Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still...

109
STUDIES IN ISLAMIC PHILOSOPHY AND SCIENCE Published under the auspices of the Society for the Study of Islamic Philosophy and Science EDITORIAL BOARD George F. Hourani, State University of New 'York at Buffalo Muhsin Mahdi, Harvard University Parviz Morewedge, Baruch College of City University of New 'York Nicholas Rescher, University of Pittsburgh Ehsan Yar-Shater, Columbia University Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle's" Topics J" "Rhetoric J" and ((Poetics" Edited and Translated by Charles E. Butterworth ALBANY STATE UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK PRESS 1977

Transcript of Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still...

Page 1: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

STUDIES IN ISLAMIC PHILOSOPHY AND SCIENCE

Published under the auspices ofthe Society for the Study of Islamic Philosophy and Science

EDITORIAL BOARD

George F. Hourani, State Universityof New 'York at Buffalo

Muhsin Mahdi, Harvard University

Parviz Morewedge, Baruch Collegeof City University of New 'York

Nicholas Rescher, University of Pittsburgh

Ehsan Yar-Shater, Columbia University

~verroes'

Three Short Commentaries

on Aristotle's" TopicsJ" "RhetoricJ"

and ((Poetics"

Edited and Translated by

Charles E. Butterworth

ALBANY

STATE UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK PRESS

1977

Page 2: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

)

Lj CJ

~3~

~CC'1crll

UNESCO COLLECTION OF REPRESENTATIVE WORKSARABIC SERIES

This bookhas been accepted

in the Arabic Seriesof the Translations Collection

of the United NationsEducational, Scientific and Cultural Organization

(UNESCO)

First Edition

Published by State University of New York Press99 Washington Avenue, Albany, New York 12246

© 1977 State University of New York

All rights reserved

Printed in the United States of America

Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data

Averroes, II 26-1I 98.Averroes' three short commentaries on Aristotle's

"Topics," "Rhetoric," and "Poetics."

(Studies in Islamic Philosophy and Science)Arabic and English.

Includes bibliographical references and index.l. Aristoteles. Organon. 2. Logic-Early works to 1800.

I. Butterworth, Charles E.II. Title. III. Series.

B749.A35B87 160 75-4900ISBN 0-87395-208-1

r

iII

II

III

I

To My Wife

Page 3: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

PREFACE

THERE WAS A TIME when Dante could be certain that even an obliquereference to Averroes would be immediately understood by any of hisreaders. Indeed, over the course of several centuries, fierce debateraged around the philosophy of Averroes: he was either extolled asthe foremost interpreter of Aristotle or vilified as the gravest menaceto Christian faith. Schools devoted to the study and propagation ofhis commentaries on Aristotle flourished, while others zealouslycommitted to combatting the teachings of those commentaries hadequal success. Today, mention ofhis name evokes no passions, promptsno discussions; rather, reference to Averroes is usually met withquerulous stares. Even in learned circles, little is known about theman and still less about his teachings.

The contemporary neglect of Averroes can be traced to the veryreason for his celebrity during the Middle Ages: his reputation as thecommentator on Aristotle. Today, few people are interested in eitherAristotle or commentary. Philosophic study having been reduced toscientific method or general culture, the passion for serious discussionabout perennial problems has waned. Thus knowledge of, muchless interest in, the problems raised by Aristotle is slight, and desirefor acquaintance with the momentous debates those problems haveoccasioned nil. Moreover, with the spread of the assumption that allthings evolve through time, inventiveness has come to be a,cclaimed themark ofexcellent thought and commentary condemned as imitative orservile. Consequently, Averroes has beenjudged as neither meriting animportant place in the history of philosophy nor deserving particularstudy.

E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are littleinclin.ed to study the commentaries by Averroes. They seem to considerthe recovery <>fthe Greek manuscripts as having diminished the signi­ficancEOfthosecommentiiries. In their eyes, Averroes performed the

vii

Page 4: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

viii PREFACE PREFACE ix

historical function of preserving Aristotle's thought until the sources

could be recovered, but his importance goes no further. As a result,

Aver~oes h~s become a figure of mild curiosity, a thinker to be studied

by onentahsts or backward looking scholastics.

For many reasons, the contemporary neglect of Averroes is unfortu­

nate. Like Aristotle, Averroes addressed himself to theoretical and

pr~c~ical q~estions of concern to human beings in all ages. As long

as It IS possIble to wonder about the origin of the world or the basis of

political justice, serious minds can delight in careful consideration

of ~stotle's ideas and in Averroes'sinterpretative presentation of

~hose Id~as. To such minds his use of the commentary can be especially

I~structIve, for the art of commenting was completely transformed in

hIS hands. Far from a servile imitation or literal repetition, Averroes

presented a unique interpretation ofAristotle's ideas under the guise of

a commentary. Indeed, an attentive reading of Averroes's commen­

taries with the texts of Aristotle shows that arguments Aristotle had

made are often omitted, notions foreign to his thought sometimes

added, and on occasion arguments even invented in his name.

Hence the recovery of the Greek manuscripts does not render

Averroes's commentaries obsolete. On the contrary, their recovery

makes the study of those commentaries immensely more fascinating.

As the thought of Aristotle is laid bare and compared with the in­

terpre~ationpres~ntedby Averroes, new questions about the meaning

of the mterpretatIOn, as well as about the significance of the distortion

arise: At ~hat point the reader can begin to appreciate the special

relatIOnshIp between the scholarly task of uncovering the thought of

someone else and the philosophic task of making that thought one's

own. Once Averroes's use of the commentary acquires this kind of

problematic significance, his reputation as the commentator on

Aristotle can again occasion serious reflection.

T~e treatises presented here are especially helpful for reassessing

t~e Imp~rtance of Averro.es. Nowhere has he been so audaciously

hberal. With the te~t of ArIstotle as in these treatises or in the larger

collectIOn from WhICh they are taken. That larger collection has long

been presumed to represent Averroes's Short Commentary on Aristotle's

Organon. It does represent that short commentary, but a short commen­

tary which transforms the Organon by adding a non-Aristotelian

treatise, as well as Aristotelian treatises not belonging to what is

usually understood to be the Organon, and by changing the order of

I

II,

the treatises in the Organon. More importantly, the treatises presented

here-which are short commentaries on individual treatises of the

extended Organon-4)ffer exciting interpretations and provocative

applications ofAristotle's teaching. Consideration of the logical arts

appears to be little more than a veil from behind which Averroes

evoked the problematic relation between philosophic thought, religious

belief, and political conviction. Even the horizons of time and culture

peculiar to the discussion serve only as reminders of how unlimited

the discussion really is.

It is especially pleasant to be able to express my gratitude to all

those who have given so generously of their time and learning and thus

facilitated my work on this book, as well as to acknowledge those

institutions which have provided material aid.

Without the help of Norman Golb, I would never have been able

to undertake this project; he gave unstintingly of his time and learning

to teach me how to decipher Judaeo-Arabic manuscripts. Lawrence

Marwick and William C. Williams helped me prepare the Hebrew

part of the critical apparatus. George N. Atiyeh offered valuable

criticism ofthe Arabic text. If! have a severe but judicious Aristarchus,

it must be Miriam Galston; she offered excellent criticism of the

finished text and invaluable advice about how to translate technical

Arabic into smooth English. Above all, the final presentation of the

book owes much to the careful eye and agile mind of Muhsin Mahdi

and to his sound advice at each stage of the project. I am especially

grateful for the friendly help extended by each of these persons.

I would like to acknowledge the assistance of the Graduate School

of the University of Maryland which awarded me a fellow8hip for the

summer of 1970 and a grant for typing expenses. I would also like to

acknowledge the assistance provided by a fellowship from the Ameri­

can Research Center in Egypt for the summer of 1972. Finally, I wish

to thank the personnel of the Centre Universitaire International in

Paris for their helpfulness.

Page 5: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

CONTENTS

Introduction

The Text .

The Teaching of the Text .

Short Commentary on Aristotle's "Topics" .

Short Commentary on Aristotle's"Rhetoric" .

Short Commentary on Aristotle's "Poetics" .

Notes .

Index " .

Arabic Texts .

xi

1

5

19

43

57

79

85

135

143

Page 6: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

INTRODUCTION

BORN IN CORDOBA IN 1126 C.E. (520 Anno Hegirae),l Abu al-WalidMu1.lammad ibn A1.lmad Ibn Rushd, known to the West as Averroes,received a traditional education in the principal disciplines of Islamicculture: jurisprudence and theology. He also studied medicine,eloquence, poetry, literature, and philosophy.. His reputation as aman of learning brought him to the attention of his sovereign, AbuYa'qub Yusuf, the ruler of the Almohad dynasty, who encouragedhim to explain the difficulties in the works of Aristotle and appointedhim as a judge, eventually naming him the chief justice of Seville.Except for a brief period of legal exile, Averroes occupied this post,also serving as personal physician and sometime adviser to the Al­mohad sovereigns, until almost the end of his life in 595/1198. Still,his reputation among learned men of the Middle Ages was due to hisskillful interpretations of pagan philosophy and defense of theoreticalspeculation, rather than to these practical accomplishments. Eventoday his theoretical accomplishments could interest thoughtful men,but most of his writings are largely inaccessible to them-existingonly in medieval manuscripts or barely intelligible Latin translations.

An attempt is made here to fill that void by presenting three treatisesof historical and theoretical significance to all interested in philosophicthought. None of these treatises has ever before been edited andpublished in Arabic or translated into a modern language.s Becausethe Arabic manuscripts were apparently lost at an early date, theclosest replicas of the original Arabic version now available to interestedscholars are two ]udaeo-Arabic manuscripts. They have been used asthe basis of this edition. According to the scribe of one of the manu­scripts, the copy was completed in 1356 C.E. Unfortunately there is noreliable information about the date of the other manuscript: the dateof 1216, written in the kind of Arabic numerals used by Westernersin recent times and in a hand other than that of the scribe, appears on

1

Page 7: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

2 INTRODUCTION INTRODUCTION 3

the title page; it has no connection with any of the textual material.

The fourteenth century manuscript contains a Hebrew translationopposite the Judaeo-Arabic text. The Arabic text was first translatedinto Hebrew in the thirteenth century. Subsequently, it was translatedinto Hebrew a number of other times, and one translation was even­tually published in the mid-sixteenth century.3 Collating the Hebrewtranslation with the Judaeo-Arabic manuscripts proved to be oflittle help for establishing an accurate Arabic text.

Numerous Latin translations of Averroes's works were made in theearly thirteenth century, many ofwhich were published in the fifteenthand sixteenth centuries. However, the only known Latin version of thetexts presented here is that of Abraham de Balmes who died in 1523C.E. This translation, made directly from the Hebrew, was publishedin Venice in the sixteenth century. It has gained wide acceptanceand is the principal source cited by those interested in the logicalthought of Averroes. It, too, was collated with the Judaeo-Arabicversions, but was of even less help than the Hebrew translation forestablishing an accurate Arabic text.

To appreciate why only two manuscripts ofsuch an important workhave survived and why those manuscripts have survived in Judaeo­Arabic rather than in Arabic, it is necessary to reflect upon the sus­picion in which Averroes was placed as a result of legal exile in thelater years of his life. It is also necessary to consider the significanceof the purge of unorthodox opinions carried out by the Almohaddynasty shortly after his death. At that time, religious intolerancereached such intensity that books suspected of heresy were frequentlyburned before the public. It is probable that in this setting worksattributed to a figure as controversial as Averroes readily disappeared.However, largely because of Maimonides's influence, Averroes hadvery early gained such fame in the Jewish community that most of hisworks were transliterated intoJudaeo-Arabic, translated into Hebrew,and widely circulated in North Mrica and even France. The collectionto which the treatises presented here belong, as well as Averroes'smore formal commentaries on works by Aristotle, were of specialimportance to those members of the Jewish community interested inperipatetic philosophy and were consequently carefully preserved.Even though Latin Aristotelian studies became more prominent thanJewish Aristotelian studies in the later Middle Ages, Jewish interest inAverroes and in Judaeo-Arabic or Hebrew versions of his works did

not diminish. As a result, many of the medieval Judaeo-Arabic andHebrew versions of his works are still available.4

However, these considerations do not explain why the treatisespresented here have been neglected since their recovery more than acentury ago. One reason for that neglect appears to be their subjectmatter: logic. The writings of Averroes on logic were not studiedvery carefully by fellow Arabs nor by the Latin Aristotelians whowere first attracted to his works. Similarly, even though the academiccommunity knew about the existence of these treatises in Judaeo­Arabic manuscripts and about the existence of the Middle Commentarieson Aristotle's Organon in Arabic manuscripts during the latter partof the nineteenth century, scholars preferred to edit Hebrew trans­lations of other works by Averroes while deploring the lack of Arabicmanuscripts. It was not until the first third of the twentieth centurythat one of the logical works was thoroughly edited.s

Another reason why these treatises have been neglected is that, ascommentaries, they were considered to be less original than otherwritings by Averroes. Throughout the nineteenth century, the imageof an Averroes who was a faithful disciple of Arisotle prevailed.For a long while it was accepted without question and passed on asrigorously confirmed. Only recently has the doctrine begun to bedoubted. However, while it reigned supreme, scholars expressed moreinterest in those works ofAverroes which were obviously independentand original. Turning their attention to these works, they left thecommentaries, and especially the commentaries on logic, aside.6

Whatever the full explanation might be, it is clear that neglectof these treatises has not resulted from an informed judgment aboutthe quality of the arguments they set forth. Far from having thoroughlyinvestigated these arguments, the academic community has never beenvery knowledgeable about the most superficial aspects of the treatises.When Munk first announced the existence ofone of the Judaeo-Arabicmanuscripts in 1847, he simply identified it as Averroes's Short Commen­tary on the Organon without any reference to its possible significance.Shortly afterward, Renan reported Munk's discovery, but paid suchlittle attention to the content of the treatise or to its identity that hespoke of the Hebrew version of the Short Commentary on Logic (which hecalled Abrege de Logique) and of the manuscript discovered by Munk(which he called Abrege de l'Organon) without ever associating the two.More importantly, he insisted that the treatises on rhetoric and poetics

Page 8: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

INTRODUCTION

contained in the Florence manuscript ofAverroes's Middle Commentarieson Aristotle's Organon, which he had catalogued, were short commen­taries. Although he recognized differences between the treatises onrhetoric and poetics in the Florence manuscript and the Latin trans­lations of these works by Hermannus Alemannus and Abraham deBalmes, he never compared them with the manuscript discovered byMunk.7

Despite Renan's acknowledgement of the manuscript's existenceand Munk's subsequent reminder of its significance as the Arabicsource, the German historian oflogic, C. Prand, showed no awareness,as late as 1861, that the treatise existed in any form but the old Latinversion. Some years later, Steinschneider attacked Prantl for thisapparent lapse of scholarship and used the occasion to announce hisdiscovery of the other manuscript containing the Judaeo-Arabicversion of this collection of treatises on the art oflogic.8 Still, nothingprompted anyone to edit the manuscripts. They remained neglectedafter Father Bouyges mentioned their existence in 1922 and erroneouslyidentified a notebook manuscript he had found in Cairo as a possibleArabic copy ofthe Short Commentary on Rhetoric. EvenWolfson's repeatedcall for a Corpus Commentariorum Averrois in Aristotelem did not lead to anedition of the treatises.9

Such neglect must be decried, for, in addition to the historical signi­ficance attached to these manuscripts, the treatises are important forother reasons. Above all, they command serious attention becauseof their daring critique of traditional Islamic thought and of thedialectical theologians who considered themselves its true defenders.Starting with the particular perspective of Islam, Averroes was ableto raise the universal question of the relation between philosophy,politics, and religion. These treatises are also of special interest due totheir form or literary genre. So little is yet known about the differentkinds of commentaries and treatises composed by Averr.oes or abouttheir functions that careful attention must be paid to examples ofeach. In that way it may be possible to learn what the art of commen­tary truly was for Averroes and how he used it to present his own,as well as Aristotle's, thought. Only then will it be possible to formcorrect opinions about the quality of Averroes's teaching. Finally,these treatises are important because of what they teach about theway Aristotle's logical writings were interpreted at that time.

THE TEXT

BEFORE CONSIDERING the teaching set forth in these treatises, it isappropriate to have an accurate idea of their character. The c~rr.ectidentification of the treatises is linked to the problem ?f ~~termmmgtheir original titles. Moreover, because of the peculIantIes presentin the formal organization as well as in the substantive ~rguments~f~he

. . h . about theIr authentICIty.treatises, senous questIOns ave ansen .Finally a description of the manuscripts and an explanatIOn of theway th~y have been edited and translated, though free ofcontroversy, .

are equally important preliminaries.In the Munich catalogue, the manuscript is identified ~s ;:e ~hort

Commentary on Aristotle's Organon and on Porphyry's Int~oductton. SI~ce. . . 1 th" ore a conjectural descnp-the manuscnpt contams no tit e, IS IS m .

tion ofthe subject matter and putative identificatI?n ofthe work than atitle.The title given the manuscript in the ~ans catalogue, on theother hand only vaguely alludes to the subject matter and. to the

. ' . s if Logic 11 In hIS IndexidentificatIOn of the commentary. .ummary o· .General Professor Va;da listed the manuscript under yet another tItle:,:J • L .) 12

al-l)ariirifi al-Man#q (What Is Necessary zn ogtc. . .Professor Vajda's choice of title is in keeping with a long tradItIOn.

I h · b' h' sketch Ibn Abu Usaybi'ah first referred to one ofn IS IOgrap IC, . . D - - f- 1Averroes's works by something like this title: Kttiib al-. arun t a -Mantiq (The Book of the Necessary in Logic), Moreo~er, a~ong thebooks of Averroes mentioned in the Escurial manuscnpt 8841S, a workbearing a title identical to the one given by Professor VaJdabTheLatin translator Abraham de Balmes also identifed the w?rk y.a

. . l' St schneI-similar title: Compendium necessanum Averroys tottUS ogtcae" ' emder who discovered this use of the title by de Balmes, orIgmally ques­tio~ed the "necessarium" and the traditional title because the! v:er:reflected in the first few words of the treatise: "al-ghara4 f~ hadhaal-qawl tajrid al-aqiiwil al-¢ariiriyah min ~inii'at ~inii'at al-man!tq (the

5

Page 9: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

6THE TEXT THE TEXT 7

~urpose of this treatise is to abstract the necessary speeches pertain­mg ~o. each ~nd .eve~ logical art)." However, he settled upon thetradItIonal title m hIS final description of the two Judeao-Arabicmanuscripts.I3

. Steinschneider's earlier doubt about the accuracy of the traditionaltitle was better founded than he realized. The only other Arabicreference to anything resembling the traditional title was Ibn al­Abbar's vague allusion: "his book in Arabic; whose title was al­J)ariiri." When al-An~ariwrote a supplement to Ibn al-Abbar's bookhe ma~~ no reference. to such a title and only spoke generally ofAverroes s commentane~ o~ Aristotle's philosophical and logicalbooks. Eve~ the noted histonan, master of tradition, and theologianShams al-Dm al-Dhahabi, who claimed to cite the works of Averroes~ccordi~~ ,~o I?n Abu U~a!bi'ah's list, omitted the qualificative

al-'()arun, calhng the book SImply Kitab fi al-Man/iq (Book on Logic).14

An even more important difficulty with the traditional title is thatit does not explain what kind of a treatise Averroes wrote. HoweverI~n_ Abu U~a~bi'ah's list. does contain a long descriptive sub-title;Kztab al-.()arunfi al-Man/zg, mullj,aq bih Talkh~ Kutub Aris/ilfiilis wa gadlakJU:hf¥ahii. ~alkhf~an tamman mustawfan (The Book of the Necessary inLogzc, Contaznzng HzsComplete andExhaustive Middle Commentary on Aristotle'sBooks).15 Although it purports to identify the kind of treatises con­tained in the collection, it cannot be considered aCCurate. In the firstplace, t~e. w~rd "talkhi~" ("middle commentary"), usually used in~,~ntr~d~s,~mctlOn to "s?ar~" or "tafsir" ("large commentary") and'J~wa.mz' or "mukhta:ar '("short commentary"), is certainly not de­

scnptIve of the treatIses contained in this collection. Even if the word"talk~~" is understood in the loosest possible sense, these treatisescertamly do no~ provide a "complete and exhaustive" commentaryon the art of lOgIC. Averroes admitted as much in the opening words ofthis collection by saying that the purpose of the work was to providean abstract ?r sum~ary ("tajri~") of what was necessary. Moreover,the manuscnpt copIes of the Mzddle Commentaries on Aristotle's Organonhave been found; those treatises are much more extensive commen­ta:ies on logic than what is found in this collecton. Finally, there is noe~denceth~t Averroes used anything resembling Ibn Abu U~aybi'ah'stItle or subtitle to refer to this work, whereas he did refer to one of hisworks in terms similar to the title reflected in the Munich cataloguelisting and in the way de Balmes used the word "compendium":

at one point Averroes spoke of "our short commentary" (al-mukhtf¥aral-saghir alladhi lanii) on 10gic.16

Consequently, the conjectural title of the Munich catalogue offersthe most accurate identification of this collection of treatises. Apartfrom the negative reasons already considered, there are positive reasonswhich confirm its appropriateness. In the first place, most of the trea­tises comment on particular books of Aristotle's Organon. In addition,the general logical theory presented in these treatises is basicallyAristotelian. Moreover, there are frequent references to Aristotle andex.planations ofwhat prompted him to write about each art. Still, thereare several superficial and substantive divergences from what might beexpected to be the form of a short commentary, and they might callthis identification into question.

For example, Averroes introduced the work by a general statementabout the reasons for studying logic without ever suggesting that thetreatises to follow depended on Aristotle's logical theory. In fact,he never mentioned Aristotle's name in that general statement.Moreover, he began the treatise by commenting on Porphyry'sIsagoge as though it were a necessary preface to Aristotle's Categories.HAverroes altered the end ofthe treatise in a similar manner by includingtreatises on the arts of rhetoric and poetics. Here, too, the change waseffected without elaborate explanation, the only preparation beingAverroes's introductory remark that rhetoric and poetics were logicalarts as much as demonstration; dialectic, and sophistics.I8

Nor did Averroes respect the order of Aristotle's Organon. For onething, he transferred the discussion of equivocal terms from thediscussion of the Categories-where Aristotle had examined the subject-to the treatise concerned with the Isagoge, even though Porphyrynever discussed that subject.19 Again, arguing that it was essentialto learn how to make syllogisms after having learned how to distin­guish their different classes, he placed the discussion of syllogistictopics immediately after the discussion of the syllogism and imme­diately before the discussion of what he considered to be the mostimportant logical art-rlemonstration. In terms of the OrganonAverroes thus placed that which corresponds to Books II-VII of theTopics after the Prior Analytics and before the Posterior Analytics.20

He also inverted the order of the treatises on the arts of dialectic andsophistry: in this work, the treatise on sophistry follows the discussionof demonstration (i.e., the Posterior Analytics) and precedes that on

Page 10: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

8THE TEXT

,THE TEXT

9

dial~ctic; in Aristotle's Organon, the treatise on dialectic (i.e.,' the

ToJncs). follows the Posterior Analytics and precedes On SophisticalRefutatzons.

Finally, there are notable discrepancies in the titles of the v .. W· anous

t:eatIses. __Ith the exce~tionof the treatises on the Categories (al-Qawl

fi al-M.aqulat) '. t_he Postenor Analytics (KittIh al-Burhiin) , and On Sophistical

R~tatlons (Kztiih al-Siifsa!ah),21 the traditional titles for the works of

ArIstotle are ~ot .used .here. For example, the treatise following that

on t~e Categones IS entitled On the Rules Peculiar to Assent (al-Qawiinin

a~lat~ tak~~ al- T~diq),22 ~ather than.On Interpretation (Pi al-'Ihiirah).

SI~larly, rather than a tItle suggestive of Prior Analytics (Kitiih al­

Qjyas).' ~verrofs called the corresponding treatise On the Knowledge

for Bnngzng about Assent (Pi al-Ma'rifah al-fl'ilah Ii al-T~diq). When he

wrote about. the syllogistic topics, he called that treatise On the

Rules h~ .Whz~h Syllogisms Are Made (Pi al-Qawiinin allati ta'mo.l hiM

al-Maqayzs)23 mstead of simply Topics (Pi al-Mawiilji').

In addition to these superficial divergences from what might be

expected to be the form of a commentary, there are substantive diver­

g~nces. Ave~ofs presented a novel classification of the different

kI~ds ofsyll~gI~msand introduced some that were never mentioned by

ArIstotle. SImIlarly, his analysis of the matters of syllogisms was

forei.go to Aristotle's logical t~lOught. In addition, he gave a dispro­

portlOnate amount of attentIOn to some subjects and completely

negle~ted others. ~is discussion of the theory of the nondemonstrative

syllogIsm set forth m the Topics, for example, was so extensive that the

reader might think Aristotle had written a book solely abo t the

dial~ctical syllogism. Conversely, Averrofs's discussion of the :rt of

poet~cs was completely free of any reference whatsoever to tragedy.

. GIVen all of these divergences, the correctness of calling the collec­

tI?n a Short Commentary might be questioned. In addition to the

divergenc.es, ~h~re is .the massive fact that Averrofs never explicitly

declared It hIS mtentIOn to set forth the teaching of Aristotle in thO11' I' IS

co e~tlOn.. t mIght therefore be argued that the extent to which the

treatIses d.Iffer from Aristotle's logical teaching will cease to be

problematic once the collection is no longer thought of as a kind of

commentary. A~errofs's allusion to his mukh~ar saghir could then

be understood SImply as an allusion to a "short treatise" rather than11 . , h '

as an a USlOn to a 's ort commentary" on Aristotle. However, such

an argument fails to account for the numerous references to Aristotle

throughout the text, references which always take Aristotle's correct­

ness for granted-as though Averrofs were simply explaining Aristotle's

thought. That argument is likewise unable to account for the fact that

each treatise ends with remarks about the kind ofconsiderations which

first prompted Aristotle to write about the particular art. Above all,

that argument is unable to explain why the content of each treatise

should correspond roughly to a particular Aristotelian text.

By his frequent references to Aristotle, Averro(!s gave the distinct

impression that his exposition was based on Aristotle's treatises about

the logical arts. At the same time, by means of the aforementioned

superficial and substantive divergences from Aristotle's Organon, he

suggested that the exposition was in no w.ay limited to Aristotle's

text. Differently stated, while generally oriented toward the logical

teaching of Aristotle, these treatises of Averroes were addressed to the

larger subject rather than to the particular arguments found in Aris­

totle's books on the logical arts. Because Averroes presented them as

setting forth in summary fashion what Aristotle had fully explained

and because he tried to keep the image of Aristotle foremost in the

reader's mind, they ought to be considered as commentaries. The

kind of freedom from Aristotle's text and attention to the general

subject which is permitted by the superficial divergences has been

observed to be characteristic of Averrofs's procedure in the short

commentaries, the middle and large being devoted to an explicit

consideration of particular Aristotelian arguments.24 Consequently,

the descriptive title of the Munich catalogue appears to be most accu­

rate and most in keeping with Averrofs's own allusions to the work.

There are problems of a similar sort with the titles of the treatises

presented here. Despite clear parallels with Aristotle's Topics, Rhetoric

and Poetics, as well as references to Aristotle's intention with respect

to each work, Averrofs used titles which did not suggest that these

treatises were commentaries on Aristotle's works. For example, the

first treatise is called The Book ofDialectic (Kitiih al-]adal) .25 Similarly,

the second of the treatises presented here is called The Speech ahout

Rhetorical Arguments (al-Qpwl fi al-Aqiiwil al-Kha!iihiyah),28 while the

last of the three treatises is entitled Ahout Poetical Speeches (Pi al-Aqiiwil

al-Shi'riyah) •

The reasoning which dictated identifying the larger work as the

Short Commentary on Aristotle's Organon also dictates identifying these

treatises as the Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, the Short Commen-

Page 11: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

10 THE TEXT11

THE TEXT

tary on Aristotle'~ Rhe.toric, and the Short Commentary on Aristotle's Poetics.M~reover, despIte hIs recourse to novel titles for these and others of thelogIcal wor~, Averroes cited them by their traditional titles in thecou~e_of hIs. argume~t. For example, he referred the reader to Kitiibal-Q]Yas. (Pnor Analyttcs), rather than to Fi al-Ma'rifah al-fii'ilah lial-Tt¥~tq (On tke Knowledg~ [or Bringin? about Assent).27 Similarly, at0n..e .p~mt he used the. tradItIOnal ArabIc title for the Topics, Kitiib al­Tubt.qt'.rathe.r than Kttiib al-ladal (Book of Dialectic) or Fi al-Q,awiininallatt ta mal bthiial-Maqiiyis (On tke Rules by Which Syllogisms Are Made).28

It should also be n?ted ~hatAverroes seemed to consider the titles Kitiib~l-J.ad~l (Book of.Dtalecttc) and Kitiib al-Tubiqi ( Topics) interchangeable :m hIS mtroductIOn to the Talkhis Kitiib al-Tiibiqi (MiDl G tA' l' Ii . .. uu, e ommen ary on

nstot esopus), he spoke of both as equally valid titles.29 Moreoverat the end ofthe Short Commentary on Aristotle'sRhetoric, he referred to tha~work a~ th: Book ofR~etoric (Kitiib al-Kka!iibah). Finally, it is clear thatAverro<:,s .dId not conSIder the treatise Fi al-Q,awiinin allati ta'mal bikiial-Maqayzs (On tke Rules by Which Syllogisms Are Made) to represent hiscommentary on the r:opics, because he so carefully explained to thereader that he was usmg the topics discussed in this treatise solely toprepar~ the way for his teaching about demonstration and becauseh~ remmded the reader quite frequently that his use of topics heredIffered f:om the way they were used in dialectic or rhetoric. Conse­que~tly,Just as there is no question that the treatises on rhetorical andpoetIcal ~peeches refer to Aristotle's books on those sUbje~ts, so therecan be lIttle doubt that the treatise on dialectic refers to Aristotle'sbook on the art of dialectic-the Topics.

Recourse to novel titles for most of the treatises in this collectionwas one more w~y for Averroes to indicate the different character ofthese com~~ntanes to the reader. In the larger commentaries, whichwere .explIcitly devoted to explaining Aristotle's arguments in anorgamzed manne:, Averroes used the traditional titles. In these~hort Co~mentar~es,where the goal was to explain the subject matterIn a. succmct fashIOn, the use of novel titles alerted the reader to as~ecial fre~dom from Aristotle in the commentary. Recognition of thedIfferent. tItles co~ld e~ther spur the imaginative reader to searchfor ot?er mstances m whIch Averroes took liberties with the Aristotelianteachmg or lull. the indolent reader into thinking that Averroes'sfreedom from Aristotle was only superficial.

** *

Of no less importance than the proper identification of these trea­tises is confirmation of their authenticity. While Prantl has been theonly one to. argue that they might be spurious, he has advancedweighty objections worthy of serious consideration.

His suspicions were first aroused because of two innovations hefound in the technical vocabulary of the treatises: he was astonishedthat the Latin terms definitio and demonstratio had been replaced bythe terms formatio and verificatio. (Both pairs of terms were used totranslate the Arabic terms tf¥awwur and tt¥diq). Acknowledging thepossible temerity of founding his critique on the Latin translationsalone, Prantl insisted that the terminological innovation was of suchmagnitude that it could not possibly be due to the translator. Stein­schneider agreed with Prantl's acknowledgement of temerity, blamedhim for failing to note that Munk had never expressed doubts about theauthenticity of the treatises, as well as for neglecting Averroes's ownreference to his Short Commentary on logic, and then dismissedPrantl's objection by citing similar examples of that innovativeterminology in the translated works of al-Farabi and Avicenna.

3o

Later, Lasinio, who agreed with Steinschneider's general condemna­tion of Prantl's scholarship, made the particular refutation moreconvincing by citing a passage in which another Latin translator usedthe terms formatio and verificatio or certificatio for tf¥awwur and ta~diq,while de Balmes-whose translation had first aroused Prantl's sus-

picions-used yet other terms.31

Another reason for Prantl's doubts about the authorship of thesetreatises was the difference he observed between Averroes's willingnessto preface these treatises with a commentary on Porphyry's Isagogeand his reluctance to preface the Middle Commentaries on Aristotle'sOrganonwith a commentary on that work. Not believing that such incon­sistency could be found in the work of one man and the authenticityof the Middle Commentaries being beyond doubt, Prantl concludedthat these treatises were to be rejected as spurious.32 Because he failedto understand the grounds ofAverroes's reluctance, Prantl's conclusionwas too hasty. Of prime importance to Averroes was the particularcontext of the commentary: he considered the Middle Commentariesto be, above all, commentaries "on the books of Aristotle."33 Theintroductory remarks to his Middle Commentary on Aristotle's Categorieslimit the collection even more by defining its goal as that of comment­ing on Aristotle's books about logic, explaining and summarizing

Page 12: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

12THE TEXT TIlE TEXT 13

them.34 For that goal it was not necessary to comment on Porphyry.

That same emphasis on the particular context of the commentaryexplains. Averroes's willingness to include remarks on Porphyry'sIsagoge In the Short Commentaries. Averroes introduced a newordering ofthe art oflogic in these treatises. He first identified concept(t~a~wur) a~d assent (~diq) as fundamental terms and then explainedthat Instruct~onabout ea~h had to proceed from that which preparesthe "':..~y for It (a!-muwti!!z' lah) and from that which brings it about(~l-fa zl lah!. ThIs meant that the art of logic fell into four parts:(1) that whIch prepares the way for a concept, (ii) that which bringsa conce~t abo~t, (iii) that which prepares the way for assent, and (iv)that whIch bnngs assent about. Averroes's discussion of words and ofPo~phy~'s account of the predicables corresponded to the first part,whIle hIs commentary on the Categories corresponded to the secondpart. Had Prantl been aware of the new ordering introduced byAverroes, he would have understood what prompted him to discussPorphyry's Isagoge in these treatises even though he was reluctantto do so in the Middle Commentaries.

Prantl ~ad an additional reason for doubting the authenticity ofthese treatIses. He thought that the clearest indication of their spuriouscharacter was the way they were ordered. Recalling Averroes's severecriticism of Avicenna for suggesting that the inquiry into dialecticalmethod (that is, the Topics) precede the inquiry into demonstrativemethod (that is, the Posterior Analytics), Prantl pointed to the way thecommentary on the Topics precedes that on the Posterior Analyticsin this .collec~ion.35 Still persuaded that Averroes was incapableof such InCOnsisten~y, he concluded that the treatises were spurious.Unfortunately for hIs argument, Prantl failed to understand Averroes'sreasons for criticizing Avicenna and failed to grasp the content of thetreatise which precedes the Short Commentary on the Posterior Analytics.

In criticizing Avicenna, Averroes admitted that probable premiseswer~ usually more readily at hand than certain premises, but insistedupon the necessity of understanding the conditions of certainty inorder to be abl~ to distinguish among the kinds of probable premisesthat were so easIly found. Consequently, it was logical for the PosteriorAnalytics (insofar as it provided the proofs and rules by which certainpremises might be obtained) to precede the Topics (insofar as itprovided the proofs and rules by which probable premises might beobtained).36 Averroes did not go against this reasoning by placing

the treatise entitled On the Rules by Which Syllogisms Are Made (Pial-Q,awtinin allati ta'mal bihti al-Maqtiyis) before the Short Commentaryon Aristotle's Posterior Analytics. The former work was limited to thediscussion of the topics occurring in Books II-VII of the Topics, butthat discussion was designed to prepare the way to demonstrationby explaining how to make demonstrative syllogisms. It was in noway concerned with dialectical reasoning.37 In fact, dialecticalreasoning was not considered until Averroes discussed it in thetreatise presented here as the Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics.To impress this order upon the attentive reader, Averroes openedthe treatise by declaring that only because demonstrative reasoninghad already been considered was it now appropriate to considerdialectical reasoning.38

Prantl also failed to note the multiple indications that Averroes wastrying to explain the art of logic and the order of the traditionallyaccepted Aristotelian books on the logical arts in an unprecedentedmanner. In accordance with the previously mentioned fourfold divi­sion of the art, Averroes presented his Short Commentary on Aristotle'sDe Interpretatione as corresponding to the third part of the art, thatwhich prepares the way for assent. This was made clear both by thetitle of that commentary, On the Rules Peculiar to Assent (al-Qawtininallati takh~~ al- T~diq), and by the opening sentences of the treatise.3D

The Short Commentary on Aristotle's Prior Analytics was designed to providethe rules for forming syllogisms, i.e., that by which assent is broughtabout, and was appropriately entitled On the Knowledge for Bringingabout Assent (Pi al-Ma'rifah al-fti'ilah li al- T~diq). However, Averroesdid not consider this kind of exposition to correspond to the part ofthe art which really treated what brought about assent and thereforeclassed this treatise as a continuation of the third part of the art,explaining that his treatise On the Rules by Which Syllogisms Are Made(Pi al-QJlwiinin allati ta'mal biM al-Maqtiyis) constituted the fourth partof the art. This meant that the Short Commentary on Aristotle's PosteriorAnalytics was an explanation ofhow one kind ofassent-the most noblekind, demonstration-worked. Similarly, the treatises on sophistics,dialectic, rhetoric, and poetics were simply so many illustrations ofhow the other kinds of assent worked.40 It is clear, then, that Averroescommitted no logical inconsistencies by his novel ordering of BooksII-VII of the Topics and certainly did nothing to call his authorshipof these treatises into question. Consequently, this objection of

Page 13: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

14 THE TEXT15

THE TEXT

Prantl's must be rejected along with his other ones and the treatisesconstituting the Short Commentaries on Aristotle's Organon accepted asauthentic.

** *Now that the treatises have been properly identified and their

authenticity assured, it is appropriate to consider their formalcharacteristics.

The Munich manuscript contains nine treatises and comprises 86folios. Each folio measures 21.5 cm. in height and 14.5 Cm. in width,with the writing occupying 15 cm. ofthe height and 8 cm. of the width.Although not completely uniform, the folios usually contain 24 linesof script.

All of the treatises but one are complete, and all are in the properorder. The introductory statement explaining the purpose of thecollection (fo1. I a-b) is followed by the commentary on the Isagogeof Porphyry (fols. 1b_6b). Mter these are the commentaries on theCategories (fols. 6b-lOb), On Interpretation (fols. lOb_16b), and PriorAnalytics (fols. 16b-303

). Then the commentary on Books II-VII ofthe Topics (fols. 303-41b) follows. The commentary on the PosteroirAnalytics (fols. 4I b-633 ) and that on On Sophistical Rifutations (fols.633-723 ) come next. They are followed by the commentaries presentedhere: Topics (fols. 723-773 ), Rhetoric (fols. 77b-863 ), and Poetics(fols. 86B-b). Unfortunately, most of folio 86b is missing, but itscontent can be reconstructed from the Paris manuscript, as well asfrom the Hebrew and Latin translations.

Some damage has occurred to the manuscript, but it is still quitelegible. The first line of the first folio has been somewhat obliterated.In addition, the upper corners ofmany folios, from folio 63 to the end ofthe manuscript, have fallen off; as a consequence, portions of the firstfew lines are sometimes missing. These page corners must have fallenofffairly recently, for Lasinio's copy ofthe Short Commentary on Aristotle'sPoetics from the Munich manuscript contains readings which can nolonger be found due to those missing corners. Many wormholes mayalso be found from folio 77 to the end of the volume. These holes aresometimes so large that entire words are missing.

The manuscript has been bound, and the flyleaves of the bindingindicate the different stages of recognition of its contents. Thus, onwhat might be considered to be the title page, the work was first

identified as having been written by Averroes, but his name has beencrossed out and Avicenna's name written in with both Hebrew andLatin characters. On the same page, the manuscript waS identified as"lib. Merlicamenta" or "Sifer Rifuot," with an explanation in Hebrewand German that the text is in Arabic with Hebrew characters. Thedate of 1216 also occurs on this page, written in what seems to be thesame handwriting as the Latin and German notations. The otherflyleaves contain pencil and pen notes from Steinschneider, dated

1864.The script, a very old Spanish rabbinical s~ript, is large and clear.

Although the script is sometimes almost undecIpherable, care has beentaken to place points, when needed, over the Hebrew letters used totransliterate two Arabic letters. There is no indication of the nameof the scribe. Many corrections of an extensive nature are to be foundon the margins and above the lines. They are all written in a handdifferent from that of the scribe.

The Paris manuscript contains the same nine treatises as the Munichmanuscript and comprises 103 folios, on 96 of which are contained thetreatises presented in the Munich manuscript. Each folio measures 31cm. in height and 20 cm. in width, with the writing occ~pying17.5 c~of the height and 13 cm. of the width. With few exceptIOns, each fohocontains 25 lines of script.

Although all of the treatises are properly orde~ed a~d t~e ~a~u­script complete, the first folio of the Judaeo-ArabIc verSIOn IS mIssmg.­The commentary on the Isagoge of Porphyry is co?tained on the fi~stfive extant folios. It is followed by the commentarIes on the Categones(fols. 6-11), On Interpretation (fols. 11-17), and Prior Analytics (f?ls. 17­33). Mter these is the commentary on Books II-VII ofthe !optCS (fo~s.33-46). Then there are the commentaries on the Postertor Analyttcs(fols. 46-69) and on On Sophistical Rifutation (fols. 69-79). These arefollowed by the commentaries presented here: Topics (fols. 79-~5),Rhetoric (fols. 85-95), and Poetics (fols. 95-96). Two short treatIsesby al-Flidibi are separated from the rest of the collection by a blankfolio· both treatises are in Judaeo-Arabic alone: "The Speech aboutthe Conditions of Demonstration" (fols. 983-1003

) and "SectionsWhich Are Necessary in the Art of Logic" (fols. 100b_I03b).41

Unlike that of the Munich manuscript, the script of the Paris manu­script is rabbinic rluktus tending toward cursive. However, it is muchsmaller and not as clear as the other. Moreover, no care has been taken

Page 14: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

16 THE TEXT THE TEXT 17

to place distinguishing points over the Hebrew letters used to trans­literate two Arabic letters. The script is so small that the Paris manu­script is only nine folios longer than the Munich manuscript eventhough it contains both the Judaeo-Arabic and Hebrew versions of thework. The Hebrew translation is placed opposite the Judaeo-Arabictext, and each page of each version begins and ends with approxi­mately the same words.

The. P.aris manuscript is in remarkably good condition. Except forthe mIssmg page ofthe Judaeo-Arabic text, no damage has occurredto the manuscript. Each of the section titles is set off by flower­like e~circlements ~n red ink. There are some marginal corrections,many m a hand dIfferent from that of the scribe. In a colophon,the scribe identified himselfas Ezra ben Rabbi Shlomo ben Gratnia ofSaragossa.42

Microfilm copies and full-size photographic prints of the manu­scripts were used for most of the editing, but both manuscripts havealso been examined directly at various stages of the project. Forpurposes of editing, the Judaeo-Arabic manuscripts were consideredto be of equal value. Both are deficient due to lacunae; transpositionof phrases, words, or letters; and simple grammatical mistakes.Despite evidence of a later attempt to correct the Munich manuscript(e.g., marginal additions and corrections in a different handwriting),many errors still remain.43 Those lacunae which have not yet beencorrected appear to be simple errors of copying: the scribe oftendropped several words which occurred between two identical wordson different lines. Such elrors make it impossible to depend on theMunich manuscript to the exclusion of the Paris manuscript. TheParis manuscript is faulty in these ways and in other ways. It suffersfrom n~~erous lacunae not encountered in the Munich manuscript."The mIssmg passages often refer to technical terms or key verbs forwhich the scribe usually left blank places, as though he had theintention of filling them in later.

In both manuscripts, fine points of Arabic orthography are missed.This appears to be a consequence of the limitations ofJudaeo-Arabic.Generally the orthographic difficulties pose no major problem in dis­cerning the sense of the argument.

When all of the evidence is considered, it appears that the Parisand the Munich manuscripts are independent of each other. Inaddition to the many instances of simple scribal errors which are not

significant, there are numerous instances of errors where each manu­script differs from what might be considered to be the correct reading.Moreover, some passages missing from the Paris manuscript were alsooriginally missing from the Munich manuscript; these were oftencorrected in the margin, and the corrections must have been inspiredby readings from a manuscript other than either the Paris or Munichmanuscript.45 Although such an observation suggests that the manu­scripts may still be faulty in ways not yet noticed, it only makes carefulstudy ofthe texts all the more necessary to those interested in Averroes'steaching.

