it was written, but it is the latest of his academic works. After the Avignon affair,

    Ockham wrote and circulated several political treatises unofficially, the most important

    of which is his Dialogue on the Power of the Emperor and the Pope. All of Ockhams

    works have been edited into modern editions but not all have been translated.

    2. The Razor

    Ockhams Razor is the principle of parsimony or simplicity according to which the

    simpler theory is more likely to be true. Ockham did not invent this principle; it is found

    in Aristotle, Aquinas, and other philosophers Ockham read. Nor did he call the principle

    a razor. In fact, the first known use of the term Occams razor occurs in 1852 in the

    work of the British mathematician William Rowan Hamilton. Although Ockham never

    even makes an argument for the validity of the principle, he uses it in many striking

    ways, and this is how it became associated with him.

    For some, the principle of simplicity implies that the world is maximally simple. Aquinas,

    for example, argues that nature does not employ two instruments where one suffices.

    http://www.iep.utm.edu/lombardhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/lombardhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/lombardhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/lombard
  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    6/39

    This interpretation of the principle is also suggested by its most popular formulation:

    Entities should not be multiplied beyond necessity. Yet this is a problematic assertion.

    We know today that nature is often redundant in both form and function. Although

    medieval philosophers were largely ignorant of evolutionary biology, they did affirm the

    existence of an omnipotent God, which is alone enough to render the assumption that

    the world is maximally simple suspicious. In any case, Ockham never makes this

    assumption and he does not use the popular formulation of the principle.

    For Ockham, the principle of simplicity limits the multiplication of hypotheses not

    necessarily entities. Favoring the formulation It is useless to do with more what can be

    done with less, Ockham implies that theories are meant to do things, namely, explain

    and predict, and these things can be accomplished more effectively with fewer

    assumptions.

    At one level, this is just common sense. Suppose your car suddenly stops running and

    your fuel gauge indicates an empty gas tank. It would be silly to hypothesize both that

    you are out of gas andthat you are out of oil. You need only one hypothesis to explain

    what has happened.

    Some would object that the principle of simplicity cannot guarantee truth. The gas

    gauge on your car may be broken or the empty gas tank may be just one of several

    things wrong with the car. In response to this objection, one might point out that the

    principle of simplicity does not tell us which theory is true but only which theory is more

    likelyto be true. Moreover, if there is some other sign of damage, such as a blinking oil

    gage, then there is a further fact to explain, warranting an additional hypothesis.

    Although the razor seems like common sense in everyday situations, when used in

    science, it can have surprising and powerful effects. For example, in his classic

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    7/39

    exposition of theoretical physics, A Brief History of Time, Stephen Hawking attributes

    the discovery of quantum mechanics to Ockhams Razor.

    Nevertheless, not everyone approves of the razor. Ockhams contemporary and fellow

    Franciscan Walter Chatton proposed an anti-razor in opposition to Ockham. He

    declares that if three things are not enough to verify an affirmative proposition about

    things, a fourth must be added, and so on. Others call Ockhams razor a principle of

    stinginess, accusing it of quashing creativity and imagination. Still others complain that

    there is no objective way to determine which of two theories is simpler. Often a theory

    that is simpler in one way is more complicated in another way. All of these concerns and

    others make Ockhams razor controversial.

    At bottom, Ockham advocates simplicity in order to reduce the risk of error. Every

    hypothesis carries the possibility that it may be wrong. The more hypotheses you

    accept, the more you increase your risk. Ockham strove to avoid error at all times, even

    if it meant abandoning well-loved, traditional beliefs. This approach helped to earn him

    his reputation as destroyer of the medieval synthesis of faith and reason.

    3. Metaphysics: Nominalism

    One of the most basic challenges in metaphysics is to explain how it is that things are

    the same despite differences. The Greek philosopher Heraclitus (540 480 B.C.E.) points

    out that you can never step into the same river twice, referring not just to rivers, but to

    places, people, and life itself. Every day everything changes a little bit and everywhere

    you go you find new things. Heraclitus concludes from such observations that nothing

    ever remains the same. All reality is in flux.

    The problem with seeing the world this way is that it leads to radical skepticism: if

    nothing stays the same from moment to moment and from place to place, then we can

    http://www.iep.utm.edu/heraclithttp://www.iep.utm.edu/heraclit
  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    8/39

    never really be certain about anything. We cant know our friends, we cant know the

    world we live in, we cant even know ourselves! Moreover, if Heraclitus is right, it seems

    science is impossible. We could learn the properties of a chemical here today and still

    have no basis for knowing its properties someplace else tomorrow.

    Needless to say, most people would prefer to avoid skepticism. Its hard to carry on in a

    state of complete ignorance. Besides, it seems obvious that science is not impossible.

    Studying the world really does enable us to know how things are over time and across

    distances. The fact that things change through time and vary from place to place does

    not seem to prevent us from having knowledge. From this, some philosophers, such as

    Plato and Augustine (354-430), draw the conclusion that Heraclitus was wrong to

    suppose that everything is in flux. Something stays the same, something that lays

    underneath the changing and varying surfaces we perceive, namely, the universal

    essence of things.

    For example, although individual human beings change from day to day and vary from

    place to place, they all share the universal essence of humanity, which is eternally the

    same. Likewise for dogs, trees, rocks, and even qualitiesthere must be a universal

    essence of blueness, heat, love, and anything else one can think of. Universal essences

    are not physical realities; if you dissect a human being, you will not find humanity inside

    like a kidney or a lung! Nevertheless, universal essences are metaphysical realities: they

    provide the invisible structure of things.

    Belief in universal essences is called metaphysical realism, because it asserts that

    universal essences are real even though we cannot physically see them. Although there

    are various different versions of metaphysical realism, they are all designed to secure a

    foundation for knowledge. It seems you have a choice: either you accept metaphysical

    realism or you are stuck with skepticism.

    http://www.iep.utm.edu/augustinhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/augustin
  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    9/39

    Ockham, however, argues that this is a false dilemma. He rejects metaphysical realism

    and skepticism in favor of nominalism: the view that universal essences are concepts in

    the mind. The word nominalism comes from the Latin word nomina, meaning name.

    Earlier nominalists such as the French philosopher Roscelin (1050-1125), had advanced

    the more radical view that universal essences are just names that have no basis in

    reality. Ockham developed a more sophisticated version of nominalism often called

    conceptualism because it holds that universal essences are concepts caused in our

    minds when we perceive real similarities among things in the world.

    For example, when a child comes in contact with different human beings over time, he

    begins to form the concept of humanity. The realist would say that he has detected the

    invisible common structure of these individuals. Ockham, in contrast, insists that the

    child has merely perceived similarities that fit naturally under one concept.

