TWO TYPES of EXTERNALISM_Wittgenstein_The Philosophical Quarterly-1997-Rudd-501-7

download TWO TYPES of EXTERNALISM_Wittgenstein_The Philosophical Quarterly-1997-Rudd-501-7

of 7

Transcript of TWO TYPES of EXTERNALISM_Wittgenstein_The Philosophical Quarterly-1997-Rudd-501-7

  • 8/13/2019 TWO TYPES of EXTERNALISM_Wittgenstein_The Philosophical Quarterly-1997-Rudd-501-7

    1/7

    TWO TYPES OF EXTERNALISM

    BAR

    Externalism I take to be the doctrine that the mind is not self-contained that inorder to understand our mental states, essential reference has to be made to facts

    about the social and/or physical environment in which we are situated. In this paperI am concerned with the relation between two kinds of externalism. The first takes

    its inspiration from Putnams arguments in The Meaning of Meaning,1while thesecond is based on arguments from Wittgenstein. What I want to consider here is

    how these two types of externalism relate to each other. Do they fit together to forma single coherent line of thought? Are they distinct but compatible? Or do they

    contradict each other? I shall be considering these issues with reference to GregoryMcCullochs recent book The Mind and its World(London: Routledge, ), which isan attempt to show that the two forms of externalism can be integrated within theframework of a strong metaphysical realism. I aim to show that this cannot be done.

    The Wittgensteinian argument for externalism can be put like this.2To under-stand a word is not to have any special subjective feeling about it. For a start, we

    usually do not have any such feelings; but even if we did, they could not in them-selves constitute understanding. The criterion for understanding a word is the ability

    to use it correctly; people who could not do that would not count as having under-stood the word, whatever subjective feelings of confidence they may have had about

    it. The conclusion is externalist in this sense: understanding is something that ismanifested in practice, in using words appropriately in contexts. So the understand-

    ing cannot be said to exist apart from the contexts in which the words are used. Thisis what the slogan Meaning is use (PI) comes down to. It is not a theory aboutwhat meaning essentially is; it is a reminder to us of the ways in which we ascribe

    mastery of a concept to a person. I shall not attempt to defend this view at anylength; rather, assuming its validity, I shall try to clarify some of its implications,

    especially for the Putnamian externalism with which McCulloch wants to integrate

    it.The arguments for Putnamian externalism are also familiar. They concern the

    ways in which we understand substance (or natural-kind) words. According to

    Putnam, we intend such words to apply to whatever things (or stuff) have the samenature as the examples pointed out to us when we learn the words. For Putnam, it is

    up to science to investigate what that nature is, so that, even if stuffvery different in

    The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly,

    1In his Mind, Language and Reality: Philosophical Papers, Vol. (Cambridge UP, ),pp. .

    2See Philosophical Investigations, trans. G.E.M. Anscombe (Oxford: Blackwell, , hereafterPI), .

    TWO TYPES OF EXTERNALISM

    byguestonJanuary9,2014

    http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/

    Downloadedfrom

    http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/
  • 8/13/2019 TWO TYPES of EXTERNALISM_Wittgenstein_The Philosophical Quarterly-1997-Rudd-501-7

    2/7

    appearance from our stereotypes of water turned out to have the same internal

    structure, it would count as water. Or vice versa; hence the Twin Earth thought-experiment. Even if XYZ on Twin Earth were phenomenally indistinguishable

    from water, it still would not be water; that privilege is reserved for H2O. And thisgenerates the externalism: even if my Twin Earth counterpart was physically and in

    terms of subjective psychological states indistinguishable from me, he would still notbe in the same state of mind as me when we both think I would like some water.

    His thought is about XYZ, mine is about H2O. So the contents of my mental states

    are determined by the way the world is, not just by how things are with me.Is it possible to make these two arguments harmonize? This may depend on how

    we interpret Putnamian externalism, for it can be taken in either of two ways. Thereis an ambitious metaphysical interpretation, according to which we should try to

    make our classifications correspond to the real, mind-independent structure of theworld to the way in which the world classifies itself, as it were. It might seem that,

    since he accepts a basically Wittgensteinian account of understanding,3McCulloch

    would wish to avoid this strongly metaphysical position. A more modest interpreta-tion of the Putnamian view would make it an empirical claim about our practices, aclaim to the effect that our scientific interests take precedence over all our other

    interests in determining how we classify things. For a Wittgensteinian, this claimmight at least seem to have the merit of being intelligible, even if not very plausible.

    Putnam himself made it clear, in some of his writings subsequent to The Meaningof Meaning, that he wanted his argument understood in this modest way, and

    has tried to distinguish this stance from Kripkes metaphysically more ambitiousproject. This is of some importance, since shortly after publishing The Meaning of

    Meaning Putnam abandoned his metaphysical realism for a much more Wittgen-

    steinian position. But he seems for some time after this to have been keen tomaintain that his version of externalism, given a suitably modest interpretation, cansurvive the transposition.4 More recently, however, he appears to have effectively

    abandoned Putnamian externalism altogether.5I shall say a little more about thislater in the paper.