Another problem arises from the fact that many of the lacunaeencountered in the Judaeo-Arabic version Of the Paris manuscriptdo not occur in the Hebrew version. Of the two explanations whichmay be offered, only one is tenable: to assume that theJudaeo-Arabicversion is a poor translation of the Hebrew translation is to reasonfalsely, for it is unlikely that a scribe could translate from the Hebrewin a manner so faithful to the Arabic style of Averroes. It thereforeappears that the Hebrew translation was originally made from abetter version of the Arabic text than that which the Judaeo-Arabicversion represents. Since the Munich manuscript fills most of thelacunae of the Paris Judaeo-Arabic manuscript, it may very likely bebased on, or have been corrected on the basis of, a text closer to theone used by the Hebrew translator.

** *In the translation, every attempt has been made to combine

readable and intelligible English with fidelity to the original Arabic.For two reasons, it has not always been possible to achieve that goal.In the first place, the technical character of these treatises at timesmade a certain kind of stiffness unavoidable. Averroes was clearlyaddressing himself to an audience familiar with the general featuresof logic and thus did not hesitate to use specialized terminology or tospeak in the arid style so appropriate to discourse about logic. Second­ly, Some awkwardness in style has resulted because insofar as has beenconsonant with intelligent speech, the same word has been translatedin the same way whenever it occurs. Here the idea was that a carefulreading of any text will at some point oblige the reader to note theoccurence and the recurrence of certain words. If words have beentranslated differently to suit the taste of the translator, that path is

Page 15: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

18 TI!E TEXT THE TEACHING OF THE TEXTclosed to the reader. In sum, while every effort was made to arrive at afaithful and readable translation, the path facilitating instruction waschosen when there was no way to avoid choosing between literalineloquence and eloquent looseness.

Numerous notes accompany the translation. Their purpose is tohelp the reader understand the text. For that reason, the notes ex­plain technical terms or give more precise information about referencesAverroes has made to different authors, books; and opinions. Similarly,the dates of authors and of their writings, as well as page referencesto their writings, have been included in the notes. When appropriate,references to Aristotle have also been included so that a comparisonbetween Aristotle's definitions and Averroes's explanations may bemade. There are no marginal references to the books of Aristotle com­mented upon in these treatises because Averroes did not follow theseworks in any orderly manner; as has already been explained, hecompletely restructured them.

Each treatise or commentary has been divided into paragraphsand into sections to permit the reader to follow Averroes's thoughtmore easily. One rule has been paramount in this task of editing:the stages of the argument must be clearly set forth. Although para­graph division as understood today was not used by Arabic writersin Averroes's time, certain conventions did prevail for denoting thechange of thought now expressed in the form of paragraphs. Inaddition, thick pen strokes were used to indicate the change inargument corresponding to the contemporary division of a treatiseinto sections. Both of these conventions have been respected in thetranslation as well as in the edition.

AVERROES'S Short Commentaries on Aristotle's Topics, Rhetoric, and Poeticsare part of a larger work, the collection of Short Commentaries on Aris­totle's Organon. Yet they differ from the other treatises of the collectionin important respects. The other treatises explain the concepts leadingup to the kind of reasoning which is based on apodeictic premises andresults in apodeictic conclusions-the demonstrative syllogism-andexplain how it is used. These three treatises, however, are concernedwith arts which use mere similitudes of apodeictic premises anddemonstrative reasoning. Moreover, while the other treatises arerecommended because they teach how to reason correctly, these threetreatises are presented as providing ways of imitating or abridgingcorrect reasoning in order to influence other human beings in anynumber of situations, but especially with regard to political decisionsand religious beliefs.

These three treatises even stand apart physically from the other trea­tises of the collection. Although neither the Rhetoric nor the Poetics wastraditionally viewed as belonging to the Organon, Averroes included theShort Commentary on Aristotle's Rhetoric and the Short Commentary on Aris­totle's Poetics as the last two treatises in this collection of short com­mentaries on the Organon. He also reversed the positions of the ShortCommentary on Aristotle's Topics and the Short Commentary on Aristotle'sOn Sophistical Refutations with respect to their order in the traditionalview of the Organon. As a result, the Short Commentary on Aristotle'sTopics, the Short Commentary on Aristotle's Rhetoric, and the Short Com­mentary on Aristotle's Poetics are the last three treatises in the collec­tion. So that the significance of this extensive reworking of the Organonnot escape attention, Averroes offered another indication of theseparate status ofthese treatises. Asjustification for having reversed theorder of the Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics and the Short Commen­tary on Aristotle's On Sophistical Refutations, he limited the art of sophistry

19

Page 16: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

20 THE TEACHING OF THE TEXT THE TEACHING OF THE TEXT 21

to deception about demonstrative arguments. Entirely without parallelin Aristotle's work, that limitation served to explain why the treatiseabout sophistical arguments followed the treatise about demonstrativearguments in this collection. Averroes then linked the art of dialecticto the art of rhetoric by extolling its usefulness for bringing aboutpersuasion and linked the art of poetics to the art of rhetoric on thegrounds that it could persuade people by means of imaginative rep­resentations.46 All of these observations suggest that while the largercollection does constitute a whole and must be studied as such in orderto grasp the full teaching, it can also be divided into two major partsand that either one of these parts can be studied separately with profit.

The reason for studying these treatises, rather than those belongingto the other division, is to acquire an understanding of the relation be­tween politics, religion, and philosophy in the thought of Averroes.Intelligent awareness ofsuch topics is important because of the constantinfluence they exert over thought and action. Learned as well asunlearned human beings are continuously seeking better ways to livewith one another as fellow citizens, as members of different nations,or simply as associates. Similarly, decisions about work, play, andfamily life are tied to opinions about one's place in the universe andabout the kind of life proper to man. Whether those opinions arebased upon precepts deriving from a particular revelation or arethe result ofsome kind of independent thought, they play an importantrole in daily life and demand the careful attention of reflective in­dividuals.

Averroes is an important source of instruction about these topics,because the problem of their relationship occupied so much of hispractical and intellectual activity. Exceptionally well informed aboutthe sources and interpretations of the revealed religion which do­minated his own community, he applied its precepts to particularmatters in his capacity as a supreme judge and speculated aboutbroader aspects of the religion in the political realm whenever heacted as adviser to his Almohad sovereigns. He becomes especiallyimportant to us because he did not restrict himself to the notionsprevalent in that community. To the contrary, he found rare philo­sophical insight in the thought ofAristotle-a member of a communitynot affected by revealed religion-and tried to persuade his learnedfellow Muslims of Aristotle's merit by writing explanatory com­mentaries on Aristotle's thought. On a few occasions, he even directed

the argument to the larger public in order to defend philosophicactivity against attacks by zealous advocates of religious orthodoxyand in order to explain the theoretical limitations of religiousspeculation, as well as the political significance of religion.47

Among all of his writings, the Short Commentaries on Aristotle's Topics,Rhetoric, and Poetics are the best sources for acquiring an understandingof the relation Averroes thought existed between politics, religion,and philosophy. In the first place, his thought about this problemwas based on specific ideas about the logical character of differentkinds of speech, their proximity to certain knowledge, and the in­vestigative or practical purposes to which each might be put. Whilethese ideas are presupposed in his other works, including his largercommentaries on the logical arts, they are explained in these treatises.Secondly, these treatises contain the fullest statement of the groundsfor Averroes's abiding disagreement with those who considered them­selves the defenders of the faith. In Averroes's view, these dialecticaltheologians and masters of religious tradition were responsible forconfusing the common people by using extraordinarily complexarguments to speak about simple principles of faith and guilty ofattacking philosophy under the pretext of saving the faith they hadgarbled. Awareness of the reasons for his disagreement with them isimportant, because it is the background against which he expressedhis ideas concerning the relation between political life and religiousbelief, as well as between religious beliefand philosophic investigation.

** *However, the substantive teaching of these three treatises is not

immediately evident. It is so intimately related to the technicalexposition ofthe different logical arts that the treatises first appear to bepurely technical. Even though it is at once obvious that the technicalexposition was designed to correct prevalent misconceptions abouteach one of the arts, the deeper significance ofthat correction must beferreted out. For example, another consequence of incorporatingrhetoric and poetics into logic is that it allowed Averroes to stress theimportance of each art for inquiry and instruction, as well as toallude to the way each art shared in the attributes of logic. He thuscountered the prevailing tendency to restrict rhetoric and poetics toeloquence and to examine each solely in terms of style. Then, byreminding the reader that rhetorical proofs were quite far removed

Page 17: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

22 THE TEACInNG OF THE TEXT THE TEACHING OF THE TEXT 23

from certainty and that imaginative representations were frequentlybased on the merest similitudes of the real thing, Averroes easilyprodded him into thinking about the status of our knowledge withregard to the generally accepted political and religious uses of eachart.48 In this way he brought an apparently abstract, timeless discus­sion to bear on concrete, actual issues. The. advantage of his procedurewas that it never obliged him to quit the cloak of scientific detachment.

Nonetheless, to appreciate the cleverness of this procedure, itsdiaphanous quality must be recognized. Averroes tried to facilitatethat recognition by the judicious use of subtle allusions. The firstoccurs at the very beginning of the larger treatise. There he justifiedhis summary account of the logical arts on the grounds that it providedwhat was needed if one were to learn the essentials of the arts whichhad already been perfected in his time. This justification was closelyrelated to the goal of the treatise: to enable the interested person toacquire the concepts by which these already perfected arts could belearned. Realization of that goal necessitated understanding howconcept and assent were used in each one of the logical arts, thesebeing identified as demonstration, dialectic, sophistry, rhetoric, andpoetics.49 Although it was never given, the obvious reason for such agoal had to be that knowledge of the essentials of those other, alreadyperfected, arts was somehow important.

In the introduction, the only example ofalready perfected arts citedby Averroes was medicine. However, in the course of the exposition,he referred less explicitly to other arts--e.g., dialectical theology,traditional theology, and traditional jurisprudence. Even though heexplicitly cited the art of medicine in the introduction, he made noattempt to correct it in the course of the larger exposition. Conversely,in the course of the larger exposition he did try to correct those otherarts which he had not previously cited in an explicit manner. From thisperspective, it appears that the ultimate goal of the treatise was toenable the reader to become competent in logic and especially compe­tent in assessing the different ranks of the classes of concept andassent used in the already perfected arts, not so much in order to learnthe essentials of those arts as in order to learn how to evaluate themcritically. The identification of that ultimate goal cannot, therefore,be separated from the identification of the already perfected arts.Once both identifications are made, the practical, reformativecharacter of the logical exposition becomes evident.

Another particularly significant hint that these abstract summaries ofthe logical arts contain a broader teaching occurs at the very end of thewhole collection. There, Averroes did not hesitate to place the differentlogical arts in a definite hierarchy. Whereas the particular skill to beacquired from poetics was explicitly judged to be nonessential for man'speculiar perfection, the proper understanding of logic-that is,knowledge of the ranks of the classes of concept and assent-wasexplicitly judged to be propaedeutic to the attainment of ultimatehuman perfection. Ultimate human perfection, moreover, was clearlystated to depend on man's acquiring true theory. The reason for thatdistinction derives from a prior judgment about the superiority oftheoretical knowledge to practical action, and the implication of thedistinction is that the things the art of poetics allows one to makeand do are inferior to the things the larger art of logic allows one tounderstand.50 What is striking about the distinction is that Averroeseschewed the easy subordination of poetics to the larger art oflogic onthe basis ofpart to whole, treating them instead as though in competi­tion for supreme recognition. That is, in fact, faithful to the claims ofthe poetical art's protagonists, and Averroes bore witness to thoseclaims before subordinating poetics to logic in such a definitive manner.

That Averroes concluded the treatise by insisting upon the essentialhierarchy is significant because ofits easily discernible implications. Inthe first place, it suggests that the art oflogic as a whole is not relative,but is guided by reference to a definite standard. Secondly, it showsth~t the different logical arts do not have equal claims to priorityand that their claims are to be judged in terms of their facilitatingthe attainment of ultimate human perfection. The basic idea is thatif man's perfection consists in theoretical understanding, then hisactions or practice should be ordered so as to allow the best develop­ment of his theoretical nature. Logic is important because the charac­teristics of theoretical knowledge are explained in it, and theoreticalknowledge is differentiated from other kinds of knowledge. Moreover,it is the only art which shows how to acquire theoretical knowledge.

It was necessary for Averroes to state the merits of logic so clearly,because its use was condemned by some people with extensive influence.Usually, those who argued against logic criticized its foreign originor claimed that other arts could provide theoretical knowledge in amore direct manner. The general tone of the larger treatise doesaway with the first kind of argument: logic is treated as an art which

Page 18: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

24 THE TEAClliNG OF THE TEXT THE TEACHrNG OF THE TEXT25

belongs to the Islamic world as much as to any other world. Thosearts alluded to in the beginning statement of the purpose of logic,the arts whose critical evaluation logic will facilitate, are among theones thought to have greater merit than logic for attaining theoreticalknowledge. It is for this reason that their critical evaluation is ofsuch importance.

** *Although prepared by the earlier investigation, the critical evalua­

tion is carried out in these three treatises by means of a very selectivepresentation of each logical art. Thus, in setting forth his account ofdialectic, rhetoric, and poetics, Averroes stressed the technical aspectsrelating to the first two arts. A very extensive explanation of the wayarguments are made in each art, of the way they are employed, andof the value of those arguments took the place of an explicit discussionabout how these arts might actually be used, that is, to what substan­tive use they might be put. As a result, essential features of both artswere neglected. For example, in the Short Commentary on Aristotle'sTopics, there is an account of the quality of dialectical premises, ofthe extent of beliefdialectical argument provides, and of the proximityof dialectic to demonstration, but there is no mention whatever of itspossible use for inquiring into the theoretical arts or into the samesubjects as metaphysics-uses clearly indicated in other commen­taries.51 Similarly, in the Short Commentary on Aristotle's Rhetoric, thestandard uses to which rhetoric may be put-deliberation, defenseand accusation, praise and blame-are passed over in silence untilthe very end of the treatise; even then, they are mentioned onlyincidentally. The Short Commentary on Aristotle's Poetics is presented in adifferent manner, however. Very little is said about the technicalparts of the poetical art, and relatively much is said about the uses towhich it may be put. To p~rceive the details of this selectiveness moreclearly and to grasp its significance, it is necessary to look at thesummary of each art.

When speaking about the art of dialectic, Averroes emphasized thatit should not be confused with demonstration despite the appearance ofcertainty which its arguments provide. The crucial difference betweenthe two arts is that dialectical premises may be false, whereas demon­strative premises are always certain and true. Consequently, not truth­as with demonstration-but renown is the basic consideration in

choosing a dialectical premise. The premises used in dialecticalsyllogisms differ from those used in demonstrative syllogisms for yetanother reason: although universal predicates, they do not encompassall of the universal predicates used in demonstration. Nor are thepremises ofdialectical syllogisms all that prevent it from being identicalto demonstration: in addition, the induction used in dialectic has avery limited use in demonstration. Finally, dialectic differs fromdemonstration because the classes of syllogism to which it has access arefar more numerous than those open to the art of demonstration.52

Obviously, one should not confuse the art of dialectic with that ofdemonstration. Still, the whole presentation appears very arid, and onecannot help but wonder why Averroes would. have been content toinsist upon all these technical considerations in order to make such a

minor point.The answer is relatively simple: the tedious technical discussion is a

screen for a more important substantive argument. The long discussionof induction, for example, prepared the grounds for Averroes'scriticism of the dialectical theologians. This becomes apparent oncethe particular induction repeatedly cited by Averroes is carefullyconsidered: it is the one used to prove that all bodies are createdbecause most of those to be seen around us are created. The conclusionof that induction was itself the major premise for the familiar syllogismabout the world being created because it is a body. Although he neverexplicitly refuted either argument, Averroes showed that the use ofinductions to arrive at premises of syllogisms was highly questionablelogical practice. At the most, inductions could be helpful for affirmingsomething that was already generally acknowledged, but never fordiscovering what was unknown. His teaching therefore restrictedinduction to a very limited role in dialectical argument. The im­plication was that those who used induction extensively and placedno restrictions on its use-as the dialectical theologians did, forexample-really knew nothing about the art they claimed to practice.

The best way of indicating this appreciation of their worth was todestroy the grounds of their arguments and to establish the correctbasis of the art. That is why Averroes tried to identify the kind ofassent dialectic provides, show what the true dialectical argumentis and how it is constructed, explain the limits of the premises used inthose syllogisms, and relate the art of dialectic to other arts accordingto the quality of its arguments. Above all, that tactic allowed him to

Page 19: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

26 TIlE TEACIIING OF THE TEXT THE TEACHING OF THE TEXT 27

avoid mentioning the dialectical theologians by name, a move thatwas masterfully subtle: rather than attack them openly here, hepretended to ignore them as though this were not the place to speakof them. The effect of his silence, then, was to suggest that they shouldnot really be associated with the art of dialectic. Even though it waspossible to say that they practiced an art in their theological disputa­tions, it was clear that the art was not dialectic.

This interpretation admittedly places extensive emphasis onAverroes's silence about the dialectical theologians. Yet no otherexplanation can account for the strange character of this treatise,especially as compared to the Short Commentary on Aristotle's Rhetoric.If a discussion about the dialectical theologians were to occur in anytreatise, it is reasonable that it occur in a treatise about dialectic­the art they claimed to practice. However, Averroes relegated thatdiscussion to his treatise on rhetoric. Even so, he did not completelyexclude consideration of the dialectical theologians from this treatisefor he made obvious allusions to their favorite arguments. It seemsnecessary, therefore, to ask about the relationship between the teachingof the treatise and the unexpectedly neglected dialectical theologians.As has already been suggested, the whole movement of the treatisetoward a strict interpretation of dialectic then becomes especiallysignificant. In addition, by insisting more upon the limitations thanupon the varied uses of dialectic and more upon what it was notappropriate for than what it was appropriate for, Averroes was ableto indicate his disagreements with the dialectical theologians.

For example, according to this treatise the art of dialectic would beentirely unsuited for investigation. Averroes remained silent about itsinvestigative possibilities here. He also emphasized the technical differ­ences between dialectic and demonstration, as though he wanted tosuggest that dialectic does not have the same force or logical necessityas demonstration. Above all, he explicitly denied that training indialectic could have any relevance for pursuit of the demonstrativearts, a denial which was simply contrary to Aristotle's view.53 Clearly,Averroes wanted to show that dialectic ought not to be used to inves­tigate the same subjects the art ofdemonstration is used to investigate.However, because of the numerous references to the investigativepossibilities of dialectic in Averroes's other writings, this presentationmust be considered partial or restrictive. The fuller teaching is thatdialectic may be used to investigate any subject investigated by the

art of demonstration, but that the degree of certainty to be expectedof dialectical investigation is inferior to what might be expected ofdemonstrative investigation.

By presenting this partial or restrictive teaching about dialectic,Averroes enabled the reader to call the whole activity of the dialecticaltheologians into question. If the art of dialectic cannot be used formost kinds of theoretical investigation, then it cannot support thecomplicated theological disputes characteristic of dialectical theology.Those disputes presuppose a detailed and deep metaphysical inquiryfor which dialectic-as presented here-would be inadequate.Consequently, either the dialectical theologians reached their con­clusions by means ofanother art and then presented them in dialecticalterms or they attributed too much certainty to their dialectical argu­ments. Whatever the explanation, their use of dialectic was erroneous.

Averroes could have made the same point without presentingdialectic in this partial or restrictive manner. In the Incoherence of theIncoherence, for example, he used dialectical arguments to counteral-Ghaziili's attacks against philosophy. The subject matter was suchthat he thus used dialectic to investigate weighty philosophical andtheological issues. Yet he never lost sight of the limitations of the artand frequently apologized for the general character of his arguments,explaining that they were based on premises which presupposed afuller examination of each issue.54 Although it suggested the problem­atic character of his own replies to al-Ghaziili, this admission of thelimitations of dialectical argument raised a graver problem withregard to al-Ghaziili's original criticisms: on what deeper investigationwere they based? The advantage of the partial or restrictive teachingabout dialectic in the Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, then, isthat this problem was raised quickly and decisively.

Averroes attempted to restrict his presentation of the art ofdialecticin another way. At the very end of the treatise, when enumeratingthe reasons which prompted Aristotle to write about the art, hedescribed dialectic as an art limited to contentious argument betweenquestioner and answerer and even suggested that Aristotle's majorpurpose in writing about dialectic was to provide each contenderwith the tools that would help defeat the opponent. The explanationwas that once Aristotle had noted that most well-known premises-thebasic elements of dialectical argument-are in opposition and maythus be used to prove or disprove the same proposition, he then

Page 20: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

28 THE TEACHING OF THE TEXT THE TEACHING OF THE TEXT 29

recognized how useful the art of dialectic was for training in conten­tious speech. Again, even though Averroes obviously recognized theneed to indicate the partial character of his presentation and thusadmitted that dialectic had uses other than contentious argument,he immediately reinforced his partial interpretation by dismissingthose other uses as irrelevant for the purposes of this treatise and didso without even listing them. As presented here, the contentious artof dialectic is more like the art of fencing: it is good for contendingwith someone else, but it should be directed by another art.

This partial or restrictive insistence on the contentious character ofthe art served two purposes. First of all, it drew attention to thequestion of the audience whom the dialectical theologians usuallyaddressed. If dialectic is really suited for contentious argumentbetween men of equal capacity, it can have little effect when it isemployed by the learned to communicate with the usually uneducatedmass of people. It appears that the dialectical theologians were tryingto use dialectic for the wrong purpose; the art of rhetoric is muchbetter suited for instructing the general public. Secondly, this partialaccount of the art provides a very accurate idea of the original dutyof the dialectical theologians: contending with each other or with themisdirected in defense of the faith.55 They seem to have neglectedtheir original duty, which was more consonant with the art ofdialectic,to attempt activities for which dialectic is very poorly suited.

These thoughts, prompted by an attentive reading of the treatise,show that in order to uncover Averroes's teaching it is as importantto ask about what is implied as to ask about what is said. Because theomissions are as significant as the declarations, the only way toexplain the whole treatise adequately is to ask about what is missing.A simple account of the technical description ofdialectic would not besufficient, because that description is at such variance with Averroes'sother explanations of the art. Moreover, an account of the technicalcharacteristics of dialectic would neglect the allusions to a broaderissue. The interpretation set forth here not only explains all the partsof the treatise, it also provides a means of relating this treatise to theother treatises as part of one teaching.

The striking difference between the Short Commentary on Aristotle'sTopics and the Short Commentary on Aristotle's Rhetoric is the emphasis onthe dialectical theologians in the latter. Abu al-Ma'ali and al-Ghazaliare named a number of times, and there are passing references to the

dialectical theologians as a group. In addition, several arguments of·Abu al-Ma'ali and al-Ghazali are cited in order to illustrate differentfeatures of rhetorical discourse.56 However, very few of the referencesare favorable. In almost every instance, Averroes cited the argumentof the dialectical theologians as a negative example and then went onto suggest the correct rhetorical argument.57

It was appropriate to criticize the arguments used by the dialecticaltheologians according to the standards for rhetorical discourse becausethe dialectical theologians were so ignorant about the technicalcharacteristics of dialectic that they sought to use it when they shouldhave used rhetoric. Rhetoric is the proper art for instructing the generalpublic or addressing it about any matter. That is why Averroesreferred to it as "this art of public speaking" in the opening lines of theShort Commentary on Aristotle's Rhetoric and arranged the discussion ofrhetoric in the treatise according to the persuasiveness of differentsubjects. For the same reason, when he set down instructions forconstructing rhetorical arguments he emphasized what would havegreatest persuasive effect on the audience.58 In fact, the wholetreatise is organized so as to show why rhetoric is more suited for pub­lic discourse than dialectic. The basic reason is one that was alludedto in the Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics: rhetoric permits thespeaker to pass over difficult matters or even to be deceptive regardingthem, whereas such practices cannot be admitted in dialecticalargument.59

One reason the dialectical theologians might have been so confusedabout the technical characteristics of dialectic that they would tryto use it when rhetoric would have been a better tool is that, super­ficially, the two arts are quite similar. They both have the samegeneral purpose of bringing about assent. They are also similar inthat each art is dependent on a kind of common opinion known assupposition. Averroes did not hesitate to point out these similaritiesnor to direct the reader's attention to them by talking about rhetoricalarguments as though they were special examples of dialectical argu­ments. The enthymeme was said to correspond to the syllogism andthe example to the induction. He even analyzed the forms of theenthymeme according to the categories normally used to discussdialectical syllogisms and, in the discussion of the material aspectsof the enthymeme, implied that parallels with the syllogism could bedrawn.6o

Page 21: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

30 THE TEACHING OF THE TEXTTHE TEACHING OF THE TEXT 31

Nonetheless, the similarities between dialectic and rhetoric are onlysuperficial. When the two arts are more closely considered, it becomesreadily apparent that they are not identical. For example, even thoughboth arts are used to bring about assent, syllogisms and inductionsare used to accomplish this task in dialectic while persuasive thingsare used in rhetoric -that is, even though enthymemes and examplesare used, persuasive devices having nothing to do with syllogisticargument may just as easily be used. Then again, while both arts aredependent upon supposition, the particular type of supposition used inrhetoric is of a lower order than that used in dialectic. A corollary ofthat difference is that rhetorical arguments induce people to belief forreasons which usually do not withstand deeper scrutiny and thusoccupy a lower rank with regard to certainty than dialectical argu­ments.61 Even the emphasis on the dialectical syllogism served todistinguish the two arts. By constantly drawing attention to thedialectical syllogism, Averroes was able to contrast it with the rhetor­ical argument par excellence, the enthymeme, and to show in whatways they differed.62

The superficial parallelism that Averroes drew between the twoarts served a dual purpose. In the first place, h:s explanations that thedifferences between the two arts were greater than their similaritiespermitted him to show why rhetoric was better suited for the purposesof dialectical theology than the art of dialectic. At one point, usingrhetoric to explain rhetoric, Averroes could even call upon the famousal-Ghazali for testimony that people with different intellectualcapacities needed to be addressed in different ways.63 Unfortunately,neither al-Ghazali nor the other dialectical theologians had thoughtabout applying such a principle to their own popular writings. ~s

has been previously noted, however, Averroes had thought about It;most of his criticism of the dialectical theologians and their argumentswas directed to that issue. It was in order to show why these argumentscould not be used to persuade people, not in order to harm religion,that he pointed out the weaknesses of their theological arguments.

The use of the superficial parallelism also permitted Averroes tomake an important substantive argument. When discussing thedifferent uses ofenthymemes and examples, as well as their similarities

.to the dialectical syllogisms and inductions, Averroes twice referred toAbu al-Ma'ali in order to show how an inadequate grasp of rhetoricled to deeper errors about important theoretical subjects.64 Because

he did not understand how to use a disjunctive conditional syllogism,Abu al-Ma'ali mistakenly believed that he had refuted the idea thatthe world might have come into being through the uniting of variouselements. This mistaken belief not only meant that he failed to refutethat idea, it was also a reason for him to abandon further inquiryinto the problem. His erroneous belief that it was possible to acq~ire

universal certainty by means of the example led to even more alarmmgconsequences: according to Averroes, to attribute such power to theexample would reduce scientific investigation to child's play and renderany kind of instruction useless. Thus, in addition to co~fusing t~e

usually uneducated mass of people by addressing them wIth complI­cated arguments, the dialectical theologians led themselves into errorby failing to comprehend the deeper significance of their own argu­ments. Another reason for showing the inadequacies in their argu­ments' then, was to show why those arguments needed to be examinedmore carefully and why the possibility for deeper philosophical inquiryneeded to be kept open. In both instances, the arguments of thedialectical theologians were refuted in order to suggest how theycould be improved.

However, the dialectical theologians were not the only ones to haveinsufficient knowledge about the characteristics of the logical arts.While they used something like rhetorical arguments without beingfully aware of what they were doing, practitioners of other arts useddifferent kinds of rhetorical devices without having an adequateunderstanding of the limitations of such devices. The last third of thetreatise on rhetoric is devoted to a discussion of the persuasive thingsexternal to the art of rhetoric, things which are explicitly assigned alower rank of logical value and rhetorical merit than the enthymemeor example.65 Central to that discussion was a consideration of howthe arguments proper to the traditionalist schools of theology andjurisprudence-testimony, recorded traditions, consensus, and chal­lenging-might be used. The traditionalist theologians and jurists hadfailed to understand the rhetorical origins of these devices and con­sequently relied upon them too heavily. As a result, conflict and strifearose concerning things allegedly proven by these devices. To remedythat situation Averroes tried to show the precise limitations of thesedevices and to clarify their very restricted persuasive qualities.66

He identified testimony as being a report about something or a seriesof reports-i.e., a tradition-about something and said that testimony

Page 22: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

32 TIrE TEACHING OF THE TEXT THE TEACHING OF THE TEXT 33

was about things either perceived by the senses or apprehended bythe intellect. Although testimony could be concerned with whatwe ourselves have perceived or intellectually apprehended, it is unusualto report such matters to ourselves. For that reason, Averroes directedhis remarks to an explanation of the extent of belief which ought to beaccorded what others claim to have perceived or to have intellectuallyapprehended.67 His argument was that unless we ourselves haveperceived what has been reported or are able to form an imaginativerepresentation of it, reporting can lead to essential certainty only if itcan be proven by a syllogism.68 Although he did not go into exten­sive detail about these conditions, it is not difficult to think ofsituationsin which they might be applied. What, for example, would be aconvincing imaginative representation of divine revelation to a par­ticular individual? Or how could a syllogism about the event beconstructed? The problem becomes more difficult when the reportsconcern sense-perceptible matters which have never been perceived;for instance, a secret and solitary voyage by an easily recognizableand famous figure.

Averroes also tried to explain the kinds ofproblems which arise withregard to what has been intellectually apprehended. Testimony aboutthis sort of thing can be ofvalue only to those unable to apprehend it,e.g., the usually uneducated mass ofpeople.69 Still, for testimony to beeffective in this instance, something more is needed. The audiencemust have some notion of the significance of what is being reported,and that can be acquired only by careful explanation. For example,it is not enough to report that a particular individual received a specialrevelation from a divine agent. In addition, an effort must be madeto explain what revelation is, how it can be transmitted, and what thatmeans for the people exposed to the revelation.

His basic argument was that, whether the matter reported about hadbeen intellectually apprehended or perceived by the senses, recourseto reports could not replace intellectual understanding. Reports arenothing more than persuasive devices and are subject to the samekinds of limitations as other rhetorical devices. For this reason hecriticized those who sought to derive certainty from reports by enu­merating conditions with which to judge the quality of differentreports.70 Averroes's goal was to underline the suppositional characterof reports so that those who used them could begin to think about theproblems of communicating the meaning of these reports to others.

Throughout the discussion he tried to insist that testimony or reportingwas only of persuasive value; the fuller context of the report hadto be understood and explained before it could have any widervalue.

When discussing the other persuasive devices external to the art ofrhetoric, Averroes reached similar conclusions. He did not consider itpossible, for example, to cite consensus to prove the validity of any­thing. As al-Ghazali had admitted, there was such confusion aboutthe whole notion ofconsensus that agreement about the exact definitionof the term was lacking.71 Averroes never questioned the principlethat when the community of Muslims agreed upon something, theiragreement was infallible. He simply argued that it was not possible toascertain how that agreement might be determined and thus notpossible to use it for deciding whether a person or doctrine had violatedthe consensus.

Even accomplishing miraculous feats in order to challenge othersto belief had definite limitations according to Averroes, since theability to perform miracles is no sign of special wisdom. At the most,Averroes conceded that such an ability ought to induce people to havea good opinion ofthe person who performs such feats and to be disposedto believe him. But the more important question was how to acquiresome kind of knowledge that would permit a sound judgment aboutthe teaching that this miracle-worker would then set forth. Once againAverroes was able to cite al-Ghazali as an eminent witness whoshared this point ofview.72

The teaching about these persuasive devices which are external tothe art of rhetoric is that they cannot be used as evidence of certainknowledge, except under limited conditions. Averroes also explainedthat these devices may stand in need of the enthymeme to achieveeven their limited effect. The significance of a report, for example,might become clear only when explained by an enthymeme. For thatreason, the art of rhetoric should be organized in a way that permitsthe enthymemes to have their rightful precedence. By organizing theart according to such a hierarchy, another benefit is acquired: to theextent that enthymemes are like syllogisms, this organization of theart insures the possibility of acquiring certainty. When the enthymemestake precedence, it is easier to guide rhetoric by a more rigoroussyllogistic art. Averroes thought that the ancients had understood theart in this way and he tried to preserve that understanding.73

Page 23: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

34 THE TEACHING OF THE TEXT THE TEACHING OF THE TEXT 35

However, in presenting this view of the art, Averroes restricted rhet­oric in an important respect. Until the very end of the treatise, rhetoricwas discussed in a context that made it seem to have use only for thepopular discussion ofreligion or for instruction. Every effort was madeto show the similarities and differences between dialectic and rhetoric.It is only in the penultimate paragraph, just before turning to a consid­eration of poetics, that the political uses of rhetoric are mentioned.The earlier portions of the treatise concentrated on the technicalaspects of the art and stressed its superficial similaritie~ with dialectic.The end of the treatise stresses the uses to which rhetoric can be put,and these uses turn out to be very similar to those of the art of poetics.

For the purposes of this collection of commentaries, then, rhetoriccan be said to occupy a middle ground between the art ofdialectic andthe art of poetics. It is similar to dialectic in that its arguments can bediscussed and analyzed in terms of their formal characteristics; it issimilar to poetics in that it has great usefulness for political matters.By neglecting the political uses of rhetoric and concentrating on theways rhetoric could be used in the popular discussion of religion or forinstruction, Averroes was able to set forth his criticisms of dialecticaltheology. Since he could not remain completely silent about thepolitical uses of rhetoric, he did the next best thing and acknowledgedthose uses briefly at the very end of the treatise when discussing thereasons which prompted Aristotle to study the art of rhetoric. Such atactic allowed him to avoid explicit endorsement of Aristotle's viewswhile suggesting at least tacit agreement with them. More importantly,that reference to Aristotle's views was sufficient to remind the thought­ful reader of what had been omitted from the preceding discussionand thus to underline the corrective teaching about the dialecticaltheologians.

Emphasis on the political usefulness ofpoetics is the dominant themeof Averroes's Short Commentary on Aristotle's Poetics. He began the trea­tise with a statement about the political uses to which the art ofpoeticsmight be put and later explained how recognition of these uses hadprompted Aristotle to write about poetics. While the acknowledgementof Aristotle's recognition of the political uses of rhetoric was perfunc­tory in the Short Commentary on Aristotle'r Rhetoric, the acknowledgementof his recognition of the political uses of poetics is given more attentionin this treatise. Here, the acknowledgement is preceded by Averroes'sown recognition of those uses, and it is complemented by the art being

recommended to our attention because of its suitability for politicaluses.74 Essentially this treatise differs from the other two treatises inthat the technical aspects of poetics are almost passed over in thistreatise in order to stress the political uses ofthe art. In each ofthe othertwo treatises, the practical uses of dialectic or of rhetoric were almostpassed over in order that the technical aspects of either of those artsmight be stressed. An example of the way technical explanations arealmost passed over in this treatise is the absence of a discussion aboutthe amount of assent provided by the speeches used in poetics. Infact, the word "assent" (t~diq) does not even occur in the treatise.Such indifference to the technical aspects of the art is counterbalancedonly by explicit admissions about the potentially deceptive qualityof poetics and by attempts to explain those admissions. 75

Poetics is potentially deceptive because of the character of thespeeches used in the art. The poet may strive to make these speechesrhythmical in order to move the souls of the listeners as he desires, buthe gives no consideration to ordering these speeches in order to bringthem closer to truth or to certainty. To the contrary, poetic speechesare explicitly said to be usually oflittle value for seizing the essence ofanything.76 The reason is that although they are meant to give animaginative representation of something, the resulting imaginativerepresentation is not designed to portray the object as it really is.Consequently, a literal interpretation of poetic speeches will quiteprobably lead to error. However, listeners can just as readily bedeceived by poetic speeches if they make a mistake about the way inwhich the imaginative representation is couched: even though thelisteners may know better than to take the speech literally, theycould fall into error by taking the speech as a metaphor when it isreally a simile or vice versa.77

Still, all of these errors can be traced to simple confusion on thepart of the listeners about the meaning of the particular poeticspeeches. Closer attention to the rules of the art and to the speechesthemselves would help to avoid these kinds of errors. In these cases theerror can be corrected by using another kind of speech to describe thething in question. When the sea is spoken of as being "the sweat of theearth brought together in its bladder," for example, it is readilyapparent that a simple physical explanation of seawater and of thetopography of the earth would dispel any tendency to literal belief inthis poetic image.78 However, there are things which cannot be

Page 24: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

36 THE TEACHING OF THE TEXT THE TEACHING OF THE TEXT 37

conceived of at all or which are extremely difficult to form a conceptabout except by the kinds of allusions given in imaginative represen­tations. Unfortunately, poetic speeches about these kinds of thingslead to error even more frequently.79 Moreover, to the extent that it isimpossible or extremely difficult to explain such things by any otherkind of speech, there is little chance of removing the error once itoccurs. Averroes gave only one example of these kinds of things: abeing which is neither in the world nor outside of it, that is, God.80

Admittedly, it is extremely difficult, if not impossible, to conceive ofGod by means of anything other than imaginative representations.Nor can it be denied that confusion, if not error, about God is wide­spread.

These things which are difficult or impossible to conceive of seemto differ in additional ways from the other things which are alsorepresented by poetic speeches but are easily conceived of. AlthoughAverroes nowhere admitted as much, clearly it is only with regard tothe former kinds of things that the practical uses of poetics come intoplay. These uses include moving the souls of the listeners to predilec­tion for something or to flight from it, moving them to believe ordisbelieve in something, and moving them to do or not do certain kindsof actions. The art of poetics may also be used simply to move thesouls of the listeners to awe or to wonder because of the delightfulnessof the imaginative representation.81 While the souls of the listenersmay be moved to predilection for God or to a desire to flee from Himbecause of the poetic speech presented to them, it is unlikely that apoetic speech about the sea would have such an effect. A poetic speechabout natural phenomena would arouse such emotions only to theextent that the listeners were moved to contemplate the cause of suchpleasing or terrifying things, but that too would be linked closely to thenotion of God. The contrast becomes starker upon considering theusefulness of poetic speeches for inducing belief or disbelief in some­thing. Similarly, imaginative representations about natural pheno­mena are not designed to move the listeners to action. At the most,poetic speeches about natural phenomena arouse feelings of awe orwonder in the souls of the listeners; such speeches instruct the listenersabout the beauty or the awesomene~s of the surrounding world.

When these explanations about the potential for deceptiveness inpoetic speeches-especially those speeches about things which it isimpossible or extremely difficult to conceive of except by poetic

speeches-are carefully considered and compared to the ~mphasis

on the practical uses of poetics, a new significance of the treatIse comesinto focus. In addition to its political uses, poetics would seem to havepatent religious uses. The reasoning behind this conclusion is that in­fluencing the opinions or beliefs and the actions of others is as much aconcern of religion as it is of politics. This is especially true of the kindof religion which strives to provide for the welfare of a community ofbelievers, that is, of a religion like Islam.82 Another way of statingthis would be to say that politics is seen to be more than secular. Byintroducing the idea of speaking about God and showing how it isrelated to the practical uses of poetics, Averroes has suggested thatpolitical concerns are necessarily related to religious concerns.

Although it becomes most apparent in this treatise, that relationshipis not introduced for the first time here. The argument of the other twotreatises presupposed the interplay between religion and politics. In thetreatises on dialectic and rhetoric, a major effort was made to correctthe evils wreaked by the dialectical theologians and to establish princi­ples which would prevent those evils from recurring. While the evils inquestion derived primarily from the realm of religious opinion orbelief, they clearly had consequences in the political realm. Thetreatise on poetics differs from those two treatises because the interplaybetween religion and politics is made more apparent and because thereis a very explicit emphasis on how the art can influence actions. Thereis, then, a movement or a shift in emphasis in these treatises, a move­ment from concern solely about opinions or beliefs to concern aboutboth belief and actions. That movement is symbolic of the movementfrom a narrow concern with religion and politics to a more inclusiveconcern with both. Insofar as the treatise on poetics represents theculmination of that movement, it stands apart from the other twotreatises.

A sig~ of the different status of the treatise on poetics is the ab­se,nce of any reference to the dialectical theologians or to the problemsthey caused. The emphasis here is massively on what the art is for, noton ways that it might be corrected. That does not mean, however,that this treatise occupies a higher rank than the other two treatises.Indeed, the art of poetics as presented here is hardly free from majordifficulties. The primary difficulty is the apparent inevitability ofdeception in the poetic speeches that deal with concepts like God.Implicitly, the argument is that such deceptiveness is part of poetic

Page 25: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

38 THE TEACHING OF THE TEXTTHE TEACHING OF THE TEXT 39

..,

~peeches qua poetic speeches, as though the art of poetics had nomter?al standards: Averroes brought the problem into sharper per­spectIve by suggestmg that speeches about such subjects, insofar as theywere deceptive, were more characteristic ofsophistry than of poetics.83

.Although he did not explain what he meant by drawing the parallelwIth reference to these speeches, he made a similar observation aboutpoetics in the subsequent paragraph. He noted that poetics wasclassed among the syllogistic arts even though the syllogism is used init only to make poetic speeches deceptively resemble speeches of otherarts.84 The implication is that poetics can be used for willful decep­ti~n. When the p~et pretends to have proofs about what he sayswIth~ut really ~avmg them, poetics strongly resembles sophistry. Inthat mstance hIS use of syllogistic arguments would not be in accordwith the logical rules for their use, but would be deceptively structuredin order to receive greater credibility than they might otherwisereceIVe.

. Suc~ a possibility arises because, with poetics as with rhetoric, thereIS no mternal control to keep it from being used for deceptive pur­poses,85 With dialectic and demonstration, however, the rules ofsyllogistic reasoning must be followed. Any purposely deceptive use ofthe arguments belonging to those arts is external to the art. Becausepoetics is not structured in that way and can therefore be used assophistry would be, the deceptiveness ofits speeches-especially thoseconcerning things which cannot be conceived of at all or onlyconceived of with difficulty by other speeches-seems inevitable. Bylinking poetics and sophistry on this issue, Averroes suggested that hedrew the same conclusion.

Yet that conclusion is not without exception. The inevitability of~ec~pt~on ~bout this kind .of poetic speech depends on a very basiclImItatIOn m the explanatIOn, a limitation Averroes need not haveimposed. Confusion about the subjects treated by this kind of poeticspeech could be removed by metaphysical investigation. However,Averroes remained silent about that possibility. Through his silencehe presented as restrictive a teaching about poetics as he did aboutdialectic. .

Inpart, this restrictive te~~~i~~aboutpoetics allowed him to criti­cize die way the art was beirigusea:''TI1af'lie was not more explicit inhis criticism can be understood by reflecting about the generallyaccepted view among Muslims that the Qur'an is the best example of

poetic excellence in Arabic. Without becoming involved in thatcontroversy, he nevertheless managed to make certain suggestionsabout Qur'anic exegesis. His belief about the potential deceptivenessof poetic speeches carried the implication that it was necessary tokeep imaginative representations simple and as direct as possible. Inthis respect, the treatise on poetics, like the treatise on dialectic andrhetoric, contributes to a solution of the fundamental practical issue.By emphasizing the dangers of poetic speech and its politico-religioususes, this treatise subtly urges great care upon those who would usesuch speech to communicate with most people and especially uponthose who might seek to interpret such speech to the people. Howeversuch advice is never given; to the extent that it is a consequence of theargument, it is only an implicit consequence. The treatise on poeticsremains at a certain level of abstraction at all times.

The restrictive teaching about poetics also allowed Averroes to putthe general argument of these three treatises into the proper perspec­tive. Because the potential deceptiveness of poetic speeches broughtthe art into close relationship with sophistry, Averroes insisted at thevery end of the treatise that perfect skill in poetics was foreign toultimate human perfection.86 He explained this judgment in hissummary of the whole collection of short commentaries by noting thatultimate human perfection depended on correct theoretical knowl­~dge.87 It was clear from the preceding exposition that poetics couldnot furnish such knowledge. It is equally clear from the presentationof dialectic and rhetoric that they could not furnish such knowledgeeither. For the attainment of ultimate human perfection or COlrecttheoretical knowledge, another art was needed-an art based on a fullmastery of logic.