    It is tempting to assume that Ockham rejects metaphysical realism because of the

    principle of simplicity. After all, realism requires believing in invisible entities that might

    not actually exist. As a matter of fact, however, Ockham never uses the razor to attack

    realism. And on closer examination, this makes sense: the realist position is that the

    existence of universal essences is a hypothesis necessary to explain how science is

    possible. Since Ockham was just as concerned as everyone else to avoid skepticism, he

    might have been persuaded by such an argument.

    Ockham has a much deeper worry about realism: he is convinced it is incoherent.

    Incoherence is the most serious charge a philosopher can level against a theory because

    it means that the theory contains a contradictionand contradictions cannot be true.

    Ockham asserts that metaphysical realism cannot be true because it holds that a

    universal essence is one thing and many things at the same time. The form of humanity

    is one thing, because it is what all humans have in common, but it is also many things

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    10/39

    because it provides an invisible structure of each individual one of us. This is to say that

    it is both one thing and not one thing at the same time, which is a contradiction.

    Realists claim that this apparent contradiction can be explained in various ways.

    Ockham insists, however, that no matter how you explain it, there is no way to avoid the

    fact that the notion of a universal essence is an impossible hypothesis. He writes,

    There is no universal outside the mind really existing in individual substances or in the

    essences of things. The reason is that everything that is not many things is necessarily

    one thing in number and consequently a singular thing. [Opera Philosophica II, pp. 11-

    12]

    Ockham presents a thought experiment to prove universal essences do not exist. He

    writes that, according to realism,

    it would follow that God would not be able to annihilate one individual substance

    without destroying the other individuals of the same kind. For, if he were to annihilate

    one individual, he would destroy the whole that is essentially that individual and,

    consequently, he would destroy the universal that is in it and in others of the same

    essence. Other things of the same essence would not remain, for they could not

    continue to exist without the universal that constitutes a part of them. [Opera

    Philosophica I, p. 51]

    Since God is omnipotent, he should be able to annihilate a human being. But the

    universal form of humanity lies within that human being. So, by destroying the

    individual, he will destroy the universal. And if he destroys the universal, which is

    humanity, then he destroys all the other humans as well.

    The realist may wish to reply that destroying an individual human destroys only partof

    the universal humanity. But this contradicts the original assertion that the universal

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    11/39

    humanity is a single shared essence that is eternally the same for everyone! For

    Ockham, this problem decisively defeats realism and leaves us with the nominalist

    alternative that universals are concepts caused in our minds when we perceive similar

    individuals. To support this alternative, Ockham develops an empiricist epistemology.

    4. Epistemology

    a. Direct Realist Empiricism

    Epistemology is the study of knowledge: what is it, and how do we come to have it?

    There are two basic approaches to epistemology: rationalists claim that knowledge

    consists of innate certainties that we discover through reason; empiricists claim that

    knowledge consists in accurate perceptions that we accumulate through experience.

    Although early medieval philosophers such as Augustine and Anselm (1033-1109) were

    innatists, empiricism came to dominate during the high Middle Ages. This is mostly

    because Aristotle was an empiricist and the texts in which he promotes empiricism were

    rediscovered and translated for the first time into Latin during the thirteenth century.

    Following Aristotle, Ockham asserts that human beings are born blank states: there are

    no innate certainties to be discovered in our minds. We learn by observing qualities in

    objects. Ockhams version of empiricism is called direct realism because he denies

    that there is any intermediary between the perceiver and the world. (Note that direct

    realism should not be confused with metaphysical realism, which Ockham rejects, as

    discussed above.) Direct realism states that if you see an apple, its redness causes you to

    know that it is red. This may seem obvious, but it actually raises a problem that has led

    many empiricists, both in Ockhams day and today, to reject direct realism.

    As the French philosopher Peter Aureol (1275-1333) points out, the problem is that

    there are cases where we perceive something that is not really there. In optical illusions,

    http://www.iep.utm.edu/anselmhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/anselm
  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    12/39

    hallucinations, and dreams, our perceptions are completely disconnected with the

    external world.

    Representationalism is the version of empiricism designed to solve this problem.

    According to representationalists, human beings perceive the world through a mental

    mediary, or representation, known in the Middle Ages as the intelligible species.

    Normally, an apple causes an intelligible species of itself for us to perceive it through. In

    cases of optical illusions, hallucinations, and dreams, something else causes the

    intelligible species. The perception seems veridical to us because there is no difference

    in the intelligible species. Even before Peter Aureol, Thomas Aquinas advocated

    representationalism, and it soon became the dominant view.

    The difficulty with representationalism, as the Irish philosopher George Berkeley (1685-

    1754) amply demonstrates, is that once you introduce an intermediary between the

    perceiver and the external world, you lose your justification for belief in the external

    world. If all of our ideas come through representations, how do we know what, if

    anything, is behind these representations? Something other than physical objects could

    be causing them. For example, God could be transmitting representations of physical

    objects to our minds without ever creating any physical objects at allwhich is in fact

    what Berkeley came to believe. This view, known as idealism, is radically skeptical, and

    most philosophers prefer to avoid it.

    b. Intuitive Cognition

    Ockham preempts idealism through the notion of intuitive cognition, which plays a

    crucial role in his four-step account of knowledge acquisition. It can be summarized as

    follows. The first step is sensory cognition: receiving data through the five senses. This is

    an ability human beings share with animals. The second step, intuitive cognition, is

    uniquely human. Intuitive cognition is an awareness that the particular individual

    http://www.iep.utm.edu/berkeleyhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/berkeley
  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    13/39

    perceived exists and has the qualities it has. The third step is recordative cognition, by

    which we remember past perceptions. The fourth step is abstractive cognition, by which

    we place individuals in groups of similar individuals.

    Notice that, if an apple is set in front of a horse, the horse will receive data about the

    applethe color, the smell, etc.and react appropriately. The horse will not, however,

    register the reality of the object. Suppose you project a realistic, laser image of an apple

    in front of the horse and he tries to take a bite. He will become frustrated, and

    eventually give up, but he will never really get it. Human beings, in contrast, have

    reality-sensitive minds. Its not a matter of thinking This is real every time we see

    something. On the contrary, Ockham asserts that intuitive cognition is non-

    propositional. Rather, it is a matter of registering that the apple really has the qualities

    we perceive. Ockham writes:

    Intuitive cognition is such that when some things are cognized, of which one inheres in

    the other, or one is spatially distant from the other, or exists in some relation to the

    other, immediately in virtue of that non-propositional cognition of those things, it is

    known if the thing inheres or does not inhere, if it is spatially distant or not, and the

    same for other true contingent propositions, unless that cognition is flawed or there is

    some impediment. [Opera Theologica I, p. 31]

    While intuitive cognition is itself non-propositional, it provides the basis for formulating

    true propositions. A horse cannot say This apple is red because its mind is not complex

    enough to register the reality of what it perceives. The human mind, registering the

    existence of thingsboth that they are and how they arecan therefore formulate

    assertions about them.