    The Wittgensteinian argument appeals to our having a form of life in which we

    interact with our surroundings and with one another. It is within this network ofpractices that we use language and understand one another. So understanding

    depends on use within a form of life. Now, according to McCulloch (p. ), whatPutnam has shown is that the understanding tracks real essence. He therefore

    recognizes that in order to make the Putnamian considerations dovetail with theWittgensteinian argument, he needs an interpretation that construes use, form

    of life, and so on, so that they too track real essence (ibid.). That is, he needs toshow that our concern in using substance words is primarily to keep track of what

    stuffs have the same essential characters as are recognized by science, rather than by

    The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly,

    3The Mind and its Worldch. .4See his Reason, Truth and History (Cambridge UP, ), pp. , and Is Water

    Necessarily H2O?, in his Realism With a Human Face(Harvard UP, ), pp. .5See the later Aristotle after Wittgenstein, in his Words and Life(Harvard UP, ), esp.

    pp. .

    ANTHONY RUDD

    byguestonJanuary9,2014

    http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/

    Downloadedfrom

    http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/
  • 8/13/2019 TWO TYPES of EXTERNALISM_Wittgenstein_The Philosophical Quarterly-1997-Rudd-501-7

    3/7

    everyday experience. Now the Wittgensteinian point was that the meanings of our

    words depend on the contexts in which we use them and the purposes for which we

    use them. (Which is not a reductive definition of meaning, since our purposes and

    social contexts themselves presuppose our being language-users.) And since we have

    many different purposes, engage in many different language-games, different

    systems of classification will emerge from these different contexts. In so far as we cantalk about their being justified at all, it is their practical usefulness which justifies the

    classifications that we make. And, of course, what is useful in one context may be

    inconvenient or unworkable in another. For instance,

    The distinction between rabbits and hares is ... from most biological perspectives ...

    trivial to the point of invisibility. It is, nevertheless, one that is commonly drawn by

    experts neither technically scientific, nor scientifically technical, such as farmers,

    hunters and amateur naturalists.6

    If we are asked whether hares and rabbits are really different or not, then we

    would have to answer that it depends on the purposes that the questioner has inmind. On this view, whether or not two things belong to the same class will depend

    on what classification we are using, which in turn depends on the interest that we

    have in the things. How then can we suppose that our form of life can be said to

    track real essence? If by real essence we just mean what science says a thing is,

    then of course we can say that our scientific forms of life do attempt to track real

    essence. But this is just to state the platitude that science pursues scientific interests,

    and nothing of philosophical importance follows from that. Our other forms of life

    are clearly not concerned to track real essence in this sense. If, on the other hand,

    we take real essence to refer to the way things are in themselves, apart from any

    human system of classifications, then we would be reverting to the strong meta-physical interpretation of Putnam a position that can hardly be reconciled with

    McCullochs supposedly Wittgensteinian stance.

    With this in mind, let us return to the Putnamian argument for externalism. The

    idea was that when I and my Twin Earth Doppelgngerboth think, in perceptually

    identical situations, This is water, or I want a drink of water, we are thinking

    different thoughts, because the objects of those thoughts are different substances.

    But this seems metaphysical that is, it seems to presuppose that we can make

    judgements about the sameness or difference of thoughts in abstraction from any

    context that could give a point to making such judgements. McCulloch has a

    Doppelgngerexample involving Liz1and Liz2. He imagines that they are switched un-knowingly from Earth to Twin Earth and vice versa. He claims that the switched Liz1,

    now on Twin Earth, would be labouring under misconceptions; asking for water

    ( =H2O) she wrongly thinks she gets what she wants on being handed a glass of

    XYZ (p. ). But the glass of XYZ iswhat she wants which is some of that clear

    tasteless liquid that will quench her thirst. What misconception is she under?

    That what she gets is H2O? But the point of making Liz1the Doppelgngerof Liz2 is

    The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly,

    6J. Dupr, The Disorder of Things: Metaphysical Foundations of the Disunity of Science (HarvardUP, ), p. .

    TWO TYPES OF EXTERNALISM

    byguestonJanuary9,2014

    http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/

    Downloadedfrom

    http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/
  • 8/13/2019 TWO TYPES of EXTERNALISM_Wittgenstein_The Philosophical Quarterly-1997-Rudd-501-7

    4/7

    that neither knows anything about the chemical composition of water, so Liz1does

    not know that water isH2O. Or is the misconception that what she asks for is thesame stuffas she had before (when on Earth)? But that is what she gets for her

    purposes (drinking it), it is the same stuff. Different language-games throw up differ-ent systems of classification, and there is no need to suppose that they can always be

    mapped neatly on to one another. If Liz1were a chemist wanting to do an analysisof the sample of water, then it would matter to her whether it is H2O or XYZ.