Such a judgment was not meant to suggest that these arts werewithout value. In the first place, it is reasonable that a similar con­clusion be drawn at the end of a collection of short commentaries onlogic. After all, the study of logic is a preliminary for the pursuit oftheoretical knowledge. Even the general order of this collectionsuggests the primary importance attached to theoretical knowledge.The first few treatises prepared the reader for the study of demonstra­tion, and it was presented as the pinnacle oflogical thinking. Thus thefirst few treatises were steps up to demonstration. From that peak, thetreatises on the logical arts concerned with opinion represented a kindof descent: they were based on varying degrees of opinion, while

Page 26: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

demonstration was based on certainty; they were used to discussparticulars while demonstration was used to discuss universals. It isalso possible to discern a descending order among these treatisesconcerned with opinion, a movement from opinion bordering oncertainty to representations bordering on error. Of the three arts,dialectic most resembles demonstration and poetics is least similar to it.By placing these treatises after the discussion about demonstration,Averroes also indicated that one can understand how to work withopinions only after adequately learning' how to acquire certain knowl­edge.

However, Averroes never insisted here that practical life had to beguided by theoretical knowledge. To the contrary, the basic andexplicit argument of these treatises is that opinion usually suffices fordecent human life. The virtues, for example, are presented as moralhabits based on what is generally accepted, not on what is certain.88

In a similar manner, the restrictive presentation of each of these threetreatises served to delineate an area ofaction in which popular opinionis sufficient. Thus, while his silence about the theoretical uses ofdialectic indicated that dialectic should'not be used for philosophicalpursuits, he argued for the art being used with confidence in otherdomains.

The goal was to show why the arts based on opinion were bestsuited for certain functions but also why they had to be limited in theirapplication to those functions. In most practical situations, timerestrictions and the intellectual shortcomings of other people makeit difficult to attain demonstrative certainty. All that is necessary is thattheoretical knowledge not be endangered by opinions used in thepractical situations. Averroes attacked the dialectical theologiansbecause they had become confused about the pursuit of theoreticalknowledge and had set forth opinions which were harmful to furthertheoretical investigation. At the same time he attempted to indicatehow common opinion should be viewed and what its limitations were.It might be said that he rehabilitated common opinion. He did soby making a strong defense of its practical merits, by proving thatthose who were most scornful of common opinion were actually mostdependent upon it for their own reasoning, and by showing how it~ht,be,used"inopubliG~8~~ay.he .was able to indicatethe need for eliminating the confusing and complicated speech usuallyused for public discourse. Similarly, his identification of the limits

and different ranks of common opinion served to restrain those whowould hastily conclude that all inquiry was relative and perhapscause greater political harm. Moreover, by insisting that the standardagainst which common opinion was to be judged was its approxima­tion to certain knowledge, Averroes kept alive the possibility ofcoming very close to the ideal of ultimate human perfection. Hisrehabilitation of common opinion in no way lowered the goal ofpractical life.

However, the larger problem behind all of this is that of the relation­ship between politics, religion, and philosophy. As these treatises havebeen examined, it became clear that religious belief was shaped andmolded by each of the different arts. It also became evident thatreligious belief was prior to political action and influenced politicalaction. Moreover, to the extent that these arts depend on correcttheoretical knowledge, the way religious belief is shaped and moldeddepends on correct theoretical knowledge. Differently stated, soundbelief depends on sound investigation. While there is a large area inwhich belief is sound on its own principles, that independence shouldnot be mistaken for opposition to theoretical investigation. The markofgood belief is that it not destroy the possibility offurther theoreticalinquiry; the mark of good theoretical inquiry is that it protect soundbelief and further its acceptance by those unable to pursue theoreticalknowledge.

41THE TEACHING OF THE TEXTTHE TEACHING OF THE TEXT40

Page 27: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

Short Commentary on Aristotle's" Topics"

Page 28: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

Outline ofArgument for theShort Commentary on Aristotle's" Topics" :

INVOCATION AND TITLE

A. Introduction: The purpose of this commentary is to discussdialectical arguments and the extent of assent they provide(para. 1).

B. The extent ofassentprovided by dialectical arguments (paras. 2-4) :

1. They provide belief approximate to certainty (para. 2).

2. However, because of the kinds of premises used in dialecticalarguments, that belief only approximates certainty (para. 3).

3. That is due to the premises of dialectical arguments oftenbeing partially false (para. 4).

C. Classes ofdialectical arguments which bring about assent, accord­ing to their forms (paras. 5-12):

1. There are three different kinds of syllogisms used in dialectic(para. 5).

2. The induction (para. 6) :

a. how it differs from the syllogism (paras. 7-8).b. how the way dialectic uses induction sets it apart from

rhetoric (para. 9).c. because of the limits of the induction, it is best used for

generally accepted premises (para. 10).d. nonetheless, there are instances when it can be used in

demonstration (para. 11).

3. Summary (para. 12).

D. Classes of dialectical arguments leading to assent, according totheir material aspects (paras. 13-19):

1. The different classes ofgenerally accepted premises (para. 13).

45

Page 29: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

46 TOPICS In the name ([[God, the Merciful, the Compassionate.[I beseech] your succor, 0 Lord!!

2. These premises are universal predicates or predicables(para. 14).

3. But only five of the eight universal predicates are used indialectic (para. 15):a. a general definition of each of the five universal predicates

(para. 16).b. although not complete, these definitions offer a sufficient

idea of the universal predicates for present purposes(para. 17).

c. because of the way dialectical syllogisms are constructed,their classes may be twice as numerous as those of demon­strative syllogisms (para. 18).

4. Logical arguments are still another class of argumentleading to assent (para. 19).

E. Summary Statement (para. 20).

F. What prompted Aristotle to write about dialectic (para. 21).

DEDICATION

THE BOOK OF DIALECTIC

[INTRODUCTION]

(1) Since we have spoken about the things by means of which thecertain assent! and the complete concept2 are distinguished andsubsequent to that have spoken about the things which lead to errorconcerning them, let uS speak about dialectical and rhetorical assentand the extent each one provides. For our purposes, it is not necessaryto speak about what makes these arts complete. Let us begin, then,with dialectical arguments.3

[THE EXTENT OF ASSENT PROVIDED BY DIALECTICALARGUMENTS]

(2) We say: the extent [of assent] they provide is supposition!which approximates certainty. In general, supposition is believingthat something exists in a particular kind of way, while it is possiblefor it to be different than it is believed to be. Therefore, its peculiarcharacteristic2 is that it may be eliminated through opposition;demonstration differs in that it has the peculiar characteristic of notbeing eliminated through opposition. There are two divisions ofsupposition. With one, namely dialectical supposition, oppositionto it is not noticed; ifit is noticed, the supposition can only exist withdifficulty. With the other, which is rhetorical, opposition to it is noticed.

(3) That this is the extent of assent this art provides is apparentfrom the definition of the arguments providing it, since the dialecticalargument is a syllogism composed from widespread, generally acceptedpremises.! Now assent about the widespread, generally acceptedpremise results from the testimony of all or most people, not from thematter being like that in itself--contrary to the way it is with demon­stration. Indeed, with demonstration, we arrive at assent which is certainthrough our assenting to premises because to our minds they appearjust as they are externally, not because they are someone else's opinion.

47

Page 30: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

48 TOPICS TOPICS 49

(4) Since that is the case, dialectical premises are often partiallyfalse. If they are found to be entirely true, that occurs by accident,that is, because it happens that what is generally accepted is the sameoutside the mind as it is inside the mind.! However, as we have said,we do not take it from this aspect in these syllogisms, but only from theaspect of it being generally accepted. Therefore, a syllogism of soundfigure2 composed from premises like these necessarily provides aprobable supposition.

[CLASSES OF DIALECTICAL ARGUMENTS BRINGING

ABOUT ASSENT, ACCORDING TO THEIR FORMS]

[THE SYLLOGISM]

(5) Since the extent of assent which this art provides has nowbeen made clear,! we shall speak about the classes of argumentscausing it. Accordingly, we say that the figure of syllogisms bringingabout something like this supposition approximate to certainty mustnecessarily be sound; otherwise, they would be sophistical, contentiousarguments. Therefore, the specific kinds of syllogism used here arethe three specific kinds mentioned in the Prior Analytics, i.e., thecategorical,2 the conditional,3 and the contradictory syllogism4-thesimple and the complex ones. Indeed, it might be possible both toestablish and to refute complex problems by means of complex,dialectical syllogisms like these, since generally accepted premisesleading to the thing sought are right at hand.

[THE INDUCTION]

(6) This art might use another specific kind of assent which is par­ticular to it, namely, induction. With this specific kind of thing whichcauses assent, an affirmative or negative universal judgment is assertedabout a universal matter because that judgment applies to most of theparticulars subsumed under that universal matter. An example ofthat is our asserting that every body is created because we find thatmost bodies are of this description. That is an argument which hasthe force of a syllogism in the first figure,! since the minor term2

is that universal matter, the middle3 the particulars, and the major4the judgment. Nonetheless, the procedure is contrary to the way it isin the syllogism.

(7) That is because with the syllogism we always proceed to theverification of the unknown, partial matter from the universal knownto us or we proceed from the equally known to the equally un.known. However, we do not take the equally-known, universal[matter] as a major premise! here due to its being equally- [known],but due to its being universal-whether that be by nature or by con­vention. Our proceeding to the verification of the partial matter fromthe universal [known] to us is like our explaining that every man issense-perceiving because every animal is sense-perceiving. For man,which is the minor term here, falls under the major premise and isencompassed within it.2 An example of our proceeding from theequally-[known] to the equally-[unknown] is our explaining thatevery man is a laughing being insofar as every man is a speakingbeing.3 For speaking is equivalent to laughing. But laughing is gene­rally taken as being encompassed within speaking and subordinateto it, even though it might be equivalent to it-since there is noharm in doing this.4 For that reason we say that something like this isuniversal by convention.

(8) With induction, we always proceed from the particular to theuniversal. Therefore, if we have, for example, explained by means ofthe induction that every body is created because we have found somebodies to be created, it is clear that we proceed to this universal propo­sition-which is that every body is created-insofar as we have foundsome bodies to be created, like earth, water, air, fire, and others. Thus,the composition of the argument which has the force of the syllogismin the first figure is brought forth like this: "Fire, air, water, and earthare bodies; they are created; so body is created." Yet when theinduction is used all by itself to explain an unknown problem,1 it isnot very persuasive. That is because if by means of the induction itappears that the predicate applies to the subject, then that problemwas not unknown, but was a self-evident premise made apparent bythe induction.

(9) Insofar as this art uses the sound syllogism for an unknownproblem, it does not take what is known in itself as being a problem;rather, something like this is more appropriate to rhetorical methods.Accordingly, in this art induction tends to be used mainly for verifyingthe major premise.! But in something like this as well, induction isuseless. That is because if we have already inductively examined mostof the particulars falling under the major premise and not one of those

Page 31: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

50 TOPICS TOPICS 51

which we have thereby inductively examined is the subject of theproblem, then how did it occur to us that it was encompassed withinthe major premise? And in general, how did certainty that that premiseis universal occur to us? If the subject of the problem was among the[particulars] which we have inductively examined, the very problemreappears as a premise made clear by induction; and the first doubtreappears.2 However, the art of dialectic, does not carry the matterout in such a manner; rather, it asserts that a judgment applies to all[of something] because it applies to most of it, for it is generallyaccepted that the lesser follows the greater.

(10) Even if all of the particulars are exhausted, induction-insofaras it is induction-does not by itself and primarily set forth the essen­tially necessary predicate. For it is not impossible for that universalto be a predicate of all of those particulars accidentally-like someonewho holds the opinion that everything which comes into being comesinto being from what already exists. Therefore, premises such as theseare generally accepted. Now the induction used in demonstration isonly used for guidance toward certainty, not for providing it primarilyand essentially. There is a major difference between what is \lsed forguiding [toward certainty] and what is used for providing [certainty]by itself. Therefore, with regard to the premises about which theinduction provides certainty, we do not require that all of theparticulars be scrutinized; rather, it is sufficient to scrutinize some.

(11) There are only two circumstances in which using induction[in demonstration] is required: (a) for that general sort of premisenone of whose individual cases has happened as yet to be perceived,for example, someone who has never perceived that scammony relievesbile. In cases like this, induction is needed to reach the essentialpredicate. Now these are known as experiential premises, and thesepremises vary in the number of individual instances which need to beperceived [so that] certainty about them then-results. That is differentfor each specific matter:1 for some, a single individual instance needbe perceived-as with many of the arithmetical premises-and withsome more than one need be perceived. The other circumstance whichrequires using induction in demonstration occurs because (b) manypeople do not admit the universality of many premises but admit oneof their particulars-like someone who admits that knowledge ofhealth and sickness belongs to one science, which is the science ofmedicine. Now if he were told that the science of opposites is one,

he would not admit this generalization until it had been made in­ductively clear to him. At that time, he would reach certainty aboutits universality.

(12) This, then, is the form of dialectical arguments leading toassent.

[CLASSES OF DIALECTICAL ARGUMENTS LEADINGTO ASSENT, ACCORDING TO THEIR MATERIAL

ASPECTS]

(13) Their matters, as has been previously [explained],! are thegenerally accepted premises. These are of [different] classes:

(a) Some are generally accepted by everybody, and this is themost noble class. It is possible for all of the different nations tomeet in agreement on this one despite the variance in their sectsand in their natural dispositions. An example is [the premise]that it is good to thank a benefactor or that it is necessary torespect one's parents.

(b) Some of them are generally accepted by most people, withoutthere being any disagreement among the rest about that. Anexample is [the premise] that God is one.

(c) Some of them are generally accepted(i) by learned men and wise men, or by most of them without

the rest disagreeing with them, for example, [the premise] thatknowledge is virtuous in itself; or

(ii) by most of them, for example, [the premise] that theheavens are spherical.

(d) Some of them are generally accepted(i) by the practitioners of the arts, without the multitude disa­

greeing with them about that, for example, [the premise] inthe art of medicine that scammony relieves bile and that thepulp of the colocynth relieves phlegm; or

(ii) by those renowned for skill in the arts, without thepractitioners of the art disagreeing with them, for example,the argument of Hippocrates that weakness arising withoutany precedent cause is a warning of sickness;2 or

(iii) by most of them.

ee) The likeness of what is generally accepted is also generally

Page 32: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

52 TOpICS TOPICS 53

accepted; for example, if it were a generally accepted [premise]that the science ofopposites is one in itself, then sense-perceptionof opposites would be one in itself.

(f) A thing opposed to what is generally accepted is also generallyaccepted. For example, if it were a generally accepted [premise]that one ought to do good to friends, then one ought to do bad toenemies.

Now the most noble of all of these is that which is attested to byeveryone or by most people; anything else will become generallyaccepted solely because of the testimony of everyone or of mostpeople to it. Thus the opinions of learned men become generallyaccepted because everyone or most people hold the opinion that theiropinions ought to be accepted. The same thing holds for the opinionswhich are particular to the arts and for the rest.

(14) These generally accepted premises are necessarily universals,since particulars change and are not perceived byeverybody in the sameway. If they were, they would be taken indefinitely in these syllogisms,and there would be no concern about stating the ellipsis explicitly.That is why these syllogisms do not lie by means of the particular.1

(15) As has been previously [explained], there are eight classes ofuniversals, both simple and complex; genus, species, differentia,property, accident, definition, description, and the statement which isneither definition nor description.1 Since this is so, dialectical predi­cates are necessarily one of these classes. However, because speciess ispredicated only of an individual and a proposition whose predicateis an individual is not used in this art, it is not enumerated here as apredicate. Description3 is subsumed under property, since they havethe same force. Similarly, the statement which is neither definitionnor description4 is subsumed under accident. It turns out, then, thatthere are five classes of dialectical predicates: definition, genus,differentia, property and accident.5

(16) It is sufficient here to describe definition as a statementpointing to that meaning of a thing by means of which its basicstructure and its being are explained.1 Genus is defined here as beingthe predicate, from the aspect ofessence, of several things which differaccording to species.s Differentia is also the predicate of severalthings which differ according to species, [but it is predicated] fromthe aspect of quality.3 Property is the predicate which does not pointto the essence ofthe thing, but applies to all of it, it alone, and alwaysf

Accident is described here in two ways: one is that it is that whichapplies to the thing and is not genus, differentia, property, or defini­tion; the second is that it is that which might apply to one specificthing and might not apply to it. It is described here in two waysbecause, taken together, they lead to accident being conceived ofabsolutely. That is because the first of the two descriptions makesspecific what is not distinctive about accident, and the second what isdistinctive.5

(17) It is clear that the descriptions [given] here are not sufficientfor each one of these to be conceived of completely, but for them to beconceived of in this way is sufficient here. That is because a perfectconcept of the things from which definitions are put together is[given] in the Posterior Analytics.1 Likewise, what is included in thedefinition of genus here is clearly the ultimate genus of the genera.2

Likewise, it is not sufficient for the differentia to be a predicate fromthe aspect of quality without it applying specifically to the thing forwhich it is a differentia.3

(18) If the predicates pertaining to dialectical premises are one ofthese five classes, the types of dialectical syllogisms must correspond towhat is composed from these five the way they are conceived of here.Thus, l they might be taken as a predicate according to the naturalcourse and then converted, and the three terms in the syllogismsmight then be related to each other either by a single one of these fiverelations (like definition or some other relation) or by a combinationof them (like one of the terms being related as a differentia and thesecond as an accident or SQme other relation). Similarly, they mightbe taken in another way; that is, two of the terms might always berelated to the third-either the major term and the middle to theminor, or the minor and the middle to the major-but the two relatedterms would be related to each other only by the predicate ofaccident.This, too, might occur in two ways. Either the two terms might berelated to the other term in a single way (like the major term and themiddle being related to the minor only as definition or any other oneof the five relations). That might be also be done in an oppositemanner (i.e., the minor and the middle might be related to the major inthis way or in any other one of the relations). The other way is forboth terms to be related to the other term in two ways (like the majorterm being related to the minor as definition and the middle beingrelated to the minor as differentia or some other relation). That, too,

Page 33: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

54 TOPICS TOPlCS 55

might be done in an opposite manner (i.e., the minor might be relatedto the major as definition and the middle might be related to themajor as differentia or some other relation). Then if these syllogismswere enumerated in this manner, there would be twice as manytypes of dialectical syllogisms as demonstrative syllogisms. That isbecause with [dialectical syllogisms] no attention is paid to whether apredicate is made naturally or essentially. Because of their strongresemblance and closeness to the types of demonstrative syllogisms,many people suppose that several types of demonstrative syllogismsare missing in Abu Na~r [al-Farabi's] book.2 In truth, they aredialectical syllogisms.

(19) There is another class of arguments here which lead to assent,those known as logical arguments. This class is composed from truepremises which are not essential but are more general than the genusin which they are used. So insofar as it is true, it is supposed thatthis class should be counted among the classes ofdemonstrations; whileinsofar as it is non-essential, it is supposed that this class is dialectical.Themistiusl explicitly stated that this class is not dialectical. However,from the force of Abu Na~r [al-Farabi's] argument, it appears that itis dialectical.2 Now I say unless certainty that a predicate is containedin the substance of a subject or a subject in the substance of the predi­cate causes assent about a given, generally accepted problem, assent isonly caused by general acceptance or by induction. And what is of thissort is necessarily dialectical. But syllogisms such as these are of ahigher rank than dialectical syllogisms, since they are neither falsenor partial.

(20) Now we have said enough for our purposes here.

[CONCLUSION]

(21) When Aristotle distinguished these dialectical argumentsfrom the demonstrative, not only with regard to the matters, butaccording to the [form of the] argumentl as well, he was of the opinionthat syllogisms like these-even if they were not demonstrative-haduses for training due to their being more generally accepted. That isbecause, since several of the generally accepted premises are opposites,it is possible on the basis of these premises to establish and refute thevery same thing. That is to say, he was of the opinion that if two

disputants use syllogisms like these in which two opposing premisesare joined to a minor premise2 in order to establish or refute something,on the condition that one wants to defend it and the other to refute it,then this will result in great training for them-the way it does witharts directed toward other ones, like the art of fencing and others. Onaccount of this, this art is made [to be exercised by] a questioner andan answerer. The questioner's role is to get the answerer to admit whatwill refute his position, and the answerer's role is to refrain fromadmitting anything which will refute his own position. It was for thisthat Aristotle set forth all of the topics from which syllogisms concern­ing every problem are derived, whether the problem be one in whichthe subject is investigated absolutely or in conjunction [with somethingelse], like seeking whether it is genus, definition, or [another] oneof the five relations.3 Then Aristotle set forth, in addition, how thequestioner asks questions and the answerer answers. Furthermore, heset forth particular instructions for the questioner and for the answerer.Therefore this art is defined as an aptitude (a) enabling the questionerto make a syllogism from generally accepted premises for refutingeither of two extremes of the contradiction to which he gets the an­swerer [to admit] and (b) enabling the answerer not to admit anythingto the questioner from which the contradiction of what he positswould necessarily follow. There are other uses of this art alreadyenumerated in the Topics.4 However, training like this seems unneces­sary for the perfection of the demonstrative arts.But if it were, withouta doubt, it would be from the standpoint of the most excellent [kindof training].

The Topics is finished. Praise be to God and His Succor.

Page 34: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

Short Commentary on Aristotle's "Rhetoric"

Page 35: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

Outline of Argument for theShort Commentary on Aristotle's "Rhetoric" :

INVOCATION AND TITLE

A. Introduction (paras. 1-3):

1. Purpose: Discussion of persuasive things and the amount ofassent they provide (para. 1).

2. Persuasive things are divided into speeches and externalthings (para. 2).

3. Order of presentation: First persuasive speeches, then theother persuasive things (para. 3).

B. Persuasive Speeches (paras. 4-32) :

1. The Enthymeme-a syllogism based on unexamined pre­viously existing opinion (paras. 4-25).

a. The forms of syllogisms bring about conclusions by theirspecial construction (paras. 5-15).

1. categorical syllogisms (paras. 6-7):

(a) how this works in the first figure (para. 6).

(b) how this works in the second and third figures(para. 7).

11. conditional syllogisms are oftwo kinds (paras. 8-13) :

(a) conjunctive-how it becomes an enthymeme(para. 8).

(i) an example ofan erroneous use of this byGalen (para. 9).

(ii) how to assure the success of this kind ofsyllogism when the conclusion is sound(para. 10).

59

Page 36: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

60 RIlETORIC RH:ETORIC 61

(b) disjunctive-how it becomes persuasive (para.11).(i) an example of an erroneous use of this by

Abu al-Ma'ali (para. 12).(ii) how to assure the success of this kind

of syllogism when deqling with negations(para. 13).

iii the contradictory syllogism (para. 14).iv. summary (para. 15).

b. Material aspects of the syllogism-a division based onthe premises of the syllogism (paras. 16-25).

1. these premises are considered from the aspect oftheir being generally accepted by unexaminedcommon opinion and fall into two classes (paras.17-19) :(a) proofs are taken from sense-perceived things

and have a further division into proofs properand signs (para. 18).

(b) generally received propositions-examples ofthem (para. 19).

11. examples ofdifferent kinds ofproofs (paras. 20-22) :(a) examples of proofs proper, i.e., those proofs

in the first figure (para. 20).(b) examples of signs in the second figure (para.

21).(c) examples ofsigns in the third figure (para. 22).

iii. major distinction for rhetoric is the status ofpremiseswith regard to unexamined opinion, not their statusas necessary or more possible (para. 23).

iv. in rhetoric, as in dialectic, the premises used may beadapted to the ends of the speaker (para. 24).

v. summary: justification of the division of premisesaccording to the necessary and the possible(para. 25).

·2. The.Example (paras•..26-32Y.".·.

a. Different instances of the kinds of examples (para. 26).b. Difference between example and induction (para. 27).

c. Examples are based on two kinds of likeness, and thesehave certain restrictions (paras. 28-31):1. with an example, it is not possible to make a parti­

cular judgment on the basis ofa universal (para. 29).

11. examples always remain close to unexaminedopinion (para. 30).

iii. Failure to recognize these restrictions led Abu al­Ma'ali astray (para. 31).

d. Summary (para. 32).

C. Persuasive Things Not Occurring by Speeches (paras. 33-44).

1. General enumeration ofthe 11 persuasive things not occurringby speeches (para. 33).

2. Some of these need a further explanation (para. 34).

a. Testimony (paras. 35-40) :1. testimony is a kind of report (para. 35).ii. the groups of theologians differ according to their

opinions about its sufficiency for intellectuallyperceived matters (para. 36).

iii. testimonies about sense-perceived matters arestrengthened when a large number of people reporthaving seen the matters (para. 37).(a) certainty can be attained about such matters

(para. 38).(b) such reports can even bring about certainty

concerning matters that have not beenperceived. (para. 39).

IV. there is no stipulated number of reporters necessaryfor certainty to be brought about (para. 40).

b. Recorded Traditions: Their strength in persuasioncomes from people being brought up according totheir dictates (para. 41).

c. Consensus: Although it has a religious basis, it is notyet clear how inviolable it is (para. 42).

d. Challenging: It is most useful with those who claimto be able to work miracles (para. 43).

Page 37: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

62 RHETORIC

3. Summary: Although all of these have persuasive value,enthymemes are more noble (para. 44).

D. Conclusion (paras. 45-46).

1. Aristotle wrote about these things when he saw their value forpublic discourse about political matters (para. 45).

2. The purpose of this treatise has now been fulfilled (para. 46).

Dedication

In the name ofGod, the Merciful, the Compassionate,

[I beseech] your succor our Lord!l

THE SPEECH ABOUT RHETORICALARGUMENTSl

[INTRODUCTION]

(1) Since we have finished speaking about dialectical syllogismsand the extent of assent they provide, let US speak about persuasivethings and the extent of assent they too provide. It is apparent thatpersuasion is a kind of probable suppositionl which the soul trusts,despite its awareness of an opposing consideration. In what preceded,we already defined supposition.2

(2) From scrutiny and inductive investigation,! it appears that thethings effecting persuasion can first be divided into two classes: oneof them consists in arguments, and the second is external things2 whichare not arguments-like oaths, testimonies, and other things we willenumerate. Similarly, from scrutiny it also appears that the argumentsused in public speaking3 fall into two classes: example and proof.(In this art, the latter is called enthymeme.) That is because whensomeone advises4 someone else to take a certain kind of medicinehe says to him: "Use it because so-and-so used it, and it helped him."He thus persuades him by citing an example. Or he says to him:"You have a disease like this or like that." It is like that with everysingle thing concerning which people converse with one another.

(3) Since it has become apparent that this sort of speaking usesthese two classes of arguments, we will speak about them first. Then,after that, we will go on to speak about the other persuasive things,for the former are more worthy of being considered persuasive thanthe latter and are prior by nature.

[THE ENTHYMEME]

(4) We say: the enthymeme is a syllogism leading to a conclusionwhich corresponds to unexamined opinion previoU31y existing among

63

Page 38: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

64 RHETORIC RJ{ETORIC 65

all or most people. Unexamined previously existing opinion is opinionwhich strikes a man as a probable supposition and which he trusts assoon as it occurs to him, even before he has examined it. Syllogismsbecome conclusive according to unexamined previously existingopinion either because of their forms or because of their matters.1

This happens because of their forms when they are conclusive accordingto unexamined opinion. It happens because oftheir matters when theirpremises are true, ('nce again according to unexamined opinion.

[FORMS OF SYLLOGISMS]

(5) The forms of syllogisms become conclusive according to un­examined opinion by not being strict with regard to them and byomitting from them the thing which causes the conclusion to follownecessarily, the way the multitude is usually content [to do] whenspeaking to one another. Therefore, we ought to consider this notion inconnection with each specific kind ofsyllogism we have enumerated;lfor, by such an enumeration, we will arrive at the types of all thepersuasive syllogisms with respect to their forms.

(6) Thus we say: from what has preceded it is clear that theuniversal premise1 is what causes the conclusion to follow necessarilyin the first figure2 and that the conjunctionS is caused by the minorpremise4 being affirmative. Since this is the case, if the major premisei'is omitted or taken indefinitely the first figure will be persuasive.However, to omit it-as those engaged in demonstration do-is morepersuasive, because omitting it may lead people to fancy: (a) that itwas omitted because there was no point of contention about it and(b) that it is extremely clear. Similarly, in some instances the firstfigure may become persuasive by omitting the minor premise or bytaking it negatively.s

(7) Since it is not clear at the outset which premise brings aboutthe conclusion1 nor which causes the conjunction in the second2 andthe thirdS figures, but it may be the minor premise or the majorpremise, there would be no harm in explicitly stating both premisesin these two [figures]. But, when this is done and neither one has beenomitted, both of them ought to be taken indefinitely; otherwise, nopoint of contention would remain in these two [figures] at all. More­over, among the kinds of inconclusive combinations are those thatare thought to be conclusive according to unexamined opinion without

really being so. Now these kinds of arguments are still persuasivebecause of their forms. An example of this is the combination of twoaffirmative [premises] in the second figure. Similarly, the conclusivetypes [of syllogisms] which are in the third figure are of this kind whentheir conclusions are taken in a universal manner.4 However, inspite of this, one ought not to state the ellipsis in them explicitly butought to take them indefinitely so that the point ofcontention in themmight be more obscure.

(8) CONDITIONAL SYLLOGISMS are disjunctive-as previously stated-and conjunctive. The conjunctive syllogism is made an enthymemeby leaving a point ofcontention in it also. It has already been explainedin the Prior Analytics1 that the conjunctive syllogism becomes conclu­sive when the consequence is valid and when the selected term2

becomes evident by means of a categorical syllogism.s If the selectedterm is self-evident, the consequence must necessarily be explained. Itwas also explained there that the selected term and the conclusioncannot be just any chance conditional or conditioned term.4 Sincethis is the case, this kind of syllogism is only made into an enthymemeby placing some of these restrictions upon it. However, it becomespersuasive primarily by the omission of the selected term. It maybecome persuasive regardless of which term-that is, the conditionalor the conditioned term~rwhich of their contraries is brought forthas a conclusion. In spite of this, however, when there is an invalidconclusion, the selected term leading to it usually should not bestated explicitly for fear the opponent might notice it-like the manwho selects the conditioned term itself and brings forth the conditionalterm as a conclusion or who selects the contrary of the conditionalterm and brings forth the contrary of the conditioned term as aconclusion.s Still, one might explicitly state the selected term in some­thing like this, and the argument will be persuasive; e.g., the argumentofone of the ancients: "If being is created, it has a beginning; but it isnot created, thus it does not have a beginning."

(9) Galen1 and many anatomists use this kind ofsyllogism to deducethe unknown causes of animal actions. For example, he says: "Whenthe reflexive nerve is eliminated, the voice is eliminated; thus, whenthe reflexive nerve exists, the voice exists."2 But it does not necessarilyfollow as stated: for when animals are eliminated, man is eliminated;yet, from the existence of animals, the existence of man does notnecessarily follow.s

Page 39: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

66 RHETORIC RHETORIC 67

(10) In the instance when the conclusion [brought forth] is valid(for example, when it is th~ very opposite of the conditioned term or ofthe conditional term), one must not state the selected term explicitly.Otherwise, unless the conjunction is omitted and is not stated explicitly,no point of contention will remain in the argument.

(11) The disjunctive syllogism becomes persuasive when morethan two opposing considerations exist and they are not all carefullyexamined or when all of the selected terms are not carefully examined.This syllogism does not become persuasive when the selected term isomitted; rather, when that is done, it remains in the very form in whichone seeks to clarify one of the two antitheses into which the problemis divided.1

(12) The argument of Abu al-Ma'ali [al-JuwayniJ,1 in his bookcalled The Spiritual Directive2 when he wanted to refute [the notion of]creation from the elements, is an example of that in which all of theopposing considerations are not carefully examined. For he said:"If a created thing were to have been brought into existence from thefour elements, then that could not help but be (a) by means of somebodies intermixing with others until the mass came together in oneplace or (b) by each one of them independently and separately arisingin the composition; and both of these classes [i.e., alternatives] areabsurd. Thus, that there should be one being created from more thanone element is absurd."3 Now one thing which ought to have been setdown in opposition in the syllogism has been eliminated from thisargument, namely, that an existent thing may come into existence inthe manner of a mixture, as is seen with oxymel4 and with otherartificial things.

(13) The type [of disjunctive syllogism] in which one begins with anegation and arrives at a negation only becomes persuasive whenthe selected term is omitted and the conclusion is stated explicitly.Indeed, when the selected term and the conclusion are both omitted,the hearer does not know which thing you intend to conclude. Here,it is not possible for the explicitly stated selected term to be any chancething nor for it to be according to unexamined opinion; rather, it isalways the assertion1 which is selected and the negation which isbrought forth as a conclusion. However, when that is done, no subjectof persuasion remains in it.

(14) THE CONTRADICTORY SYLLOGISM.1 Ifwe wish the contradictorysyllogism to be persuasive, the doubt-provoking subject and the

consequent absurdity ought to be stated explicitly, while suppressingthe premise from which the absurdity necessarily follows. Still, itmight be explicitly stated when the consequence is not apparent. Thiswould be like our argument: "If every man is not sentient, then everyanimal is not sentient; for every man is an animal."2 This consequenceis in the third figure.

(15) These are the classes of enthymemes according to their forms.They correspond absolutely to the classes of syllogisms.

[MATERIAL ASPECTS OF SYLLOGISMS]

(16) With respect to their matters, syllogisms should be dividedinto classes in the same way premises themselves are divided, especiallythe major premise, since it is the one which brings about the conclusion.With the minor premise, however, it is possible to pay no attentionwhatever to whether it is persuasive, generally accepted, or anythingelse.

(17) Thus we say that the premises used in this class of arguments,especially the major premise, are taken here insofar as they are general­ly accepted according to unexamined common opinion. In whatpreceded, we have defined what unexamined opinion is1 and thatdialectical premises are used only insofar as they are truly generallyaccepted.2 Now just as generally accepted things may accidentally betrue and may not, similarly, premises which are based on unexaminedopinion may accidentally happen to be generally accepted or true andmay not. However, in general, they are taken here insofar as they aregenerally accepted according to unexamined opinion, just as dialecticalpremises are taken solely insofar as they are truly generally accepted.What is generally accepted according to unexamined previouslyexisting opinion is divided into (a) generally received propositions­and these are premises which are taken universally according tounexamined previously existing opinion-and into (b) sense percep­tible things which are taken as proofs of other things, also accordingto unexamined opinion.

(18) Among these proofs are (a) those that are taken as proofs of theexistence of a thing without restriction1-like our taking the emptyvessel as proof of the existence of void-and (b) those that are takenas proofs of the existence of a predicate for a subject. When the latterare more universal than the subject and more particular than, or similar

Page 40: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

68 RHETORICRHETORIC 69

to, the predicate, they belong in the first figure; these were specificallyassigned the name "proof" by the ancients.2 If they are more universalthan the two extreme terms, they belong in the second figure. If theyare more particular than both [of the extreme terms], they belong inthe third [figure]. These latter two were specifically assigned thename "sign" by the ancients.3 The proofs wh:ch are taken up heremay be matters which are subsequent to the thing proved-e.g., itsconsequences-and they may be prior [to it}-e.g., its causes.

(19) Now each ofthe two classes ofpremises-the generally receivedpropositions and the proofs-may occur in matters which are necessary,possible for the most part, and equally possible. An example of thegenerally received propositions occurring in the necessary matter is:"everything which is done has a doer." An example of those occurringin the matter which is possible for the most part is: "any sick personwho obeys his passions and does not heed the saying of the doctorswill not be cured." An example of those occurring in the equallypossible is: "whatever is more agreeable and easier is preferable."However, in itself, this could be used to allege that the matter is notpreferable.

(20) PROOFS. The one in the necessary matter in the first figurewhich is what is specifically assigned the name "proof," is like ourargument: "The brightness of the moon increases bit by bit, so it isspherical." What occurs in the matter which is possible for the mostpart is like our argument: "So-and-so is gathering men, preparingarms, and fortifying his towns. There is no enemy near him. He is,therefore, resolved upon revolting against authority." This was knownamong the ancients as "specious proof." Those occuring in the matterwhich is equally possible are like our argument: "So-and-so did notbudge from his position, and all of his companions retreated so thathe was felled. He is, therefore, courageous." However, in itself thismay also be used as proof of the cowardice which prevents a manfrom fleeing. This proof, too, the ancients identified as "doubtfulproof."l

(21) SIGNS. The ones occurring in the necessary matter in thesecond figure are like our argument: "The nerve grows out of thebrain because it is implanted in it." What occurs in the matter which ispossible for the most part is like our argument: "So-and-so showed theenemy the vulnerability of the town because he climbed up on the wall

and watched for the enemy, and the one who points out the vulnera­bility [of the town's walls] does that." Those occurring in the matterwhich is equally possible have the same force as the proofs whichoccur in this matter, since the universals in it have the same force asparticulars and particulars may be converted and brought back tothe first figure. So if they were taken universally, their falsity would beas great as the falsity of particulars. For this reason, the ancientsrejected the type of signs which occur in this matter.

(22) PROOFS WHICH ARE IN THE THIRD FIGURE.l The ones in thenecessary matter are like our argument: "Time is the celestial sphere,because all things are in time and all things are in the celestialsphere." Those occurring in the matter [which is possible for the] mostpart are like our argument: "Wise men are virtuous, because Socrates~as a virtuous wise man." The reason for rejecting those occurringIn the matter which is equally possible [in the third figure] is thevery same reason for rejecting those in the second figure.

(23) You ought to be apprised that this division-i.e., the divisioninto the necessary and the possible-is not essential to the premisesofenthymemes inasmuch as they are premises of enthymemes. That isbecause the premises of enthymemes are taken insofar as they aregenerally received according to unexamined opinion-as we havesaidl---or insofar as they are signs and proofs according to unexaminedopinion, not insofar as they occur in a necessary or possible matter.For it is with regard to demonstrative syllogisms that premises aretaken according to this description; i.e., they are the ones which takepremises insofar as they are necessary or possible for the most part.Those which are equally possible are thought to be more characteristicof these arguments, since the demonstrative art does not employ them.But this art-i.e., the art of rhetoric-does not employ them from thestandpoint oftheir being equally possible either; for ifit were to employthem from this standpoint, one thing would not be more likely to followfrom them than would its opposite. Rather, they are used insofar asone of them preponderates, even if slightly, according to unexaminedopinion, either at a certain moment or in a certain condition. Somepeople who were ignorant of this idea, denied that this art couldemploy a ~roof occurring in the matter which is equally possible,for they claImed that no persuasion is brought about by that which isequally possible.

Page 41: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

70 RHETORIC RHETORIC 71

(24) As has been said, this art does not have a particular subject,just as the art of dialectic does not have a particular subject. For thepremises employed in these two arts are not grasped in the mind in thesame way as they exist outside the mind. Rather, a predicate is alwaysasserted to apply to a subject because of what is generally accepted,either according to unexamined opinion or according to the truth,not because it is of the nature of the predicate to apply to the subjector of the nature of the subject that the predicate should apply to it.Nor does this art only take premises insofar as they are widespreadaccording to unexamined opinion, without qualifying them withregard to mode of existence. Rather, it may take the necessary asthough it were possible according to unexamined opinion and,similarly, the possible as though it were necessary. As for taking thenecessary as though it were possible, that is like someone who fanciesthat the heavens could possibly exist in another form and that it ispossible for everything to be created out of any chanced-upon thing.As for imagining that something is impossible when it is possible,there are many things whose existence is not difficult when the beliefsof the multitude about them are considered. However, the kind ofassent to which we have inclined since youth is that all things arepossible-to the extent that the argument of anyone who says thisthereby loses its necessary character. For instance, in Plato's confuta­tion of Protagoras, when Protagoras said: "there is nothing that isperceived," Plato replied: "there, now, is something that is perceived"-meaning this assertion Protagoras had made.1

(25) Now we have finished what we were about. So let us go back towhere we were and say that it appears likely that what compelled theancients to divide the premises ofenthymemes in accordance with theirmatters is that premises which are widespread according to unexam­ined opinion are invested with weakness and strength in accordancewith each particular matter. For that reason, premises according tounexamined opinion are more persuasive when they happen to occurin the matter which is possible for the most part than when they occurin the equally possible. Now it has become clear from this argumenthow many classes ofenthymeme there are from the standpoint of formand matter.

[THE EXAMPLE]

(26) We ought to speak about the example. There are [different]classes of. the examp.le. (a) With one, it is decided whether a predi­cate apphes to a subject or does not apply to it because of that predi­~ate applyi~g~o the likeness of that subject or because of it not apply­mg, when It IS better known whether the predicate applies to thelikeness or not; like our argument that the heavens are createdbecause the wall is created. (b) With another, we decide whethera predicate applies to a subject or does not apply to it because thelik~ness of t~at. predicate applies to that subject or does not applyto l.t, when It IS better known whether that likeness applies to thesubject or does not apply; for example, our deciding that the heavensare changeable. because of the fact that they move. (c) With yetanother, we decIde whether a predicate applies to a subject or does~ot apply to it be~ause the likeness of that predicate applies to thehkeness of that subject or does not apply to it, when it is better knownthat the li~e~ess of the predicate applies to the likeness of that subjector when It IS better known that it does not apply' for example"h d'l "oney 1 utes because sugar dissolves."

. (27) The judgment may be universal, while the likeness is par­tIcular, e.g., our argument: "Pleasures are bad because wine is bad."Now the difference between this and induction is that in inductionwe confirm the universal by the particular, whereas here we confirmone thing by another insofar as it is a likeness-not insofar as one ofthem is particular and the other universal.

(28) LIKENESS. There are two classes: either a likeness in a commonmatter or a likeness by analogy. An example of the likeness in a com­mon matter is what preceded. An example ofthelikeness by analogy is~ur argument: "The king in the city is like the deity in the world andJust as the deity is one, so too ought the king to be." ,

(2.9) In general, regardless of the example, judgment about apartIcular based on a universal does not occur in it, because neitherone of the two similar things is more general than the other. Nor dothey exist as similars in this respect. It is clear from what preceded in~he P~ior Analytics1 that the apodeictically conclusive speech is the oneIII whIch the particular is explained by the universal. Since that isthe ~as~, no ot~er argument follows apodeictically from the example,nor IS It essentIally conclusive. An example of that is our deciding

Page 42: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

72 RHETORICRHETORIC 73

that the heavens are created due to their similarity to created b~dies

with respect to extension, alteration, conne~tedness, a.nd other thl~gS.

For the heavens in this argument are the mmor term m the syllogIsm,since they are the subject of the problem;2 being created. is the maj~r

term, since it is the predicate of the problem; and the mIddle. term ISextension and alteration. Now when we compose the syllogIsm, wespeak in this manner: "The heavens have extension, and what has

d "extension is created, thus the heavens are create .

(30) However, it is not sufficient that our saying "what has exten­sion is created," be taken indefinitely, if we want "the heavens" to ~e

encompassed apodeictically under it; rather, w~, shoul~ e~en ~ake Ituniversally, i.e., "every extended thing is created. No~ Ifth~sumversalhad resulted from our scrutiny of some extended thmgs m the wayparticular premises result, then to state it e:xplicitly by a~ exam?lewould be superfluous-unless it were t~ken as a me~ns of mst~uctlOn

and guidance for bringing about certamty concernm~ the umversal.But if our having perceived some of the extended thmgs as createddid not lead us to universal certainty and this premise remainedindefinite for us, nothing would result necessarily from o~r.perceivingit-except according to unexamined opinio~. From t~IS It appears:(a) that with regard to these kinds of pr~Illlses, certamtyabout theuniversal is not attained by sense perceptIon but by another power,since by sense perception only individual instances ofa limited numberare discerned and (b) that the ranks ofsuppositionl are in accordancewith their nearness and their distance from this universal decision.In general, supposition is a universal judgment based on sense percep­tion alone.

(31) Because one of the later dialectical theologiansl-and he .isthe one called Abu al-Maclili [al-Juwayni]-was not aware of thIS,he said: "The example provides certainty as a means of guidance,not only as a way toward the syllogism and sc~tinY."2 ~owever,

since he did not speak of the syllogism of a vahd figure, It wo~ldfollow for him that all of the sciences are preexistent. Thus, nothmgwould be known by means of the syllogism, so that it could happen,for example, that a man who has'" not theoretically investigatedanything'at "all'Telating'tO'.geomctPy'."would·be able to read theBook of the al-Magesfl and that the origin of the world would beself-evident.