    Strictly speaking, when one has an intuitive cognition of an apple, one is not yet thinking

    of it as an apple, because this requires placing it in a group. In normal adult human

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    14/39

    perception, all four of the above steps happen together so quickly that it is hard to

    separate them. But try to imagine what perception is like for a toddler: she sees the

    round, red object and points to it saying That! This is an expression of intuitive

    cognition.

    Intuitive cognition secures a causal link between the external world and the human

    mind. The human mind is entirely passive, according to Ockham, during intuitive

    cognition. Objects in the world cause us to be aware of their existence, and this explains

    and justifies our belief in them.

    Despite his insistence on the causal link between the world and our minds, Ockham

    clearly recognizes cases in which intuitive cognition causes false judgment. (See the last

    line of the above quotation: unless that cognition is flawed or there is some

    impediment.) For example, when you see a stick half-emerged in water, it looks bent.

    This is because your intuitive cognition of the stick is being affected by your

    simultaneous intuitive cognition of the water, and this causes a skewed perception. In

    addition to leaving room for error on his account, Ockham also leaves room for

    skepticism: God can transmit representations to human beings that seem exactly like

    intuitive cognitions.

    Given that direct realism cannot rule out skepticism any more than representationalism

    can, one might wonder why Ockham prefers it. In the end, it is a question of simplicity.

    Whereas Ockham never uses his razor against metaphysical realism, he does use it

    against representationalism. Intuitive cognition is necessary to secure a causal link

    between the world and the mind, and, once it is in place, there is no need for a middle

    man. The intelligible species is an unnecessary hypothesis.

    It is worth noting that intuitive cognition also provides epistemological support for

    Ockhams nominalist metaphysics. Representationalists typically hold that the

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    15/39

    intelligible species emanates from the universal essence of the thing. In their view, you

    perceive an apple as an apple because the apples universal essence of appleness is

    conveyed to you through its intelligible species. In fact, many metaphysical realists

    would argue for the superiority of their view precisely on the grounds that universal

    essences provide a basis for intelligible species, and intelligible species are necessary for

    us to know what we are perceiving. They would ask: how else do we ever identify apples

    as apples instead of just so many distinct individuals?

    As we have seen, Ockham argues that there is no universal essence. There is therefore

    no basis for an intelligible species. Each object in the world is an absolute individual and

    that is how we perceive it at first. Just like toddlers, we are bombarded with a buzzing,

    booming confusion of colors and sounds. But our minds are powerful sorting machines.

    We remember perceptions over time (recordative cognition) and organize them into

    groups (abstractive cognition). This organizational process gives us a coherent

    understanding of the world and is what Ockham aims to explain in his account of logic.

    5. Logic

    a. Mentalese

    Although the human mind is born without any knowledge, according to Ockham, it does

    come fully equip with a system for processing perceptions as they are acquired. This

    system is thought, which Ockham understands in terms of an unspoken, mental

    language. He is therefore considered an advocate of mentalese, like the American

    philosopher Noam Chomsky.

    Ockham might compare thought to a machine ready to manipulate a vast quantity of

    empty boxes. As we observe the world, perceptions are placed in the empty boxes. Then

    the machine sorts and organizes the boxes according to content. Two small boxes with

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    16/39

    similar contents might be placed together in a big box, and then the big box might be

    conjoined to another big box. For example, as perceptions of Rover and Fido

    accumulate, they become the concept dog, and then the concept dog is associated with

    the concept fleas. This conceptual apparatus enables us to construct meaningful

    sentences, such as All dogs have fleas.

    The intuitive cognition in Ockhams epistemology provides a basis for what is today

    called a causal theory of reference in philosophy of language. The word dog means

    dog because the concept you think of when you write it or say it was caused by the dogs

    you have perceived. Dogs cause the same kinds of concepts in all human beings. Thus,

    mentalese is universal among us, even though there are different ways to speak and

    write words in different countries around the world. While written and spoken language

    is conventional, signification itself is natural.

    Early in his career, Ockham entertained the notion that concepts are mental objects or

    ficta which resemble objects in the world like pictures. He abandoned ficta theory,

    however, because it presupposes a representationalist epistemology, which in turn

    presupposes metaphysical realism. Arguing instead for intellectum theory, according

    to which objects can have causal impact on the mind without creating mental pictures

    of themselves; he offers the following analogy. Medieval pubs received wine in

    shipments of wooden barrels sealed with hoops. When the shipment arrived, the pub

    owner would hang a barrel hoop outside the front door to communicate to the

    townspeople that wine was available. Although the hoop did not resemble wine in any

    way, it was significant to the townspeople. This is because the presence of the hoop was

    caused by the arrival of the wine. Likewise, dogs in the world cause concepts in our

    minds that are significant even though they do not resemble dogs.

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    17/39

    It must be noted that there is a drawback to both the barrel hoop analogy and the box

    illustration: they portray concepts as things. For convenience, Ockham often speaks of

    concepts loosely as though they were things. However, according to intellectum theory,

    concepts are not really things at all but rather actions. Perceiving a dog does not cause

    an entity to exist in your mind; rather, it causes a mental act. Today we would say that it

    causes a neuron to fire. Repeated acts cause a habit: the disposition to perform the act

    at will. So, repeated perceptions of dogs cause repeated acts of dog-conceiving and

    those repeated acts cause a dog-conceiving habit, meaning that you can engage in dog-

    conceiving actions whenever you want, even when there are no dogs around to

    perceive.

    b. Supposition Theory

    In Ockhams view, any coherent thought we have requires connecting or disconnecting

    concepts by means of linguistic operators. Ockham has a lot of ideas about how the

    linguistic operators work, which he develops in his version of supposition theory.

    Although supposition theory was a major preoccupation of late medieval logicians,

    scholars are still divided over its purpose. Some think it was an effort to build a system

    of formal logic that ultimately failed. Others think it was more akin to a modern theory

    of logical form.