    Since she just wants to drink it, it does not matter. For purposes of drinking it isthesame stuff. For purposes of chemical analysis it is not. Yes, but is it just the samestuff? Outside any context, outside any language-game within which there would bea point to asking it, that question has no clear sense. Equally, there is no clear sensein asking whether Liz1and Liz2, prior to the switch, have the same thought when

    they think about water. If this is right, Putnamian externalism itself is not a doc-trine with any clear sense.

    Putnamian externalism has of course, been criticized along similar lines before.

    For instance, Laird Addis argues that if my Doppelgngerand I share a purely phen-omenal concept of water, then the extension of that concept will also be the same forboth of us it will consist of everything of whatever chemical composition [which]

    is a clear, odourless liquid that would quench my thirst.7So we are not forced todescribe the situation in the way Putnam requires, as one in which we have the same

    (subjective) concept, but different extensions. A Putnamian might reply that thismisses the point: purely phenomenal concepts are inadequate because they are not

    sensitive to differences in real essence. But if this response is meant to be a meta-physical one, it would not be available to a Wittgensteinian. The Wittgensteinian

    point is that judgements of sameness and difference can only be made within

    language-games; accordingly, one cannot insist that our concepts be answerable towhat are supposed to be real differences and samenesses existing outside ourclassificatory practices.

    This takes us back to the modest, non-metaphysical interpretation of Putnam.According to this, if we did say that Twin Earth water was a different substance

    from our water, it would not be on the basis of a metaphysical insight into what it

    really was, from Gods perspective, as it were. It would have to be on the basis ofarguing that we do in practice accept scientific classifications as trumping everyday

    ones, and that it is therefore by reference to them that we can make judgementsabout what is reallythe same and reallydifferent. However, as is shown by the rabbit/

    hare example, and in general by the fact that, as Paul Churchland laments,8we havenot come to replace our folk-physics with scientific physics in everyday life, this

    seems just false as an empirical claim about what our classificatory practices are. Wedo not in fact think that science trumps everything else. And it is not at all clear why

    anyone should suppose that it ought to do so, unless relying on the strong, meta-physical view that science is our attempt to mirror the way in which Nature classifies

    itself. In which case the weak empirical interpretation of Putnam collapses back intothe strong metaphysical one.

    The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly,

    7L. Addis,Natural Signs: a Theory of Intentionality(Temple UP, ), p. .8See his Scientific Realism and the Plasticity of Mind(Cambridge UP, ), esp. ch. .

    ANTHONY RUDD

    byguestonJanuary9,2014

    http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/

    Downloadedfrom

    http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/
  • 8/13/2019 TWO TYPES of EXTERNALISM_Wittgenstein_The Philosophical Quarterly-1997-Rudd-501-7

    5/7

    Putnam himself has come to accept that we should distinguish ordinary ques-

    tions of substance-identity from scientific questions, and that, therefore, there is noneed to make an issue about the logical possibility of water not being H2O. If you

    have a hypothetical situation you want to describe that way, describe it that way.9

    He has, however, still wanted to insist that

    a community can stipulate that water is to designate whatever has the same chemicalstructureor whatever has the same chemical behaviouras paradigms X, Y, Z ... even if it doesnt

    know, at the time it makes this stipulation,exactly what that chemical structure, or exactly what that

    lawful behaviouris.10

    But it is hard to imagine why anyone should disagree with this, or why it shouldbe supposed to have philosophically interesting consequences. Presumably a com-

    munity can stipulate whatever it wants to, and scientific communities do no doubtsometimes behave in this way. (Of course, such stipulations may or may not pay off

    in their own terms the various phenomena identified as paradigms may turn out to

    have no chemically interesting properties in common.) But there is no reason to sup-pose that these practices of the scientific community should be normative for the restof us, or should determine the meaning of meaning.

    Nor, for that matter, need there be any single system of classification shared byscientists who have different interests. Science, after all, is not a single monolithicentity, to be contrasted with an equally monolithic (and equally mythological)common sense, so there is no reason why different scientific practices should not

    establish different classifications, none of which can be said to be the right one inan absolute sense. This point is indeed made by Putnam himself in a paper more

    recent than the one I quoted from in the last paragraph. Considering whether we

    should say that it is part of the essence of dogs that they are descended from wolves,he points out that this is indeed the case for an evolutionary biologist, for whomspecies are essentially historical entities, very much like nations, but not for a

    molecular biologist, for whom animals are viewed simply as finished products.11

    For the latter, having a certain kind of DNA is an essential property of a dog, and

    Putnam creates a thought-experiment in which a synthetic dog is created in a

    laboratory, with the right DNA but not, of course, descended from wolves. Would itbe a real dog? There is no single correct answer to the question. It would be a real

    dog from one point of view, not from another. And of course, we also have other,completely non-scientific interests in dogs. And from these perspectives, neither of

    the scientific properties mentioned above is essential.