(32) The rank of the example with regard to assent has now beenexplained. In this art it corresponds to the induction in dialectic, justas the enthymeme here corresponds to the syllogism in dialectic.

[PERSUASIVE THINGS WHICH DO NOT OCCUR BY

ARGUMENTS]

(33) After this, we ought to proceed to speak about the persuasivethings which do not occur by arguments and about the extent ofassent they provide. All together, there are thirteen kinds ofpersuasivethings: l

[1]. Among them is [proclaiming] the virtue of the speaker andthe defect of his opponent, for it is clear that by this a man acquiresa good reputation and acceptance of what he is saying.

[2]. Among them is bringing the listeners around to assent bymeans of the passions; for example, strengthening the passions in thesoul of the listener so that he must assent because offanaticism, mercy,fear, or anger. Now it is evident that this also inclines a man to assent.

[3]. Among them is what inclines the listeners by means of moralspeeches; this is done, just as Galen used to do, by making themimagine that the chaste, the people ofpreeminent character, and thosewho are neither sullied by corrupt thought nor false [in their thoughts]accept their speech.

[4]. Among them is extolling and belittling the matter which isspoken about, for when the speech is extolled, the soul is more inclinedto it. On the contrary, when it is deprecated, the soul avoids it; and noinclination for it takes place.

[5]. Among them is consensus.

[6]. Among them are testimonies.

[7]. Among them is awakening a desire for, or apprehension about,something.

[8]. Among them is challenging and betting.

[9]. Among them are oaths.

[10]. Among them is for the quality of the speech, the voice, andthe inflection to be in such a condition that they cause the existence ofthe matter whose affirmation is desired to be imagined; for example,

Page 43: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

74 RI!ETORIC RHETORIC 75

someone whose face has already become pale and whose voice hasalready risen recounting a fearful matter.

[11]. Among them is distorting speeches and dropping much fromthem and putting them into a form in which their repulsivenessappears and opposition to them is simplified; now these enter moreinto sophistry than they do into rhetoric.

These, then, are all of the external persuasive things.

(34) With many of these, it is immediately evident that they onlyprovide persuasion; with others, that may be somewhat obscure. Wewill speak about the latter.

[TESTIMONY]

(35) Testimony holds the most powerful rank. In general, testimonyis a certain kind of report. Those who bring the report can either beone or more than one. When they are more than one, they may eitherbe a group which it is possible to enumerate or they may be a groupwhich it is not possible to enumerate. Things reported are eitherperceived by the senses or intellectually apprehended. Those whoreport things perceived by the senses are either those who haveperceived these things themselves or those who report them fromothers like, fewer, or more numerous than themselves. Now thingsperceived by the senses which are reported either concern past mattersthat we have not perceived or matters occurring in the present butabsent from us.!

(36) Reports about those things we have perceived by the sensesare of no use or benefit. It seems this is likewise the case concerningintellectually apprehended things for those practitioners of arts whosehabit it is to deduce such intellectually apprehended things in theirart. For the multitude, however, testimony about them may possiblybring about persuasion. For this reason, you will find that the sectamong the people of our religious community known as the dialecticaltheologians does not limit itself only to the testimony of the Legislator[Mu1}.ammad] concerning knowledge of the origin of the world, theexistence of the Creator, and other things; rather, concerning know­ledge of that, it also employs syllogisms. Now the sect known as thelfashawiyah! rejects that.

(.37) Assent to testimonies and reports of sense-perceived matterswhIch have not been witnessed is strengthened and weakened inaccordance with the number of the reporters and other considerations~elating to them. T~us, the most powerful assent resulting from reportsIS what a group whIch cannot be enumerated reports it has perceivedor what a group reports on the authority of another group whichcannot be enumerated but which has perceived it. Now it [powerful~sse.nt about the report] is like that, however much the group increasesm SIze, to w~atever extent it reaches, if in the beginning, the middle,a.nd th~ end I.t remains the same in that determining their number iseIther ImpossIble or difficult. This class of reports is the one that iscalled continuous tradition'!

(38) Certainty w!th regard to diverse matters-like the sending ofthe Prophet, the eXI~tence of Mecca and Medina, and other things­may res~lt fr~m th.ls. But we should theoretically investigate themanner III ",:hlch thIS results, for there are some things that produceassent essentially and some accidentally. Now it is clear that assentabout. the existence of sense-perceived matters results, primarily andessentially, through sensation. Thus, whoever loses some kind ofsenseloses some kind of sense perception. Nor does [assent to] the existenc~?f sense:perceived things result essentially only through sensation;mdeed, It may also result through an imaginative representation ofthem .accor.ding to their essence.! Then, too, certainty about theessent~al eXIstence of sense-perceived things may result through thesyllogIsm; an example of that is: "This wall is built, thus it has abuilder." However, the essential form of the particuiar builder doesnot result through it,

(39) Certainty may be obtained about the existence of sense­perceIved matters which have never been perceived and whose exis­tence we have .no way of apprehending by means of a syllogism, butvery s~ldom-jus~ as we very seldom manage to conceive of themaccordmg to theIr essence.! However, even if individual instancesofsuch matters cannot be distinguished by sensation there is no doubt?ut what their names or what indicates them can b~ distinguished byIt., Now for the greater number of people, assent to something likethIS Comes about by means of the continuous tradition and exhaustivereports.

2However, it is clear that this is an accidental effect because

that about them which brings about assent rarely follows f:om what

Page 44: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

76 RHETORIC RHETORIC 77

is presumed3 to be its cause, namely, the reports-just as effects4

rarely follow from their accidental causes.s

(40) In this science, it is not necessary to dwell upon the causefor this accidental certainty resulting nor upon how it results; for it hasalready been spoken about in Sense and Sensible Objects. l When somepeople became aware of this, they wanted to set down as conditionsfor reports a specific number from which certainty would resultessentially. When this did not succeed for them, they said: "In itselfit results, even if it does not happen for us." Now this is a clear falsifica­tion, for if there were some essential number which would lead tocertainty, continuous accounts with respect to the number of reporterswould not vary, and it would be possible to perceive and to grasp thisnumber. But the many and the few are closely related. Thus, whensome of them wanted to set down conditions with regard to the conti­nuous tradition which would lead to certainty and they did notsucceed at it, they said; "One of its conditions is that it lead to cer­tainty:" Since that is the case, there is no condition at all which couldbe set down and no means by which certainty could result essentially.Now this art employs the reports and the testimonies in the mannerin which they are taken for the most part, which is according to suppo­sition. For it is very seldom concerned with something which no artemploys at all.

[RECORDED TRADITIONS]

(41) The situation with regard to quoting recorded traditions isalso clear; however, whatever assent to them results because ofbeing brought up with them or because of habit is very powerful.Thus, you see many who are brought up according to the ignorantways oflife believing fables from which we are not able to turn them

away.

[CONSENSUS]

(42) The foundation for the persuasiveness 0: ~onsensus-w.hich isthe mutual understanding ofthe people ofthe religIOUS commumty an~

their agreement about something pertaining to the reli~io~sco~~~m~

ty-is the Divine Law's testimony to them a~out therr .mf~~hbl1ity.When a group of people became aware of thiS they said: He whodeparts from consensus is not an infidel." Abu l:Iamid [al-Ghazali]

explicitly2 stated this idea about consensus in the first part of hisbook called The Distinction Between Islam and Atheism.3 He said: "Whatconsensus -is has not yet been agreed upon."4

[CHALLENGING]

(43) A challenge may be made by means of different things.However, the most persuasive of challenges is the one that is made bymeans of the completely unprecedented miracle, i.e., by the perfor­mance of something considered impossible by mankind. But it isobvious, even if the feat is extremely marvelous, that it providesnothing more than good opinionl about the one who performs thefeat or nothing more than trust in him and in his excellencewhen the feat is divine. Now AbU l:Iamid [al-Ghazali] has explicitlystated this in his book called The Balance.2 He said: "Faith in theMessengers [i.e., the Prophets] by the way of the miracle, as thedialectical theologians have described it, is the popular way; and theway of the select few is other than this."3

(44) These external matters which we have enumerated are the onesfrom which it is supposed that certainty will result. The persuasive­ness of the others is self-evident. Now the enthymemes are more nobleand take precedence over these, because they may be used to establishthose which are neither clearly existent nor clearly persuasive. Forexample, when the moral excellence of the speaker is neither evidentnor generally accepted, they are used to make it evident. Similarly,when someone supposes that he who claims to be a miracle-worker isnot a miracle-worker, they are used to make it clear to him that he is amiracle-worker. The same holds with testimonies, traditions, and otherthings when the opponent contests them. All of these persuasive things-whether they be arguments or external matters-may be used in allof the reflective arts in the way that those ancients who precededused to use them, because they supposed that they were ways tocertainty.

[CONCLUSION]

(45) When Aristotle became aware of the rank of these [argumentsand external things] with regard to assent, he saw that these thingswhich bring about assent were valuable because the multitude used

Page 45: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

78 RHETORIC

them with one another for particular voluntary things which judgesdecide are good or bad. Among the voluntary things which judgesdecide are good or bad, some are to be found in a man himself and inthe present time; these are virtues and vices. Some are to be found inthe present time in another person; that is injustice and justice. Somewill occur to him in the future; these are useful and harmful matters.Now speech addressed to others about the first kind of things is calledcontradictory [epideictic] ;1 when it is about the second kind of things,it is called forensic;2 and when it is about the third kind of things,it is called deliberative.3 Moreover, to the extent that man is a socialbeing and a citizen, he necessarily uses rhetorical arguments aboutthese three categories of things. [Once he recognized all of this,]Aristotle began4 to set forth rules and things which would enable aman to persuade about each and every one of these things in the bestpossible manner with regard to that thing. Therefore, this art isdefined as being the means by which man is able to effect persuasionabout each and every one of the particular matters and to do so inthe most complete and most artful manner possible with regard toeach thing.

(46) Now we have said enough for our purposes.

All of the Rhetoric is completed. Praise be to God the Exalted.

Short Commentary on Aristotle's "Poetics"

Page 46: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

Outline of Argument for theShort Commentary on Aristotle's "Poetics" :

INVOCATION AND TITLE.

A. The character of poetical speeches (para. 1).

B. Problems arising from the way poetical speeches are understood(para. 2).

C. The syllogistic limits on the art of poetry (para. 3).

D. Why Aristotle wrote about poetical speeches (para. 4).

E. The ultimate purpose of the collection of Short Commentaries onthe logical arts (para. 5).

81

Page 47: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

In the name of God the Merciful, the Compassionate.!

ABOUT POETICAL SPEECHES!

(1) Poetical speeches are rhythmically balanced speeches. Withthem, one strives for an imaginary representation or exemplificationof something in speech so as to move the soul to flee from the thing, orto long for it, or simply to wonder because of the delightfulness whichissues from the imaginary representation. They are set down in arhythmically balanced way, because they thereby become morecomplete in imaginary representativeness. Now just as the sense­perceptible matters which many of the arts-like the art of decorationand others--eause to be imagined are not really sense-perceptiblematters, likewise, speeches which cause something to be imagined arenot speeches which make its essence understood.

(2) There are two classes of representations: either (a) the classin which one thing is likened to another by one of the particles ofsimile! or (b) a representation taken as though it was the very thingbeing represented, and that is by means ofsubstitution2 and metaphor,like our saying: "He is the sea in whatever way you approach him."3Some of these representations are closely similar and others are far­fetched. Now it is evident that this art does not take the represen­tations of something as though they were the thing itself. But manypeople might err about that and thus take the representation of some­thing as though it were the thing itself; for example, the speech ofEmpedocles about the water of the sea being the sweat of the earthbrought together in its bladder.4 Now one errs with regard to theserepresentations when they are set down as a substitution and noparticle of simile is offered. For the most part these representationscause error concerning the things which can be conceived of only bytheir representations or which can be conceived ofonly with difficulty;thus, there is much error about the latter, as with someone who isnot able to conceive of a being which is neither inside the world noroutside it. But the most suitable place for this kind of error is the bookOn Sophistry.

83

Page 48: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

84POETICS NOTES

(3) Even though this art is syllogistic, the syllogism is not actuallyused in it, nor is there any kind of syllogism peculiar to it; rather,when a syllogistic argument is actually used in it, it is in the manner ofdeceit and in order to make it similar to another art.

(4) Aristotle came to the opinion that this art was highly useful,because by means of it the souls of the multitude could be moved tobelieve in or not believe in a certain thing and towards doing orabandoning a certain thing. For that reason, he enumerated thematters which enable a man to devise an imaginative representationfor any particular thing he wishes and to do so in the most completemanner possible for that thing. Thus, the art of poetics is that whichenables a man to devise an imaginative representation of each parti­cular thing in the most complete manner possible for it. However,these are perfections external to the primary human perfection.

(5) In sum, anyone who has understood what we have written inthese treatises1 and had no knowledge about all this by nature isnow able to discern the rank of every argument he hears with respectto assent or concept. This rank [of understanding] is part of whatis noble because man is prepared for ultimate perfection through it.For if man's perfection comes about by his attaining true theory andif he becomes prepared to accept it by this amount [oflogical study],then by this amount [of logical study] he attains the rank whichprepares him for ultimate perfection.

God is the One who gives success to what is correct.1

1. Henceforth, the dates of the Anno Hegirae will be given first andseparated from the corresponding date of the Common Era by aslash (!) mark; for example, the above date would read 520/1126.

2. In the nineteenth century, the Italian orientalist Fausto Lasiniotransliterated the Judaeo-Arabic manuscripts of Averroes's Short~omme~tary on .A~istotle' s Poetics into Arabic and published the trans­lIteratIOn. LaSInI? used a copy of the Munich manuscript (cf. infra,n. 10) sent to hIm by the well-known German orientalist MoritzSteinschneider, to the point where the Munich manuscript b;oke off;t~en he us~d a copy of the Paris manuscript (cr. infra, n. 11) sent toh~m by MOIse Schwab of the Paris Bibliotheque Nationale. Because hedId not have a full copy of the Paris manuscript, Lasinio had no wayto control the Munich manuscript readings. This transliterationappea~ed a~ an appendix to his edition ofAverroes's Middle Commentaryon Arzstotle s Poetzcs; cf. Fausto Lasinio, "11 Commento Medio diAverroe ana Poetica di Aristotele" in Annali delle Universita ToscaneXIII (1873), ~arte Prima, pp. xvii-xviii, Appendix A.

More attentIOn has been paid to the Middle Commentary on Aristotle'sPoetics. Lasinio's edition was based on a single Arabic manuscript(Florence Laurenziano Manuscript CLXXX, 54). Once he becameaware of th.e .existe~ce of a second manuscript (University of Leiden2073), LasIn~o. prInted the variants and suggested better textual~eadI.ngs; cf. zhzd., pp. 1-45 (Arabic) and "Studi sopra Averroe, VI"In Gzornale della Societa Asiatica Italiana XI (1897-1898), pp.14l-l52and. ~~I (1899), .I~p. 197-206. .'Abd al-Rabman Badawi reprintedLa~lI~I~ ~ 1873 ed~,tI~n of the MIddle Commentary; cr, Talkh~ KitahArzstutalzsji al-Shz r In Aris!u!l1lis: Fann al-Shi'r (Cairo: Maktabat al­Nah~ah al-Mi~riyah, 1953), pp. 199-250. Apparently, Badawi knewnot?Ing ~~out Lasinio'~ later publication of the variants. More recentlyS~hm SalIm ha.s publIshed a new edition of the same commentaryUSIn.g all the avaIlable manuscripts; cf. Talkh~ Kitah Aris/u/alisIi al-Shi'r(CaIro: Dar al-Tabrir, 1971). It is not believed that Averroes wrotea Large Commentary on the Poetics.

85

Page 49: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

86 NOTES NOTES 87

There are no Arabic editions of the Middle Commentary on Aris­totle's Topics by Averroes, even though it is known to be extant in theFlorence and Leiden manuscripts. It is not believed that Averroesever wrote a Large Commentary on the Topics.

Lasinio also published an early edition of part of Averroes's MiddleCommentary on Aristotle's Rhetoric. His edition, based on both the Florenceand Leiden manuscripts, stopped shortly before the end of the firstmaqiilah of Averroes's commentary; cf. Fausto Lasinio, "!l ~o~mentoMedio di Averroe alIa Retorica di Aristotele" in Pubblzcazzom del R.Instituto di Studi Superiori Pratici e di Perfezionamento in Firenze, Sezion~ diFilosofia e Filologia, Accademia Orientale, I (1878), pp. 1-96 (ArabIc).'Abd aI-Rahman Badawi was the first to edit the whole book; cf.Talkhi~ al-Kha/iibah (Cairo: Maktabat al-Nah<;lah al-Mi~riyah, 19~0).Salim Salim has also edited the work; cf. Talkhi~ al-Kha/iibah (CaIro:Dar a1-Ta1;Irir, 1967). It is not believed that Averroes wrote a LargeCommentary on the Rhetoric.

3. The French orientalist and historian Ernest Renan identifie?Jacob ben Abba-~aria ben Anatoli as. th: first to translate thIScollection of treatlses on the art of lOgIC mto Hebrew. AlthoughRenan did not state the precise date that Anatoli completed the trans­lation, the context suggests it was completed between 123~-1232.Renan also cited a translation of the collection made by RabbI Jacobben Makhir ben Tibbon of Montpelier-known among the Christia?sof his time as Profatius Judaeus-and claimed it was completed 10

1298. Cf. Renan, Auerroes et I'Auerroisme «Paris: Michel Levy Freres1866), 3rd. edition, pp. 188-189.

Some years later, Steinschneider challenged Renan's identificatio~of Anatoli as a translator of this collection, asserting that Anatohhad translated nothing more than the Middle Commentaries o~ Aristotle:sOrganon in 1232. He also contended th.at the first transl~tlon of thIScollection was Rabbi Jacob's and that It was completed 10 1289, not1298. (This date corresponds tp the one given in the Pari~ cat~logue:Kislew 5050' cf. Manuscrits Orientaux: Catalogue des Manuscrzts Hebreux etSamaritains de la Bibliotheque Imperiale [Paris: Imprimerie Imperiale,1866], p. 160). Steinschneider also noted that Samuel ben yehuda. ofMarseilles expressed displeasure withRabbiJac~b'st~anslatlon.(whIchis, incidentally, the translation published at Riva dl Trento 10 1559as Kiaur mi-kol Meleket Higayyon, that is, Summary of the Whole Ar~ ofLogic) ~nd did a translation of his own in 13~9 or 1~30. Cf. M: Stem­schneider, Alfarabi in MhnoirtstJec;I~AttlIlimieImpenale des. Scunc~ deSt. Petersbourg, VIle serie, XIII (1869), no. 4, p. 147 and Dze hebrazscheVbersetzungeit des Mittelalters (Berlin: Jtzkowski, 1893), p. 54, n. 55.

(The dates 1189 and 5 Kislew 50 in the latter work are obvious mis­prints and should read 1289 and 5 Kislew 5050 respectively).

4. Cf. Renan, op. cit., pp. 29-42, 79-84, and 173-199. Consideras well the remarks of the noted French orienta1ist, S. Munk, inthe article "Ibn Roschd" in Dictionnaire des Sciences Philosophiques(Paris: L. Hachette et Cie., 1847), Vol. III, pp. 163-164 and inMelanqes de Philosophie Juiue et Arabe (Paris: A. Franck, 1857), pp.422-429 and 439-440. Leon Gauthier also discussed this problemin his study of Averroes; cf, Leon Gauthier, Ibn Rochd (Auerroes)(Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1948), pp. 9-11.

5. Father Maurice Bouyges edited the Middle Commentary on Aris­totle's Categories in 1932; cf. Auerroes Talkhif Kitab al-Maqoulat (Beirut:Imprimerie Catholique, 1932). In the introduction to this edition,he noted that the work had been neglected in the West and among theArabs; only Jewish Aristotelians seemed to have had any concern orknowledge about it (pp. v-vi). Cf. also R. de Vaux, "La PremiereEntree d'Averroes chez 1es Latins" in Reuue des Sciences Philosophiqueset TMologiques XXII (1933), p. 193.

Renan first described the Florence Laurenziano ManuscriptCLXXX, 54 to the learned community in a letter from Rome dated 27February, 1850; cf. "Lettre aReinaud" in Journal Asiatique XV (1850),Serie IV, pp. 390-391. By 1874, Lasinio was aware of the existence ofthe University of Leiden Manuscript 2073; cf. "Studi sQpra Averroe,V" in Annuari della Societa !taliana per gli Studi Orientali II (1874),pp. 234-267. For the Judaeo-Arabic manuscripts, cf. infra, p. 4, n. 7.

6. Although still under the influence of the older opinion to someextent, Gauthier noticed a tendency toward independence in Averroes'sthought; cf. op. cit., pp. 15 with 257-258 and 278-281. Like Gauthier,Alonso could not deny that Averroes explicitly differed with Aristotleon certain issues; however, he could not completely relinquish thenotion that the commentaries were less original than the other works;cf. P. Manuel Alonso, Teologta de Auerroes (Madrid: Maestre, 1947),pp. 26, 36-41 with pp. 33,89, and 99.

In recent years, there have been more careful arguments about theway in which Averroes is to be considered a disciple of Aristotle. Cf.Michel Allard, "Le Rationalisme d'Averroes d'apres une Etude sur laCreation" in Bulletin d'Etudes Orientales XIV (1952), pp. 21, 23, 25, and53-55; G.F. Hourani, Auerroes on the Harmony ofReligion and Philosophy(London: Luzac and Co., 1961), p. 25; H. Blumberg, Auerrois Cordu­heTl;Sis Compendia Libromm Aristotelis qui Parva Naturalia vocantur (Cam­bndge: The Mediaeval Academy of America, 1954), p. xi, and AuerroesEpitome of Parua Naturalia (Cambridge: The Mediaeval Academy of

Page 50: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

88 NOTES NOTES 89

America, 1961), pp. xiii-xiv; Herbert A. Davidson, Averroes MiddleCommentary on Porphyry's Isagoge and on Aristotle's Categoriae (Cambridge:The Mediaeval Academy of America, 1969), pp. xiii-xiv, xv, and xix.While the argument that Averroes differed from Aristotle only becausehe did not understand the text still attracts some attention (cf. FrancisLehner, "An Evaluation of Averroes' Paraphrase on Aristotle'sPoetics" in TIr.e Thomist XXX [1966], pp. 38-65 and "The Lambda­Ennea Case" in The Thomist XXXII [1968], pp. 387-423), there is anew willingness to consider Averroes capable of intentionally differingfrom Aristotle (cf. Helmut Gatje, "Averroes als Aristoteleskom­mentator" in Zeitschrijt der deutschen morgenliindischen Gesellschaft CXIV[1964], pp. 59-65).

7. Cf. Munk, article "Ibn Roschd," op. cit., pp. 161-162, 164. Aspart of his general presentation of Averroes, Renan sought to explainthe difference between the Great Commentary (Grand Commentaire),Middle Commentary (Commentaire Moyen), and Short Commentary(Analyse, Paraphrase, or Abrege). However, he mistakenly identifiedthe Commentary on the Rhetoric and the Commentary on the Poeti~s containedin the Florence Laurenziano Manuscript CLXXX, 54 as "les para­phrases sur la Rhitorique et la Poetique." That is, according to his ownterminology, as "Short Commentaries." This is one of the two manu­scripts used by Badawi and Salim in their editions, and it fits Renan'sown definition of a middle commentary perfectly. Cf. Renan, op. cit.,p. 68 with p. 53, and pp. 58-61 with pp. 82-83.

8. Cf. Renan, op. cit., p. 83 (the first edition of this work waspublished in 1852); Munk, Melanges, op. cit., p. 140, n.l; and C. Prantl,Geschichte der Logik im Abendlande (Leipzig: S. Hirzel, 1861), Vol. II,p. 374 ff. Prantl's error is all the more surprising as he cited bothMunk and Renan. Cf. also Steinschneider, Aljarabi, op. cit., pp. 148-149.

In an earlier publication, Steinschneider had hinted at his discovery.Among fragments of Munich Codex Hebraicus 356, he had found aloose folio which he recognized as belonging to a commentary onthe Poetics; it was a misplaced folio, number 86, of the MunichJudaeo-Arabic manuscript. Cf. "Uber die Mondstationen (Naxatra),und das Buch Arcandum" in Zeitschrift der deutschen morgenliintfischenGesellschaft XVIII (1864), p. 169, n. 65. Only after additional searchingwas he able to bring all the material together ; cf. Hebriiische Biblio­graphie, "Briefkasten," VIII (1665), p. 32 and "Hebraische Hand­schriften in Miinchen iiber arabische Philosophie" in Serapeum IX(1867), p.138.

9. Cf. Bouyges, "Notes sur les Philosophes Arabes Connus des Latinsdu Moyen Age" in Melanges de l' Universite Saint-Joseph (Beyrouth) VIII

(1922), p. 10. The Cairo publication which Father Bouyges cited bearsno resemblance to the Short Commentary on Aristotle's Rlr.etoric presentedbelow,. bu.t is simply a haphazard copy of different paragraphsoccurrmg m the first maqiilah of Averroes's Middle Commentary on Aris­totle's Rhetoric. Apparently, these paragraphs were taken from Lasinio'searly partial edition of that middle commentary; cf. Lasinio, "11Commento Medio di Averroe alla Retorica di Aristotele," op. cit. Inshort, the Cairo publication cited by Father. Bouyges is of no valuefor the serious study of Averroes's rhetorical thought.

Cf. also Harry A. Wolfson, "Plan for the Publication of a CorpusCommentariorum Averrois in Aristotelem" in Speculum VI (1931), pp. 412­427 and "Revised Plan for the Publication of a Corpus CommentariorumAverrois in Aristotelem" in Speculum XXXVIII (1963), pp. 88-104. Theextent to whic~ the existence of the Judaeo-Arabic manuscripts hasbeen neglected m the academic community is amply illustrated by thef~ct that, as la~e as 1943, Wolfson appeared to have no knowledge ofeIther manuscnpt and restricted himself to the Riva di Trento Hebrewtranslation and the Venice 1574 Latin translation for speculationsabout the Arabic equivalents of certain Hebrew words appearing inthe t:xt; ~f. Harry A. Wolfson, "The Terms t~awwur and ta1diq inArabIC PhIlosophy and their Greek, Latin, and Hebrew Equivalents"in The Moslem WorldXXXfII (1943), p. 114, n. 9 and p. 115, notes 20,23, and 25. Similarly, as late as 1969, a scholar publishing a logicalwork as part of the Corpus Commentariorum Averrois in Aristotelem projectw~s unaware of the Munich Judaeo-Arabic manuscript; cf. Averroes~uldle G.?mmentary on Porphyry's Isagoge and on Aristotle's Categoriae, op.Clt., p. xu, n. 8.

1o. ~f: Verz~ichnis der orientalischen Handschriften der K. Hof- undSt~tsbz?lzothek zn Munchen (Munich, 1875), Vol. I, pars quarta, p. 162:Dze E.pztome des Organon von Aristoteles mit der Einleitung des Porphyrius,Arablsch von Averroes. The manuscript is identified in the catalogueby the number 964, but it carries the number 650a in the MunichCodex Arabicus and is also identified by the number 309 in the MunichCodex Hebraicus.

II .. CF- Manuscrits Orientaux: Catalogue des Manuscrits Heoreux etSam~ntatns de la Bihliotheque Imperiale, op. cit. p. 182: "Risume de laLogzque, par Averroes en arabe et en caracteres hebreux." It is not clearwhe~her "la Logique" refers simply to the art or alludes to "la Logiqued'Artstote." The manuscript is classified as number 1008 in the Hebrewcollection an~ car.n~s the additional cl~ssification of "Sf 835 [7A]~FALSAFA]. ThIS IS the same manuscnpt that formerly carried themdex number 303.

Page 51: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

90 NOTES NOTES 91

12. Cf. Georges Vajda, Index General des Manuscrits Arabes Musulmansde la Bibliotheque Nationale de Paris (Paris: Centre Nationale de Recher­ches Scientifiques, 1953), pp. v and 320.

13. Renan published the biography by Ibn Abu U~aybi'ah in thesecond and third editions of his study; cr. op. cit., pp. 448-456, and es­pecially p. 454.-Born in 600/1203 in Damascus, Ibn Abu U~aybi'ah

was a renowned physician who composed a book of biographies aboutfamous physicians and professors of medicine: 'Uyiln al-Anba' fiTabaqiit al-A/ibba'. The selection published by Renan is taken fromthat book. Ibn Abu U~aybi'ah died in Sarkhad, near Damascus, in668/1270.

Renan also published a copy of the Escurial manuscript 884,folio 82; cf. ibid., p. 462.

Cf., as well, Steinschneider, "Une Dedicace d'Abraham de Balmesau Cardinal Dom. Grimani" in Revue des Etudes Juives V (1882), pp.115-117. This use of the title occurs in Vatican manuscript 3897,which contains a translation by de Balmes of Ibn Bajjah's Risiilatal-Wadii'. Cf. also Steinschneider, Die hebriiische Vberset;:,ungen, op. cit.,p. 54, n. 54.

14. Ibn al-Abbar, an historian and master oftradition, was born inValencia in 595/1199 and died in Tunis in 658/1260. He wrote Kitiibal- Takmilah li Kitiib al-$ilah, a supplement to the biographical dic­tionary, Kitiib al-$ilah fi Ta'rikh A'immah al-Andalus (BiographicalDictionary about the Leading Men ofAndalusia), of the master of traditionfrom Cordoba, Ibn Bashkuwal (494/1101-578/1183). Renan reprintedthe portion of Ibn al-Abbar's book relating to Averroes; cf. op. cit.,pp. 435-437, esp. p. 436. Although al-An~ari's dates are not known,he obviously lived after Ibn al-Abbar, for Renan presented theselection from his book as a supplement to the books of Ibn Bashkuwaland Ibn al-Abbar; cf. op. cit., pp. 437-447, esp. p. 444.

Shams aI-Din Mul).ammad ibn Al).mad ibn 'Uthman al-Dhahabiwas born in Damascus in 673/1274 and died there in 748/1348 aftertravel and residence in many other cultural centers of the Muslimworld. Although the list of works given by al-Dhahabi is not asexhaustive as Ibn Abu U~aybi'ah's, it does follow that list quitefaithfully, except in this instance. cr. Renan, op. cit., pp. 456-460,esp. p. 457.

15. There are some technical problems with Ibn Abu U~aybi'ah's

subtitle. First, the text reads "KitahAris!il!iilis (Aristotle's Book)," not"Kiltuh 'Art!fii!iilis t:Aristotle~sBtmks)~~' here;· the plural object"ha" of the verb "lakhkh~" dictates the correction. Secondly, the textcontinues after "mustawfan" with the words "Talkhi~ al-Iliihiyiit li

Niqilliiwus (Middle Commentary on Nicolas' Metaphysics"). These words arepresented as belonging to the Kitiib al-l)arilri fi al-Man/iq subtitle, butthat makes no sense. Consequently, it was decided to read them as atitle of another work by Averroes ofwhich nothing is known. H.Jahieran~ A. ~oureddine also understood these words as a separate title intheIr edItIOn and translation of the text: Ibn Abi U;aibi'a: 'Uyiln al­Anba' fi T'abaqat al-At'ibba', Sources d'Informations sur les Classes desMidecins, XIIIe Chapitre: Midecins de l'Occident Musulman (Alger:Librairie Ferraris, 1958), pp. 136-137.

16. The Middle Commentaries on Aristotle's Organon are contained inthe previously ~ent~oned Florence Laurenziano Manuscript CLXXX,54 and the UmversIty of Leiden Manuscript 2073. There is no otherreference to a talkhi~ on logic in Ibn Abu U~aybi'ah's list, whichs~~gests possible confusion on his part about the logical treatise he waslIstmg. However, the Escurial manuscript refers to this collection andals? to a Talkh~ Kitiib Aris!il fi al-Man/iq (Middle Commentary onArtsto~le's Book about Logic or Middle Commentary on Aristotle's Organon);that tItle corresponds perfectly to the work contained in the Florenceand Leiden manuscripts.

Cf. also Averroes Rasii'il Ibn Rushd (Hyderabad: Matba'ah Da'iratal-Ma'arif a~-'Ut~maniyah,1947), pp. 2-3. In this con'text, Averroeswas contrastmg hIS mukht~ar ~aghir on logic to books on logic writtenby al-Farabi. Cf., as well, Ave"oes: Compendio de Metaflsica, ed. andtra~~: by ~arlos Quiros Rodriguez (Madrid: Maestre, 1919), p.XXXlll, as CIted by Alonso in Teologla de Ave"oes, op. cit., pp. 55-56.

17. Porphyry was born in Tyre in 232 C.E. and died in Rome in305 C.E. A ~ealous student ofPlotinus, he had the reputation ofbeing aNeo-Platoms~. Porp~yry's t:eatise was translated into Arabic very~arly an~ qUIckly gamed WIde acceptance. It was considered a goodmtroductIOn to logic by al-Farabi and by the time of AveiToes wasthe customary preface to discussions on logic. Cf. Averroes Middle~omme~tary o~ Porphyry's Isagoge and on Aristotle's Categoriae, op. cit., p. 6:

The mtentIon of the present work is to explain the contents ofPorphyry's introduction to the science of logic. [I am undertaking thiscommentary] because it has become customary for the logical corpusto open with the Isagoge."

~f. also .Prantl, op. cit., Vol. I, pp. 626-631; J. Langhade and M.Gngnaschi, Al-Fiiriibi: Deux Ouvrages In/dits sur la Rhitorique (Beirut:Dar el-Machreq, 1971), pp. 130-131, n. 4; and Ibrahim MadkourL'Organon d'Aristote dans Ie Monde Arabe (Paris: Vrin, 1969), 2nd. ed.:pp. 9-11, and 70-75.

18. Apparently, the inclusion of rhetoric and poetics among the

Page 52: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

92 NOTES NOTES 93

logical arts can be traced back to two representatives of the Alexan­drian school, Olympiodorus and Elias; cf. Richard Walzer, "ZurTraditionsgeschichte der Aristotelischen Poetik" in Richard Walzer,Greek into Arabic, Essayson Islamic Philosophy (Oxford: Bruno Cassirer,1962), pp. 129-136, esp. pp. 133-135; originally published in StudiItaliani di Filologia Classica, N.S., Vol. XI (1934), pp. 5-14. Althoughal-Farabi and Averroes followed the idea of including rhetoric andpoetics among the logical arts, neither accepted it without preliminaryconsideration; ef. al-Farabi IMii' al-'Ulum, ed. 'UthmanAmin (Cairo:Dar al-Fikr al-'Arabi, 1949), pp. 63-74 and Averroes Talkh~ al­Kha!iibah, ed. 'Abd al-Ral:;lman Badawi, op. cit., 4, 9-10, 11-13, 18, and248-249.

19. Cf. the Munich Judaeo-Arabic manuscript (hereafter referredto as M.), folios Ib line 24-3b line 2 and also the Paris Judaeo-Arabicmanuscript (hereafter referred to as P.), folios 2a line 2-3a line 15.(Henceforth, references to folio and line will be cited without explainingthat the first number refers to folio and the second to line; thus, theabove references would read M.lb24-3b2 and P. 2a2-,-3a15). Cf. alsoAristotle Categories la 1-15.

20. In the introduction to his Middle Commentary on Aristotle's Topics,Averroes said: "This art has three parts. The first part sets forth thespeeches from which dialectical conversation is composed-i.e., i~

parts, and the parts of its parts on to its simplest components. ThISpart is found in the first treatise on Aristotle's book.

"The second part sets forth the topics from which syllogisms aredrawn-syllogisms for affirming something or denying it with respe~t

to every kind of problem occurring in this art. This is in the next SIXtreatises of Aristotle's book.

"The third part sets forth how the questioner ought to question andthe answerer answer. It also sets forth how many kinds ofquestions andanswers there are. This is in the eighth treatise of Aristotle's book."Cf. Florence Laurenziano Manuscript CLXXX, 54, folio 88a, as citedby Fausto Lasinio in "Studi sopra Averroe, II" in Annuari della SocietaItaliana per gli Studi Orientali I (1873), pp. 140-142.

21. The title On Sophistical Refutations or, more literally, On Sophistryexists only in M.; P. has no title.

22. This is the title in M. In P., the title Treatise on Assent (al-Q,awl fial- T04diq) is followed by the subtitle Treatise on the Knowledge Preparingthe Way to Assent (al-Q,awl fi al-Ma'rifah al-muwa!ti'ah Ii al-T04diq).

23. As part of the title in P., the words "and they are called Topics"(wa hiy al-musammiit MawMi') are added. Although these wordsoccur in M. as well, they are not placed in the title.

24. Cf. references to Alonso, Blumberg, and Davidson in n. 6, supra.Cf. also Gauther, op. cit., p. 16. To date, insufficient attention hasbeen given to the substantive divergences from Aristotle's text in all ofthe different kinds of commentaries by Averroes.

25. Although Aristotle wrote no book on dialectic as such, in thistreatise Averroes discussed the theory ofthe nondemonstrative syllogismset forth in Book I of the Topics as though it had been a book on dialec­tic. He also emphasized the general rules for dialectical argument givenin Book VIII of the Topics, the discussion of topics per se having beenput into closer relation with the discussion of the demonstrativesyllogism. As has been observed (ef. supra, n. 20), Averroes consideredthe Topics to be comprised of three distinct sections: Book I, BooksII-VII, and Book VIII. A further indication of the extent to which hethought of these sections as distinct is that in his Middle Commentaryon Aristotle's Topics he cited the date on which the second section wascompleted, something usually done only upon the completion of awhole work; cf. Florence Laurenziano Manuscript CLXXX, 54, folio116a, as cited by Lasinio in "11 Commento Medio di Averroe alIaPoetica di Aristotele," op. cit., preface I, pp. xii-xiii, n. 2.

26. This title occurs only in M. and in the Hebrew translation ofthe Paris manuscript. In the Judaeo-Arabic version of the Parismanuscript, there is a blank space where the title ought to appear.However, that space is too small for the Munich title.

27. Cf. Pi al-Q,awiinin allati ta'mal biM al-Maqiiyis, M. 38b19, P.43all. Cf. also infra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, para. 5, andinfra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Rhetoric, end. All of these referencescan only be to Averroes's own Short Commentary on Aristotle's PriorAnalytics, for they refer to issues not occurring in Aristotle's text.

28. Cf. Pi al-Q,awiinin allati ta'mal biM al-Maqiiyis, M. 41a3, P. 45a21.

29. Cf. Florence Laurenziano Manuscript CLXXX, 54, folio 88a,as cited by Fausto Lasinio in "Studi sopra Averroe, II," op. cit., p. 140:"Among the multitude the term dialectic (al-jadal) signifies conversa­tion between two p~ople, each one of whom seeks victory over hisfellow by any kind of speech whatever. That is why Aristotle assignedthe term this meaning; it is the one which is closest in sense to whatthe multitude means and is the meaning we have defined. This bookmay also be called Topics (Tubiqi). What topics (mawiirji') are will beset forth later."

30. Cf. Prantl, op. cit., Vol. II, p. 374, notes 289-290 and pp.385-386, n. 346; also Steinschneider, Alfarabi, op. cit:, pp. 146-148with p. 5, n. 7 and pp. 38-39.

Page 53: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

94 NOTES NOTES 95

While Prantl's particular arguments against the possibility ofthe collection being written' by Averroes do merit serious attention,his general view of Averroes's writings on the. Organon was .badly ~~n­

fused. He was correct in stating that the medIeval scholastIc tradItionspoke of three kinds of commentaries by Averroes on the PosteriorAnalgtics: a short commentary, a middle commentary, and a lo~g

commentary. Similarly, he was correct in reporting that the scholastIcsthought Averroes had written two kinds of commentaries on the otherbooks of the Organon: short commentaries and middle commentaries.However, in his discussion of Averroes's logical theory, he tried tocorrect the division set forth by the scholastics and their identifi­cation of the different commentaries. He thereby betrayed his ownconfusion about these works. For example, never citing the shortcommentaries, he identified the Middle Commentary on Aristotle'sCategories as a short commentary. He further argued that the MiddleCommentary on Aristotle's Posterior Analytics was a mixture betweena short commentary and a middle commentary. Consequently, he triedto show that the Epitome in Libros Logicae Aristotelis, i.e., the ShortCommentaries on Aristotle's Organon was still another kind ofcommentary,one which had to be rejected as spurious despite its acceptance bythe scholastics. Cf. ibid., pp. 374, 377-378, and 384--385. Gauthierdemonstrated a similar kind of confusion about the differences be­tween short commentaries and middle commentaries; cr. Ibn Rochd,op. cit., pp. 12-14, 16, and 52, n. 1.

31. Cf. Lasinio, "11 Commento Medio di Averroe alla Poetica diAristotele," op. cit., preface I, pp. xvi-xvii. In a different con.text,Horten cited additional inconsistencies in the philosophical termmol­ogy of the Latin translations; cf. Die Metaphysik des Averroes, trans.Max Horten (Halle: Max Niemayer, 1912), pp. ix-xi. A major reasonfor this inconsistency in the Latin translations seems to be the heavyreliance of the translators upon Muslim or Jewish interpreters dueto their own insufficient grasp of Arabic. Cf. R. de Vaux, "La PremiereEntree d'Averroes chez les Latins," op. cit., pp. 197, n. 2 and 199,notes 1-2; also Harry A. Wolfson, "The Twice-Revealed Averroes"in Speculum XXXVI (1961), pp. 373-392.

32. Cf. Prantl, op. cit., Vol. II, p. 376, n. 294. Steinschneider soughtto refute this objection by asserting that Averroes often altered in a sub­sequent work what he had set down in an earlier one. Consequently,inconsistencies in doctrine could be no proof of the spurious characterof a work. In these terms, Steinschneider's argument is overstated andraises as many problems as it attempts to solve. Cf. Steinschneider,Alfarabi, op. cit., pp. 149-150.

33. Cf. Averroes Middle Commentary on Porphyry's Isagoge and onAristotle's Categoriae, op. cit., p. 27: "This completes the subject matterof the Isagoge. I was led to comment upon it by friends in Murcia,men who are keen and eager for theoretical knowledge, may Godshow them mercy, and were it not for them, I would not have takenthe trouble, for two reasons. One is that I do not consider the Isagogenecessary for beginning the art of logic, since its contents cannotbelong to what is common to the entire art, as some imagine; for ifwhat has been stated here in connection with the definitions of thepredicables is demonstrable, it belongs to the Posterior Analytics, whileif it is generally accepted opinion, it belongs to the Topics. In fact,Porphyry made these statements not as definitions, but rather asexplanations of the meanings of the terms in question [so that theymight be understood] whenever Aristotle uses them in his book. Fromthis point of view, the Isagoge is not a part oflogic. Alfarabi, however,implies that it is a part of logic. This is one thing that would havedissuaded me from commenting upon the book as part of my com­mentary on the books ofAristotle, and the second is that what this mansays in the Isagoge is self-explanatory. Nevertheless, I wished to obligethe aforementioned scholars and assist them in everything that they,from their desire and love ofscience, considered to be to their benefit,and thus I was led to comment and dilate upon this book. In the fewremarks I have made, I have alluded to most [of the things that shouldbe discussed]. At some points there is room for speculation, but this isnot the place for it." Cf. also ibid., pp. xiii-xv, xvii-xviii, and xix-xx.

34. Averroes explained: "The purpose of this treatise is to present aMiddle Commentary on the ideas contained in Aristotle's books onthe art of logic, summarizing them according to our ability, as wehave customarily done with his other books. We shall begin with thefirst of his books about this art, that is, the book about the Categories."Cf. Averroes Talkhif Kitab al-Maqoulat, ed. Bouyges, op. cit., p. 3.

It is possible that Averroes composed his Middle Commentary onPorphyry's Isagoge after the other Middle Commentaries, for the onlymention of the Arabic text of this commentary was the descriptionof the Florence Laurenziano manuscript CLXXX, 54 byJ.B. Raimun­dus in about 1610. That description is not entirely trustworthy,however; cf. Lasinio, "11 Commento Medio di Averroe alIa Poeticadi Aristotele," op. cit., preface I, pp. viii-x.

35. Cf. Prantl, op. cit., Vol. II, pp. 390-392, n. 372 with pp. 384-385,n. 334 and pp. 360-361, n. 230. Cf. also supra, p. 7 . For Averroes'scriticism of Avicenna, cf. Magna Commentaria Posteriorum Resolutionarumin Aristotelis Omnia quae extant Opera... Averrois Cordubensis in ea... Omnes...