    Ockhams interest in supposition theory seems motivated by his concern to clarify

    conceptual confusion. Much like Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889-1951), Ockham asserts that

    many philosophical errors arise due to the misunderstanding of language. He took

    metaphysical realism to be a prime example. Conceiving of human beings in general

    leads us to use the word humanity. Metaphysical realists conclude that this word

    must refer to a universal essence within all human beings. For Ockham, however, the

    word humanity stands for a habit that enables us to conceive of all the human beings

    http://www.iep.utm.edu/wittgenshttp://www.iep.utm.edu/wittgens
  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    18/39

    we have perceived to date in a very efficient manner: stripped of all of their individual

    details. In this way, Ockhams supposition theory is designed to support his nominalist

    metaphysics while elucidating the rules of thought.

    The word supposition comes from the Latin word stand for but it closely

    approximates the technical notion known as reference in English. At its most basic

    level, supposition theory tells us how words used in sentences, which Ockham calls

    terms, refer to things.

    Medieval logicians recognize three types of suppositionmaterial, personal and

    simplebut their metaphysical commitments affect their analyses. Most everyone

    agrees about material supposition. It occurs when a term is mentioned rather than

    used, as is the term stop in the sentence, The sign says stop. But they disagree over

    personal and simple supposition. For Ockham, personal supposition occurs when a term

    stands for an object in the world, as does the term cat in the sentence, The cat is on

    the mat and simple supposition occurs when a term stands for a concept in the mind,

    as does horse in the sentence, Horse is a species. For Ockhams realist opponents, in

    contrast, the term species stands for a universal essence, which is an object in the

    world. They therefore have a different account of personal and simple supposition.

    In addition to three types of supposition, medieval logicians recognize two types of

    terms: categorematic and syncategorematic. Categorematic terms refer to existing

    things and are called categorematic because, in his Organon, Aristotle asserts that

    there are ten categories of existing things. Syncategorematic terms do not refer to

    anything at all. They are logical operators, such as all, not, if, and only, which tell

    how to associate or disassociate the categorematic terms in a sentence.

    Among categorematic terms, some are absolute names while others are connotative

    names. Ockham describes the difference as follows:

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    19/39

    Properly speaking, only absolute names, that is, concepts signifying things composed of

    matter and form, have definitions expressing real essence. Some examples of this sort of

    name are human being, lion, and goat. Connotative and relative names, on the

    other hand, which signify one thing directly and another thing indirectly, have

    definitions expressing nominal essence. Some examples of this sort of name are

    white, hot, parent, and child. *Opera Philosophica IX, p. 554]

    The terms human being and parent are both names for Betty. The term human

    being signifies Betty in an absolute way because it refers to her alone as an

    independently existing object. The term parent signifies Betty in a connotative way

    because it signifies her while at the same time signifying her children.

    c. The Categories

    Although the distinction between absolute and connotative terms seems minor,

    Ockham uses it for radical purposes. According to the standard reading of the Organon,

    Aristotle holds that there are ten categories of existing things as follows: substance,

    quality, quantity, relation, place, time, position, state, action, and passion. According to

    Ockhams reading, however, Aristotle holds that there are only two categories of

    existing things: substance and quality. Ockham bases his interpretation on the thesis

    that only substances and qualities have real essence definitions signifying things

    composed of matter and form. The other eight categories signify a substance or a

    quality while connoting something else. They therefore have nominal essence

    definitions, meaning that they are not existing things.

    Consider quantity. Suppose you have one orange. It is a substance with a real essence of

    citrus fruit. Furthermore, it possesses several qualities, such as its color, its flavor, and

    its smell. The orange and its qualities are existing things according to Ockham. But the

    orange is also singular. Is its singularity an existing thing? For mathematical Platonists,

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    20/39

    the answer is yes: the number one exists as a universal essence and inheres in the

    orange. Ockham, in contrast, asserts that the singularity of the orange is just a short

    hand way of saying that there are no other oranges nearby. So, in the sentence Here is

    one orange the term one is connotative: it directly signifies the orange itself while

    indirectly signifying all the other oranges that are not here. Ockham eliminates the rest

    of the categories along the same lines.

    Interestingly, Ockhams elimination of quantity precipitated his summons to Avignon

    because it pushed him to a new account of the sacrament of the altar. The sacrament of

    the altar is the miracle that is supposed to occur when bread and wine are transformed

    into the body and blood of Jesus Christ. This process is known in theology as

    transubstantiation because one substance changes into another substance. The

    problem is to explain why the bread and wine continue to look, smell, and taste exactly

    the same despite the underlying change. According to the standard account, the

    qualities of the bread and wine continue to inhere in their quantity, which remains the

    same while substances are exchanged. According to Ockham, however, quantity is

    nothing other than the substance itself; if the substance changes then the quantity

    changes. So, the qualities cannot continue to inhere in the same quantity. Nor can they

    transfer from the substance of the bread and wine into the substance of Jesus because

    it would be blasphemous to say that Jesus was crunchy or wet! Ockhams solution is to

    claim that the qualities of the bread and wine continue to exist all by themselves,

    accompanying the invisible substance of Jesus down the gullet. Needless to say, this

    solution was a bit too clever.

    One question scholars continue to ask is why Ockham allows for two of the ten

    categories to remain instead of just one, namely, substance. It seems that qualities, such

    as whiteness, crunchiness, sweetness, etc, can just as easily be reduced to nominal

    essences: they signify the substance itself while connoting the tongue or nose or eye

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    21/39

    that perceives it. Of course, if Ockham had eliminated quality, he really would have had

    no basis left for saving the miracle of transubstantiation. Perhaps that was reason

    enough to stay his razor.

    6. Theology

    a. Fideism

    Despite his departures from orthodoxy and his conflict with the papacy, Ockham never

    renounced Catholicism. He steadfastly embraced fideism, the view that belief in God is a

    matter of faith alone. Although fideism was soon to become common among Protestant

    thinkers, it was not so common among medieval Catholics. At the beginning of the

    Middle Ages, Augustine proposed a proof of the existence of God and promoted the

    view that reason is faith seeking understanding. While the standard approach for any

    medieval philosopher would be to recognize a role for both faith and reason in religion,

    Ockham makes an uncompromising case for faith alone.

    Three assertions reveal Ockham to be a fideist.

    i. Theology is Not a Science

    The word science comes from the Latin word scientia, meaning knowledge. In the

    first book of his Sentences, Peter Lombard raises the issue of whether and in what sense

    theology is a science. Most philosophers commenting on the Sentences found a way to

    cast faith as a way of knowing. Ockham, however, makes no such effort. As a staunch

    empiricist, Ockham is committed to the thesis that all knowledge comes from

    experience. Yet we have no experience of God. It follows inescapably that we have no

    knowledge of God, as Ockham affirms in the following passage:

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    22/39

    In order to demonstrate the statement of faith that we formulate about God, what we

    would need for the central concept is a simple cognition of the divine nature in itself

    what someone who sees God has. Nevertheless, we cannot have this kind of cognition in

    our present state. [Quodlibetal Questions, pp. 103-4]

    By present state Ockham is referring to life on earth as a human being. Just as we now

    have knowledge of others through intuitive cognitions of their individual essences, those

    who go to heaven (if there ever are any such) will have knowledge of God through

    intuitive cognitions of his essence. Until then we can only hope.

    ii. The Trinity is a Logical Contradiction

    The Trinity is the core Christian doctrine according to which God is three persons in one.