    ... to tell me [simply as a dog owner] that I dont know the nature of dogs if I dont

    know they are descended from wolves ... is nonsense. And of course, millions of

    people know and have known a good deal about the nature of dogs without having

    any idea that there is such a thing as DNA.12

    The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly,

    9Is Water Necessarily H2O? pp. .10Is Water Necessarily H2O? p. , italics original.11Aristotle after Wittgenstein pp. , .12Aristotle after Wittgenstein p. .

    TWO TYPES OF EXTERNALISM

    byguestonJanuary9,2014

    http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/

    Downloadedfrom

    http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/
  • 8/13/2019 TWO TYPES of EXTERNALISM_Wittgenstein_The Philosophical Quarterly-1997-Rudd-501-7

    6/7

    In making these points Putnam seems to be abandoning Putnamian externalism

    altogether. However, McCulloch, who does not refer to any of these later writings

    by Putnam in his book, is still determined to defend that doctrine. He is sensitive to

    the charge that it involves implausibly over-rating the importance of scientific

    considerations in determining our classificatory practices; but his response to this is

    to move away from the modest, non-metaphysical, priority-of-science interpretationaltogether. Accordingly he argues (p. ) that Putnamian externalism need not de-

    pend on an over-reverential attitude to science, as opposed to ordinary experience,

    but just involves the realist assumption that something could, possibly, impinge on

    our awareness in normal conditions in exactly the same way as water yet still fail to

    be water. But by taking this line he seems to be openly reverting to the strong

    metaphysical interpretation of Putnam, not simply contrasting scientific and every-

    day practices, but trying to draw a contrast between all our practices on the one

    hand and the way things are in themselves on the other.

    It seems clear that this distinction cannot be drawn on the Wittgensteinian

    premises which McCulloch himself wants to maintain. For, if understanding must bemanifestable in practice, how could we manifest our grasp of what is supposed to

    be the reality of things in themselves, as opposed to the ways in which they might impinge on

    us? And even if we could make sense of such a metaphysical realism, why should itmatter to us? Why should we take an interest in what water really is, as opposed to

    the way it seems to us as it impinges on our experience? If the stuffis to play some

    role in our form of life (if it does not, we would have no motive for wanting to

    include it in our classifications anyway) then it will do so in virtue of the ways it

    impinges on us. McCulloch claims (ibid.) that to deny the possibility set out in the

    quotation above is to embrace a very forthright form of idealism. But this will only

    seem the case to someone whose thinking moves within the metaphysical frameworkwherein one must be either an idealist or a realist. In the non-metaphysical sense,

    Wittgenstein is thoroughly realist, for he insists that our thought and language

    emerge from the practical need to engage with the world in which we find ourselves.

    But this is not the metaphysical realism that sees the task of thought as the mirroring

    of the structure of the world as it is in itself.

    The Wittgensteinian view that meaning must be manifestable in use not only

    establishes a kind of externalism (my understanding something is not a private

    mental act but an ability to participate in a practice); it also demonstrates the vacuity

    of metaphysical realism. For the way the world is in itself, considered as something

    distinct from the way it does or may impinge on us, is something that is irrelevant to

    our practices. On the Wittgensteinian view, the mind is not self-contained, but

    neither is the world; the world which has to be taken into account in determining

    mental content is the world as it impinges on us. The point of Putnamian extern-

    alism is that the contents of our thoughts depend on the way the world is, quite

    apart from whether or not we know it. Which is why two Doppelgngerare supposedto think different thoughts when they both think This is water, even if they do not

    know and will never learn anything about the chemical composition of water. For a

    Wittgensteinian, however, the question of whether their thoughts are reallydifferent

    The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly,

    ANTHONY RUDD

    byguestonJanuary9,2014

    http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/

    Downloadedfrom

    http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/
  • 8/13/2019 TWO TYPES of EXTERNALISM_Wittgenstein_The Philosophical Quarterly-1997-Rudd-501-7

    7/7

    is an entirely empty one. We can say what we like here, but nothing of metaphysical

    significance will follow.13

    University of Bristol

    The Editors of The Philosophical Quarterly,

    13I am grateful to Carlos Fane and Ross Cogan for their helpful comments on drafts ofthis paper.

    TWO TYPES OF EXTERNALISM

    byguestonJanuary9,2014

    http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/

    Downloadedfrom

    http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/http://pq.oxfordjournals.org/