Page 54: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

96 NOTES NOTES 97

Commentarii (Venice: apudJunctas, 1562), Vol. I, pars secunda, p. 7a:"Circa quod iam erravit Avicenna errore manifesto, cum putaret,praeponi Topicam arti Demonstrativae..." (trans. Abraham deBalmes); or "Et idea Manifeste erravit Avicenna circa hoc, cumexistimet, dia1ecticam facultatem, seu topicam, debere precedereartem Demonstrativam..." (trans. Jacob Mantinus); cf. also 6a.

36. Cf. Averroes Magna Commentaria Posteriorum Resolutionarum, op.cit., pp. 7b-8b.

37. Cf. On the Rules by Which Syllogisms Are Made (Fi al-Qawanin allatita'mal biM al-Maqayis) , M 30a19-31a8, P 33a22-34a2l. Steinschneiderwas so convinced Averroes'had not spoken about dialectical reasoningin this section of the collection that he denied it shruld even be entitledTopics, reserving that title for the first treatise presented here; cf.Alfarabi, op. cit., p. 148.

For some reason, none of the Latin editions presented the treatiseon dialectic (Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics) as a separatetreatise. Instead, it was incorporated into the Epitome in Libros Elen­chorum as chapter V and given the title De Rationibus probabilibus et liti­giosis. Cf. Aristotelis Omnia quae extant Opera... Averrois Cotdubensis in eaOmnes... Commentarii, op. cit., Vol. I, pars prima, p. 72b; Vol. I, parstertia, p. 72b; and Vol. II, p. 189b (in this volume, it is not set off as aseparate chapter, and the title is in the margin). Cf. also AristotelisOmnia quae extant Opera... Averrois Cordubensis in ea Omnes... Commentarii(Venice: apudJunctas, 1552), Vol. I, p. 357 (here it is not set off as aseparate chapter). Cf. also Aristotelis Omnia quae extant Opera... AverroisCordubensis in ea Omnes... Commentarii (Venice: apud Cominum deTridino, 1560), Vol. I, p. 332b.

Similarly, there is confusion in these editions about the order ofthe treatises belonging to the collection. Despite Averroes's statementthat his treatise On the Rules by Which Syllogisms Are Made (Fi al-Qawaninallati ta'mal biM al-Maqayis) should precede the Short Commentary onAristotle's Posterior Analytics, it is placed after the Short Commentary onAristotle's Posterior Analytics in the Junctas 1562 edition. Moreover, onlythe Junctas 1552 edition presents the collection as a whole. TheJunctas 1562 edition presents the Short Commentary on Aristotle's Rhetoricand the Short Commentary on Aristotle's Poetics in a separate volume, whilethe Tridino 1560 edition presents the Short Commentary on Aristotle'sPosterior Analytics in a separate volume and the Short Commentary onAristotle's Rhetoric and the Short Commentary on Aristotle's Poetics in yetanother volume.

38. Cf. infra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, para. 1.

39. "There are two kinds of assent. One kind is for verifying theproblem and dividing it into one of the two parts of the contradictionso that what is true is contained within one of them. The second kindis for verifying the composite argument bringing about assent; it iscalled syllogism. We shall begin with the first kind, since it is the onewhich ought first to be verified with regard to the problem, as itconstitutes the knowledge preparing the way to assent." As has alreadybeen noted (supra, n. 22), the subtitle in the Paris Judaeo-Arabicmanuscript is even more explicit: Treatise on the Knowledge Preparingthe Way to Assent (al-Qawl fi al-Ma'rifah al-muwat#'ah li al- Tafdiq).Cf. M. 10b19-11a2, P. llalo-15.

40. Cf. On the Rules by Which Syllogisms Are Made, M. 30a19-30b3,P. 33a2o-25: "We say: since the rules given in this art are of two types(a type which brings about and a type which makes known) and sincethe discussion which preceded has been about the things by whichthe species and classes of syllogisms are made known, we now oughtto speak about the rules enabling us to make syllogisms." Cf. also M.30b3-3la8, P. 33a25-34a18, and M. la4-8 (the corresponding folioin P. is missing).

41. The "Sections Which Are Necessary in the Art of Logic" werementioned by Munk (Melanges, op. cit., pp. 351-352, n. 1) and Stein­schneider (Alfarabi, op. cit., pp. 15-16), but Professor H. Blumberg wasthe first to discuss them in any detail. Cf. "Alfarabi's Five Chapters onLogic" in Proceedings f!f the American Academy for Jewish Research VI(1934-1935), pp. 115-121. Although Blumberg promised a subsequentedition of the treatise, it never appeared. Only twenty years later whenProfessor D.M. Dunlop discovered the manuscript, apparently withoutever having heard of Blumberg's article, were the "Sections" edited.Dunlop viewed the Paris manuscript as an inferior source and preferredto depend on the Istanbul Hamidiye Manuscript 182, folios 3a--5b.The treatise was edited and translated by Dunlop as "al-Farabi'sIntroductory Sections on Logic" in The Islamic Quarterly II (1955), pp.26~~82. Professor Mubahat Tiirker edited the treatise again, usingaddItIOnal manuscripts, and translated it into Turkish; cr. "Farabi'ninbazi Manti!.;: Eseleri" in Ankara (}niversitesi Dil ve Tarih-CografyaFakilltesi Dergisi XVI (1958), pp. 165-181, 195-213.

Professor Tiirker has also edited "The Speech about the Conditionsof Demonstration"; cr. "Farabi'nin Sera'it ul-yakini" in Araftirma I(1963); Felsefe Ara~tirmalari Enstitiisii, Ankara (}niversitesi Dil veTarih-Cografya Fakilltesi Dergisi, pp. 173 ff.

42. This is the same scribe who made the copy of Kitab al-Jfiss waal-Maf:zsils found in Modena (Biblioteca Estensis Manuscript 13, J.D.

Page 55: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

98 NOTES NOTES 99

10); he claimed to have finished copying it in 1~56 C:.E., the sameyear he finished copying this manu~ript. c:r. Dte Epttome der ParvaNaturalia des Averroes, ed. Helmut GlitJe (Weisbaden: Otto Harrasso­witz, 1961), pp. x-xi.

Some question about the identity of the Hebrew translator hasarisen, because neither the colophon nor any other passage of the textprovides specific evidence about his identity..In an extre~ely am­biguous footnote, Renan attributed the translatIOn of the Pans man:u­script to Jacob ben Abba-Maria ben Anatoli (cf. Renan, op.at.,p. 188, n. 2). Munk later resorted to an equally ambiguous footnotein order to attribute the translation to Samuel ben Yehuda of Mar­seilles, but never explained why he disagreed with Renan (cf. Melanges,op. cit., p. 489, n. 3). Yet another candidate was s"';lgges~ed by Zo:tenberg, the compiler of the Paris catalogue. He IdentIfied RabbIJacob ben Makhir of Montpelier as the translator because of thecloseness between the translation of the Paris manuscript and anothertranslation of this work definitely attributed to Rabbi Jacob (cf.Manuserits Orientaux, op. cit., pp. 160, Ms. no. 917; 167-168, Ms. no.956; and 182). Steinschneider and Lasinio accepted the identi~cationof the Paris catalogue and rejected Renan's and Munk's conJec~ures

without explaining the reasons for their decision (cf. Alfarabi, op. at., p.147; Die hebriiische Vberset;::ungen, op. cit., pp. 54-56; and "11 CommeJ.1.toMedio di Averroe all Poetica di Aristotele," op. cit., preface I, p. XVll).

Father Bouyges did not reconsider the problem; .like SteinschJ.1eiderand Lasinio, he accepted the judgment of the Pans catalogue w~thoutquestion (cf. "Notes sur les Philosophes Arabes Connus des Latms duMoyen Age," op. cit., p. 9). .. ..

Had Lasinio paid more attention to hIS own edItIOn of t~e ShortCommentary on Aristotle's Poetics, he might have come t~ a dIff~re~tconclusion: in the printed version of the Hebrew translatI?n. (whIch ~sdefinitely Rabbi Jacob's translation), there is a passage ~mssmg that.Ispresent in the Paris manuscript translation; ~nd there I~ a passage. mthe printed translation that does not occu.r m the P~rlS ~anuscnpt

translation. The problem is that the Pans maJ.1uscnpt IS n~ ~ore

similar to the translation known to be by RabbI Jacob than It IS toanother translation executed by Samuel. Zotenberg was clearlycorrect in his judgment that Samuel's translation diff~rs little fro~Rabbi Jacob's, despite Samuel's allegation t.hat he ~ecided, to do. hISown translation in order to correct the errors m RabbI Jacob s verSIOn.However, the differences between these two identified translations areother than the differences between either one of them and the transla­tion of the Paris manuscript.

43. For example, cf. infra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, para.

3, n. 3; Short Commentary on Aristotle's Rhetoric, para. 4, n. 12; andShort Commentary on Aristotle's Poetics, para. 2, n. 9.

44. For example, cf. infra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics,para. 1, n. 3; Short Commentary'on Aristotle's Rhetoric, para. 1, n. 4; andShort Commentary on Aristotle's Poetics, para. 2, n. 18.

45. Cf. infra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, para. 8, notes 5-6and para. 16, note 3; also Short Commentary on Aristotle's Rhetoric, para.23, note 4. Examples of passages where each manuscript differs fromthe best reading are: infra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics,para. 9, n. 20; Short Commentary on Aristotle's Rhetoric, para. 2, n. 3;and Short Commentary on Aristotle's Poetics, para. 2, n. 10.

46. Cf. infra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, para. 1: "Sincewe have spoken about the things by means of which the certain assentand the complete concept are distinguished and subsequent to thathave spoken about the things which lead to error concerning them,let us speak about dialectical and rhetorical assent and the extenteach one provides.'" Cf. also, infra, Short Commentary on Aristotle'sRhetoric, para. 1. Although the art of poetics does not use syllogisticarguments, it persuades by means of imaginative representation; cf.infra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Poetics, paras. 1 and 3.

The interpretation expressed here develops SOme ideas first expressedin an article entitled "Averroes: Politics and Opinion," AmericanPolitical Science Review LXVI (1972), pp. 894-901.

47. The works in question arc the Kitab Fa# al-Maqal wa Taqrir mabayn al-Shari'ah wa al-lfikmah min al-Itti~al (Book of the Decisive Treatiseand Stipulation of the Relationship between Divine Law and Philosophy),ed. by George F. Hourani (Leiden: E.J. Brill, 1959); the Kitab al-Kashf'an Manahij al-Adillah fi 'Aqa'id al-Millah (The Book of Uncovering theClear Paths of the Signs about the Beliifs of the Religious Community), ed. byMal).miid Kassem (Cairo: Maktabat al-Anglii al-Mi~riyah, 1963); andthe Tahiifut al- Tahiifut (The Incoherence of the Incoherence), ed. by FatherBouyges (Beirut: Imprimerie Catholique, 1930).

48. Cf. infra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Rhetoric, paras. 38-40;and Short Commentary on Aristotle's Poetics, paras. 1-2.

49. Cf. General Introduction, M. la4-11: "The purpose of this treatiseis to abstract the necessary speeches pertaining to each and everylogical art by explaining the ranks of the kinds of concept and assentused in each and every one of the five arts-i.e., the demonstrative,the dialectical, the sophistical, the rhetorical, and the poetical. Thereason is that this extent of this art is what is most necessary forlearning the arts which have already been perfected. And in this time

Page 56: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

100 NOTES NOTES 101

of ours most of the arts, like medicine and others, are like this [i.e.,perfected]." The corresponding folio in P. is missing.

50. Cf. infra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Poetics, paras. 4-5. Theprior judgment was made in the Short Commentary on Aristotle's PosteriorAnalytics where it was explained that man's ultimate perfectionconsisted in having certainty about the most remote causes of the beingsand that philosophy provided such knowledge. It was also explainedthat a further development of the issue belonged in another work.Cf. M. 57a 17-19, P. 63a 2-4. The same sort of judgment applies torhetoric, for the final definitions of rhetoric and of poetics are nearlyidentical; cf. infra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Rhetoric, para. 45.Poetics, however, can only be spoken of in terms of what it allows oneto make and do, because Averroes denied that it had any contributionto make towards understanding; cr. infra, Short Commentary on Aristot­le's Poetics, paras. 1-2.

51. Cf. infra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, para. 21. Cf. alsoAverroes Short Commentary on Aristotle's Posterior Analytics, M. 56b 22­57a24, P. 62a 15-63a6; Averroes Talkhi~ Kitiib mii ba'd al-Tabi'ahed. by 'Uthman Amin (Cairo: Mu~tala. al-Babi al-J:Ialabi, 1958),pp. 1:10-2 :8, 5: 12-6:14; and Aristotle Posterior Analytics n a29-35,86a22-30.

52. Cf. infra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, paras. 1-4, 6,8-11, 15-19.

53. Cf. ibid., para. 21 and n. 3.

54. Cf. The Incoherence of the Incoherence, op. cit., pp. 207-209, 356-358,427-430, 514-515, 527-528. Concerning al-Ghazali, cr. infra, ShortCommentary on Aristotle's Rhetoric, para. 42, n. 2.

55. Cf. al-Farabi IIHii' al-'Ulum, op. cit., chapter 5, pp. 107-108:"The art of dialectical theology is a skill enabling a man to use argu­ments for defending the established opinions and actions declared bythe Lawgiver and for refuting anything which contradicts them. Thisart [like jurisprudence] is divided into two parts: one concerningopinions and one concerning actions. It is unlike jurisprudence in thatthe jurist takes the opinions and actions declared by the Lawgiver asindisputable and considers them as principles from which he deducestheir consequences, while the dialectical theologian defends the thingsused by the jurist as principles without deducing other things fromthem. Ifit happens that one man has a facility for both tasks, then he isa jurist and a dialectical theologian-a dialectical theologian insofaras he defends these [principles] and a jurist insofar as he deduces[other things] from them." The same role is assigned the dialectical

theologians by Louis Gardet in his article "Quelques Reflexions sur laPlace du 'Ilm al-Kalam dans les 'Sciences Religieuses' Musulmanes" inArabic and Islamic Studies in Honor of Hamilton A.R. Gibb, ed. by. GMakdisi (Leiden: E.J. Brill, 1965), pp. 258-259, 262-267.

56. Cf. infra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Rhetoric, paras. 12, 31,36, 42, and 43. Concerning Abu al-Ma'ali, cf. ibid., para. 12, n. 1.

57. Ibid:, paras. 12, 29-30, 31, 36, and 44. For a fuller discussion oft~is issue, cr. "Rhetoric and Islamic Political Philosophy" in Interna­ttonal Journal of Middle East Studies III (1972), pp. 187-198.

58. Cf.. infra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Rhetoric, paras. 2, 3, 6, 8,12, 13 (wIth paras. 7 and 10), 18-19, and 33.

59. Cf. infra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, para. 9; alsoOn the Rules by Which Syllogisms Are Made, M. 37a24-37blO, P. 41a20­~2a2,.where rheto~ic is substituted for sophistry as though they wereIdentlcal. Cf. also mfra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Rhetoric, para. 17.

60. Ibid., paras. 4-5, 6-7, 8-13, 14, 15, 16-22, 23-24, and 26-32.

61. Ibid., paras. 1-5, 12, 29 and 31.

62. Ibid., paras. 5, 15-17, and 23-24.

63. Ibid., para. 43.

64. Ibid., paras. 12 and 31.

65. Ibid., paras. 33-44.

66. Ibid., para. 34.

67. Ibid., paras. 35-36.

68. Ibid., paras 38-39 and cr. infra, Short Commentary on Aristotle'sTopics, para. II.

69. Cf. infra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Rhetoric, para. 36.

70. Ibid., paras. 37 and 40.

71. Ibid., para. 42.

72. Ibid., para. 43.

73. Ibid., para. 44

74. Cf. infra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Poetics, paras. 1 and 4.

75. Ibid., paras. 1-3.

76. Ibid., para. I.

n. Ibid., para. 2.

Page 57: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

102 NOTES NOTES TO THE TRANSLATION OF THESHORT COMMENTARY ON ARISTOTLE'S TOPICS78. Ibid.

79. Ibid. "For the most part these representations cause errorconcerning the things which can be conceived ofonly by their represen­tations or which can be conceived of only with difficulty; thus, thereis much error about the latter..."

80. Ibid.

81. Ibid., paras. 1 and 4.

82. Cf. al-Farabi Kitiib al-Millah [Book ofReligion], ed. by~. ~ahdi(Beirut: Imprimerie Catholique, 1972), para. 1: "RelIgIOn IS theopinions and actions which the first ~ler prescrIbe~ to ~he collec­tivity. They are determined and restrIcted by qualIficatIOns as heseeks to obtain a specific goal with respect to the people or by means ofthem, through their practicing these opin~ons and. actions....the craftof the virtuous first ruler is kingly and linked wIth revelatIOn fromGod. Indeed, he determines the actions and the opinions which arein the virtuous religion by means of revelation..."

83. Cf. infra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Poetics, para. 2.

84. Ibid., para. 3.85. Cf. Averroes Talkhif al-Kha!iibah, Badawi edition, op. cit., pp.

13-14.

86. Cf. infra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Poetics, para. 4.

87. Ibid., para. 5.

88. Cf. infra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, para. 13.

INVOCATION.

1. The clause "[I beseech] your succor, 0 Lord" was omitted fromthe Paris manuscript. In its place is the clause: "I have recourse toHim, and in Him I place my trust".

PARAGRAPH (1).

1. The word translated here as "assent" (tafdiq) is one of two keyterms for Averroes, the other being "concept"; cf. below, n. 2. At thevery beginning of the collection ofthese Short Commentaries, Averroesexplained that his whole analysis centered around these two termssince all the problems considered in the rational arts may be explainedby means of them. "Assent is the firm assertion or denial of something,and it comes about in two ways: (a) either absolutely, like our saying'does vacuum exist?' or (b) with qualification, like our saying 'is theworld created?' Now this sort of seeking is always asked about by theparticle 'does' [or 'is' (hal)]." Cf. M. lb3-5; there is no correspondingfolio in the Paris manuscript, as has been noted in the Introduction.Cf. also Harry A. Wolfson, "The Terms tafawwur and tafdiq in ArabicPhilosophy and their Greek, Latin, and Hebrew Equivalents," op. cit.,pp. 114-128.

2. "Concept" (tafawwur) is "the understanding of something inaccordance with what gives an analogy of its essence or with what issupposed to give an analogy of its essence, and it is asked about­for the most part and primarily-by the particle 'what'; like oursaying 'what is nature?' and 'what is the soul?' " Cf. M. la23-l b2.

Because the word "form" (furah) is derived from die same root, theterm "concept" is used in a very strict sense; i.e., the mental image ofthe form ofsomething.

3. The word translated here and in what follows as "arguments"could literally be translated as "speeches" (aqiiwil). Because the wordmeans "arguments" in this context, because "speeches" are used asarguments in the art of dialectic, and because both here and in thefollowing Short Commentary on Aristotle's Rhetoric the word is used torefer to those aspects of speech which produce assent rather than tothe whole speech, this translation has been adopted.

103

Page 58: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

104 NOTES NOTES 105

PARAGRAPH (2).

1. The arabic word ~ann is translated here as "suppositio~." I! isusually used to denote the thought someone holds about t~a! m whIchhe believes. For instance, al-Farabi defined ~ann as: "behev~n.g that athing is such or not such." He also expl~i?ed: "~uppOSItI?n .andcertainty have in common that both are 0'pII~IOn. ~pmIOn (ra y) IS tobelieve that a thing is such or not such. It IS hke theIr genus, ~nd theyare like the two species." Cf. al-Farabi Kitah al-K.ha!iibah~ edIted_ ~n?

translated by J. Langhade, in Langhade ~nd Gngn~schI, Al-Farabt:Deux Ouvrages Inidits sur la RMtorique, op. at., p. 31, hnes 6-8; p. 33,lines 8-9. .. "T

AVlcenna also defines supposition as a kind of opm~o?: .ruesupposition is an opinion about something being so, whIle It I~ possI?lefor it not to be so." Cf. A.-M. Goichon, Lexique de la Langue Phtlosophtqued'Ibn Sina (Paris: Desclee de Brouwer, 1938), para. 405. .

Although some similarly does exist between ~ann and ra'y, there IS adifference. These authors have tried to distinguish between the twowords and apparently considered it possible for opinion, but notsupposition, to reach the level of certainty.

2. The word translated here as "peculiar characteristic" is really theword for "property" (khi#fah); cr. infra, paras. 15 and 16, as well aspara. 17, note 3.

PARAGRAPH (3).

1. According to Aristotle, "a premise is an af!ir~ative ~r ne~ative

statement about some subject... [and] a SyllOgIstIC premIse w~ll besimply the affirmation or negation ofsome pre?icate of some subJect...while the dialectical premise will be, for the mterrogator, an answerto the question which of two contradictory statemen:s is to be acc~pted,

and for the one making the syllogism, an assumptIOn of w~at IS ap­parently true and generally accepted..." .Cf. Prior Analytt~s 2~aI7­

24b12; also Topics 104a2-37. Averroes saId that the,pr~mIse IS thesmallest statement which admits of truth or falsehood. It IS comp~sed

of a predicate and a subject, and insofar as it is a part of a syllogIsI?'it is called a premise." Cf. Short Commentary on Aristotle's Prio~ A~lyttcS

M. 17a6-7; P. 18a8-9. A syllogism results from the combmatIOn oftwo or more premises.

PARAGRAPH (4).

1. Or "The same outside the soul as it is inside the soul" (khiirijal-nafs 'ala mil huw 'alaihfi al-nafs).

2. Aristotle classified syllogisms as belonging to three different"figures" in accordance with the different manner in which the middleterm (cf. infra, para. 6, note 3) might be arranged. This classificationalso served to distinguish the character of the different kinds of syllo­gisms; i.e., a syllogism occurring in the first figure was said to beperfect because "it requires nothing, apart from what is comprise~ init, to make the necessary conclusion apparent," whereas a syllogIsmoccurring in either one of the other two figures was imperfect beca~seit "requires one or more propositions which, although they necessanlyfollow from the terms which have been laid down, are not comprised inthe premises," and for this reason, such a syllogism was said to bemerely valid. The superiority of the syllogisms occurring in the firstfigure is also apparent from Aristotle's contention that "it is possibleto reduce all syllogisms to the universal syllogisms in the first figure"and that "all imperfect syllogisms are completed by means of the firstfigure." It is in this latter way that the syllogisms of the second andthird figures ultimately become valid. Cf. Prior Analytics 24b23-27,29b24-25, and 40bI5-16. In the Short Commentary on Aristotle's PriorAnalyties, Averroes followed Aristotle's schema and, after distinguishingthe different kinds of premises and terms, explained that any problemwhich occurred to mind could be classified in one of three waysaccording to the different manner in which its subject and predicatemight be related to the major term (cf. infra, para. 6, n. 4). Byex­plaining the possible relations of the subject and predicate to themajor term and the effects of each relation on the other two terms,Averroes was able to offer a plausible argument that there was noreason to adopt the fourth figure which Galen (cf. infra, Short Com­mentary on Aristotle's Rhetoric, para. 9, n. I) had tried to impose uponAristotle's classification. Cf. M. 17b16-18a2 and 19a3-24a8; P. 19a5­10 and 20al4-26a6. For examples ofsyllogisms occuring in each of thethree figures, cr. infra, para. 6, n. 2.

PARAGRAPH (5).

1. Cf. supra, para. 2: "We say: the extent [of assent] they provideis supposition which approximates certainty." The meaning of thisstatement was explained in paras. 2-4.

2. All of the syllogisms which are divided into figures fall underthe grouping "categorical syllogism" according to Averroes. Cf.Short Commentary on Aristotle's Prior Analytics M. 24a6-8, P. 26a5-6.Such a distinction does not occur in Aristotle's Prior Analytics becauseAristotle insisted that all syllogisms are brought about by means of oneof the three figures. Cf. Prior Analytics 40b22-23 and 41 bI-5. Because

Page 59: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

106 NOTES NOTES 107

Aristotle made this statement subsequent to the long discussion ofsyllogisms based on modal attributions (ibid., 29b29-40bI6), heapparently did not intend to place them in a different class from thesyllogisms which conclude immediately in one of the three figures(ibid., 25b26-29b28).

3. Although Aristotle did not treat the conditional syllogism as aseparate kind of syllogism, Averroes thought that arguments exhypothesi (ef. Prior Analytics 40bI7-4lb7, 45bI5-20, 50al6-50b4)should be understood as conditional syllogisms. In the Short Commentaryon Aristotle's Prior Analytics, he explained that "the conditional syllogismis usually composed of two premises, a major and a minor. The majoris composed of two categorical premises to which is attached aconditional particle (~arf al-shari!ah). The minor is a part of thismajor and is that which is selected from one of the two categoricalpremises from which the major is composed." Cf. M. 24a8-27b6; P.26a7-30a8. Conditional syllogisms are further divided into conjunctiveand disjunctive (ef. infra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Rhetoric, para.8). One example of the conjunctive conditional syllogisms given byAverroes is: "If this entity is a human being, then he is an animal;but he is a human being, so he is necessarily an animal."

It appears that Averroes followed a well-established tradition bydividing the syllogisms into classes other than the three figuresmentioned by Aristotle. Both Avicenna and al-Farabi made the samekind of distinction. For Avicenna, cf. al-Najiih (Cairo: Matba'at al­Sa'adah, 1938), pp. 32-52 and al-Shifii': Talkh~ Kitiib al-Qjyiis (Cai~o:

Wizarat al-Thaqafah, 1964), pp. 231-426. For al-Farabi, ef. Kztiibal-Qjyiis, Hamidiye Manuscript no. 812 (Istanbul), folios 28b-42b.The tradition that all three followed seems to have had its originsin the theory of the hypothetical and disjunctive conclusions firstpresented by Theophrastus (371-288 B.C.E.) and later developedby Porphyry, both of whom were well-known to Arab thinkers. Cf.Prantl, op. cit., Vol. I, pp. 294-295, 374-393, and 470-482; Vol. II,pp. 301-302, 309-311, 357-359, 368-370, and 379-384. Cf. alsoJ. Tricot, Traite de Logique Formelle (Paris: Vrin, 1930), pp.227-235.

4. Averroes defined the contradictory syllogism in the followingmanner: "The contradictory syllogism is composed from the categori­cal and the conditional [syllogisms]. It is used in this way: when wewish to explain the truth of a certain proposition, we take its oppositeand we join to it a true premise whose truth is not doubted. Fromthem one of the conclusive constructions is constructed, according toany of the categorical figures chanced upon. Ifa clear falsehood results,we know that the falsehood does not derive from the way the syllogism

is constructed-since it is a conclusive construction-nor from the truepremise; so all that is left is that it is derived from the opposite of thecommon premise, and if its opposite is false, then it is true." Cf. ShortCommentary on Aristotle's Prior Analytics M. 27b6-28a 23; P. 30a 8-3Ia8.This classification seems to be based on Aristotle's discussion of aparticular kind of argument ex hypothesi, the reductio ad impossible; cf.Prior Analytics 45a23-45bI5, 50a28-39, and 62b30-63b20.

PARAGRAPH (6).

I. The first figure, according to Aristotle, is the one in which theperfect syllogism occurs. A syllogism is perfect when its terms, i.e.,the subject and predicate of the premises, are so arranged that "thelast is wholly encompassed within the middle, and the middle iswholly encompassed within or excluded from the first." When hesaid that "one term is wholly encompassed within another," Aristotlemeant that the latter may be "predicated of all of the former." Cf.Prior Analytics 24b27-31, 25b26-32. Averroes explained that thefirst figure occurs when the middle term is the subject of the majorpremise and the predicate of the minor premise. Cf. Short Commentaryon Aristotle's Prior Analytics M. 17bI8-23; P. 19a6-9.

Since a syllogism in the first figure is perfect, i.e., so formed thatthe necessary conclusion is readily apparent, it is very convincing;consequently, its force is very strong. The example given here isdeveloped more fully in para. 8, infra.

2. Every syllogism has at least two premises and three terms. Whena syllogism has more than two premises and three terms, there isalways one term more than the number of premises. With respect tothe first figure, Aristotle identified the minor term as "that which issubsumed under the middle term." By saying this, Aristotle meantthat it is wholly encompassed within the middle term, i.e., that themiddle term can be predicated of all of the minor term or that themiddle term is more comprehensive than the minor term. In thesecond figure, as well as in the third figure, the minor term is mostdistant from the middle term. Cf. Prior Analytics 42a32-42b27,24b28-30, 25b26-35, 26a23, 26b38, 28a14. Averroes expressed theidea somewhat differently: according to him, the minor term is thesubject of the proposition resulting from the syllogism. Cf. ShortCommentary on Aristotle's Prior Analytics M. 17bI2-13; P. 19a3-4.

An example of a syllogism occurring in the first figure would be:"Every body is composed; every composed thing is created; thus, everybody is created." In this example the terms are "body," "composed,"and "created," and the minor term is "body." An example of a

Page 60: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

108 NOTES NOTES 109

syllogism occurring in the second figure would be: "~very body iscomposed; no eternal entity is composed; thus, no body IS eternal." .Inthis example, the terms are "body," "eternal," and "composed," "':lth"body" again being the minor term. Finally, an example.of a S~IlOglS~

occurring in the third figure would be: "Every theo~etlcal.sC1enc.e ISlearned [i.e., acqui~ed by learning]; e~ery theo:et1cal sC1enc~ IS ~

virtue' thus some VIrtues are learned [I.e., acqUIred by learnmg].In thi~ example, the terms are "theoretical science," "learned,".a~d"virtue," with "virtue" being the minor term. Cf. Averroes, zbul.,M. 19b8, 2lb23-22a2, 23a20-22; P. 2la5-6, 23a17-l8, 25a9-l0.

3. In the syllogisms occurring in the first figure, Aristotle i?e~tified

the middle term as that term "which both is encompassed w1thm an­other and encompasses another." In the syllogisms occurring in thesecond figure, the middle term is that term "~hi~h is pre?icated ofboth subjects." F~nally, in the,~yllogi.smsoccurnn~m ~he thIrd figur~:the middle term IS that term of whIch both predIcatIOns are made.As a consequence, it literally occupies a middle position only in thesyllogisms of the first figure. Cf. Prior. Analytics 2.5b35-37, 26b36,28aI2-l3. According to Averroes, the mIddle term IS the part of thesyllogism which is common to both of the other terms. Cf. Short Commen­tary on Aristotle's Prior Analytics M. 17b13; P..19a4.

Taking the syllogism cited in the precedmg note as an ex~mple

of those syllogisms occurring in the first figure, "composed" IS themiddle term. With regard to the syllogism cited as an ex~mple oftho~e

syllogisms occurring in the second figure, "composed" IS once ag~m

the middle term. L. the syllogism cited as an example of those WhIChoccur in the third figure, "theoretical science" is the middle term.

4. With respect to the syllogisms occurri?g .in the. first figur~, Ari~­

totle identified the major term as "that w1thm whIch the m1ddl~ ISencompassed." In syllogisms occurring i~ the ~,econd fi~re, the ma}orterm is "that which comes next to the nuddle. In syllogIsms occurn?gin the third figure, he stated that the major term actually occupIesthe middle, but it is difficult to understand what he meant by SUC? adefinition. Cf. Prior Analytics 26a22, 26b38, 28a13-l~: Accord~ng

to Averroes, the major term is the predicate ofthe'pro~oslt1?nresultlI~g

from the syllogism. Cf. Short Commentary on Anstotle s Przor AnalytzcsM. 17b13; P. 19a4. .

Taking the syllogism cited in note 3 as an example of those syllogIsmsoccurring in the first figure, the major term wo~ld be "cre~te~." Inthe syllogism cited as an example of those syllogIsms occurnng m thesecond figure, "eternal" would be the major. term. Wit~ re~ard to ~he

syllogism cited as an example of those syllogIsms occurrmg m the thIrdfigure, "learned" would be the major term.

PARAGRAPH (7).

I. Although Aristotle discussed the major premise in the PriorAnalytics, he does not appear to have presented a detailed explanationof what it is anywhere in that book. Apparently, the student of logicwas expected to deduce the definition by reference to the previouslypresented analysis of the syllogisms. Accordingly, the major premiseof the syllogism cited as an example of those occurring in the firstfigure would be the premise which has the middle term as its subjectand the major term as its predicate, i.e., "every composed thing iscreated." For the syllogism which was cited as an example of thoseoccurring in the second figure, the major premise would be the onehaving the major term as its subject and the middle term as its predi­cate, i.e., "no eternal entity is composed." Finally, the major term ofthe syllogism cited as indicative of those syllogisms occurring in thethird figure would have the middle term as its subject and the majorterm as its predicate, i.e., "every theoretical science is learned [i.e.,acquired by learning]." Cf. supra, para. 3, n.l, para. 6, n. 2, and infra,para. 21, n. 1.

Averroes defined the major premise as "the premise whose predicateis the major term," a definition which can be valid only for the majorpremise of syllogisms occurring in the first and third figures. Whenhe presented the example of the syllogism occurring in the secondfigure, he identified its major premise as being universal and negative,i.e., "no eternal entity is composed." However, when he presentedthe example of the syllogism occurring in the third figure, he explainedthat its minor premise could be converted to a particular and thusplaced into the third type (mode) of syllogisms occurring in the firstfigure; by process of elimination, that means that the major premiseof this syllogism must be "every theoretical science is learned [i.e.,acquired by learning]." Cf. Short Commentary on Aristotle's Prior AnalyticsM. 17bl6-l7, 2lb22-23, and 23a22-23 with 20a3-7; P. 19a5-6,23a16, and 25a9-10 with 2lal6-l9.

2. Part of the syllogism, namely the minor premise, is left unstated.The complete syllogism would be: "Every man is an animal; everyanimal is sense-perceiving; thus, every man is sense-perceiving."The minor premise is "every man is an animal," and the major premiseis "every animal is sense-perceiving." When the syllogism is fullystated, it is the kind of syllogism that would belong to the first figure.

3. The word translated here as "speaking being" (niitiq) is equivocal.It could be translated "rational being" with equal accuracy, becausethe verb root (n!q) is as rich in meaning as the Greek word logos; infact, one form of the verb root is the Arabic word for logic (mantiq).

Page 61: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

110 NOTES NOTES III

Here "speaking being" appeared to be more analogous to the idea of"laughing being" tban "rational being."

Here, too, the syllogism is incomplete. However, this syllogism isincomplete only because the major premise is not stated in the begin­ning. The complete syllogism would be: "Every man is a speakingbeing; speaking is the same thing as laughing; thus every man is alaughing being." Given the qualifications established by Averroes,this syllogism could also be classified as falling within the first figure.

4. For a different perspective,.cr. "AI-Farabi's Introductory Rislilahon Logic," ed. by D.M. Dunlop in The Islamic Quarterly III (1957),p. 229, lines 2-9. Actually, a better syllogism can be constructed if"laughing" is taken as encompassed within "speaking": "All laughingis speaking; every man is a speaking being; thus every man is alaughing being." This syllogism would be classified as falling withinthe second figure.

PARAGRAPH (8).

1. The argument of the rest of the paragraph, as well as that ofthe following paragraph, will be much more easily understood once it isnoted that the word "problem" (maflub) is used here in the sense ofthe proposition which is the conclusion of some kind of syllogisticreasoning and that. as a proposition it has a subject and predicate.

PARAGRAPH (9).

1. In effect, with some more elaboration, the example of inductiondiscussed in paras. 6 and 8 could be used to verify the major premiseof the syllogism presented as an example of syllogisms occurring inthe first figure, namely, "every composed thing is created" (cf. para. 6,n. 2). By reflecting on the difficulty of verifying that premise byinduction, the reader will readily grasp the argument developed hereand in the next two paragraphs by Averroes.

2. That is, the doubt raised in the last sentence of the precedingparagraph.

PARAGRAPH (11).

1. The word translat~d here as "matter" (mliddah) is to be under­stood in both a material and a qualitative sense. It refers to thematerials which constitute the syllogism-i.e., to the premises­and to their quality-i.e., whether they are "necessary," "possiblefor the most part," or "equally possible."

PARAGRAPH (13).

1. Cf. supra, para. 3: " ... the dialectical argument is a syllogismcomposed from widespread, generally accepted premises."

2. In the Aphorisms, Hippocrates said: "spontaneous wearinessindicates disease." Cf. Hippocrates Aphorisms, Section II, no. 5, inHippocrates, trans. by W. H. S. Jones (London: William HeinemannLtd., 1931), Vol. IV, p. 109. Hippocrates lived from 460-370 B. C. E.

PARAGRAPH (14).

1. Cf. supra, paras. 3-4 and infra, Short Commentary on Aristotle'sRhetoric, para. 21. Although dialectical syllogisms may be partiallyfalse, that is not because the premises used in them are based onparticulars. Rather, it is because the premises used in them are basedon what is generally accepted and thus might not correspond to whatis really true.

PARAGRAPH (15).

1. The discussion of the universal predicates was part of Averroes'sShort Commentary on Porphyry's Isagoge; cr. ibid., M. 4a15-6b4; P. 4alO­6a17. As has already been explained, this commentary served as ageneral introduction to the rest of th~ Short Commentaries on thelogical arts.

Actually, Porphyry only discussed five universal predicates in theIsagoge: genus, species, differentia, property, and accident. In theShort Commentary on Porphyry's Isagoge, Averroes introduced the otherthree universal predicates (definition, d,scription, and the statementwhich is neither definition nor description) as representative of thetwo types of meanings composed from those five original universalpredicates; cf. ibid., M. 6a7-6b3; P. 6a5-17. His explanation of thethree additional universal prcdicat s illustrated how the meaningwhich each of these could provide was identical to the meaning thatcould be provided by different combinations of two of the originalfive universal predicates. Cf. also "AI-Farabi's Introductory Risalahon Logic," op. cit., pp. 228-229.

Incidentally, it ought to be not~d that when the word "predicate"occurs in the text with reference to on: of these five or eight universalpredicates, the reader might understand it as "predicable." However,since Averroes did not consider th,~ distinction sufficiently importantto warrant a change in terminology, it did not seem appropriate tocorrect his style.

Page 62: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

112 NOTES NOTES 113

2. According to Averroes, species (naw') and genus (jins) areconceived of by analogy to each other, genus applying to what is moregeneral and species to what is more particular. "When there is morethan one universal distinguishing what a certain individual is andsome are more-general than others, then the more general is genus andthe more particular is species" (cf. ibid., M. 4aI6-19; P. 4aI2-13)."For example, body, the self-nourishing, animal, and man are alluniversals distinguishing what an individual man, who is pointedout, is. Now some of these [universals] are more general than others.There is nothing more general than the universal, 'body,' and nothingmore particular than the particular, 'man' " (ibid., M. 4a22-4b3; P.4a 15-17).

3. Description (rasm) , according to Averroes, is "a conditionallycomposed composite argument which illustrates the meaning alludedto, [but] not according to everything that is analogous to its essence.For the most part it is put together: (a) from genus and property,like our saying that man is an animal who educates his children inthought and deliberation; or (b) from genus and accident, like oursaying that man is a writing animal" (ibia., M. 6aI3-19; P. 6alO-12).

4. According to Averroes, "The statement which is neither defini­tion nor description is put together: (a) from species and accident,like our saying about Zayd that he is a white man; or (b) from acci­dents, like our saying about him that he is an excellent scribe. Now thisis peculiar to the concept (t~awwur) as employed in rhetoric" (ibid.,M. 6aI9-22; P. 6aI2-14).

5. In the Topics, Aristotle only discussed four universal predicates:definition, property, genus, and accident; cr. Topics 10IbI3-25,1OIb35-102b26, and 103b20-21.

PARAGRAPH (16).

1. Cf. Aristotle Topics 101b21, 10Ib35-102aI6.

2. Cf. Aristotle Topics 102a30-102b3.3. Cf. Aristotle Topics 1OIbI7-18: "Since the differentia is of the

same nature as the genus, it ought to be classed under it."

4. Cf. Aristotle Topics 1OIbI9-22, 102aI7-30.

5. Cf. Aristotle Topics 102b3-25.

PARAGRAPH (17)

I. In the Posterior Analytics, Aristotle discussed the definition atgreat length in order to distinguish it from the thesis (cf. 72a 20-25)

and from the hypothesis (cf. 76b35-77a4), as well as to explain itsrelation to demonstration (cf. 89b23-100bI7). In the course of ex­plaining the relation of the definition to demonstration, Aristotleimplicitly touched on matters pertaining to the other universal predi­cates; cf. ibid., 91b27-33, 96b15-97b8 with 73a35-74bI2; 99b9-14with 73a7-8; and 96b35-100bl; (cf. also Topics 102b26-103a5 for theexplanation of why all of the universal predicates are implicit in anydiscussion of definition). Averroes also stressed the importance of thedefinition in his Short Commentary on Aristotle's Posterior Analytics.However; he was much· more explicit about the relation of the otheruniversal predicates to the definition and structured his discussion interms of the different relation each had to the definition. Cf. ibid., M.42al4-42bI5, P. 47a9-22; M. 42b22-52a14 (especially 46a16-23and 46b6-20), P. 48a2-57a21 (especially 51a19-22 and 52a2-9); andM. 52aI5-56a27, P. 57a22-62a5.

2. At the end of the Posterior Analytics, Aristotle spoke of the ultimategenus of the genera as though it were a category; he developed thisstatement more thoroughly in the Metaphysics. Cf. Posterior Analytics100al4-100b4; Metaphysics 1014a26-1014bI5; and Hugh Tredennick'stranslation of the PosteriorAnalytics (London: William Heinemann Ltd.,1960), note e, p. 259. Although Averroes extensively developed theimplications of the end of the Posterior Analytics in his short commentaryon that work, I can find no discussion of this particular point.

3. The reasoning here would seem to be that the differentia riskslooking too much like the genus, if it does not apply specifically to thatwhich it differentiates; cf. Aristotle Posterior Analytics 91 b27-33and 96b15-97b8 with 73a35-74a4 and 100al4-100b4; also Metaphysics1014b5-15.

PARAGRAPH (18).

1. In the Arabic text, this is the beginning of a long conditionalsentence. Literally, the sentence begins "that is because if..." andthe apodosis is not reached until the words "then if these syllogismswere enumerated in this manner..."

2. When he commented on Aristotle's Posterior Analytics, al-Farabiexplained that there were really only three classes of demonstrativesyllogisms: the demonstration that a thing is, i.e., the demonstrationofits existence; the demonstration of why a thing is, i.e., the demonstra­tion of its cause; and the demonstration that encompasses both ofthese. Although each of these classes could be subdivided into varioustypes of demonstrative syllogisms, depending on the way the universal

Page 63: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

114 NOTES NOTES 115

predicates or predicables were used with them, al-Farabi explicitlydeclared that many of the syllogisms resulting from such uses of theuniversal predicates were not demonstrative. Cf. Kitlib al-Burhiin,Hamidiye Manuscript, op. cit., folios 62b23-63a9 and 63alO-68b17;cr. also Prantl, op. cit., Vol. II, pp. 318-325.

PARAGRAPH (19).

1. Themistius was born in Paphlagonia, a province of the easternRoman Empire in Asia Minor near the Black Sea. (roughly the areabetween Ankara and Sinop of modern Turkey), CIrca 317 C.E. anddied in Constantinople circa 388 C.E.. He first gained recognition forhis numerous commentaries on Aristotle's logical, physical, and philo­sophical writings. Although his interests turned more to practicalmatters later in life and he was raised to the post of prefect of Con­stantinople in 384 C.E. by the Roman Emperor Theodosius I, ~e

did not abandon his philosophic activity. Unfortunately, f~w of hISwritings have survived until this day, and thus far nothIng .IS knownof the Arabic translations of his works to which Averroes mIght havehad access.

It is said that Gerard of Cremona translated Themistius's Commentaryon Aristotle's Posterior Analytics from Arabic into Latin some time in thelatter halfof the twelfth century, but no copy ofthat translation remains.Cf. Pauly-Wissowa Real-Encyclopaedie (Stuttgart: J.B. MetzlerscheVerlagsbuchhandlung, 1934), V<,>l. VA, co~s. l642-l6~0.

For an indication of the notIOn to whIch Averroes referred, cr.Themistius Analyticorum Posteriorum Paraphrasis, 1. vi, xx,iv, and xxvii.Prantl, op. cit., Vol. I, pp. 639-640 and 720-724, also gIVes adequatecitations for identifying the idea.

2. Although Themistius is never mentioned by name in al-Farab~'s

Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, there are at least three passages Inwhich an argument is made that could have prompted such a state­ment by Averroes; cf. Hamidiye Ms., op. cit., folios 90a2-4, 10-17;9la22-9lb16; and 104aI5-l05a12.