    Christians traditionally consider the Trinity a mystery, meaning that it is beyond the

    comprehension of the human mind. Ockham goes so far as to admit that it is a blatant

    contradiction. He displays the problem through the following syllogism:

    According to the doctrine of the Trinity:

    (1) God is the Father,

    and,

    (2) Jesus is God.

    Therefore, by transitivity, according to the doctrine of the Trinity:

    (3) Jesus is the Father.

    Yet, according to the doctrine of the Trinity, Jesus is not the Father.

    So, according to the doctrine of the Trinity, Jesus both is and is not the Father.

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    23/39

    Providing precedent for a recent presidential defense, many medieval philosophers

    suggested that the transitive inference to the conclusion is broken by different senses of

    the word is. Scotus creatively argues that the logic of the Trinity is an opaque context

    that does not obey the usual rules. For Ockham, however, this syllogism establishes that

    theology is not logical and must never be mixed with philosophy.

    iii. There Is No Evidence of Purpose in the Natural World

    Living prior to the advent of Christianity, Aristotle never believed in the Trinity. He does,

    however, seem to believe in a supernatural force that lends purpose to all of nature.

    This is evident in his doctrine of the Four Causes, according to which every existing thing

    requires a fourfold explanation. Ockham would cast these four causes in terms of the

    following four questions:

    First Cause: What is it made of?

    Second Cause: What does it do?

    Third Cause: What brought it about?

    Fourth Cause: Why does it do what it does?

    Most medieval philosophers found Aristotles four causes conducive to the Christian

    worldview, assimilating the fourth cause to the doctrine of divine providence, according

    to which everything that happens is ultimately part of Gods plan.

    Though Ockham was reluctant to disagree with Aristotle, he was so determined to keep

    theology separate from science and philosophy, that he felt compelled to criticize the

    fourth (which he calls final) cause. Ockham writes,

    If I accepted no authority, I would claim that it cannot be proved either from statements

    known in themselves or from experience that every effect has a final cause. Someone

    who is just following natural reason would claim that the question why? is

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    24/39

    inappropriate in the case of natural actions. For he would maintain that it is no real

    question to ask something like, For what reason is fire generated? *Quodlibetal

    Questions, pp. 246-9]

    No doubt Ockham put his criticism in hypothetical, third-person terms because he knew

    that openly asserting that the universe itself may be entirely purposeless would never

    pass muster with the powers that be.

    b. Against the Proofs of Gods Existence

    Needless to say, Ockham rejects all of the alleged proofs of the existence of God. Two of

    the most important proofs then, as now, were Anselms ontological proof and Thomas

    Aquinass cosmological proof. Although the former is based on rationalist thinking and

    the latter is based on empiricist thinking, they boil down to very similar strategies, in

    Ockhams view. There were, of course, many different versions of each of these proofs

    circulating in Ockhams day just as there are today. Ockham thinks that the most

    plausible version of each boils down to an infinite regress argument of the following

    form:

    If God does not exist, then there is an infinite regress.

    But infinite regresses are impossible.

    Therefore, God must exist.

    The reason Ockham finds this argument form to be the most plausible is that he fully

    agrees with the second premise, that infinite regresses are impossible. If it were

    possible to show that Gods non-existence implied an infinite regress, then Ockham

    would accept the inference to his existence. Ockham denies, however, that Gods non -

    existence implies any such thing.

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    25/39

    In order to understand Ockhams aversion to infinite regress, it is necessary to

    understand Aristotles distinction between extensive and intensive infinity. An extensive

    infinity is an uncountable quantity of actually existing things. Mathematical Platonists

    conceive of the set of whole numbers as an extensive infinity. Ockham, however, deems

    the idea of an uncountable quantity contradictory: if the objects exist, then God can

    count them, and if God can count them, then they are not uncountable. An intensive

    infinity, on the other hand, is just a lack of limitation. As a nominalist, Ockham

    understands the set of whole numbers to be an intensive infinity in the sense that there

    is no upward limit on how far someone can count. This does not mean that the set of

    whole numbers are an uncountable quantity of actually existing things. Ockham thinks

    that infinite regresses are impossible only in so far as they imply extensive infinity.

    i. The Ontological Proof

    According to Ockham, advocates of the ontological proof reason as follows: There would

    be an infinite regress among entities if there were not one greatest entity. Therefore,

    there must be one greatest entity, namely God.

    One way to counter this reasoning would be to deny that greatness is an objectively

    existing quality. Ockham does not, however, take this approach. On the contrary, he

    seems to take the Great Chain of Being for granted. The Great Chain of Being is a

    doctrine prevalent throughout the Middle Ages and beyond. According to it, all of

    nature can be ranked on a hierarchy of value from top to bottom, roughly as follows:

    God, angels, humans, animals, plants, rocks. The Great Chain of Being implies that

    greatness is an objectively existing quality.

    Ockhams curt response to the ontological argument is that it does not prove that there

    is just one greatest entity. Bearing the Great Chain of Being in mind, it is evident what

    he means to say. If God and the angels do not exist, then human beings are the greatest

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    26/39

    entities, and there is no single best among us. Notice that, even if there were a single

    best among humans, he or she would be a god in a very different sense than is

    required by Catholic orthodoxy.

    Some scholars have interpreted Ockham to mean that the ontological argument

    succeeds in proving that the Father, the Son, and the Holy Ghost exist, but not that they

    are one. It is not clear, however, how Ockhams empiricism could permit such a

    conclusion.

    ii. The Cosmological Proof

    According to Ockham, advocates of the cosmological argument reason as follows: There

    would be an infinite regress among causes if there were not a first cause; therefore,

    there must be a first cause, namely, God.

    There are two different ways to understand cause in this argument: efficient cause

    and conserving cause. An efficient cause brings about an effect successively over time.

    For example, your grandparents were the efficient cause of your parents who were the

    efficient cause of you. A conserving cause, in contrast, is a simultaneous support for an

    effect. For example, the oxygen in the room is a conserving cause of the burning flame

    on the candle.

    In Ockhams view, the cosmological argument fails using either type of causality.