PARAGRAPH (21).

1. Literally, "according to the argument." However, according. topara. 12, supra, the discuss~oninyar.as. 5-11 was about th~ f~rm ofdIa­lectical arguments. The dISCUSSIOn In paras. 13-19 was lImIted to thematters of dialectical arguments.

2. Cf. supra, para. 3, n. 1, para. 6, n. 2, and para. 7, n. 1. Aristo.tlewas as laconic about the minor premise as he wa3 a bout the major

premise. However, if the syllogism cited as an example of thoseoccurring in the first figure is considered ("every body IS composed;every composed thing is created; thus, every body is c:eated"), theminor premise would be the premise which has the mInor term asits subject and the middle term as its predicate, i.e., "every body iscomposed." For the syllogism which was cited as an example of thoseoccurring in the second figure ("every body is compose~; no eterr~al

entity is composed; thus, no body is eternal"), the mInor premIsewould be the premise which has the minor term as its subject and themiddle term as its predicate, i.e., "every body is composed." Fina~ly,

for the syllogism which was cited as an example of those occurrIngin the third figure ("every theoretical science is learned [i.e., acquiredby learning]; every theoretical science is a virtue; thus, some virtuesare learned [i.e., acquired by learning]"), the m~nor premise w~uldbe the premise having the middle term as its subject and the mInorterm as its predicate, i.e., "every theoretical science is a virtue:" .

Averroes defined the minor premise as "the one whose subject ISthe minor term," a definition which can be valid only for the minorpremise of syllogisms occurring in the first and second figures. Forexample, when he presented the example of the syllogism occurring inthe second figure, he identified its minor premise as being universal andaffirmative, i.e., "every body is composed." However, when Averroespresented the example of the syllogism occurring in the third figure, heexplained that its minor premise could be converted to a particular andthus placed into the third type (mode) of syllogisms occurring ~n t~efirst figure. If the example that Averroes gave of such a syllogIsm ISconsidered, it becomes apparent that the minor premise of the pre­viously cited syllogism would be "every theoretical science is a virtue."That this is an accurate interpretation of Averroes's explanation canbe shown by converting this premise into a particular so as to make asyllogism representative of those occurring in the third type (mode)of syllogisms of the first figure, according to the necessary component.The new syllogism would be: "Some virtues are theoretical sciences;every theoretical science is learned [i.e., acquired by learning]; thus,some virtues are learned [i.e., acquired by learning]." Cf. ShortCommentary on Aristotle's Prior Analytics M. l7b15-l6, 2lb23, and23a22-23 with 20a3-6; P. 19a5, 23a17, and 25a9-1O with 2lal6-l9.

3. Because the problem is composed of a subject and a predicate,to solve a problem requires identifying the correct predicate for agiven subject. The other idea is that some problems are pursued fortheir own sake, while others are pursued because they are relatedto another, more interesting, problem. Cf. Aristotle Topics 104bl-12and 1Olbll-103a5.

Page 64: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

4. In the Topics, Aristotle explained that in addition to mentaltraining, the art of dialectic was useful for engaging in conversations,pursuing the philosophic sciences, and discovering the ultimate basesof each science. His reasoning was that the art of dialectic "is usefulfor conversations, because, having enumerated the opinions of themajority, we shall be dealing with people on the basis of their ownopinions, not of those of others, changing the course of any argumentwhich they appear to us to be using wrongly." Similarly, Aristotledeemed it useful for the philosophic sciences "because if we are ableto raise difficulties on both sides, we shall more easily discern bothtruth and falsehood on every point." The art of dialectic was con­sidered to be useful for discovering the ultimate bases or groundsof each science because of the impossibility of discussing those basesor grounds from the perspective of "the principles peculiar to thescience in question, since the principles are primary in relation toeverything else." The art of dialectic would permit one "to deal withthem through the generally accepted opinions on each point." Cf.Topics IOla25-101b2.

Because Averroes's Middle Commentary on Aristotle's Topics was notcompleted until 1168 C.E., whereas this Short Commentary on Aristotle'sTopics is thought to have been completed prior to 1159 C.E. (cf.Alonso, op. cit., pp. 55-61 and 77-78), Averroes was clearly not refer­ring to anything he had said in another commentary. What is signif­icant, however, is his silence about the possible use of dialectic forconversations, as well as for the philosophical sciences, and above allhis explicit denial of what Aristotle considered to be the fourth useof the art of dialectic, namely, its use with the ultimate bases of eachscience. Given al-Farabi's emphasis on the uses that the art ofdialectichad for both philosophy and demonstration (cf. Commentary on Aris­totle's Topics, Hamidiye Ms., op. cit., folios 88bI9-22, 89a26-100aI8)and given the emphasis that Averroes placed on the close relationshipbetween dialectic and philosophy earlier in this collection of commen­taries and in other writings, such a posture is most striking.

116 NOTESNOTES TO THE TRANSLATION OF THE SHORT

COMMENTARY ON ARISTOTLE'S RHETORIC

INVOCATION

. 1. The ~lause "[I beseech] your succor; our Lord" was omittedIII the Pans. manuscript. Instead, it reads: "And in Him I place mytrust; there IS no Lord other than He."

TITLE

1. Cf. supra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, para. 1, n. 3.

PARAGRAPH (I)

1. Cf. ibid., para. 2, n. 1. Cf. also Aristotle Posterior Analytics 88b30­89b9.

2. Cf. supra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, para. 2: "Ingeneral: supposition is believing that something exists in a parti­cul~r kInd of way, while it is possible for it to be different than it isbelIeved to be." Cf. also n. 1 of the same paragraph.

PARAGRAPH (2)

1. The word translated here as "inductive investigation" is theterm normally translated as "induction" (istiqrii').

2. Literally, "things from outside." These are the things Aristotlecalled "nori-technical" or "inartificial" (atechnoi); cf. Rhetoric I. ii.l355b36-38, and 1. xv. l375a22-1377bI2.

3. In ~rabie t~e two words translated here as "public speaking"(al-m.ukhatabah al-.Jumhuriyah) carry the connotation of speaking to themultI.tude, becausejum~ur means multitude or the many, i.e., the demos.As wI!1 be made clear In the sequel, speaking in public usually meansspeakIng to the large body of citizens; therefore, arguments used insuch speech must not be too complicated.

. 4. Aristo.tle divided rhetoric into three general classes: delibera­tIve: ~orensIc, and epideietie. The use of deliberative rhetoric entailsadVISIng others, especially the ruler. Cf. Rhetoric 1. iii-iv. 1358a35-1 360b3. Cf. also infra, para. 45, n. 3. With regard to the secondexample, cf. Aristotle Metaphysics 981a6-13.

117

Page 65: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

118 NOTES NOTES 119

PARAGRAPH (4)

1. Cf. supra, Short Commentary On Aristotle's Topics, para. 11. n. 1 andcf. also infra, paras. 16-25.

PARAGRAPH (5)

1. Cf. supra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, para. 5 and notes2-4.

PARAGRAPH (6)

1. According to Aristotle, at least one of the premises must beuniversal for a syllogism to be possible. In syllogisms of the first figure,the major premise must be universal-either affirmative or negative.He defined a universal premise as "a statment which applies to all,or to none, of the subject." Cf. Prior Analytics 24aI7, 26aI6-20, 41a6­41 b35. In the Short Commentary on Aristotle's Prior Analytics, Averroesexplained that to say that something is universal means that it "existsas a predicate, either possibly or necessarily, for everything charac­teristic of its subject." Cf. M. 18b6-l9a6; P. 20a3-l6.

2. Cf. supra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, para. 6, n. 1.3. In order to relate the two extreme terms of a syllogism, it is

necessary to have a middle term. This is what is meant here by theconjunction. According to Aristotle: "We must take some middle termrelating to both, which will link the predications together, if there isto be a syllogism proving the relation of one term to the other." Cf.Prior Analytics 40b37-4la12. Averroes explained that "if there is noconjunction at all between the two premises, then these two do notbring about any conjunction between the predicate and the subject ofthe problem and thus there is no syllogism at all." Cf. Short Commentaryon Aristotle's Prior Analytics M. 17b2-5; P. 18aI9-23. A little later, i.e.,in the same passage cited in note 1 of this paragraph, he explainedthe need to have a universal major premise and an affirmative minorpremise in order to effect the conjunction in a syllogism of the firstfigure. Cf. also Aristotle Prior Analytics 26aI6-19, 26a37-26b25.

4. Cf. supra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, para. 21, n. 1.5. Cf. ibid., para. 6, n. 4.6. The statement would not be accurate if the minor premise were

also particular. Cf. Prior Analytics 26a3-26b30.

PARAGRAPH (7)

1. Literally, "the controlling premise with regard to the conclusion"(al-muqaddamah al-malikah fi al-intaj), but it is obvious that Averroes

meant ~he prem!se which brings about the conclusion. This is usuallythe. major premIse; cf. infra, para. 16 "al-muqaddamah... al-malikah lial-zntiij."

2.. For Aristotle, the second figure occurs "when the same termapphes to all of one subject and to none of the other or to all or noneof both," cf. Prior Analytics 26b34-36. Aristotle als~ said that in this~~ure the middle term is the one that is predicated of both subjects; cf.zbzd.,. ~6b37. Averroes made this latter statement the basis of hisd~fill1tlOn of ~he second figure, saying that it is the one in which themIddle term IS the predicate of the major and the minor extremes. Cf.Short Commentary on Aristotle's Prior Analytics M. 17b23-18al' P 19a9Cf. also ibid., M. 21b2l-23a11; P. 23a15-25a3. ,..

3. Aristotle explained that the third figure is the one in which"o~e of the terms applies to all and the other to none of the samesubject, or both. terms apply t? all or none of it"; cf. Prior Analytics28a1?-l ~. In thIS figure the mIddle term is "that of which both thepredI~atlOn~ are made"; cr. ihid., 28a13. Averroes expressed this lastIdea.m a s.hghtly different way by saying that the third figure is theone m whIch the middle term "is a subject for the two extremes."Cf. Short .C?mmentary on Aristotle's Prior Analytics M. 18al-2; P. 19a9-1O.Cf. als? zlnd. M. 23all-24a8; 25a4-26a6. The conclusion of the thirdfigure IS not usually stated as a universal.

4. Cf. Aristotle Prior Analytics 27blO-39, 29a15-l7.

PARAGRAPH (8)

1. Cf. supr~, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, para. 5, n. 3.The explanat~on allud:d to here occurs within Averroes's expositionof all of t~e dIfferent kmds of conjunctive syllogisms. Cf. Short Commen­tary on Arzstotle's Prior Analytics M. 24a21-26bll especially 25all-15'P. 26a15-29a8, especially 27a15-18.' ,

2. Cf. supra, S~ort Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, para. 5, n. 3.The selected .term IS the one which is selected as affirmative or negativean~ from whIch the affirmation or the negation of the term conditionedby It follows. Cf. Goichon, op. cit., paras. 73, 76, 574, 586, and 611.

3. Cf. supra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, para. 5, n. 2.

~. A~cording to Averroes, "the first part of the conditional syllogism,whIch IS the cause of something resulting, is called the conditionalterm (al-muqad~i:n); the second part, which brings about the result, iscal.led the c~nditlOnedterm (al-tiiliy)." Cf. Short Commentary on Aristotle'sP~z?r Analytzcs M. 24a17 and margin; P. 26aI2-l3. The first, or con­dItional, term of a conditional syllogism would be "if the sun has risen,

Page 66: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

120 NOTES NOTES 121

it is daylight." The second, or conditioned, term is what restricts theconditional term and affirms or denies one part of it, e.g., "but thesun has risen." The conclusion of the syllogism is: "therefore, it isdaylight." Cf. also Goichon, op. cit., para. 573. Averroes sometimesused muqaddim to speak of the first half of the condition ("if the sunhas risen"), while using the tiilin to speak of the second half ("it isdaylight") .

5. Averroes was apparently thinking of the following kind ofinaccurate conclusion: "Man exists because animals exist." The first,or conditional, term of this syllogism is: "if man exists." If the second,or conditioned, term ("then animals exist") is selected and the con­ditional term brought forth as a conclusion, the syllogism is not accu­rate, e.g., "but animals exist, therefore, man exists." The reason. thesyllogism must be inaccurate is that the conditioned term has a WIderscope than the conditional term. Similarly, if the opposite of theconditional term is selected and the opposite of the conditioned termbrought forth as a conclusion, the resulting syllogism is not accurate,e.g., "but man does not exist; therefore, animals do not exist." Theinaccuracy of this syllogism is due to the same reason as in the firstexample: the conditioned term has a wider scope than the conditionalterm. The same problem occurs in a slightly different manner in thenext paragraph.

PARAGRAPH (9)

1. Galen (129-199) was born in Pergamum (now Bergama inwestern Turkey) and died in Rome. He has long been considered oneof the greatest medical writers of Greek antiquity and was reputedamong the Arabs as an anatomist, physiologist, practicing physician,and philosopher.

2. Cf. Oeuvres Anatomiques Physiologiques et Medicales de Galien, trans.by Ch. Daremberg (Paris: J.-B. Bailliere, 1854-1856), Vol. I, pp.498-508; Vol. II, pp. 167-171. Although it is not possible to fi~d .thedirect quotation, many of Galen's remarks and proofs are SImIlarto the way in which Averroes characterized him here.

3. Averroes refuted this very example on logical grounds, withoutnaming Galen, in his explanation of the conjunctive syllogism. Cf.Short Commentary on Aristotle's Prior Analytics M. 24b7-l7; P. 26a22-27a4.

PARAGRAPH (11)

1. According to Averroes: "The disjunctive syllogism is the oneto which particles of disjunction, like 'or' and 'either,' are attached."

He also explained that it is composed of opposing considerations andstated: "It is peculiar to the disjunctive syllogism that the conditionalterm in it is not a conditional term by nature and that the conditionedterm is not a conditioned term by nature; rather, it may be possiblefor the conditional term to convert to a conditioned term and for theconditioned term to convert to a conditional term." Cf. ibid., M.24aI9-20, 26bll-27b6; P. 26al4-l5, 29a9-30a8. Thus, the disjunctivesyllogism has an either/or quality. "Either this number is even, or it isodd." If the selected term "but it is not even" were omitted, thestatement of the conclusion "thus, it is odd" would only raise theproblem of how that conclusion might be proven.

PARAGRAPH (12)

1. AbU al-Ma'ali 'Abd aI-Malik ibn 'Abd Allah ibn Yusuf al­Juwayni, known as Imam al-.ij:aramayn, was born in Bushtanikan,a village near Nishapur, Iran in 419/1028 and died in the same villagein 478;1085. During his lifetime, he taught in Baghdad, Mecca, andMedina. He was especially noted for his work in dialectical theologyand for havmg been the teacher ofal-Ghazali (cf. infra, para. 42, n. I),but he spent much time as well in the study of Islamic jurisprudence.

2. This book, Kitiib al-Irshiid ilii Qawii/i' al-Adillahfi U~ill al~I'tiqiid,has been edited and partially translated by J.-D. Luciani (Paris:Imprimerie Nationale, 1938).

3. Cf. ibid., Chapter XIX, Section XVII, pp. 215-216 of the trans­lation and pp. 133-135 of the Arabic text. Although Averroes did notquote Abu al-Ma'ali literally, he expressed the core of this author'sthought very accurately. The divergence from lIteral quotationpermitted Averroes to summarize Abu al-Ma'ali's argument.

4. Oxymel (Arabic: sakanjabin) is a mixture of honey and vinegar.The Arabic word is derived from the two Persian words which describethe elements of the compound: sukar (honey, sugar) andjabin (vinegar).

Averroes was apparently referring to the fact that if these twoliquids are cooked long enough, they will form a hard, chewy sub­stance; thus, a new kind of existence arises from the mixture of thetwo ingredients.

PARAGRAPH (13)

1. Literally, "affirmative statement" (al-miijab).

Page 67: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

122 NOTES NOTES 123

PARAGRAPH (14)

1. Cf. supra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, para. 5, n. 4.

2. This syllogism could be reordered so that it would be suitablefor classification with syllogisms of the first figure: "Every man is ananimal; every animal is sentient; thus, every man is sentient." How­ever, if it were presented in that manner, it would no longer be acontradictory syllogism.

PARAGRAPH (17)

1. Cf. supra, para. 4. Note, however, that the earlier definition wasactually the definition of "unexamined previously existing opinion."Averroes apparently considered the terms "unexamined opinion"(biidi' al-ra'y), "unexamined common opinion" (biidi' al-ra'y al-muskta­rak), and "unexamined previously existing opinion" (biidi' al-ra'y al­sabiq) to be equivalent in meaning. Cf. infra, para. 23.

2. Cf. supra Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, paras. 3-4, 13-17,and 21.

PARAGRAPH (18)

1. Literally, "absolutely" ('ala al-illaq).2. This will be discussed more fully in para. 20, infra. It should

be noted, however, that what is identified here as "proof" is the middleterm of a syllogism occurring in the first figure; cf. supra, Short Commen­tary on Aristotle's Topics, para. 6, and Aristotle Prior Analytics 70all-23.The way in which Averroes has used the term "proof" both here andin para. 20, below, indicates that he was thinking of the term Aristotlecalled tekmerion, not pistis; cf. Rhetoric I. ii. 14-17, 1357a23-1357b10,II. xx. 1393a20-1394a14, II. xxii. 1395b 27-1397a6; Prior Analytics70bl-6.

3. This will be discussed more fully in paras. 21-22, infra. It shouldbe noted, however, that what is identified here as "sign" is the middleterm of a syllogism occurring in the second or third figure; cr. supra,Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, para. 6, n. 3. Cf. also PriorAnalytics 70a4-29. The way Averroes has used the term "sign" herecorresponds to Aristotle's use of the term semeion; cr. Rhetoric I. ii. 18,1357b12-28.

PARAGRAPH (20)

1. To the best of my knowledge Aristotle never used the terms"specious proof" or "doubtful proof" in a technical sense. Averroes

may have been alluding, however, to some ofthe examples offallacioussigns cited by Aristotle in the Rhetoric; cf. II. xxiv. 5-11, 1401b7­1402a30.

PARAGRAPH (22)

1. In order to remain consistent with his previous terminology,Averroes ought to have spoken here of "signs in the third figure." Cf.supra, para. 18 and note the order of paras. 20-21. Nonetheless the?ifferent ter~inologyused here does not appear to suggest any si~nif­Icant change In the argument.

PARAGRAPH (23)

1. Cf. supra, para. 17: "Thus we say that the premises used in this~lass of arguments, especially the major premise, are taken hereInsofar as they are generally accepted according to une~amined~ommon?pinion... What is generally accepted according to unexam­Ined prevIOusly existing opinion is divided into (a) generally receivedpropositions... and into (b) sense perceptible things..."

PARAGRAPH (24)

1. Averroes used this example in his Short Commentary on Aristotle'sPrior Analytics, but he did not mention Protagoras by name. Cf. ibid.,M. 26al4-15; P. 28a22.

The confutation of Protagoras to which Averroes alluded is not asstark as the example suggests. There is an exchange in the Protagoraswhere Socrates said something similar to what is reported here (cf.331c-e), but the reference is much more suggestive of the way in whichthe doctrine ofProtagoras is refuted in the Theaetetus. In the course ofadiscussion with Theodorus (a friend of Protagoras) and Theaetetus(a student of Theodorus), Socrates set out to examine the doctrine ofProta~oras that "man is the measure of all things." The relativismto whIch the doctrine leads was clearly identified and harshly de­nounced, as were the doctrines which may have given rise to it. Eventhough Protagoras was dead- when the conversation took place,S~crates resurrected him, so to speak, by addressing questions to1 heodorus as though he were Protagoras--questions to which Theo­dorus replied without insisting on his Own identity. Some of theseexchanges come very close to the example given here. Cf. Theaetetus167c, 169d-l 72c, 182c-183b, as well as the exchanges between Socratesand Theaetetus at 151e-154b, 157d-158a, 159c-160e, 164b-d, 165e­168c, 186e-187a. Cf. also Aristotle Metaphysics 999bl-15, lO07b18-

Page 68: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

124 NOTES NOTES 125

lO11b23, and 1062bI3-1063bI8; Averroes Tafsir ma ha'd al-Tahi'ah,ed. M. Bouyges (Beirut: Imprimerie Catholique, 1967),238: 17-241 :13and 382 :10-454:11 (esp. 383 :4-14 and 423 :1-427 :15); and Alfarahi'sPhilosophy ofPlato and Aristotle, trans. Muhsin Mahdi (New York: TheFree Press of Glencoe, 1962), p. 54.

PARAGRAPH (29)

1. Cf. Aristotle Prior Analytics 25b31-26a2, 26b22-33,29b29-30a14,32a7-14. Cf. also, Averroes Short Commentary on Aristotle's Prior Analytics,M. 18b6-19a7, 20bI3-21b20; P. 20a3-16, 22al1-23aI5.

2. Cf. supra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, para. 8, n. 1 andpara. 6, notes 2, 4.

PARAGRAPH (30)

1. The notion that supposition (~ann) is a species of opinion (ra'y) isevident here. Cf. supra, para. 1, notes 1 and 3. The term "ranks of sup­position" refers to the different degrees ofconviction an individual mighthave about the correctness of his supposition. Concerning the limitsof sense perception for certainty about universal matters, cf. AristotlePosterior Analytics 87b28-88aI8, 99bl5-100bI7; Metaphysics 1009b13­17; and Averroes Tafsir ma ha'd al-Tahi'ah, op.cit., 417:14-418:9.

PARAGRAPH (31)

1. Although the term "dialectical theologian" (mutakallim) OrIgI­nally referred to any Muslim theologian, it later came to have a morespecific connotation. Both the term for theology ('ilm al-kallim) andthat for theologian were used to refer to scholastic theology with anatomistic basis, taking its roots from Democritus and Epicurus. It isto this distinction that Averroes was obviously alluding when he saidthat those authors who wrote about physics in verse could moreproperly be called dialectical theologians than poets. Just prior tothis observation, Averroes had mentioned the name of Empedocles.Cf. Averroes Talkhif Kitiih Aris/ii/litis fi al-Shi'r, Badawi edition, op. cit.,204:1-10 and Aristotle Poetics 1447b9-23.

2. Partially because of textual difficulties; it is not easy to seize theprecise nature of Averroes's criticism. All texts but one read: "Theexample only provides certainty as a means ofguidance and scrutiny."Unfortunately, it has not been possible to locate anything resemblingthis statement in the few works ofAbu al-Ma'ali that are now available.

Averroes's criticism of Abu al-Ma'ali seems to be based on theargument of the preceding paragraph about the inadequacy of the

example for acquiring certainty about a universal (cf. also supra, paras.27 and 29). Because Abu al-Ma'ali only partially understood thelimits of the example, he failed to account for the role of the syllogismin instruction and in scientific investigation. Averroes had alreadydemonstrated the inadequacy of the induction for scientific investi­gation (cf. supra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, paras. 6-11,esp. para. 10) and carefully prepared the way for the role of thesyllogism in that task (cf. Short Commentary on Aristotle's Posterior Ana­lytics, end). The larger problem here is how to get at the fundamentalprinciples of each science: since it is not possible to do that by meansof the principles peculiar to the science, one must have recourse toreasoning based on probable opinion-the dialectical syllogism; butAbu al-Ma'ali's statement has the consequence of eliminating thattool, since neither induction nor example can provide the neededpremises. As Averroes pointed out here, that consequence is disastrousfor learning-unless it is presupposed that the sciences already existand one has only to select premises as one wishes. Abu al-Ma'ali'sother major error was forgetting that examples are based on senseperceptions and could not therefore be used to reason about a sciencewhose subject is free from matter, a science like geometry. Cf. alsoAristotle Prior Analytics 68b30-37, 69aI2-l8; and Topics 101a33-lOl b3.

3. The reference is to the Almagest of Ptolemy. Ptolemy, or ClaudiusPtolemaeus, was an astronomer, geographer, and mathematician wholived during the 2nd century C.E. He was born in Greece but passedmost of his life in Alexandria, and it was there that he composed hisencyclopedic work on astronomy called The Mathematical Collection.This work was translated into Arabic in the 9th century C.E. and cameto be known as the Almagest or "the Great." It was widely read andcommented on by Arab thinkers.

PARAGRAPH (33)

1. Averroes apparently considered the enthymeme and the exampleto be the first and second kinds of persuasive things. Since these havealready been discus~ed, the other eleven are presented here. Cf. al­Farabi Kitab al-Kha/libah, op. cit., 69: 7-81 :11 for a similar enumeration.

PARAGRAPH (35)

1. If Abu al-Ma'ali can be trusted in such matters, Averroes hasfaithfully presented the traditional view concerning the report. Cf.Kitlib al-Irshiid, op. cit., pp. 345-351 of the translation and pp. 231-236of the Arabic text.

Page 69: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

126 NOTES NOTES 127

PARAGRAPH (36)

1. The term is usually used to designate the more literal traditionalists,i.e., those scholars who specialized in gathering, perfecting, passingon, and studying the deeds and sayings traditionally attributed to theprophet Mu1).ammad. They influenced Islamic jurisprudence as muchas they did Islamic theology. Averroes singled them out for criticismin some of his other writings because of the confusion to which theirliteralness sometimes led the people in matters of faith; cf. Fa~l

al-Maqiil, op. cit., 7:17-8:5 and Kashf, op. cit., 133:4-19 (paginationof Muller edition: 27-28), 134:4-135:8 (Muller pagination: 28-29).

PARAGRAPH (37)

1. Abu al-Ma'ali explained the continuous tradition in much thesame way, but he also indicated that the reason for considering thenumber of people an essential element in making this kind of reportmore believable is that if it can be believed that these people knewwhat they were talking about, their number makes it unlikely that theyhave contrived a false tale. Because those making the report arepresumed to have had no previous contact and to be ignorant of whatothers have reported about the particular event, the agreement ofmany people about something makes the truth of what they say morelikely. Cf. Kitiib al-Irshiid, op. cit., pp. 346-350 of the translation andpp.232-235 of the Arabic text; cf. also Mu1).ammad A'la ibn 'Alial-Tahanawi, Kitiib Kashshiif I~!iliibiit al-Funiln (A Dictionary of theTechnical Terms Used in the Sciences of the Musalmans), ed. M. Wajih,'Abd al-I:Iaqq, and Gh. Qadir (2 vols.; Calcutta: W.N. Lees Press,1862), Vol. II, pp. 1471-1473.

Throughout this section Averroes has used the term "report" as ageneral instance of the more specific term "tradition" (~adith). Thetradition was generally considered to be second in authority to theQur'an and was divided into two basic classes: the ~adith nabawi andthe ~adith qudsi. The former is either an account of something theprophet Mu1).ammad said or did, or it affirms his tacit approval ofsomething said or done in his presence. The latter is an account thatexpresses God's words, that is, not God's exact words, but wordsexpressive of the meaning of His exact words. The continuous traditionwould be one kind of hadith nabawi. Neither of these classes of traditionsis considered to fulfill the conditions permitting it to be acceptedas revelation. Nonetheless, well-attested traditions should be acceptedas explanations of ambiguous matters.

PARAGRAPH (38)

1. Literally, "as they are" ('alii mii hiy 'alaih).

PARAGRAPH (39)

1. Cf. supra, para. 38, n. 1.2. Exhaustive reports are considered to be a little less compelling

than the continuous tradition and a little more compelling thangenerally accepted reports (mashhilriit). Cf. al-Tahanawi, Kitiib Kashshiifhtiliibiit al-Funiln, op. cit., Vol. I, pp. 748-749.

3. Literally, "supposed" from ";;.ann," "supposition." Cf. supra,Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, para. 2, n. 1.

4. Literally, "caused things" (al-musabbabiit).

5. Cf. Aristotle Metaphysics 1025a14-34, 1026a33-1027b16, 1064b15-1065b4; Averroes TaJsir mii ba'd al-Tabi'ah, op. cit., 693:7-696:10and 716:10-736 :8, esp. 719:15-18, 720:17-721 :13, 725:14-17,726:10-728:16, 734:1-4, and 736:5-8.

Cf. also Maimonides Maqiilahfi $inii'at al-Man!iq, ed. by MubahatTurker, "Musa ibn-i Meymun'un al-Makalafi Sina'at al-Mantil$:," inAnkara Oniversitesi Dil ve Tarih-Cografya Fakiiltesi Dergisi, XVIII (1960).p. 55, lines 14-16: "In general, all of the natural things that usuallyexist are essential; whenever they rarely exist, they are said to beaccidental-like someone who digs a foundation and finds money.In general, all chance matters, whether they are things not intendedby man or not intended by nonman, are said to be accidentalwhenever they occur."

PARAGRAPH (40)

1. According to the strictest teaching of the Metaphysics, there can beno accidental certainty (cf. supra, para. 39, n. 5). Nor did Aristotle everspeak of accidental certainty in Sense and Sensible Objects. To thecontrary, he attacked his predecessors and contemporaries in thatwork for having confused accidental and essential causes; certaintycould be attained only about essential causes (cf. Sense and SensibleObjects 437a18-438b16, 441a4-442b27, and 445a16-445b3).

The real issue, then, must be belief which is so strong as to be likecertainty and which is due to accidental causes: how does it comeabout? There is a discussion of accidental causes in On Prophecy inSleep (462b27-464bl9), and it results in casting extensive doubt onthe phenomenon of prophecy. Aristotle thought dreams were more

Page 70: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

128 NOTES NOTES 129

often to be explained as coincidences than as sigm or as caus~s ofsome­thing. Since Averroes considered the treatise On Prophecy in Sleepto be part of the book Kitiib al-lfiss wa al-Ma/.tsiis (Sense and SensibleObjects), he may have been referring to that argument. When he latercommented on that collection, he paid careful attention to the questionof prophecy in dreams, denying that there was any basic mysteryabout it. He attributed the phenomenon to the kind of knowledgeof causes that arises from a highly developed imaginative faculty. Cf.Averroes TaWzif Kitiib al-lfiss wa al-Ma/.tsiis li Aris!ii in Aris!ii!iilis fial-Najs, ed. by 'Abd al-Ra1)man Badawi (Cairo: Maktabat al-Nah<;lahal-Mi~riyah, 1954), pp. 224-226.

If Alonso and Gatje are correct in their dating, the commentary onSense and Sensible Objects was written eleven years after these com­mentaries (554/1159 versus 565/1170). Consequently, Averroes'sreference here would be to Aristotle's work, not his own. Alonso,Gatje, and Wolfson also argue that despite the title of Talkhif (MiddleCommentary), Averroes's book on Sense and Sensible Objects is a ShortCommentary (jawiimi'). Cf. Alonso, op. cit., pp. 55-82 and the corrobo­rations from the secondary literature cited by him; Gatje, Die Epitomeder Parva Naturalia des Averroes, op. cit., p. v, n. 2 and pp. x-xi, andWolfson, "Revised Plan for the Publication of a Corpus CommentariorumAverrois in Aristotelem," op. cit., pp. 90-94.

PARAGRAPH (42)

1. According to different traditions, the Prophet claimed that Godwould never let the nation of Islam agree about something that couldlead them astray. It is in this sense that the Muslims are infallible.However, there is a problem about how to treat a member of thecommunity who disagrees with the consensus which the others havesupposedly reached. The problem arises from the difficulties of exactlyidentifYing the consensus of the community on any given issue,particularly on theoretical issues. Averroes discussed this problemmore fully in the Decisive Treatise; cf op. cit., 8:15-10:18.

One tradition quotes the Prophet as saying: "Verily, God would notlet my nation agree about an error." Another tradition reports avariant of that statement: "Verily, my nation would not agree aboutan error." In a different tradition, he is reported to have commandedMuslims: "Do not come to agreement about an error." Yet anotherversion quotes the Prophet as praying: "Do not let them agree aboutan error." Cf. A.J. Wensinck et aI., Concordance et Indices de la TraditionMusulmane (7 Vols.; Leiden: E.J. Brill, 1936-1969), Vol. I, pp. 97,364, and 366; Vol. III, p. 517.

2. Abu Hamid Muhammad ibn Muhammad al-Tusi al-Ghazali(450/1058-505/1111) ~as born at Tus,· a small to~n in Khurasannear the modern city of Meshed, Iran, and, after living in many otherparts of the Middle East, returned there at the end of his life. He wasa student of Abu al-Ma'ali for many years and taught theology inBaghdad and later in Nishapur. The best source for a biographicaland intellectual account of al-Ghazali is his own al-Munqidh Minal-l)aliil, a book which is translated into English as The Deliverancefrom Error. Of al-Ghazali's intellectual activities, the most importantare his attacks on philosophy and his attempt to reform or renewreligious belief and pratice. The attack on philosophy was brilliantlyanswered by Averroes: to al-Ghazali's Tahiifut al-Faliisifah (TheIncoherence of the Philosophers), Averroes replied with the Tahiifut al­Tahiifut (Incoherence of the Incoherence).

3. This work was written between 493/1099 and 499/1106 andprovided a defense of al-Ghazali's views. He examined the questionof interpretation and the extent to which tradition and consensuscould be used as a basis for knowledge about religious matters. Thecentral theme in the book is indicated in the title: he wished to deter­mine how atheism could be clearly defined.

The difficulties of identifying the precise date when the book wasfinished are presented by Father Bouyges. He did think, however,that the book was written after The Balance (cf. infra, para. 43, n. 2)and before the Deliverance from Error; cf. Maurice Bouyges, Essai deChronologie des Oeuvres de al-Ghazali, edited by Michel Allard (Beirut:Imprimerie Catholique, 1959), pp. 50-51, 57-58, 70-71 and 4-6.

4. The quote is not exact, but Averroes caught the spirit of al­Ghazali's thought. According to al-Ghazali, one is not called a hereticfor holding different opinions about the "branches" or side issues ofIslam, except under special circumstances. The only clear case for de­ciding that someone is a heretic is his denial of the three roots ofIslam, i.e., belief in Allah, his Messenger, and the Last Day-beliefsthat Averroes accepted as crucial in the Decisive Treatise, cf. op. cit.,14:13-15 :8.

All other questions lead to the charge of heresy only under certainconditions, such as denying the religion passed on by Mu1)ammad orharming the belief of the common people. Consensus is a very obscurematter that al-Ghazali preferred to leave for skilled jurists to settle;he even argued that the palpable error of Abu Bakr al-Farisi aboutconsensus did not warrant the charge ofheresy. Cf. Fay~al al- Tafriqah inal-Q,u~iir al-'Awiili Min Rasii'il al-Imiim al-Ghaziili (Cairo: Maktabat

Page 71: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

130 NOTES NOTES 131

a1-Jundi, no date), pp. 165:14-17; 166:5,14-17; 166:18-167 :6;169:16-170:11.

The Munich manuscript has a sentence explaining this citation, butit has been bracketed as though if were not part of the text: "That isbecause the dialectical theologians disagree about the conditions to beset down about consensus." (Reading "ijma'" [consensus] for "iqna'"[persuasion]) .

PARAGRAPH (43)

1. The text reads f:zusn al-;:.ann, i.e., literally, "good supposition."

2. This book was written between 493/1099 and 499/1106 but. atany rate, prior to The Distinction between Islam and Atheism; cf. supra,para. 42, note 2 and cf. also M. Bouyges, op. cit., pp. 50-58, 70-71,and 4-6. The Balance is the last of five treatises written by al-Ghazaliagainst esoteric doctrines.

3. There is no remark in the book which corresponds to this quota­tion. Moreover, in this treatise, a1-Ghazali never used the term al­jumhar to refer to the common people; instead he used the termal-'awam.

Averroes nevertheless summarized the main idea of the latter partof the book, for al-Ghazali did make a distinction between the way thelearned grasped religious notions and the way the common people did.The only mention of "miracle" occurred in a context which wouldmake Averroes's statement appear to be a fair abridgement-but anabridgement, nevertheless. Cf. al-Qjs!as al-Mustaqim in al-Q.u~ar al­'Awali, op. cit., pp. 70:9-71 :2. Cf. also pp. 59:1-60:9, 68:6-7, 69:11­15. Note the long digression on pp. 68:7-69:11 in which al-Ghazaliexamined the question of the extent to which dialectic was of anyscientific value.

PARAGRAPH (45)

1. Epideictic rhetoric is concerned with praise or blame, is usuallyaddressed to mere spectators, and has honor or disgrace as its end.Cf. Aristotle Rhetoric 1. iii. 3-5. 1358b4-20 and 1. ix. 1366a22­1368b1; cf. also Averroes Talkhif al-Khatabak, Badawi edition, op. cit.,pp. 28-31, 71-82.

2. Forensic rhetoric is concerned with accusation or defense,is usually addressed to those who judge things that have taken place,and has justice or injustice as its end. Cf. Aristotle Rhetoric 1. iii. 3-5.1358b4-20 and 1. x-xv. 1368b2-1377bI0; cf. also Averroes Talkhi~

al-Kka!abak, Badawi edition, op. cit., pp. 28-31, 83-130.

. 3. Deliberative rhetoric is concerned with exhorting or dissuading,IS usu~lly addressed to judges of things to come (like rulers), and hasexpedIency or harm as its end. Cf. Aristotle Rhetoric I. iii. 3-5.1358b4-20 and 1. iv-viii. 1359a25-1366a21; cf. also Averroes,Talkhi~ al-Khatabah, Badawi edition, op. cit., pp. 28-31, 32-71.

.4. In the Ara~:c text, th~s is the apodosis of the sentence beginningWIth the words: When ArIstotle became aware... "

Page 72: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

PARAGRAPH (5)

1. The word translated here as "treatises" is the same word whichhas been translated as "speeches" and as "arguments" (aqawil).Because each of the commentaries in this collection has been spokenof in a speech or an argument about a certain subject, Averroes couldconclude by speaking of all which preceded as so many speeches orarguments, i.e., aqawil.

is part of a proof of how close the Prophet is to the believers-so closethat his wives could be their mothers.

It is of some interest that Averroes considered the substitutionused in the art of poetics to be more noble than the simile, just as heconsidered the syllogism used in dialectic to be more noble than theinduction and the enthymeme used in rhetoric to be more noble thanthe example. Cf. Middle Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, BibliotecaLaurenziana, Florence, Codice Orientale Laurenziano, Ms. CLXXX, 54,fol. 91a14-18.

3. This verse was cited by Averroes in the Middle Commentary onAristotle's Poetics in exactly the same manner, and the editor of thatwork presented the complete verse in its correct version: "He is thesea from whichever direction you approach him / for his depth is thegood deed, while generosity is his coastline" (huw al-babr min 'ayy al­nawabi ataytah / jalujjatuh al-ma'rilj wa al-Jtid sabiluh). According to theeditor, the verse is from a poem by Abu Tammam, cf. Middle Commen­tary on Aristotle's Poetics, Badawi edition, op. cit., p. 202 and note 2.

4. In the Middle Commentary on Aristotle's Poetics, Averroes alsoreferred to Empedocles, identified him as a natural scientist, and ex­plained that he was a poet only insofar as his arguments were set forthin meters. Averroes then suggested that those who made meteredarguments about physical questions deserved ~o be called dialecticaltheologians more than they deserved to be called poets. Cf. supra,Short Commentary on Aristotle's Rhetoric, para. 31, note 1 and MiddleCommentary on Aristotle's Poetics, Badawi edition, op. cit., p. 204; cf.also Po.:tics 1447b18, 1457b24, 1461a24 for Aristotle's references toEmpedocles. Empedocles (490-430 B.C.E.) thought that all thestructures in the world arose from combinations of four primarysubstances-fire, air, water, and earth-by means of two forces: loveand strife. Because he held that these primary substances are neverdestroyed, but only undergo alterations in their mixture, he deniedgeneration and destruction.

133NOTES

TITLE

PARAGRAPH (2)

1. In the Middle Commentary on Aristotle's Poetics, Averroes gaveexamples of the particles ofsimile; cf. Talkhi~ Kitab Aris!ti!alisfi al-Shi'r,Badawi edition, op. cit., pp. 201-202.

2. Substitution (tabdi!) is an Arabic grammatical and poeticalterm. When an author places a word or letter in place of another heis said to employ "substitution." Examples of substitution are:"thehabits of the gentlemen and the gentlemen of habits"; " ... the firsthouse set down for mankind was at Bekkah," Q!Jr'an III. 97, whereBekkah is used in place of Mekkah; " ... Dh, God, make me wealthythrough need of You, but do not improverish me through belief insufficient wealth to do without You." Cf. al-Tahanawi, Kitab KashshafI~!ila&at al-Funtin, op. cit., Vol. I, pp. 145-146; Vol. II, pp.978-989,1171-1172. Note also the discussion of substitution in Averroes'sMiddle Commentary on Aristotle's Rhetoric, Badawi edition, op. cit., pp.204-209. Cf. also Abu 'Abd Allah Mul)ammad al-Khuwarizmi,Kitab Mafatib al-'Ultim, ed. G. Van Vloten (Leiden: E.]. Brill, 1895),p.73.

In the Middle Commentary on Aristotle's Poetics (op. cit., p. 202),Averroes gave two examples of substitution, one a clause from aQur'anic verse and the other the verse of poetry quoted in the nextsentence of this text (cf. note 3, infra). The citation from the Q,ur'an,occurring in surah XXXlII, verse 6 ("... his wives are their mothers..."),

132

1. Although the word aqawi! has often been translated as "argu­ments" (cf. supra, Short Commentary on Aristotle's Topics, para. 1, n. 3),it seemed more appropriate to translate it as "speeches" in this context.

INVOCATION

1. In addition to this phrase, the Munich manuscript has thefollowing phrase: "Praise be to God, Lord of both worlds." However,the Paris manuscript has the phrase, "I have recourse to Him and placemy trust in Him," in addition to the phrase translated in the text.

NOTES TO THE TRANSLATION OF THE SHORTCOMMENTARY ON ARISTOTLE'S POETICS

Page 73: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

134

EPILOGUE

NOTES INDEX

1. The scribe of the Hebrew translation added a colophon in whichhe stated: "It is finished and completed, praise be to the Lord of theworld. The summary of the Art of Logic was completed, praise be toHim who dwells in a hidden, lofty place, on the third day of themonth of Tishri in the year five thousand one hundred and seventeensince the period of creation. It was written for myself, as well as foranyone else who wishes [to read it]-Ezra bar Shlomo (may hismemory live in the world to come), ben Gratnia of Saragossa (may thename protect them)." The Latin edition adds the following: "Verily,God is on high; it is God who aids and sustains; there is none otherthan God; praise be to God forever. Amen."

~he p.urpose of this index is two-fold. In the first place, it is designedto IdentIfy the proper names, titles and technical terms which occurin ~hese texts and the passages ~here they occur. Secondly, it isdesIgned to serve as a glossary; for that reason, the Arabic equivalentsof the technical terms are given. References are to the paragraphsof the texts presented here.

A. NAMES AND TITLES CITED BY AVERROES

Abu I:!amid, see al-GhazaliAbu al-Ma'ali, see al-]uwayniAbu Na~r, see al-FarabiAnatomistsAncientsAristotle

On Sophistical RifutationsPosterior AnalyticsPrior Analytics

Sense and Sensible ObjectsTopics

Dialectical TheologiansDivine Law

Empedodes

al-Farabi

Rhetoric, 9Rhetoric, 8, 18,20, 21, 25,44Topics, 21Rhetoric, 45Poetics, 4Poetics, 2Topics, 17Topics, 5Rhetoric, 8, 29Rhetoric, 40Topics, 21

Rhetoric, 31, 36, 43Rhetoric, 42

Poetics, 2

Topics, 18, 19

135

Page 74: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

136 INDEX B. TECHNICAL TERMS USED BY AVERRO£S

Galenal-Ghaz~ili

The BalanceDistinction between Islam andAtheism

ij:ashawiyahHippocrates

al-JuwayniThe Spiritual Directive

al-MagestMeccaMedinaMu1:lammad

PlatoProphet, see Mu1:lammadProtagoras

Socrates

Themistius

Rhetoric, 9, 33Rhetoric, 42, 43Rhetoric, 43

Rhetoric, 42

Rhetoric, 36Topics. 13

Rhetoric, 12, 31Rhetoric, 12

Rhetoric, 31Rhetoric, 38Rhetoric, 38Rhetoric, 36, 38

Rhetoric, 24

Rhetoric, 24

Rhetoric, 22

Topics, 19

Absolute (i!liiq)

Accident ('arat/)

Affirmative (miljab)

Analogy (muniisabah)Argument (qawl)

Art (~inii'ah)

Assent (t~diq)

Cause (fii'il, sabah)

('illah)Certainty (yaqin)

Challenge (taJ;,addan)Class (~anf)

Concept (t~awwur)

Conclusion (natijah)Conjunction (itti~iil)

Consensus (ijmii')Consequence (luzilm)Convention (wal')

Decision, see JudgmentDeduction (istinbii!)

Topics, 16Rhetoric, 15Topics, 4, 10, 15, 16, 18Rhetoric, 17, 38, 39, 40Topics, 6Rhetoric, 6, 7, 13Rhetoric, 28Topics, 1,3,5,6,8, 12, 13, 19,21Rhetoric, 2, 3, 7, 8, 10, 12, 14, 17,

20, 21, 22, 23, 24, 25, 26,27, 28, 29, 33, 44, 45

Topics, 1, 3, 5, 9, 13, 15, 21Rhetoric, 2, 23, 24, 32, 36, 40, 44,

45Poetics, 1, 2, 3, 4Topics, 1, 3, 5, 6, 12, 19Rhetoric, 1,24,32,33,37,38,39,45Poetics, 5

Topics, 5, 6, 19Rhetoric, 2, 6, 7, 18, 19, 36, 39, 40Topics, 13Topics, 2, 5, 9, 10, 11, 19Rhetoric, 30, 31, 38, 29, 40, 44Rhetoric, 33, 43Topics, 5, 13, 15, 18, 19Rhetoric, 2, 3, 12, 15, 16, 17, 19, 25,

26,28Poetics, 2Topics, 1, 16, 17, 18Rhetoric, 39Poetics, 2, 5Rhetoric, 4, 5,6, 7, 8, 10, 13, 16Rhetoric, 6, 7, 10Rhetoric, 33, 42Rhetoric, 8, 14Topics, 7

Rhetoric, 9, 36

137

Page 75: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

138 INDEX INDEX 139

Topics, 4, 6, 7, 8, 9, 10, 11, 14, 19Rhetoric, 18, 21, 27, 29, 30

Topics, 11, 13Rhetoric, 4, 16, 19,20,21,22,23,25Topics, 16Topics, 11, 13Rhetoric, 2Poetics, 2Topics, 13Rhetoru, 5, 24, 36,45Poetics, 4

Topics, 13Rhetoric, 26, 27, 28Topics, 19

Topics, 7, 18Rhetoric, 3Poetics, 5Topics, 6Rhetoric, 6, 13

Rhetoric, 2, 33Topics, 3, 10, 13, 21Rhetoric, 4Poetics, 4Rhetoric, 4, 5, 7, 13, 17, 23, 24, 25,

25,30Unexamined Opinion (biidi'al-ra'y)Unexamined Common Opinion(badi' al-ra'y al-mushtarak) Rhetoric, 17Unexamined Previously ExistingOpinion (badi' al-ra'y al-sabiq) Rhetoric, 4, 17

Likeness (shabih)

Logic (man/iq)

Matter (maddah)

Meaning (ma'nan)Medicine (/ibb)

i.e., Drug (dawii')Metaphor (isti'arah)Multitude (jumhilr)

Nature (tab')

Negative (siilib)

Oath (yamin)Opinion (ra'y)

Particular (juz')

Topics, 8Rhetoric, 1, 2, 3, 5, 6, 7, 8, 11, 13,

14, 16, 23, 25, 33, 34, 36,42,43,44,45

Poetics (shi'r) Poetics 1 4Point of Contention (mawda' 'ina£!) Rhetoric 6 7 8 10Predicate (ma~mi1l) . Topics, 8, '10: Ii, 15, 16, 17, 18, 19

Rhetoric, 18, 24, 26, 29

Peculiar Characteristic,see PropertyPersuasion (iqna')

Topics, 4, 5, 6, 8Rhetoric, 6, 14, 18, 20, 21, 22, 31Topics, 12Rhetoric, 4, 5, 7, 11, 15, 25, 33, 38

Topics, 3,4, 5, 9, 10, 13, 14, 19, 21Rhetoric, 16, 17,24,44Topics, 17Rhetoric, 23Topics, 15, 16, 17, 19, 21

Rhetoric, 38Poetics, 1, 4Topics, 14Rhetoric, 6, 7, 30Topics, 6, 8, 9, 10, 11, 19Rhetoric, 2, 27, 32

Topics, 6, 9Rhetoric, 26, 27, 29, 30

Topics, 11, 13Rhetoric, 36

Topics, 3, 15, 16, 17, 18, 21Rhetoric, 17, 45Topics, 2, 3, 10, 11, 18, 19, 21Rhetoric, 6, 23Topics, 6, 15, 16, 17Rhetoric, 23Topics, 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 9, 12, 15, 18,

19, 21Rhetoric, 1, 17,24,32Topics, 15, 16, 17, 18Rhetoric, 42

Rhetoric, 12Topics, 14Rhetoric, 7Rhetoric, 2, 4, 8, 15, 23, 25, 32,44Topics, 10, 11, 16, 18, 19Rhetoric, 23, 29, 38, 39, 40Topics, 6, 7, 8, 13Rhetoric, 2, 7, 9, 12, 19, 26, 28, 29,

30, 31, 32, 38, 44

Generally received (maqbill)

Figure (shakl)

Form (~ilrah)

Imaginative Representation(takhyil, takhayyul)Indefinite (muhmal)

Genus (jins)

Example (mithiil)

Generally accepted (mashhilr)

Knowledge (ma'rifah)

Induction (istiqrii')

Enthymeme ((!amir)Essence (mii huw, dhat)

Judgment (~ukm)

Differentia (f~l)

Divine Law (shari'ah)

Element (is!aqis)Ellipsis (i(!mar)

Dialectic (jadal)

Description (~ifah)

Demonstration (burhiin)

Definition (~add)

Page 76: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

140

Premise (muqaddamak)

Major Premise (muqaddamakkubra)

Minor Premise (muqaddamah~ughra)

Presume, see SuppositionProbable (gMlib)

Problem (ma{lilb)

Proof (datil)(I.zujjah)Doubtful Proof (mushtabah)Specious Proof (ashbah)

Property (kh~~ah)

Proposition (qar/iyah)

Quality (ayy shay' huw)

Relation (nisbah)Religious Community (millah)Report (khabar)

Exhaustive Report (mustafit/)Representation (khayalah)Rhetoric (kha!iibah)

(baliighak)Epideictic (munafariy)Deliberative (muskiiwariy)Forensic (mushiijariy)

Science ('ilm)

Scrutiny (t~affih)

Sign ('alamah)Simile (tashbih)

INDEX

Topics, 3,4, 5, 8, 9, 11, 13, 14, 18,19,21

Rhetoric, 4,6, 7, 14, 16, 17, 19, 23,24,25,30

Topics, 7,9Rhetoric, 6, 7, 16, 17

Topics, 21Rhetoric, 6, 7, 16

Topics, 4Rhetoric, 1Topics, 5, 8, 9, 19, 21Rhetoric, II, 29Rhetoric, 17, 18, 19, 20, 21, 22, 23Rhetoric, 2Rhetoric, 20Rhetoric, 20Topics, 2, 15, 16Topics, 8, 15Rhetoric, 17

Topics, 16, 17

Topics, 18, 21Rhetoric, 36, 42Rhetoric, 35, 36, 37, 39, 40Rhetoric, 39Poetics, 2Topics, 2, 9Rhetoric, 23, 33, 45Topics, 1Rhetoric, 45Rhetoric, 45Rhetoric, 45

Topics, 11, 13Rhetoric, 31, 40Topics, 10Rhetoric, 2, 30Rhetoric, 18, 21, 23Poetics, 2

INDEX

Sophistry (saJsa!ah)

Species, see Specific kindSpecific kind (naw')

Speech (qawl)

Subject (mawr/il')

Substance (jawhar)Substitution (taMi!)Supposition (~ann)

Statement which is neitherdefinition nor description (rasm)Syllogism (qiyiis)

Categorical (~amaliy)

Conditional (shar/iy)

Conjunctive (mutta~il)

Disjunctive (munf~il)

Contradictory (qiyiis al-khulf)

Term (larj, ~add)

Conditional (muqaddim)Conditioned (tiilin)Major (!arf a'{..am)

Middle (larf awsa!)

Minor Uarf a~ghar)

Selected (mustathnii)Testimony (shahiidah)

Topic (mawr/a')

141

Topics, 5Rhetoric, 23Poetics, 2

Topics, 5, 6, 15, 16Rhetoric, 5, 7, 24Poetics, 3Rhetoric, 29, 30, 33Poetics, 1, 2Topics, 8, 9, 19, 21Rhetoric, 18, 24, 26, 29Topics, 19Poetics, 2Topics, 2, 4, 5Rhetoric, 1, 4, 30, 39, 40, 43, 44

Topics, 15Topics, 3,4,5,6, 7,8,9, 14, 18,21Rhetoric, 1, 4, 5, 9, 11, 12, 15, 16,

23, 29, 31, 32, 36, 38, 39Poetics, 3Topics, 5Rhetoric, 8Topics, 5Rhetoric, 8Rhetoric, 8, (9, 10)Rhetoric, 8, 11, (12, 13)Topics, 5Rhetoric, 14

Topics, 18Rhetoric, 18Rhetoric, 8Rhetoric, 8, 10Topics, 6, 18Rhetoric, 29Topics, 6, 18Rhetoric, 29Topics, 6, 7, 18Rhetoric, 29Rhetoric, 8, 10, 11, 13Topics, 3, 13Rhewru, 2,33,35, 36,37,40,42, 44Topics, 21

Page 77: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

142

Tradition (sunTUZh)Continuous (matawiitar)Recorded (sunTUZh maktfibah)

Type (rJarb)

Universal (kull)

Widespread (dhii'i')

INDEX

Rhetoric, 44Rhetoric, 37, 39, 40Rhetoric, 41

Rhetoric, 7, 13

Topics, 6, 7, 8, 9, 10, 11, 14, 15Rhetoric, 6, 7, 17, 18, 21, 27, 29, 30

Topics, 3Rhetoric, 25

ARABIC TEXTS

Page 78: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

~ ~.J 4.l i~.J ~

~JJ~ uJJ~

Page 79: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

• JI~.r/

. ~.r.-JI ~~I if r" ~ ri..> ' ti.Jz'. y:Jt\ ~\ 41:.# - i

. ~.r.-JI ~~I if , •• /\ ri..> ' ~..>~ ~.;J\ ~\ 41:.# - I...J

• « '-:'» 41:.~ ~.r.-J\ ~;JI - t.

«~..> I.i!\ Cf' c:. ~\1~) '-?' ~~) ~~I ~:;J\ J

. <' 0"\' '.' ~.})

. .u..i> CpA;.J ~pl } 41:.~1 J - [ ]. 4:iL,.;1 CpA;.J ~~\ } 41:.~1 J~ - <>

Page 80: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries
Page 81: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

<~I>

Y-il.::ll .)~~ -~\ ~..l.,4;;)1 \;.~:l ~\ JI ~~~I J \:..li ~lJ .,

44\ w~..l.,4;;)1 J 0 J4:.U tl.t.:i ~ Y' JI ~~~\ J ~~ ~ \:..liJ

~ J..,Al1 c..'ti . ~ ..\>o~ ..\>o~ [bVY i] 'o~ Lo )~J 4~~

~~ if vi..li-'J . W.f J ~)J..rP ~ ~1:...aJ1 o.Lt. ~ -f [J 1\. ~]

. 441 Ju\i~4

<~"'J:-I J!J\i~I ~ 'i..ul J!..L.,.2;JI ;IolAo >• «~ ~)W.I -j;J1 ..Hi ,o~ Lo \)~ c..i)) : J~ .Y

0~ 0\ §..c.J Lo J~ ~i ~~I J~ 0i Y' 44 Y-j;J1iLo 0~Y' .:l~ JJf. 0i §..c. ~i ~\>. ~.lJJ . ~ ~I Lo 0~

''-:''- (f :~~I

. '-:" 4:i (t "J- <'"iJp (0 ~ '-:" JS"yi ~l~J .j"..::...1 ~) (Y

'io~ ("\ nc:u't ,~,:v, j~:V'lr~ ,,~, .,~,

....... , i i.s...l;:J) (V . J- ~t

(Y) (')....... - (' ...... ~ ... ('" ..~

. i 'jal~ (Y i . ·11 (Y" r-151

Page 82: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

152 ARABIC TEXTS ARABIC TEXTS 153

'Y \.. ~~1 • 0~ tl..lA.J . 1".)~ J.JY. 'Y 01 ~6:- -0li 01A)\ ~

• J~~ ,·J41 ·JaJl yo \..lA.J O.)~.J ~ .J-:. 01/ o.)~ A.~<,>..kL:\ YO.J 00.)~ A ':? JlI YO.J

~1:..,.zJ1 0..lA o¥ ':? JlI yo ~..l.,a:\1 :.r- )...L4l.1 \..lA 1.01 C.li .f

wl-J41 tJ.,Al1 0\S' ~1 ,4.l1";;~:4l\ -y'.Jli)lI·~:.r-.;AU; Yo!Jl.u

~~I "lu\..·...L4l.~ . 04..J\~ ~~ uw·..lA.. (f ~J:,~ (J"l:i ;.

:.r- 'Y APS--)l\ .J1 ~I ;;.)~ ~~ :.r- 4-! ~..l.,a:\1 ~ Lo.:jl V4..JIJlI

.01A)\ J -r)ll ~ \.. 0~ • Wi I' J o!Jl..iS'"' -r)l\ ~-01 ~~

'+! ~..l.,a:\\ I:J c!! u \..•..t4.. (f "~ I:J c5 Lo.:j1 ~I ~..l.,a:\\ -0!i

:.r- 'Y • ~I C..>6:- ~ if \.. J&- 11"1:.......4;1 J if \.. ~ 1Y:.r-

. l;~ (5L o!Jl~ -01 ~

~~\ u\..·...L4l.I 0..lA 10"S::; \.. I~ ,o!Jl..iS'"' ~U~ 0\S' 1~1.J .f

• ~.JJ~ 4-:i o!Jl~ ~.Y. Lo.:j!i .~~ .o.)L,., u~~ 01.J . ,.};-4 Y~~\S'

yo \.. J&- ~I C..>6:- O.)~.J J 0\S' 01 ..>~ ~.r \.. ~~ :.r- ,:?1

0..lA :.r- o~)l1 0..lA J Wi lS"" o,b:.\; tw (;1 1" \11 . ~I J ~

. t- ('\ . i C.;...·u.\ ..j , ~~) (f

. J , t ''''':' - (V . i 01.lA (t. i ]531 (A et haec est , t ' ""':"' - (0

."",:", - (\ topica, altera autem est,. i ()z-ll j) ) ('. quod non conjectetur eius

·t-(" .J contradictorium. i \.. (H (f)

. J in rebus, ""':"' 4-4jl ("" . i ()WI Jj) ('(t)

."",:",~..ill (Y• "",:",0§... ('

• ""':"' ..::,,~~lS'" (Y , t O'l":1'M~M , i o..l:A1' (f

. i ()z-ll Jj) (f .J facientium... acquirere

'i ~ (t ."",:", - (t

'i ~)l1 (0 ."",:", - (0

(J"l:AJI [.JVf i] J ~.J~ i J! o!Jl-U.J . .kAt ~~I ~~ :.r- J ' ~I. i~~ Q; "I~ 01 u\..·...L4l.I 0..lA J.- :.r- ~:,.tl ~I ~I

<J!~ &\AJI J!J\i~1 J~>

YJ~ • ~..l.,a:\\ if ~ I:..,.zJI 0.1A lo¥ \.. )..lA.. 0-d "u ~1.J .01.1A J.- ~ i J! JI 4.-~)l1 C.1) : J"A:J . 4.l &1AJ1 -y'.Jli)l1 01:..,.,1 J..:..;\S' \ll.J J~)l1 ~~ 1"0~ 01 ~.J~ i J:.i ~ ~}.4l1 -J:ZJI"l4A ~I 4.-~)I\ &1 0~ o!Jl-U.J . {( 04;~.. f~~\1.-~ Juli1

(J"l:i.J ~rJ~ ~I ~1 • (J"l:AJ1 ~I::S' J ~.,5""..u1 &)1\ 4:~1V~)\ ~\kl\ uWl .s:.. "u ~j\j • ....:s II \" . .k-JI _ ~I. . -.J. ...r'J "t'"'" ••

o!Jl~ J 1'4~4 0\S' ~~1 ~)I ~~I AuL.l:AJ1 0.1A y..: \J,lkd", .

. ~)kl\ Jl ~ ~~ u\....t4..

<~~~I>

..J--A.J ~ t,., 6:- ~..l.,a:\\ :.r- .r=J i~y ~ 1:..,.zJ\ 0..lA~ "u.J . i

-r1 J&- ~ 01 yo ~..l..<z::.ll &1AJ1 ,.~)l1 :.r- u:J1 1.1A.J . ,.~'YI

YuL;J:.\ ps--1 J Pi o!Jl~ ~) ~L. } ~y 1J5'~ J5'.:...-~ ~.J5"" 01 ~ 01 ~ij~ J\:.. . :;ts:J\ -r)l\ ~ij~ 1"~ JI~I J (J"l:i 0"; 4j"; J) YO.J • 4.4..,aJ1 0.1A J&- i\~)l1 ps--i .J4 04

.J , t ' ""':"' - (V 'i ~ ('\

. i 4...l.:Al1 (A (0)."",:", I~~ ( .. . i (J..U.I J) ('. i \j~~ ('. . ""':"' JA:.li (Y

('\) ."",:",0§... (f

. '-' - (' ."",:", ' i 4lk-iY'" (t

. i "::"~);-I (Y . ""':"' ~I.r" (0

. '-' - (f ."",:", (~ ~jJ U) U lA ('\

Page 83: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

154 ARABIC TEXTSARABIC TEXTS 155

(«~~»JI<<~.l.i'"J!L.JS'") (0

oJ '0..:-I~» JI 10J.... l.i'" J! L. JS'") ('

. i (J..lJ.1 ~ , ~~• lAAlI (V'i ~

. Jaqua (/\

. J terra (~

'i-("oiL....:.. ("

. "":" .~ (\Y

o "":" ..~) (,ro Jfecerimus per, t'~T M"~~ (' t

. i iJ§... ('0

. i (~I!:~) ("

o i ("k-JI Jj) ~~ (\V

. i iJ§... ('/\

(~)

o t. f'l'~C''t:l M~l:t''t:lM ( ,

. J , t. ' "":" - (Y

. i (;')~) (r

. "":" r.l 'i (>-II Jj) (t

. t. ' "":" - (0

. "":" - ('

0i "::"'~~I (V

• ,,":,,)1 (/\

. i iJ§... (~

o "":" t-a..l>i (,.

"y "0i r..I'J ~I v~lI \olA J1 .r.-i ki1 t:;\ o~ ,\f~

~!,J.~ ~~1I.~ A..i'J<J\ y.. ~~ i 4 <J\ ~ ~:All 04 ~'~ ~~I J ifY 0"; 4:j"; <$.1l1 \. J."Al1 ~h JL} 0 ~~ J'i-.J );.J~

••' • ..\ \" I \Y \ \. \\'" ....J.I)) 0 I~ J-J~I, 4J ~ o...\A.J '~)'J ~I.O.J ~!JA.J JU ...... r--' 0

0l:! J 4:j1~ (.)~ ~I)::....~\ \t~1 cj" ~i \'1 . «~'~ rJ:.\;0i ~1)::....~4 j+!; 1~1 .l:ji ~~.J ' t.1:.i'i\ ~.J; \00~~ r J~ o..:.".lk.­":".J~ I~ ~! 4.--~ o..:)kll ~~ 0\S'" , U"";)I wJ \'1J~\

.~* \A~ r.J ~~A::....~4

[.JYt i] "J.&- Y~I ifl:Al\~ Lo ~~ 0". \~1:...,aJ1 oolA.J 0"r.5y-i lolA y.. J ~}k.o .l:;i J.&-~ i."wl .b:-I; t~ J.J+f o..:}k.oLo.:;l ~1:...,aJ1 °oolA ..:..)..... lolA ~i if.J • ~ <I) .b;L:\ Jj .6J4~I)::....~I ~ 0 r.5~\ 'I4.--..L4lI~ J ;s-<JI J ~I)::....":J\ ~

v..:..C;.JJ:.I ;S-i q.;A::....1 ..u C:s" 01 t:;i ~~.J 0 ~ti J'i- ~i \..Lot> y.. J~~ J q.;A::....\ \ 0 Lo ..l:>-i ~~ r A.J r.5~1 4.--..L4l1 U. 4.l:;.1..\11

(V)

('(Y

(r

(t

(0

('(V

• "":" "!.,ro4i. i <.>1);-1

."":,, ~ •..*'oJet,t.""":".J

o~i..w• 0

. i ()a..J' Jj)

o i lSJLo

0"":,, <.>..*' \ i .~":/I

o t. Mn '''":'' ~~)

. i 4i1

oJ -

O":,,C;jJ;.\ yo .b....}J~ :;tsJ1 tr<J' ~~ yot ~<J\ ~)zll ~1 ' Jj<JI

o'I ifl:Al' J r<JI ~: \.. ~~ ~ r<J1 -0i \'1 ' pi yo ~<J~Y~.JJ:.I r<J\ ~::l i~i \~ .r.-i\ w1 ifl:Al1 -0i ~~.J .Y

t."i t~ [.l;YY' i] ti..l:s- 0\S'" <$.111 "~\ [.J"\ 0..:] if J#\

i."wl <$.JWI ~\ -0i J.&- ,J#I <$.JWI JI i."wl <$.J71 if\..A ~ if J v.JL. '1yo \.. ~ if 0r.5Jf 4.0-~ 4A o.b:-ti I:..J

~ ~ ~.r.-i" Lo C.i . ~)4 ."i ~4 ~~ 0\S'" ~r ~ Ayo

01-;1 -JS"' -0i ~ 0i ~ ,ti..l:s- <$.1l1 ~I if \. ~.JJ:.I r<J1

~<JI ~j.6J1 yo <$.1l1 01-;'i' -0lt 0 ifL-- 0~Z"" -y -04 ifL-­if \Y~ .r.-i Lo J \:.o.J 0 ~ \\~.J r.5~1 4.--..L4lI U. J>-b 4A01-;1 -JS"' -04 \1'~l.,.; 0L.i1 -JS"' -0i ~ 0i <$.JWI JI <$.JWI

44 .b:-f \O~L,.2JI ~.J \0~\...Q.ll H;L. Jk\:JI -0lt oJkti

J'i- ~~ 0\S'" ~1 ' 41 4.JL. 0\S'" 01.J ,do ~b.J Jk\:JI J 4~o~)4~ ~1 lolA J.- J \:l; l!.Ull.J 0 ~l.,.;

Y~ll.J 0 ~I J1 \ ~.JJ:.I if I~i ~ .r.-i wlt ' ~I)::....":J\ C~ ."

i4<JI~ 1:.:AJr' 04 ~'~ ~. -y "0i t~I)::....":J4 ~ ~ 1~1 "t:;1

o i t,)~I!\~) (/\ 0"":,, - (t

• "":" ..r....:.i (~ ~ i ..::...~I);-I (0

o "":" <.>..*' \ i <.>1);-1 (,. "PM~ \ "":" (,)"'I-;:All iJl.~1 ('· "":" "lL.o (" .t. f'l~''t:lM

. "":" - (\Y

.,,":,,!.l~ (""

· i <'>.JLo (\t

o "":" !.lL..4ll (' 0

(/\)

('(Y(r(t

Page 84: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

156 ARABIC TEXTS ARABIC TEXTS 157

J [($]~ ~~ -0i li~ ~ w~i \Y~ "\••)kll ~Y~ ~'.'.: II ""li~ L__ . i . aJ-1 ~. ""II • - .~I,• • iJ:":' u--- ~ if . ~.J . c.>~ 4.o-'A.l,

\.. ~ J ''I ,,-:,,)kl\ ~Y ,o4~1 ..L..i H8"" 01.J Y4,:..l4l1

. J~~'1 -~..~.1I .)~.J .~\'4 ~ 4-.-..L4.. ~ ,,-:,,)kll .)~ , "4';':"'1

'Y'~I 1.lA '~y.. '''r)/IJrv~ ~ J..t:l:-I ~~ ~

~ 4::.)/ Yl"X~ yy0~.J ~i ~ ~ Pi *.J~ YI~ J.X~ c::.1;j -ji)/I ~0i J~l

~ ~ t.:.~\ 01.J 4::.li .~I 'r ~I .~\'I (.~ .,.

~ 0ts"" ~1 ' ~\.lJ1 ~J.J.ril1 J.J...sh1 \'~~ 4i\~ j-J.~ Y":"L;):-'

'~.J.J4 l"":"Y):-1 ~ ~ o,J,~ \'~ ~I· ~~ 0~ 0i c::­uts"" ~..i.l.J .~4 ,)~Y y- 0~ L..:i1 0~ -~ -0i c.>G ~ y..J o~1 .~\'I t(.~ .~~ [.JAY ,,-:,,] ":"\,,-..L4.. 0.lA J~t

.. ..:,,1..i.l4.J \'~i v4i,)\j1 J1 \' ~\ J1 ,)~JiU 'I~ L..:ili ' 0~)1~..i.l.J . 4i1.1 ~(..L..4.. " I_.~ ...• \... (..t.:." L.~. \... ~ •.. . u---.. ~.J ~ u---.. ~ i.- '-'J'.J

0i J1 .~\'4 4-! ~, "~ JI ..:,,\..-..l4l1 J ,. ~k.,.a; U,·

.~ ~~ J~ J I l"..:"Y):-\ ct: \Y~J.>.)/ ~! .~\'I [J; Vf i] YJ~I J1 ,~ L..:i1.J ."

dl-'j l"~ ~>~. r-3 ..:,,\..-..l4l1 ~ ~I ~~ -0i (.1 : ~ri

y.. -0li .•~I J~ ~."...A-l\ -0i .hi -~ rl ~ y.. , ~~io4t.J.rJ.1if 0.lA.J . JI.lJI J~I ~ ~ .~\'\ J1 ~ t~~ 1.lA

"~~~ \.. )..L4.. J J.PIA;;; ..:,,\..-..l4l1 vo.lA.J ,'Ii:~.&1 ..:,,\..-..l4l4

{,)\..~ ~~.J . If! ~I ~ "~.J ' ~~i ~~ -~ 0tJ.>.I .~ \". Il"-~ 0i HI .... ~ \Y " ,o:2AJ • {,)\..

!J "". - ........ V·. ~ ~.. (,,).

Xi ~ Il"-~ 0i J1 ~.J ' 4,)"WI ..:,,\..-..l4l1 ~ ~ .kAi

•I)::..-\'1 IOJ~1 J1 ~ H~ ($.lJ1 ;>'1\ r)/I (.~ . J.>.!J ~..:,,\..-..l4l1 ~ .#' (-I~ .,j~ A d\;.}\ ~ I~ -0i ..,..; 0~)1 Jr-W w ~)!J ~I 4t.J~ -d .,j~ J ' "1+iL;.?- J.>.4 .,j~ Jr-3 ,J.>.!J ~ '~,)\..l.;)/I -0i .u '''J:i 0li ,~I ~ r.J J.>.!J

.,-:-, ~ (n JI «,-:-,#1. ~ J! to JS"') (". r ,)..P-:' (n .t. - («t."";'.".. • . r I.1AJ (V . J non oportet (\ •

~ t. - ~ r fl~1 (T\" 4I...J:-4JJ JI «~.~~ to JS"') (\ T . J oportet ~ f ,.,'C:t.,~ (/\ . '-:-' J.oa.i ("'-

(\ .) . r (~~I J ,~~ «~ . '-:-' ;r (~ ~'-:-'~ ~ r~ (\T

.,-:-, - (\ .,-:-, L:J (\\" . J ut (\. . t. ,.,at:1r"~

':' t. c'p!mM ~ r "::"~4-*1 (T . J fuerit (\t ·r~ (" . r ..::..4;1:-1 (\\"

. r "::"4';:1:-1 (\" .J - (\0 . J oportet ~ t. ,.,'CK' (\ T (\\)

. r - (1 . '-:-' - (" . J sentiamus (\ \" ~t. ,.,'C:t~ ~ '-:-' ..,-1a..ai (\

; J fit ~ t. l"'1ll':V~M (0 perficitur~,-:-,~~r~ (\V . J indigemus (\ 1 . J indigebimus

. J fit ~ t. M~:V' (' .J . J faeere ~ t. n'''ll'ol' (\ 0 . J faeere ~ t. n""~:v (T

.t."n'~pM ~ '-:-' 4;,) It ~ r <li..ult (V .,-:-, - (\/\ . t. l~n;"= ~ r ~4'?- (" .t.- (\"

':' J fit ~ t. M~:V~~ (/\ . r ()a-ll J) (\~ .t.- (W . J indiget ~ t '.,'CZ" (1

. J utile (~ ~'-:-' ~I ~ r ~I (T' .J diceremus ~ t."=at~ ~ r Ji (\ /\ . r ~.,..LI (0

.J perfeetione . '-:-' ,)I..l.;\ (\~ .,-:-, ~-*\ ('

Page 85: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

.YT~~IYY ~ e~ ~ Y\t>?~ T'~I o~ ~~

. 1~J..,a;j1 ~..l:l:-\ JU\i)l1 OJ"'''''' o-4-i .'"

159

o t. ;:ll:N ~~N (\'\

o ~ - (W

o ~ - ('"

o i 1;::..4.-11 (\ ~

°i~ (y­

o i jlaJ-l (T\

o ~ J...\J.4 (TT

o ~ ..l.~1 (Tf. J labores ~ i ~y'1l (T t

o ~ , i .;:....)IJ,.I (To

; ~ 'i ..>..c.. (T'\

• ~ ~li (TV

ARABIC TEXTS

o ~ ~I (T"

. J - (T~

o t - (f­

. i ..>~\ (f'

~ t ~n'Nnm ~ ~ •li...l...... '11 (fToJ amico

o ~ c.:r..J: (ff

~ t N~,mn ~ i "I...L-"llt (ft

oJ inimico

o t. - (fO

• ~ ..>L,.; (f'\

. 4"'.? ,.Ic-ll -0i J~ r-";S""i ~ <,-:,,>

oJ~ <./' \.. I.f...l <t>, J~I ~,; J ~~ 0i ~ if ~1:.....aJ1 ~i ,,~ <i>,.~I T'J+-; "~rA-l1 IA-0i ~I ~I;..,., IVJ \.. ~

} .~I Y\FI ~.l

~~ 0i ~ if C:l:...all J T\;.Ll~ 0~J~1 ~ <,-:,,>if TO~,,6L1 Tt,,~~1 -01 T1" .k1).,,!1 J"'; y.. ,~l:...all ~i

~I 0 T" -. 0

.l 'If'~ J..c.,. i...l..4;:.. ~ ..J':f'

. r-";S""i ~ <2if" 0\5' 01 .Gi y.. , J"'~ J~~ TA~I TVi~~ <0>1"·u("W~ -~l; ~ ..b-~ u("W~ r-W1 -0i "J.l~\

.~ ..l>~

J~I if 0\5' 01 J~ 'J"'~ 1"\J~U -"L.,Q11 ~1 <,>0i ~ 1"t,,\~)ll; 't+J1 1"1"0--~ 0i ~ 1"T,,\i...l.,.<O)l1 -0i. ,

. t+J1 ,,~

1"'JL,., W1.l ' ;S"")I\ } ~I "-! ~ \.. 1"04J), olA ~~~

ARABIC TEXTS

o~.;:...~,(y­

~ ~ t;.-..::-r ~ i .s~ (y,

. J inquirat

. J illius universalitas (T Y(\T)

oJ - ('

("")

. r \.lA ('

p~Mn'C .,n'" 'P~Mn nT' (To tC'?lll'i o~ 0"

o ~ J)\.~ (t

o ~ rL.'1\ (0

.Jregionarum \ t - ~ i ~ ('\

<y!..wdl i:J~1 ~J\i~1 -.)~>. i-JAj I.S"" ~~\ uL:..ill1 ~ ,IA-,,!y

·t~t-~~.J(""

JI • tjS"l» rf ~ L.~) (H,~ - (<<~ .JI If;l..ll»

oJ, t. i ~lJI ('0

. t C~"~:P' (V

~ t C","OMn M~mm ("commendatio studiosorum

.J. ~ ~.ll~' (~

. ~ .J:::i~\ ~ i ~~\ ('-o ~ , i I..1>!J ("

c,,:p,,"n, C"~,mN.,n C"~~Ml"\ (' Y

c.tt .n": ~I;..,.,i

, T4-t~i ~, 1.1A/ ,~\ ~ oJ~ <./' \.. ~ <, >'L# ~~ ~ ~I 0('"'")11 if.' \j"j.;;; 0i §..c. 1"'-4(.l

.~~ "~..u!Jl' ~.l ~ A~, ~ -0iA y.. ,vlA)a;.l

I· ~l:J' ~ 0~ 0i ~ if ;S"")l1 ~ 0J~ <./' \.. 1.f...J <y>"..l>1 ..:ill -0i l'~ , ~'}.>. ~,; J. ~ ~ .

~~I I.f...l <f>0i ~ if Itt;S""i ~ 11"} IT,.~~ ,.IJ..JIIT ~ <i>} , ~\.l.l a,.;l; 4;.;.J.1 [.lVO i] -0i ~ , I00."il:JI ~~

158

, .o..L-A.J

Page 86: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

160 ARABIC TEXTSARABIC TEXTS 161

~UJI ~~T -~li t, p)ll } l! ~I o,)~ 1"~1~~ l"Alg,iJ,) l"VL.

~ ~~~T -~i ~.J.r. p)l\ } ~I -~)I ~~ tluJI..,.., l..:il

.; .!.l.l.i.S'.J ' ul&.\:...,all -~ JI ~~\l1 .!.l.l.i.S'.J ' J.;(j [.JAr ~] ~i

. lA)L.

u\$'" ~1 ,uL;ls'" I~.J~ if ~~I uL.:..l4l.\ o..k.J ., t

,;;u~ ~1.J .~ ..,..,1...>),1 ~;.;.. ~.J l"~(~ Yuq):.1

C~ ~i ~ ~I if & 0~.J ~ \)'~~l4l1 o..k J ..b:-y l..:il

. A~):.4 ~~ VL. .!.l.l.1J.J . iJ~)'4 \.c.:i

~II : ~I:..,..i ~Lc" y)~ I.g.:... o.).,Al1 i-J.A.j lS"" uQSJ~ . '0':/.J & ~ ~ ~.1J1 J.,AJ~ r)~ -J.J-~ ~.rJ~ ~lJ,:~ J.a.4l~ I t..J:J~

..b-I ~p [.1; vo i] ~.J"'; 8J.J-1 u':/ ~li ~1f.i.S' :",...- I"..r .' ~ 1,;..\1 ... 0 ,)l.J· rJ

Y(,.2Al~ , u~ ~ \tl~ ':/ t..J~1 ~\$'" 0. ,§J . ~I:..,..)rl o..k

t~ ~ r ,~\:...,all o..k J~ l"~ ~ l!~ ~I

.!.l.l.i.S'.J . o..b-~ 01.+<'; u\$'" ~1 ~lJ,:1 J J>b .J+i r)l Gb . ':/~

u':/~I ~~ . i~i ~.rJ1 J J>b rJ ':/.J -~ ~ ~..ill J.JAII

• ~f.J ~\>..J J.ai.J~.J -..b- : ~I:..,..i ~ (~\ 4::JJ.J-1& • •

• '-' :C'..~

· J­.J 't' '-:'- \ i (J-oU,1 J)

. '-' u.~

(")

(\

(T

(Y'

(t

· J - (0

~,m~" \'-:' ' i ~i J~\ ('. t 1:1 '03

· J - (V

'i"" (A

· J - (~

.t- \ '-:' .s..ul (\ •·t-(\\

. '-:' ~y (\T

1:1 '03 em,," \'-:' 'i i~i("f. (\ Y'

·t

. J 't' '-:' - (H

· i ~.;.) (\ 0

. i J~\ (\,. J una (\V

. J attribuitur (\ A

(\V)

· i l.k (\. '-:' 4:tts"" (T

. J - (Y'

· i l.k (t

. '-:' J~ (0

. J , t ' '-:' - ('. J significato (V

. J perfectio enim (A

. t 1:1'" (~

.. J - \i 4lLf (\.

J.II.O ~ -J~ J) ~i Y~ 4lt'J if IA ,-J.J-I Gi ."

~4 o~ t-~ ~1i ,~I Gb . o.)~.J.J 44!Ji 1"~ ~ ~..ill ~&JI

~li 'J.a.4l1 Gb . yo L. ~;. if u:J4~ 0!.#'~ iJ~'~lJ,:~ . yo ~.; ~i ~;. if u:J4~ 0!.#' ~ v~i J~\

~ IY~.Y..J ~ ~I yo l. ~ II -J~ ,:/" I' ~..ill ~J~I Ad'

~..ill ~ji ~..b-i :~.r. ~ 11"(---;' ~li '~.rJ1 Gb . 'ilbJ O..b-~J

~.1J1 yo J~~ '-..b- ':/.J ~ \>. ':/.J J.ai ':/.J ~ ~J ~~ ~.J~\.. ~ 10} - It & • &

.:..yo r J k ilJ . .J ~.J~ ':/ ~~ ~ ..b-~ ..~ ~y. ~\ 0~

~i ~U~.J . liJ~)'1 ~ ~.rJ\ J~~ ~ l~.J~. -~)r ~.r.. J)Al\ J~~ , J)A~ ':/ L. ~.rJ\ if IA -~ ~ IVJ~)l1 r)l

...l.->~ J~ J Y~~ ~ ~ p ....)1 lolA -~i ~.J . W

VlA.ri J J~I iJ~1 yo \..k 0§J , -i\::l\ J~I to..k if l"..b-~

~I:S' J I '.JlS"" .)JJ.J-I ~ ~ JI \~)rl J~~ A-~i .!.l.l~l '4A

. '-:' ,f (Y'V

. J - (Y'A

· i .J~.. (Y'~

JI «p~l» ,f ~ \.. J5"') (t·

• '-:' - ( «JI ~I »· i ':")L,.; (t \

(H)

. i ~)J~ (\

. '-:' ':"~I.hl (T

. J latentes (Y'

. '-:' ' i (~ yJ :~) ~l4I.l (t

· i ~J (0

(V

(A

(\ 0)

(\

(T

O·(t

(0

('

.t1"'CM mlM. J in enuntiatione

. '-:' ~

• '-:' oW \ i \:..II u.~

. i 4r.,i.J -

\ t r"'tmt~ \ '-:' ' i .J~ ':/1 ('. J signis

. J­. O>'M~

Page 87: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

d \:.;:-)1 \ if ~i \Y~ ~I W..b- .j 4A ".b:.f (,?..il\ ~.lS'"., . 0tA~1

'Y'':1~ [.,Y' i] 0~ 0i ~ ~~ ~I ~.lS'"., . e)ll ~I

. J ~ yo (,?..ill .. -;J4t,., \>. 0.,~ 0i 0.,~ yo .. -i' ~ i J!..;1 if

~1:...,.:.)l1 o.lA ..b-i 4..lJ:.\ 'ul.eW..lAl\ .j u':1~1 ..:..;15"" l~l.1 . \/\

o.lA if ~~ I.e~ 4..lJ:.1 ~L4l\ ~.,~ 0P 0i ~., , ~\. r ~... . .. ..

bl <L,I ~~.1 . J~::ll if ~I YI-4! ~~ d" I.e ~ if ~\

.j U'*!\ ~.,J.:LI ~.1 'J-~ ~I t.s..i~\ J;- ~~ u.b:.f

~\ ~I o.lA if o..b-), o..b-~ °Col~ Jl~ ~ri.. ~L4l1

v~ 0P 0i J=.- ;.;sf Col.1 ' ~I if tA~ } i wJ.:L1 ~ J=.­, ~I if tA~ [.1At ~].,i ..Jojtll ~ JW), J-.:Ull ~ ~.1J.:L\ ..b-i

JI,. W W ~ ~ ~ ~ '" ~ f ~

~ ~..b- \~\ \+~ ~ 0\ yo., .sri ~ J;- A\~I u.b:. .11

.k,....,)I), ;.....)11 Col.1 ' ;.....~ .k,....,)I), ~)l1 ~)zll Col : II -:.J WI

J ' ~\ o.lA if ~ 0:!.,....il' W;i)all 0:! 0~ 0i ~ if ~~

'Y~ 01 Col U;+~.1 J;- ~i ~~., '..Jo.rJ4 <l+~ >~ 0.,~

~)all'i ~ ,o0P 0i J=.- ' o..b-), ~ H..b-!,Jl ~)all Jl 'Y'~

'Ao..b-), o..b-),'A .1i 1V..hA; WJ.:L\ ~ ~)I\' Jl .k,....1)I), 'i~)I\

. J propositionibus

'i o~. i ­

• '-:' ~I.' ,,-. i (oJ.?'"")

o i ')J..l:L1

.J,t.­. J semper

j •.,p)ll H~ w0i ~i _ YI~~ Y'~ } ,~I '\__\1I if

C.l., , HI-+-- O..b-~ o..b-),H } ~\ o-4! ~)l1 Jl .k,....1)l1 YI" .1

~)zll ~ 0~ 0i J=.- ~ ..b-!,J\ ~)all Jl Yi~ yo~ 0i

YA} J-.:Ull 4:-; ;.....)11 Jl YV.k,....1)I), wJ.:L\ ~ ;.....)1\ Jl ~)l1

;.....)1\~ 0P 0i ~i - ~~ ~ Y~.1i , ~\ if tAP.&­

.,i J-.:Ull ~ Y'Y~)I\ Jl .k,....1)I), Y',wJ.:LI 4:-; Y"~)I\ Jl

Y'AIlA L4l\ Y'vo.lA Y'i.. \....a>.\ J Y'o~ Y'tl~lt ~\ 0 Y'Y'tA~~ ~. ~. if .

• L;tA JI L4l1 t· ~I....,.;i UJ.:LI L4l\...... 0 ":"'jl5"" Y'~clLll• ~ ~ • 0 ~ • .,~

n.s~1 J;- jJ-4 ~~ t,~ ':1 4:,j)l ~~ 015"" [J;y, i] ~1.,

~~L4l1 ~.1.ri' ifH ~~}.1 tY'~~ {.cJ.1 . JI..il\ jJ-4 ':1., ~kll

;;'" ~ J,a". ~i ~\;;S'" to.j ..kA.... ~i dl:J\ if ~ W;} H~tA)1

. i:J..b- \.4.. 4.W.:L1 . tv . L;tA'l L4l1 ti...... .• 0 ~ • -; if.1 • ~ ~ o'J~

162

. J uno (~

• '-:' cJI...I.> (,.