    Consider efficient causality first. If the chain of efficient causes that have produced the

    world as we know it today had no beginning, then it would form, not an extensive

    infinity, but an intensive infinity, which is harmless. Since the links in the chain would

    not all exist at the same time, they would not constitute an uncountable quantity of

    actually existing things. Rather, they would simply imply that the universe is an eternal

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    27/39

    cycle of unlimited or perpetual motion. Ockham explicitly affirms that it is possible that

    the world had no beginning, as Aristotle maintained.

    Next, consider conserving causality. Conceiving of the world as a product of

    simultaneous conserving causes is difficult. The idea is perhaps best expressed in a story

    reported by Stephen Hawking. According to the story, a scientist was giving a lecture on

    astronomy. After the lecture, an elderly lady came up and told the scientist that he had

    it all wrong. The world is really a flat plate supported on the back of a giant tortoise.

    The scientist asked And what is the turtle standing on? To which the lady triumphantly

    replied: Youre very clever, young man, but its no use its turtles all the way down.

    Ockham readily grants that if the world has to be held up by conserving causes, then

    there must be a first among them because otherwise the set of conserving causes would

    constitute an uncountable quantity of actually existing things. It is in fact a tenet of

    belief that God is both an efficient and conserving cause of the cosmos, and Ockham

    accepts this tenet on faith. He handily points out, however, that, just as the cosmos

    need not have a beginning; it need not be held up in this way at all. Each existing thing

    may be its own conserving cause. Hence the cosmological argument is entirely

    inconclusive.

    Ockhams fideism amounts to a refusal to rely on the God hypothesis for theory

    building. It is worth bearing in mind that there were no philosophy departments or

    philosophy degrees in the Middle Ages. A students only choices for graduate school

    were law, medicine, or theology. Wanting to be a philosopher, Ockham studied theology

    and ran through his theological exercises, all the while trying to carve out a separate

    space for philosophy. The one area where the two worlds collide inextricably for him is

    in ethics.

    7. Ethics

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    28/39

    a. Divine Command Theory

    Many people think God commands human beings to be kind because kindness is good

    and that God himself is always kind because his actions are always in conformity with

    goodness.

    Although this was and still is the most common way of conceiving of the relationship

    between God and morality, Ockham disagrees. In his view, God does not conform to an

    independently existing standard of goodness; rather, God himself is the standard of

    goodness. This means it is not the case that God commands us to be kind because

    kindness is good. Rather, kindness is good because God commands it. Ockham was a

    divine command theorist: Gods will establishes right and wrong.

    Divine command theory has always been unpopular because it carries one very

    unintuitive implication: if whatever God commands becomes right, and God can

    command whatever he wants, then God could command us always to be unkind and

    never to be kind, and then it would be right for us to be unkind and wrong for us to be

    kind. Kindness would be bad and unkindness would be good! How could this be?

    In Ockhams view, God always has commanded and always will command kindness.

    Nevertheless, it is possible for him to command otherwise. This possibility is a

    straightforward requirement of divine omnipotence: God can do anything that does not

    involve a contradiction. Of course, plenty of philosophers, such as Thomas Aquinas,

    insist that it is impossible for God to command us to be unkind simply because then

    Gods will would contradict his nature. For Ockham, however, this is the wrong way to

    conceive of Gods nature. The most important thing to understand about Gods nature,

    in Ockhams view, is that it is maximally free. There are no constraints, external or

    internal, to what God can will. All of theology stands or falls with this thesis in Ockhams

    view.

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    29/39

    Ockham grants that it is hard to imagine a world in which God reverses his commands.

    Yet this is the price of preserving divine freedom. He writes,

    I reply that hatred, theft, adultery, and the like may involve evil according to the

    common law, in so far as they are done by someone who is obligated by a divine

    command to perform the opposite act. As far as everything absolute in these actions is

    concerned, however, God can perform them without involving any evil. And they can

    even be performed meritoriously by someone on earth if they should fall under a divine

    command, just as now the opposite of these, in fact, fall under a divine command.

    [Opera Theologica V, p. 352]

    One advantage of this approach is that it enables Ockham to make sense of some

    instances in the Old Testament where it looks as though God is commanding such things

    as murder (as in the case of Abraham sacrificing Isaac) and deception (as in the case of

    the Israelites despoiling the Egyptians). But biblical exegesis is not Ockhams motive. His

    motive is to cast God as a paradigm of metaphysical freedom, so that he can make sense

    of human nature as made in his image.

    b. Metaphysical Libertarianism

    Metaphysical libertarianism is the view that human beings are responsible for their

    actions as individuals because they have free will, defined as the ability to do other than

    they do. Metaphysical libertarianism is opposed to determinism, according to which

    human beings do not have free will but rather are determined by antecedent conditions

    (such as God or nature or environmental factors) to do exactly what they do.

    Suppose Jake eats a cupcake. According to the determinist, antecedent conditions

    caused him to do this. Hence, he could not have done otherwise unless those

    antecedent conditions had been different. Given the same conditions, Jake cannot

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    30/39

    refrain from eating the cupcake. Determinists are content to conclude that freedom is

    an illusion.

    Compatibilism is a version of determinism according to which being determined to do

    exactly what we do is compatible with freedom as long as the antecedent conditions

    that determine what we do include our own choices. Compatibilists claim that the

    choices we make are free even though we could not do otherwise given the same

    antecedent conditions. On this view, Jake chose to eat the cupcake because his desire

    for it outweighed all other considerations at that moment. Our choices are always

    determined by our strongest desires according to compatibilists.

    Metaphysical libertarians reject determinism and compatibilism, insisting that free will

    includes the ability to act againstour strongest desires. On this view, Jake could have

    refrained from eating the cupcake even given the exact same antecedent conditions.

    While desires influence our choices they do not cause our choices according to

    metaphysical libertarianism; rather, our choices are caused by our will which is itself an

    uncaused cause, meaning that it is an independent power, stronger than any

    antecedent condition. This notion of free will enables the metaphysical libertarian to

    assign a very strong conception of individual responsibility to human beings: what we do

    is not attributable to God or nature or environmental factors.

    Many people make the assumption that all medieval philosophers were metaphysical

    libertarians. Whereas Protestant theology classically promotes theological determinism,

    the view that everything human beings do is foreordained by God, Catholic theology

    classically promotes the view that God gave human beings free will. While it is true that

    every medieval philosopher endorses the thesis that human beings are free, few are

    able to maintain a commitment to free will, defined as the ability to do other than we

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    31/39

    do given the same antecedent conditions. The reason is that so many other theological

    and philosophical doctrines conflict with it.

    Consider divine foreknowledge. If God is omniscient, then he knows everything that you

    are ever going to do. Suppose he knows that you will eat an apple for lunch tomorrow.

    How then is it possible for you to choose not to eat an apple for lunch tomorrow? Even

    if God does not force you in any way, it seems his present knowledge of your future

    requires that your choices are already determined.

    Medieval philosophers struggle with this and other conflicts with free will. Most give up

    on metaphysical libertarianism in favor of some form of compatibilism. This is to say

    they maintain that our choices are free even though they are determined by antecedent

    conditions.

    In his Sentences Commentary, Peter John Olivi makes a long and impassioned argument

    for an unadulterated metaphysical libertarian conception of free will. Ockham embraces

    Olivis position without ever making much of an argument for it. In Ockhams view, we

    experience freedom. We can no more dismiss this experience than we can dismiss our

    experience of the external world. Ockham goes to great lengths to adjust his account of

    divine foreknowledge and anything else that might otherwise threaten free will in order

    to accommodate it. He writes,

    The will is freely able to will something and not to will it. By this I mean that it is able to

    destroy the willing that it has and produce anew a contrary effect, or it is equally able in

    itself to continue that same effect and not produce a new one. It is able to do all of this

    without any prior change in the intellect, or in the will, or in something outside them.

    The idea is that the will is equal for producing and not producing because, with no

    difference in antecedent conditions, it is able to produce and not to produce. It is poised

    equally over contrary effects in such a way in fact, that it is able to cause love or hatred

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    32/39

    of something. To deny every agent this equal or contrary power is to destroy every

    praise and blame, every council and deliberation, every freedom of the will. Indeed,

    without it, the will would not make a human being free any more than appetite does an

    ass. [Opera Philosophica, pp. 319-21]

    Ockhams reference to an ass here is significant in connection with the famous thought

    experiment known as Buridans Ass.

    Jean Buridan was a younger contemporary of Ockhams. Although he embraced and

    elaborated Ockhams nominalism, he openly rejected metaphysical libertarianism,

    arguing that the human intellect determines the human will. He may have engaged in a

    public debate with Ockham over the nature of human freedom. At any rate, his name

    somehow became associated with the following thought experiment.

    Imagine a hungry donkey poised between two equally delicious piles of hay. The donkey

    has reason to eat the hay, but because he caught sight of both piles at the same time,

    he has no more reason to approach one pile than the other. For lack of any way to break

    the tie, the donkey starves to death. A human being, in contrast, would never make

    such an ass of himself. The reason is that, in human beings, the will is not determined by

    the intellect. Free will is the uniquely human dignity that enables us to break the tie

    between two equally reasonable options.

    The French philosopher Pierre Bale (1647-1706) is the first on record to call this thought

    experiment Buridans Ass. Although Buridan mentions the case of a dog poised

    between food and water, he never discusses the case of the donkey in connection with

    freedom. It is therefore somewhat of a puzzle why the thought experiment is named

    after him. Interestingly, Peter John Olivi does discuss the case of the donkey in

    connection with freedom, and we see Ockham echoing that text here.

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    33/39

    So, in the end, Ockhams ethics is dictated by his empiricism. We experience free will.

    Therefore, free will is at the core of human nature. Theology tells us that we are made

    in Gods image. Therefore, free will is at the core of Gods nature. But theology also tells

    us that God is always good. Therefore, Gods free will must be the objective

    determinant of goodness.

    Setting aside his divine command theory, Ockhams ethics is rather unremarkable,

    coming to more or less the same thing as that of his colleagues who reject divine

    command theory. One might think Ockham takes a long way around the barn just to

    arrive at yet another conventional account of Christian virtue! But Ockham never minds

    taking the long way around for the sake of consistency. We see the same unflagging

    determination in his political theory

    8. Political Theory

    Although Ockham was summoned to the papal court in Avignon to defend a number of

    suspect theses extracted from his work, largely concerning the sacrament of the altar,

    he was never found guilty of heresy, and his conflict with the papacy ultimately had

    nothing to do with the sacrament of the altar. While staying in Avignon, Ockham met

    Michael Cesena (1270-1342), the Minister General of the Franciscan Order, who was

    there in protest of the Popes recent pronouncements about the Franciscan vow of

    poverty. Michael asked Ockham to study these pronouncements, whereupon Ockham

    joined the protest and soon became irretrievably entangled in a political imbroglio.

    Leaving academia behind for good, he nevertheless marshaled his central philosophical

    insights into the debate. While Ockham was not allowed to publish his political treatises,

    they circulated widely underground, indirectly influencing major developments in

    political thought.

    a. Rights

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    34/39

    Who would have guessed that at the root of these developments lay the Franciscan vow

    of poverty? In Matthew 19, Jesus says to a man, If you wish to be perfect, go, sell all

    you have, give your money to the poor, and come, and follow me. The man who was to

    become St. Francis of Assisi (1182-1226) took these instructions personally. Raised in a

    wealthy family, St. Francis gave up the worldly life, founding the Order of the Friar

    Minor, and requiring all its members to take a vow of poverty. From the very beginning

    there was controversy over what exactly this vow entailed. By the 1320s, various

    factions had come to the breaking point.

    Michael Cesena promoted the radical interpretation, according to which Franciscans

    should not only live simply but also own nothing, not even the robes on their backs.

    Pope Nicholas III (1210/1220-1280) had sanctioned this interpretation by arranging for

    the papacy officially to possess everything that the Franciscans used, including the very

    food they ate. Living in absolute poverty enabled the Franciscans to preach convincingly

    against avarice, and, much to the chagrin of Pope John XXII (1244-1334), raise questions

    about the ever-expanding papal palace in Avignon.

    John was determined to amass great wealth for the church and the Franciscan vow of

    poverty was getting in the way. Trained as a lawyer, John worked up a good argument

    for revoking Nicholass arrangement. Given that the Franciscans enjoyed exclusive use

    of the donations they received, they were the de facto owners. Papal ownership of

    Franciscan property was ownership in name alone.

    As a nominalist, however, Ockham was in an excellent position to show why reducing

    something to a name is not the same as reducing it to nothing at all. A name is a mental

    concept, and a mental concept is an intention. Ockham set out to show that the

    intention to use is distinct from the intention to own.

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    35/39

    Ockham derives his definition of ownership from metaphysical libertarianism.

    Ownership is not just a conventional relationship established through social agreement.

    It is a natural relationship that arises through the act of making something of your own

    free will. Free will naturally confers ownership because it implies sole responsibility.

    Suppose you freely make a choice. Since you could have done otherwise, you are the

    true cause of the result. To own something is to do what you will with it.

    The Franciscans do not do as they will with the donations given to them, according to

    Ockham, but rather as the owner wills. They are therefore merely using the donations

    and do not own them. Granted, in normal practice, this distinction may be entirely

    undetectable, because the will of the owner matches that of the user. But if a conflict of

    wills should arise, the distinction would become readily apparent. Suppose someone

    donates some cloth to the Order intending it to be used for robes. The friars must use it

    for robes even if they would rather use it for something else. And if the donor wants the

    cloth back even after it is made into robes, the friars will have no basis for refusing and

    no legal recourse. Ockham puts the crucial point in terms of crucial language: the owner

    retains a right (ius) to what he owns.

    The notion of a right is one of the most important features of modern political theory.

    Its emergence in the history of Western thought is a long and complicated story.

    Nevertheless, the Franciscan poverty debate is standardly considered an important

    watershed, in which Ockham played a significant role.

    b. Separation of Church and State

    Ockham extends his commitment to poverty beyond just the Franciscan order,

    convinced that wealth is an inappropriate source of power for the Catholic Church as a

    whole. In his view, the Catholic Church has a spiritual power which sets it apart from the

    secular world. This conviction leads Ockham to propose the doctrine that was to

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    36/39

    become the foundation of the United States Constitution: separation of church and

    state.

    Throughout the Middle Ages, popes and emperors vied for supremacy across Europe.

    The political momentum was split in two directions and it was not at all clear which way

    things would go. One side pushed for hierocracy, where the pope, as the highest

    authority, appoints the emperor. The other side pushed for imperialism, where the

    emperor, as the highest authority, appoints the pope. Often the pushing came to

    shoving; it seemed there would be no end to the ill will and bloodshed.

    Ockham boldly proposes a third alternative: the pope and the emperor should be

    separate but equal, each supreme in his own domain. This was an outrageous

    suggestion, unwelcome on both sides. Ockhams argument for it stems from reflections

    that foreshadow the state of nature thought experiments of premier modern political

    theorists Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679), John Locke (1632-1704) and Jean-Jacques

    Rousseau (1712-1778).

    In the Garden of Eden, God gave the earth to human beings to use to their common

    benefit. As long as we were willing to share there was no need for property among us.

    After the fall, however, human beings became selfish and exploitative. Laws became

    necessary to restrain immoderate appetite for secular or temporal goods and to

    prevent the neglect of their management. Since laws are useless without the ability to

    enforce them, we arrived at the need for secular power. The function of the secular

    power is to punish law breakers and in general coerce everyone into obeying the law.

    By renouncing property, the Franciscans were attempting to live as God originally

    intended. In a perfect world, there would be no need for property and the coercive

    authority it spawns. All Christians should aspire to this anarchic utopia, even though

    http://www.iep.utm.edu/hobmoralhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/lockehttp://www.iep.utm.edu/rousseauhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/rousseauhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/rousseauhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/rousseauhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/lockehttp://www.iep.utm.edu/hobmoral
  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    37/39

    they may never fully achieve it. In the meanwhile, they should avoid mixing the spiritual

    and the secular as much as possible. Ockham writes,

    For this reason, the head of Christians does not, as a rule, have power to punish secular

    wrongs with a capital penalty and other bodily penalties and it is for thus punishing such

    wrongs that temporal power and riches are chiefly necessary; such punishment is

    granted chiefly to the secular power. The pope therefore, can, as a rule, correct

    wrongdoers only with a spiritual penalty. It is not, therefore, necessary that he should

    excel in temporal power or abound in temporal riches, but it is enough that Christians

    should willingly obey him. [A Letter to the Friars Minor and other Writings, p. 204]

    For Ockham, the separation of church and state is a separation of the ideal and the real.

    Ockham mentions democracy only in passing, arguing in favor of monarchy as the best

    form of secular government. Moreover, he finds representational forms of government

    objectionable on the grounds that there is no such thing as a common will. Ockham is

    not holding out for a superhuman leader. On the contrary, he seems to think that a

    fairly ordinary, good man can make a decent king. One wonders if Louis of Bavaria, to

    whose protection he and Michael fled, inspired this confidence. Perhaps Ockham is

    content with monarchy because, in his view, the secular world will always be

    intrinsically flawed. He sets his hopes instead on the spiritual world, and this is why he

    was so bitterly disappointed in Pope John XXII.

    c. Freedom of Speech

    Ockhams battle with the papacy continued after Johns death through two successive

    popes. Although Ockham never came to criticize the institution of the papacy itself, as

    would later Protestant thinkers, he did accuse the popes he opposed of heresy and

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    38/39

    called for their expulsion. Ironically, Ockhams extensive analysis of the concept of

    heresy turns into a defense of free speech.

    In keeping with his doctrine of the separation of church and state, Ockham maintains

    that the pope, and only the pope, has the right to level spiritual penalties, and only

    spiritual penalties, against someone who knowingly asserts theological falsehoods and

    refuses to be corrected. A man might unknowingly assert a theological falsehood a

    thousand times, however. As long as he is willing to be corrected, he should not be

    judged a heretic, especially by the pope.

    Ockhams political treatises are strewn with biblical exegesis, often glaringly ad hoc and

    sometimes quite interesting, as in the present case. In Matthew 28:20 Jesus promises

    his disciples: I will be with you always, to the end of the age. This text traditionally

    provided justification for the doctrine of papal infallibility according to which the pope

    cannot be wrong when speaking about official church matters. Ockham rejects this

    doctrine, however, arguing that the minimum required for Jesus to keep his promise is

    that one human being remain faithful at any given time, and this one could be anyone,

    even a single baptized infant. This implies that the entire institution of the church could

    become completely corrupt. As a result, any theological claim, no matter how ancient or

    universally accepted, is always open for dispute.

    Even more interesting, however, is Ockhams view of non-theological speech. He writes

    that

    purely philosophical assertions which do not pertain to theology should not be

    solemnly condemned or forbidden by anyone, because in connection with such

    assertions anyone at all ought to be free to say freely what pleases him, [ Dialogus,

    I.2.22]

  • 7/31/2019 William of Ockham-Encyclopedia

    39/39

    This statement long predates the Areopagitica of John Milton (1608-1674), which is

    typically heralded as the earliest defense of free speech in Western history.

    Ockhams contributions in political thought are less known and appreciated than they

    may have been if he had been able to publish them. Likewise, there is no telling what he

    might have accomplished in philosophy if he had been allowed to carry on with his

    academic career. Ockham was ahead of his time. His role in history was to make way for

    new ideas, boldly planting seeds that grew and flourished after his death.