. i "':'i~1 ("

. J ponamus ~ i ~ ('Y

amborarum ~ t. 001"l'l (' f

. J illorarum

.J - ('1

• '-:' cJ~ (' 0

. J termini (' '\

olr, • JI «JI D "'" J! \.. JS') (\V

. i (J-oU,1 J ' ~\&. «~I. J unius ~ i ...I.>~ ('A

ARABIC TEXTS

. J accepimus ~ ,-:,..l>i ("

. i ()a..ll J.}) (\Y

. i (O;~) ('f

( 'A)

('(Y(f

(t

(0

('\

(V

(A

ARABIC TEXTS

.cp 0:1 ;''':ll''l~,-:,'(~IF~I (fY

. i oJf (ff

. t"ll'N~' (ft

t. '~~;l"l ~ i ~..lS' (fO

. J processerimus

. J combinationibus (f'\

o t. - (fV

. t. nNT~ ~ i olA (fA

o t. ,::l"l"l ~ i ..;WI (f~

'i 0t....,..1 (t·

. J servant ~ '-:' ' i ~ (t,o '-:' ~I (ty

. J assimilationis ( t f

o i - (tt

. '-:' "'" ( t 0

oJ - (t'\

o '-:' .J"'J ( t V

o i ,-:,.."...ill (' ~o '-:' ~4 (y •

o t. ' '-:' - (Y\

~ t. om'l'lll' ~ '-:' ~ (n

o J proportionetur

. i JI (Yf

. J alterius illorum ( yt

. J ponamus ~ '-:' ~ (yo

o t. 'OM'I ~ '-:' ~j (Y,\

JI dL.~,.~rl D "'" J! \.. JS') (YV

o J - (<< ...\=ll 4.:-i D

. '-:' J (YA

o i (O)'~4) (Y~

'i ~i ~~I (f'

JI «..l:LI» "'" J! \.. JS') (f'

~ , ~\&. «4.:-i ~~I D

. i (J-oIJ,I

163

Page 88: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

164 ARABIC TEXTSARABIC TEXTS 165

. i ~~ (0

. i ..:..YlAJ. ('\. J exercitium ~ '-:' ~l; (V

•.1\iJ'11 »~iS" .§J.J ~~) (A

· J - 'i ('1J i)a..l' Jr-i WS::~ I-Ulb) (~

'i (<<~'). i ..:..L;..l4.. ..:..L.•...L4l.\ (\ 0

.t..rl~'l:l'?MM~ ~ '-:' ~t::.;..iAl.~ ("

. t.. rl~~':lp'l:ln ~ '-:' ~~tA::l.\ (' Y

· t.. t'1~" 't'1'1ll (\ ~

o '-:' 0!J;t:::.l1 (\ t

· J et eveniet (' 0

~ ...... ~l::ll ~ i L.4il::l1 (\'\

.J dialectica ~ t..n,''l:l,n

0\S" 0. 4:ji ~~J . \";~J~\ lA.;~i if v~l:.A U. -0lJ '~lA.r. 0§.:;~ ..l>!,J1 ~~I t' -!/z 0i ~i \:'I~\A::.. O;~I ~\..-..lAl1 if .#'4,.-..lA1.\ J1 ~i 1~1 ~~J '~J [JVV i] '·~\..-..l4l1 o~ if

'\.:r.j;l:.::l.1 J~I ,r-0i '?1'r \Y0~lA:1.\ "0\.::..-..lAl1 (.S.;,;.,.,a)1

[JI\O ,-:,,] \..t'..l>i 0~ 0i J.&- .o~lJ ~~I ~Y1 J ~~l o~ J~i

~ \.. ~ J.&- ~ ..,.;~) u. ,o~ .o~l .r~~ ~ iJ.r.

if wJ . lAyfJ "4.4i~1 ~I:...,.£ lAyf ~ {..I"t.e ~ JI ~1.:.."aJ1 J'A~ I~LJI 1__ .~ I~\...· ~1.:.."aJ1 o~ ~ I~ I~i

•. lJ ~'"J 0 •• '"J lJ ~ ~

~ \Ii ~\ Y.~J . '~~J ~ ~ \.. ~I if~ 0i

Y\~~ \~ JI ~~I ~ ~.ll ~b . ~J ~ Jh~ ~

~)I J~ U ,-:,,)kl\ 0\S" H~~ ,~IkI.\ ~ J ~~I..4l\

yt~ ~ ~ ~ 0i ~ ,Yr!.l~4 ~ 0\S" } J~~

~ nl~ L~i -. .J:I ~I . Y0..l>\ i -..l> i Yo. c::.~ {.V"" 0 if 'JJ J

-u~ ';1I ~l.,.::.)1 ~~ c::. ~b .~\ YA~J j-JLJI YVJL~

. i - (\V

. t.. '.,,:l 't'1!;,llt'lll ~ '-:'~ (\ A

J.' «~.J (( .:r- .}. L. JS') (' ~.,-:, -(<<~~~»

. J modum instituit (Y 0

'i ~ (Y\. J sicut (H

. i .11;~1~ (T~

. '-:' ~ (U

..I>~J ..I>~ ~ i 1..1>~ .J' \~, (Yo

. '":"' 'i I~ (Y '\

. '-:' J-! ~ i J~ (TV

.~J»~~)a..lIJjo.iA) (YA

. i ()a..l' ~~

(\ ~)

(\

(Y(~

(t

(0

o '-:' -

• 'lA'\°i "::' ~. i "",t1L-.tJ

. J verborum ~ i 41::inos autem ~ t.. "'l:lllt~ ~~mllt'\

. J dieimus

. t.. - ~ '-:' ' i ~~ ('\L. B iJ.Ps ~t ',§.r.•.J) ~ L. (V

M'l:l ~ '-:' ~:.l\ (<< ~ ~

quod ~ t.. 'IllEl~M .,''Ill''Ill

oJ putatur in anima

o i ()a..ll Jj «,j B .J) ~ (A

<,.\p~' >~lA.r.ll if 4..tJ:.\ J.J\i~1 o~ .0 '~;; 0. 4:jlJ ~) C.1 ..,.,

r 01 t J r~~\ o~ y.. -0i Y(.SL ,Jy4l4J J ..kAt -.)~I iJ ~

o t.. \ (~

· i - (\ 0

· i - ("o '-:' ~) (\ Y

(Yo)

o i li~.f (\. i JiS" (Y

(Y\)

o i jf (\

. t.. :l'lllM (Y

oJ - ~ i ~~'1\ (~

· i - (t

~J.;til d"J ~..L.,a;:!1 J.J\i~1 o \:..pi if fi ~ ~J ., ~

JI ~.)~, ~\..-..lAlI if c...Al;~ <,?..ul >~\ ~J. ~I J.J\i~4

~ ~ ~ . '~ ~ JI ~\ if -ri ~ J ~\~ ~.. • .. .. til _, _

yf ~ \.. ~ ifJ . Y0:;A\).1 0\:..p1 iJ ')J..I"t.e ~I ~ ~ ,-,.)l.,.::. ~

~i ~I I~ J r...~ r..,..~\; C.i .-~ ~i ~ -A ~I~

\;b .-~ ~i t.o) 0"'; if .;~ ,?.llli ~ 'y'i C.b .-J~ ~v~\ ~>Pv '-:"~ ~~J\ UJ ~ '~ r 1~1 ~1 : 0JJii

~ A ,Jr~1 f>Y':" J ~)I ~} ~)\ f>Y':" AJ J~\ -0i

~ ~ o~ L..J . ~~~I } 0~1 yf ,.~.; ~~ J ~..L.,a;:!1

1..4l1 0 ~ H,.; i ".AI ....u1..4l\ o~ J~i .('t • -J~ O;J/~ if.'J ~ I.:> v... d" .

• 0 ~):-4 ~J ~~\S" ~ ..::..;\S" ~1 4..tJ:.\

o Y0\S" 4A 'w.;.~ oW ,?..ul )..l4l1 I~; . .,. 0

Page 89: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

166 ARABIC TEXTS

~\;,.,.zJ' oolA Y" .:./1.:.. \..~.1l . ~I y~ - .~-.E. -\1 "'\.pll I~W\Y~!J • __ r..r- l.? - 'Y'J tJ

J~l J i....l:i O)~ Y'\~\..-..l4.o ;,,0 J.-! iJt ~ JW\ )~ ~ ~~

~ '1 iJt ~I )~J . ~\ ;,,0 JWI w.,; Y'Y~\ J)~ ~t

W~-Js. .Ai ;:f ~l:... ~\;,.,.zJ1 Y'Y'o"uJ . t!J \..~ .;; ~~~ JW...l~ ~)J~ iJ~ \It ~ uo"~)'1\ lolA ~ -iJt \11 . J..l:l:-\ ~\:;S'" J

Y't~)r\ ~ ~ -~ '1J iJlS' iJ1 J 4La.)\ t\;,.,.zJ1 JLf

Y'o 4i .ill ~ J..l:L-1 . .Y'o'Y'J ., t.J'

. '-:' (O)-~) crr. J manifestioris (,..t

. J , t' '-:' - ("'0

• '-:' - (Y ..

. '-:' ~~ (,.... J propositionibus (""

. i v4~1 ("'Y

Page 90: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

o~ L. )..u.. J.J 4~1 \..,,..~!1A.l1 J J.;JI ~ \:.i.} ~ ~1.J .,

~t ~t o~ L. l"~I..u.. TJ.J ~I ..~)'1 J y.a; ,~...\...dl ~

c::- ~I ~1 §-; ~~ L. -j; ~I:.AJI -lJt jAil; YO.J . t~~1. -J2l1 yo L. ~ Yli,)-~ "u.J . O~~ lA.J""";

~ t,.:;t '''~A:....~~ ~4 .)~.lZ:i • ~I:.AU 4klAJl ..~)rl G~ . 'I'

~.Jli4 ~ ~.J\>. ~ ..~t JW~ • "JlJlit l...~t : 0:..A:..,., Jl ~~t~ ~t ~Js'"".J .oO,)-.J...e:.- U ~U~ .I::-i:-/ tub~~ l"1JU:)'lS'""

: IJ~ ~.J~I ~~I o..iA "J~ ~J1 J!.Jli)r1 -lJt ~4

. t' "':" - (t

(Y)

'i~Ii;"''Y1 (\. i J!JIi)r1 (Y

~ "':" .)L.... '11) ~ i iJW'Y1) (r

. tn,~,'C~.::l

. i ':"I~I (t

. J - (0

. i (O)~) (.i

169

':>!p~ "':" oyf "':") 'Y JS'"ji ~J (\

".,:1 <j~~> jT~ l;'''~ ''1;)7'. J - ~ t ,n,'T

in librum Rhetorices ~ "':"_ (Y

.J(\)

. i ("""! yJ l:A) lJ'"'! lAl.1 ( \

. i ~j.J (Y

. i ),)\U (r

Page 91: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

<~,>

-.?111 tp4 I..:-'.....s: \!?'. [Jvt\ i] \.t't:i.J'" ~II "01 JJA:.t .tt ~\i 1.)1 -.?.lll -.? LII.J'" J!WI -.? Lll tp4J . '";s--~ } ~ YJ!WI

. ~~ 0i Ji :r ~1 ~ 0~J ~~ 'I.. -.11; ~ ~ °& ' 01.-i)f1

G1l IA.JJ"" J~:r G1 J!WI -.? 111tp4~v~ p.~ L.:;1 ~!\Al~

"Gb -.? 111ts.)4~4~ 0J~ 0u ,"IA)J"" ~• .1A Gi . 1A~}.o J;' :r. .si 1\ !>.)\,~ 'Li"i ~.)L,.., \Yl.j\..-..IA.o :, ~ ":,t; ,,\- - I J"'" 'Y ..." ~ \oIJ \01' VI> .)~ .J 1,).

"1.)1 ,~i ~.)J . I~ ~U\ o.1A J~I J"J v4.>-J JI:..

-0~ ~I» : ~ J~ ,\.. " ..~.) ..,1,:.4 .;>-T ~ r+-" ...\>-~ )u,i

~ ~» : 'Y~ J~ Ji '~4 ~ , « ~ ~\i' ~I "t".>\t. ~ 0J~~ L: .. ..; ..~ J ~.15"""J ' ''"(I I.15"""J 1.15"""

.1~J... '~ ~~\ :r J%JI [Jt\i ~] 1.1A -0i R ..Ii .)1J .\"'

J J..,AlI J1 ~.) ~ ~ -f· ':Jji W J4:.U 'J~Jli~1 :r .:.r;..i·~1

l../'J ' ~ :r~ 0~ 0i y -~i 4.5" oJ... ..:..;\5" .)1 ' ;:;.~I ~~I" l

. ~4 1.~ ;s--i

<~\Al' )~>

te.-~ 04 -.?Lll !>.)4 '"~ Y~ 0~ L..:i1 ~\All '.JJ~J .0

.J~I 0G \.. ~ 'p)lI f..~)J~ ~ -.?.lll ..~I \+-.0 0J~~J \+:iI . IJ-' i ".ll - f'" vI".LA l.T~ 4J ~ ~ll 'J • \~ ~~ 4~~ t.) ~ J ;~; 01

..L.a.>~ -0ii ,1A~i JI ~\Al\ "&i :r ti U J ~J.I

. IA)J"" ~ Y \Y~\ ~\All ~ ~J~ \:J "~ ~U.)

iJ)l1 t4)J~ ~j '" JI -0i Yi"~ L: .~ '~;l : J~ .i

0i J" J\~':JI ~ <$.lll -0b ~I °4.--.l4l1 ..t Jj~\ ~\ J4.--.l4l1 ~.b: \.)ii ~.15""" ~.) 0\5" 1.)1J . ~y .s~1 4.--.l4l1 0~

~i.l:>o -JJ .44+. "1A,1,:.~ "} i..:.io vJj~I ~;JI '~ .sA'\+:i ~ ,,~~ ..:.J~ \":;1 \+:;i \.c.i..l>. r-A; ..Ii ~~ "ip\;.i1 ;s--i

. 0.foA~1 ~.) ~ \.. ~ JP ,I"~ )~I ~ ~b .)\:s. c:!J"\t i .s:' -II ''"~~ \Y '1'1.' . ~ 'k.A.. i..,.vi ..Ii ~.15"""J '.r-' .~:r J"! y " ~ J

. ~\.... '°1..,1,:.4

170

(t)

.r (oJ"}:..) ('

.r J!L.. (Y

. '-:' ;s--~;s--i (\"'. '-:' - (t

.r c!JJ (0

. '-:' - ('

. J concludunt ~ r~::" (V

.r - (A

. J sed (~

. J suam materiam (,.

.r (O)~) ("

.r I~~ (\Y

ARABIC TEXTS

argumentatio- ~ t n'~:n:l (V

. J nes

. '-:' & (A

. ,-:,.l>~ (~

~ t.. ""n ~ '-:' 'r ~~ (\,. J nominis

.r 1J')U ("

quando sic est, ' '-:' "4;'1 ~J (\Y

. J concluditur sic

. '-:' - (H"

("')

r J-=-i (\.r (Ja-ll Jj) ->.r\ (Y

ARABIC TEXTS

. J exacta sunt (Y

• '-:' <$ .ill ('"

• '-:' OJJ~ (t

.r ..:..l:..IAl.1 (0

JJ'11 ~I ~»..:..VSJ~) ('.r (OJ~« t.:..;..

. J , t' '-:' - (V

. J aut similiter (A

. t np;n'G'~ ~ r u..l>\ (~• '-:' t...:il (, •

.r \j '1 ("

.r ~J\l.I ('Y

. '-:' ~.b: (' '". '-:' J (H

. '-:' u..l>\ (' 0

171

• '-:' 0)-""" (' (0)

. J concludunt (Y

.r (,b-JI Jj) ('"negligunt ~ t ';pm:1 ~ '-:' - (t

.J. t ,.,0\"1'" (". t' r - ('

~ t..''':1~'''G' ~ '-:' - ~ rJ~ (V

. J observunt

.r - (A

.r to ~.ilJ (~

.r tJil (, •

·r j...ai (". J rhetoricorum (' Y

'r\il ('(')

Page 92: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

172 ARABIC TEXTS ARABIC TEXTS 173

~ ~I (j~J p)1 ~ (j~ (j4 ~ (j~ 1...::;1 ~i U"'l:All

<"1> ',(' ~ " I,· , • ..~ 11 :,1 ....... "'\ • I... l..AJ I,· ,U,) u~, 4.-A:.~ I-.~ 4-:;t ~ .... 0 ,-,&J. ~ U"'.. ~

~ ~ji II!JO ~i 0-dJ . ;.;..,. (ji J1 ~\~ .::; O)J~ ViJ),

~I \.~c5- ~i 'lJ ~ ~I jA ~ JI; } tJA. ~ ~I ~~ ~ i

t:.jJ1 \.iIl>·\Y~ L.:;1 \\(j~1i' l!.uJi I!.u~ (jl5" l~lJ. ~I jA \.~

"Jji W<;J \0 J . \t .1J fJl o.ill> ~~ \1"~ (j4 \~.; U"'!:A1I ~

u ~ (jt ~ ~-,..li'J .~ "~ II ~.l> .AI ~ '" \V~ \..• 1.:..., J~ ~ J~ • -

~ y \.iIl> C. -12 ~ . li-4\.io } \II",JI; } i·...LQ.. W,. ~I ~~i

[J V\ i] Y·,:?.lll ~L~ p)ll J c..~ 'ii ~\;,i)f\ ~ \~~

<1:...."" JI::lI Yo '.- • \" <'" > Yt~\ Y1" • (ji n~~ Y'.s.:s. )Y\". ~If . i~ ~ i

./~ ..li'J • JUI J'L4.. ~ i·.illl .l,li. . ~.::i-, n} i~.ill\ ~,-J~. • 'I.:.. • \"i........ I.:.. •

(jl5" (j1)) : ~\.....tAlI ~~ JJAS" , 'ki. Jy4l\ (j~, 10k y,. J ~4. (( i~ Y\J YII~ ,(j~ YV~ ~~ ,i...t;.A .u; ,(j~~ ~)I

J U"'l;Al1 ~ t:.jJ1 10k (j~~ .J?-:r.t\ ~ .#'J U"'Y:!6:-J . \.... .... J

.;.)) : J~ 00\ ~~ J~ . (j~1 \JWI ~ ~~I ~ \.. .1~1

Yw \~ r \~ [.1; VA i] ,~~~ JUI J~lI (.1 ,v->.;A...<zJ1 (j~ ~ OJ .;04)1\ Jji u,A ~ t~\;;i'll J t 4>J1l\ 1"~.:.ill1

(ji 1~L,.; 'w~~ ~ , J~~ ~IAJI ~·.illl ~UJ)"J ' L>~1I 0J<;'v ..liJ

V~..b-i ~.ls: ~J ~iJ~ JoJ J-o~ wt;J . iA?; ~·~t41~ l~~ c~'" ~ '" ~ \. ~~ ~ I " -I ~ .• II 1• • ~\

~ \~~ . ~..... \ ,)I:.AU c:!'r ~~ ~ I" J 1J '.:r;::.........- J>.y u

if \Y~ ~i ':? 111 \\ t>,)~ J ~ •u~ \.. ~ ...?ll .,:.,~t-;J\ t?;ii.,?1!> J~J\j)l\ ~ ~i &)11 o.ill>J . ~I J .!..\!J)" (j~ (ji Wf:.S­

JI:lI ~I J ~":"r w,A ....At~ \.. ~~ J~ , \.If>.).t"" ~ \tA...:.A..

\0($ ~\;;;\O .,:.,.b:-f \~1 ' ~1:l1 ~I J JI ~I ~J~~

".)Ic,.;)f~ \~ c..~ 'ii ~.\l~ c:. ~~ w<;J • ~\ \.iIl> ~ ..::.Jl5"

.~i ~~ )!;..J\ ~r (j~ ~ J>.YJ

: \~fJ\ u~~L4l\ c..1\'" .,.. $ .. y" t~ y::: .,

J~\ 1-.1 .~~ - [JAV~] i...lA; l.</ - ~\~,A (j1i .1\

~\::S"" J 0-~ ...t~.,)I:.A.\l ~r ~i o~ ~ (j4 (~...; t(j~ 1"L..:i1i

''"':'' - (H" (V)

.t.l:I~~::t;M "r'l;~ ~ '"':" ~.J';~ (H ''"':'" i0~ (' 'i Jl; ('" . i (~l1\ ;j , 4..a..~) ('suntduae ~ i ~lf)s'~l~i ('0 . '"':" 4:t (Y 'i0~('\ . J coniunctio (Vconc1usiones universales . i .:"l,.'..l4tl (\" . J - ~ i (o.J~) (y. . '"':" ~t... (A

.J ~ t. l'"I';'r'l~ ~ i c:\;:i~1 r~ (t . J - (Y\ 'i Jl; (\

~ t.r'l'~'M:l ~ '"':" ' i .;!P~4 (" . J rem in conc1usione , ..... 4i~ (n ...... .;£;1~ ('.. J signa .,",:" - (0 . J putet (Y\" . '"':" ' i (~ ~~ t...) (.;1' ("

(") 'i 0~ (' . t. M~"'~M ,'"':"p' (H JI ((~D <f ~ L.. JS}) (\Y;j 0~ ~I 0.1.-. ~~s') (' . '"':" ~1..l>1 (V . t. «l'"I~m"m» M~m,"m (yo 'i (~l1I;j ,..,.a..~ «l,.JJI D

. (':"lk~1 . '"':" J.:;.,j ~ i J.:;...f.. (A ''"':'' J (Y"\ ~ t. ,~ ~'T)'''m~ ~ i ~ (' \".J - (Y 'i~ (\ ,,",:,,~l (YV . J subtrahemus

. i l..:...j (\" . '"':" 4:t (,. . '"':" - (Y" . '"':" ..b:1rJ1 (H.,",:" - (t . i tp~ (" • '"':" 4lt (Y\ .,",:" - ('0. i 4:t (0 01 ~ <f ~» .:,,~~) (\Y (\) 'i JJI ("

. J - (<<0~ . i J-il (' 'i (o.J~) (W

Page 93: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

:~I dl:i c.)

~i ~ ~ ~i l_;,)) 1~1 ~ ~i!i ' ~\ dl:i Coi 'J . \t

~ i.A JI 4.A-.ill1 y~J ij~1 J~~ o\~ !J~I c:!')4 c~

~lj t~..l>~ [J;y" i] -Y ~i ~ ~~}...I>-~ ~lS:.. J i....VI· ... • s:, . t; JI ~ '.:' _II • 'I........ 0 - •.

""Y' '-'.)-'. '-' • I>~ 0!...\A .J'~ J ' .~A~! ~)I ..)JJAlI \.lAJ . «( J~ ...I>-~ .:l~r ~ II~~ J.>-~ if Xi uWk.,..\

~~ ~i ~~J ' dl:All J (..lit,.,.~ ~i ~ ~I$"'" \.A J.>-i ".:..0 JaA...J iiJ:!; JJ" ;J.:~<:...II J ~~ \s;' Lr .1~)f1 ~J ~~J~I

. "4~.,a.l1 [J /\/\ ,-:,,] ~~~I if ~~

4.:i!i ' ~\.... Jl ~J ~\.... if ~ t>~ ~.lll ,-:"..r2l\ (.1 .''''<S- O~!i . ~:J4 tC~J \"~, \j~.l~ ~4 '..kAt t.:.A.. ~. ~\;;;I \.:.....I..,Q.j ~~ ~i ~l-ll 'I)~ ~ ,i.... ¥~ ~\ .,j.L,..

J )fJ ~I ~~ ~i ~ IIC"-rv. ~i I:.fA ~I ~J~ ~i J..!.. ,r:h~0~ . wUI ~ ,~)I (--4i ~ ~ w( J ,~111 ts,)4

• t.1:.i\ c:!'r ~ ,,~~ t ' ~~~ JJ ~

174 ARABIC TEXTSARABIC TEXTS 175

· i ~ (r

· i ~ (t.<-; ~I (0

. i I.i!-UI ('• <-;~! (V

· J - (A

(\ T)

. <-; 'i 1J..f-! ( \(~ y.J ~) 'l;Ilt,;Ilt'C ~::11lt (T

y.J ~) Abualmaphal I t..J (~

'i ,)\.)1 (r

. '-:' <-;.;JI (T :i (~U.IJ '~~ •.j~.. i (~U.I J ' ~~) (r

.,-:, 'i I..+-- (t

0l::..JS'" 1..iA ~.J) IJ~I r:!)1 (t. J ostendemus (t ....... - Ii ~ (0

'i 0!-i)'1 ()z...J1 Jj IJI:.,.Z...~'i ~~ (0 Accipiamus itaque Ii JS" ('

(\.). i ':?A (' . J ambas

'i ~ (\. t. l~~~ I '-:' <-;~ (V . '-:' (~ ~.J ~) ~ u. (V

It. l'CtlO'l'll) 1,-:, ~ (T. '-:' C..r-a; \ i C.r" (A . i ( «IJ"A. Jj~~~) (A

. J insinuetur. <-; J), (\ . <-; 'r. (\

. i J.a=;)'1 (r. '-:' ' i ~ (\ • . J - (\.

.t.- (t( \t) ( \r)

(\\).,-:, - (\ .J,t.''-:'- (\

....... - (\. J Notemus I...... ~ (T . J subtrahemus (T

. t.'O~M Ollt (T J' «~'. ,j" J. lA JS') (r

Page 94: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

176 ARABIC TEXTS ARABIC TEXTS 177

'Y ..l.iJ 4t,)L,.:. } 0J~ 0~ 0i J'rl~ \!~ ..l.i '-?111 ts,)~ J ..;11ts,)~ J ~~ i./' ~ if 4A .b:.j; L..: j1~~ ~i ':11 ,~J ~~ if' ~ if J.>.Y 1...:;1 4~1 ....:..\..-..illl -0i LS"" ',-?11',":"'Y.,,~ ~Ui J1~ J!LlI '-?111ts,)~ J .;' ~~~ . .b.4; ~,

"'.~i "J1J ' I'J!WI 1$111 ts,)~ J Qs' .1,:,y ,,:,,\,,-..lL. if'J.la,i ~itl ts,)~ j ·i .ui I", J~"Y} .b:." I,{,~ :!t-''''.;' .. ? ~ y':J-

; YJ~'i I~ ~. ,-?:J\ ,)~J ~ y"Y,) .b:.Y \.. ~ J~"Y..ll1 I o.1AJ ., A

J"Y,) .b:.Y \.. I~J ' .')\;L:\ ~." ~ '1~,) 0 t j L.:lI t~U'i1 '{'\j.b:.is"

-~b U';)I if -r i ~\5"" ..;.. , o.1AJ . ~r-U J~\ ,)~J ~

..l:.&- ~~." , J~)rl ~I J <":">~I ,~ ~JL. } J~\ if

~I J <":">~I , ':'>;t)all if -r i ~\5"" 01J . JJ..ll1 f"~ .\....l411

..l:.&- 0~ 01.1AJ . ~l:l\ J .:....i.l:1\ v~ -~i ~\5"" 01J . Jl:lI

,~ I'.b:.y .. ~\ J1"Y..l1l o.1AJ . "4..~1 [J A~ ~] f"~ •\....lA!I

~~ It..l.iJ - I'{'4b.~ _ J)...\ll ~ "'oJ:':'\::.. \~yi "0J <;:'; ..l.i

• ~~is" 104-.-...lA::,.

~ 01» : I:J"; y.. , (.;.a.lb i J.)11 '{'~ r ..;.. ~ C~ ..l~ . J~'0w1 -JS' ~1 'ILl-- °0~;::>- -JS'0 ~ , ti....l..>- 0W1 -JS' '{'~

. ~l:J1 ~\ J yo i J)l1 I.1A -0}i . «( 0~

~I:...,.,)r O,)~ i./'J . tAJ~ .i~ if )\c4l1 ~I:...,.,i Ii./' 0-4.; .'0" "

. J ~U.l~ ..r:~ill\

<~\Al' ..,)~>~ if I.b:.Y 0i~ '-,)!Jl1 4.~ if \.c.il:...,.,i .t-i Cob ."..:..j\5"" ~1 ,'{'~~, 4.:..ill1 i',.,G:J '4-Aii \:..\..-..ill\ ~1 ~ \..

~I \.. ~ .b:.Y 0i 0<):.t.. ...\Ai ,O~jt..4l\ Cob . t[.\::jiU ~U.I if'.~~ ~ Ji ~~ Ji '1~ ~fi' if

~\ 1.1A J '('4l-::..J.1 Y..:..\..-JA1.\ -01 IJ~ [J A• i] .,V

~.,,~ if' ~ if Y .b:.j; L..:j1 ,t~~1 i',.,~J 'j!J\i)r\ if

-~i LS"" '-?!)\ ts,)~ .".eo \.. '1....:.u.., 0y U,)-..t>- ..l.iJ . Bp;ll ,-?~II ts,)~ JLS""J .~I J ~*. if' ~ if J..~ L..:j1 i:J~1 ..:..\..-..lAli..:..\..-..illI~..lS"" , 0.,,<;:.; "':IiJ 4t,)L,.:. vlJ~ 0i 4-:& ~..l.i ":"G~\ -0i

. J Rhetorica ('\ .r iJ§... O·(\V) · i "",t..- (t

.r Jp cllJ5J (\ . J omne est animal (0

~ t.. m'D,p'PM ~ r 4:..lA!.1 (Y ·r "",t..- ('\

. J praemissa (\0)

. J facta ~ r .:,,')\...,,::..}.I ('" .,-:" - (\

..... ~I (t ( \ '\)

.r \...r.i (0 . '-:" ~y ~ r JS"y (\

. J exactis ('\ . i .:,,\..",)lA!.1 (Y. '-:" iJ§... (V .,-:,,~I ('"

et quae non ~ '-:" iJj::l~ (A .r ~l;.,~ (t

. J sint • '-:" Ijo...a!I (0

. t.. 'P'M ~ '-:" ~;lAlI (0

.r Jf~,) ('\

. J - ~ '-:" ~ (V

~ t.. n'rl'li.tn ~ '-:" ':"\..~I (A

. J Signorum

. '-:" II (~

·r ~ (\.·r§;(\\

. '-:" I~t:.. (H

. J Sicut passiones (\ '"

.r (~"j:...) (\t

. '-:" .:"ys- \..-...u::.. ~ i 4.:..llo (\°

.r .:,,\..'..llo (~

.r ()WI Jj) (\.• IJ,I J ,t,a..\&.~I 4..A..) \\~. . ".J (

.~i J1J» :!;; iJl ~J

.~i Js- J~,) J.>.y <4...J'"")~

.r ( <$~I :.P~ <J .r:-i>. t.. C".,:l'M ~ '-:" .~)rl (\ Y

. t.. «C'l'll'm'DM») C"'Il'n''DM (\ '"

(\A)

·rl..\A (\

· '-:" J~l (Y

• '-:" l;J.>.ti ('".r ~~I (t

Page 95: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

178 ARABIC TEXTS ARABIC TEXTS 179

:,,~ "u - J~~...ll~ u~",~\ - ul.:..\Al1 ~ if ..\>~ -J$"'J . \\

J., ~S::.J.~ ,;~~I ~ ~~ , 4~J.rZl1 [.t Ao i] {.)1l1 J-:"i 1"~ , Y4)J~1 {.)1l1 J :J",s:,; JI u~",~1 I C.i . l>J\~11

.P ' ;S--~I ~ ~I 0-.)1.\.\ J 0 JI C.1 . tJ.,1.t .J J~; -~... c. ," .,....

L-~. ~ ~ .,~':JI J~I Jl~ ~J ~!J~ ~ J:l? -~ -:JiJ&--"1 ~O\;\:,.. ;S'i yo \.. -J$'" -:Ji AJ~ , ~Jl-il' ~ ~U\ J VJI

.. oil" .. _, .. ..f·'1\ :J\ ~ ~ "~~ :JI 0S::~ ..L; ":": I~ -:Jl. • '·;T ~

>t IY .J. .J' . u.: J~~...lll c.~

r"~ -A ~.1l1 ",II>J ,Jj~1 ~I J I~:J~ \.. C.i .yo

~ toJy;, 1"~ YrAJI) : I:J"'; ~ , 4)J~1 {.)1l1 J J}...lll

, ;S--~I ~ ~U\ {.)Il\ J ~ :J~ \.. (..1 ((. l> - ~ .-4i , 0 Sui.J..nr •

" I· - ~ A-, O.)")~ ~J' C")l..lI ~J' VJ~)1 ~ :J~ II : 'U"'; ~

'~J «(. :JU:zW1 10~ :Ji It Cj- ;:J';l ."...; , IfJ..\? \Y~) AJ

~I W{.)111 J J\ C.1 . \'\~~I J}...u4 ~\....\ill ..I:.? .j~ :J~

i ft.il "uJY. ,~y ~ '~i f. t :J~) : IAI:J",; ~ '~Jl-ill ~"'~ - Y f- ~

~ "U ~ ~\ 1.lA :Jlt «( • t.~ :J';l ."...;, .~ ~';:> ~\.-¢'\

'~J . YY..>~AlI [~] ~ :JI.-;),I ~ ~ ~.1l1 Y\~+I ~ ~b~I 11...ll1.. 4i 0 '" Y1"..L•..L4lI :J~ \",.;."i I l...lll•• c..J':'. ~J. • (f.:'

: u\..")W1 C.1

: I I:J"'; ~ JI;l\ ~\ J 4..>J.rZl1 {.)Il\ tJ ~ :J~ \.. C.i .y\

J ~ :J~ \.. 1" C.1 (( . ~ jJ;'" .G~ t\.....lll if Y~ ~I -:Jl))

'0..>",., ~ J..wl 0 - J.) :J~)) : t I:J"'; ~ , 4;S--~\ ~I {.)\il

~~ -J\...ll~ [J A\ r] , J..wl AJl V2k~ ..>rll ~ ...u....:> ~~ .tl}1

, ~Jl-ill .? o:J.\ {.)11I I· J o~ if JI C.1 «(. 10k ~ ~oJ"',J\

: c::;-'~ ~o «c.>~ (' \) (n) oJ- , t..'~ (\Y

Luna auget suum lumen . i - (' . J ut dicendo , i - (' ·i ~~ (H"

paulatim secundum luna- . i 0;-'.riJ1 (Y .,,:",":"'~ 'i~ (Y utitur , t.. M~,~nt'1 M'll'" ('1

rem figuram ipsa itaque °i~ (r . i L..Jb (r oJ versutia

oJ (est spherica oJ Patienti sit agens (t oJ dicendo (t .,,:", - ('0

o":"' -'~ (r . ":"' ,?jJl (0 . J percussit (0 0 ...... ~\r~ (',0,,:", 0;.".... , i ~ (t ...... i , .> (' oi \J." ibyJl (' o":"' (oJ".f..) (\V

• 0 :J~ . i ~

oi (';"'l.l.I.) (0 • ":"' ':? jJ\ (V tf ~1 ol.-A ~ ..:...<-:)-,) (V oJ exemplum ( 'A

. J n:cere ('. t.. ,~ ~'ll''CM M~M (A :r:;.-4£' J}:-~o (I \J." ))JI «~-')) . J recessit, t.. ~,t'1'll'~, i i .i. <'\

·i ~~I '" « lA \;1:'" » -~t ;\;1:,..) (\ et obviam factus est ei "j"'\~~n '~~:lM "~:I' (yo(V .t.. C:lO,'C , i (J..-l.l.1 ipse inimicus: significans , t.. M~6l"lM 'Ml"llltJ'C'll'

.,,:",~ (A ....... JS" ( , 0 autem injuriam est hic et superavit suum rivalemenses et , t.. q~~'CM' t'1,~.,n (\

°i ~ (" .J (actus et adeo quo successit illi. J arma .J - (\Y .i ()a.-ll Jj «( Jl I) .}J-,) <J~ (A oJ lassitudo

.,,:",~ ( , 0 (yo) JrJ (( 1I ~)) .}J-,) O;y (\ .,,:",~I'i~1 (n

moenia , t.. ,:z.,llt n''C,n (" . i - (' oi ()a.-ll or .)~I (H

. J suae terrae ... .,rAIl» 4\ oJ." ..:...<-:)-,) (Y . i - (' 0. J primi (yr

Page 96: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

i'".; ~:,; ~ ~Q5J\ ~\S' ~1 ' 0-.)\11 0..L. J ~11 }\'..\ll (; ~~.4i

..;:.J,b.:.f \~1i ' S'}il ~I Jl CJ.J~ \Y~q):-~ , \\~q):-,

.hA,..i ~.l~ '0~q):-\ '-;JjS' ~ X\ ~jS' It§.: ~ , ''''(-I)'

o0-.)\1\ 0..L. J J' ~1..')W1 ~ '-;J~I I..L. .1.....L411

: ~~I J~I J ~11 }\'..\l\ C.1~ 01..jl -0!n : \:J.Ji Ji ,4).J~1 0-.)\11 J ~ 0\S'1.. C.i 0 n« ."'~I o~~ \;~ .~)1~ '01..jl J ~ .~)11 -0)1 ~I (~

-iJ)1 "l0}.;\i 0.~1) : t\:J.Ji J.it ,4;s')11 {.)\1\ J JI C.1

, <$.JWlI ~ ~I J 0..L. ~ JI L.1 «( • AJ"';\i Vi-f.> .1~

[J 4,. '-;J] J~I J ~\.4....1 J '~ ~\ 4./" "'.1\.4....1 J ~\j

. J~I}\c.,al\ ~l..-..ill 4:;\~ ..::..-~ 4.-.411 0..L. -0i 'rW 0i if-2.J .r,",-iJi ~~J 0 0~1~ ~-'.J.J"~I J1~ ~i - }Ie;. ~1..-...L4.. 4./" l,:

I.:.li lfl' ,:?~11 tp4 J Y41J zA.e 4./" ~ ~ ,b.:.j; wi }\c.,all ~1..-...L4..

J ~ji ~ ~ \' , '"':? ~11 tp4 J J~\'.)J ~l..')\&. 4./" ~ ~ }

o~ ~ ~l..-..ill\ ,b.:.j; JI t~~)1\ -0)1 , 4:S..l .,i 4-'J~ {.)l..

~ ~ ~l..-..illl ,b.:.t; JI te.=;i ~i _ ~~)I o~illl ~ ~I

J' 4./"J '<$.JWlI J; ~I "I G1 o4Xi 4:S..l .,i 4-,~~ 4./"

v~ ~ ~\S' ~lv ~.Jli)1, o~ -~i ~i <4 > -;1;'1

~ - ~\.Y:I ~~ ~i - ~i ~UI 0..L. -01i ' ~~f. ~~A

~ ~I 0-4! '~'-::""'I JJ te.=;~ <$.JWlI J; 4./" l.. ~~ ~ A~

W1 ''''J'~ i;4 0i \Y~ '\sri .-.s.tll ~ i.;4 0i "~

[ .1;,,\ ] '"I~j .·,)i .I l~..b-i '0 - . ..:....,;... 0 1t1.1._.~i \",.." ..) i.5 yJ ~~. if ......--

~..J.I I..L.~ llJ 0 C. Jl> .,i C. ~J J C.1 ~~.J 0 ':? ~1I tp4 J<$JWlI Y'J; {.)\11 J ~.) ~UI '\..L. ,,..~ 0i \V~~i , i";

o t.\:.i1 ~ ~ ~J <$.JWlI J; yo l.. -0i~F) Y\~~

A If .U""b:- ~y U A 'J:i I.f ,~UI 0..L..J 0 yt

t~ "'0~U' Y0\;~ ~\S' ~1 ' -U""b:- t.J.py J~\ '~l~

~-,b:- ~.~ 4./" JI ~I J; ~I J 0 l+:i .u......:-tl ~l..-..illl ,b.:.l;

,0~1 J~i ~v ~)I J JJ..$I -0i (~i"l~ W1 J ,~I

180

oJ dicere

. J philosophi

. J studiosi ~ '-:'~ Ii

o J philosophus

. J studiosus\ .'i ~

oJ sciamus

o '-:' ~.;..

. '-:' ­~ i (J-.oIJ,\ J ,t,4,.\&;)

·J,t''-:'

(0

('\

(V

(A

(..(Yr)

('(Y(r

(t

ARABIC TEXTS

..:..;IS" 4)' ,§.t.. J..'J) .hI ("0..L-- ~J~ -iJi \'1 «~lj-I »o,-:,~.hl ~ i(~J.r~1

. '-:' ~.h' ~ i ~lj-I (' Y. i - (,r

'i iJ~ (H

. '-:' ~.hl ~ i ~lj-I (' 0

(n)

. '-:' iJL.j ( ,

. J , t - (Y

o i t'WI (r

sicut, exempli gratia (t

ARABIC TEXTS

. t ,-altlnm'l (' t

. '-:' r5";'" ~ i r:::-J.i (' 0

. '-:' r5"j (\'\o J abjecerunt (' V

o t M-al,n ('A

. i IJ.. ('". '-:' J-&- (Y'

. J - (Y \

(yt)

o '-:' ~L,.. ('

0i ~t. (Yo i u:~l:..,.all (r

o '-:' ' i ~ (t

'i '+.:i (0o J judicant ('\

• '-:' (,J"'!.1A1.1 (0

o i W1J ('\. t Om'tlm l'l~ ''IM'I~ (V

. i (J-.olkl J ,t,4,.\&;) (A

. '-:' ~I ( ..

0i iJ~ (,.

o i -.>.l>I ("

. t'l'C ("1'

«J» 1:1'~I oJ..~ .:.J:jJ) (' r:r:r'J!-~ «~!)1~,)~» JISed utitur illis ex parte

qua cognoscitur unum

illorum medica judicii

inclinatione in initio

.J (opinionis

181

Page 97: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

,\~~ J J~\ -0i J:-i if V'Y , ¥I J L.1J ',?!)\ ls.)4 J L.l

~J . J~\ ~ \\~.Y. 0i ~)\ \. t.~ J } ~.rJJ ~~.Y. 0i

ls.)~ j HWl;. \1"d' ~ if ul.e-.,illl 4?UI o..iA \YJ.:,,:.l; ..kAt

.? ~~J~I \0J.:,,:.~ .Ai J '.)~J ~~ ~ j,'A 0i yf:- if ',?~1Ic..i . ~JJ.ri' ~i J&- ~\ ~.lS"J ',?~1I "ls.)4 ~ :l~ ~i

\V0J~ 0i·~ "WI 0i ~~ if ~ ,~ ~i J&- ~JJ~I J.:,,:.i

. ~I "& ~i if ,,~ -JS' 0~ \~0i ~\~ ~;b \'\.fI A- & • c. ., &., T· t c.t

\..ll.)~J ~ ~ oR ,,~\j ',:r. .JIbJ ~ 4,j\ J-:>-~ 0 ~

~I n \:l. ',?.ill J~\ 0\5"' 01J ' ~ J~\ ul.)~1 J.l; Y\~

~ "& 'Y ~b ~ ~ ,,~)/' -0i .)A Yl":~\ J.:... ~~\ d

U- , yo·t~JJ.ri' 1..iA ~.; 0~ Yl';Ji ~~ Jli if i~ ~i ~':.>- ~

: YV.}JJplji ~ Jli ~ YV.}JJplji 0.,,1~i Y'l4..,Qj1:.,. J J:i, 1'" «!JJoM I.e ,,~)) : l~0.,,1')Ui ~ JLU , Y,\« !JJoM I.e ..~ 'YJ ))

.<LII"\I·,~ .·r~..l+· ~

4....,j1 Y Jp , C:s"" ~ J1 C;.!i ~ C:s"" \ II ~) .AiJ . yo

~ )~I ulo-...L4..~ J1 "I.e...lAl1 ~I ',?.il\ f)/I 0~ 0i Y~

~ ',?LlI ls.)~ J twWI ul.e-..lWl l"~~ [JAY i] ~i -.)!Jl1

~.)&- 1';1 ',?~lIls.)~ J ~1I u\..-.,illl 0P ~.ilJ . {.)\.. {.)\..~ o:';J

01+-.. i&-\:.i1 -.c.i [J ~ , .~] ;s-")rl J&- ~I {.)\1.1 tY 0P 0i l!

.jl:."",i vrS' JJAlI 1..iA if~ ..w . ',?JWlI J&- JI 'I J ~\5"' 1';1

. {.) \1.), 'OJJ..all ~ tY )\c,.2l1

JWlI

Y~ 0i ~ : .jl:.....,i J~), . \J~\ J JJA; 0i ~J\ .Y'

J J~I 1!Jl'; .)~J ~i if ~ ~ } ~y J Jr ~J J&­~ ~} ~I J o.)~J 0\5"' t\';l ,l"~ ~} ~)I ~,; ~

'Ip 0i o~:"J « • 0~ .k1lJ..1 -0)/ 4;~ "WI)) : I:J'; ~ , 0.;&-i

J JJ~I 1!Jl'; ~ .)~J J:-i if ~ ~ } ~r J J~ .)~J~

1!Jl'; J~ , 0 f i~ } ~I ~J 0\5"' 1';1 ' ~ ~ } ~)I 1!Jl';

,\P 0i 4--J .v~ ~i if~ ~i "WI J&- 'Ip 0i

~ J \\J~I 1!Jl'; ~ ~Jl ~ ~ \. } ~~) J~ .)~J~

182

. i \.. (Y'

. J qui vero (Y\

. ~ ~ (n

.~ ~l:-ll (yr

J:i» JI «'11 DIf ~ \.. .1$') (H

. t - (<< J'i -.?.JJ~ (Yo

.~ - (n

Socrates ~ ~ ~).Y U,I)I (YV

.J. J Scitur (Y"

. i iJ."blii (Y\

. J Scitam (r·. i o~ (r\

ARABIC TEXTS

. i (~U.I ~ ,~~) (V

. i ~~ ~I:..,.. ("

• ~.l,:.Y. ( \

'i ('iu, (\.

· ~ .l,:.Y. (\\

• ~ .l,:.~ (\Y

. i ()L.J' Jj ,~~) (\r

n'~'ID~n'Cn"N'::l'C ~ ~ ~ \.;. (\ t

. J notae divulgatae ~ t· ~ .l,:.~ (\ 0

. ~ '->,)~ J (\'· ~ iJ~ (W

.~ ~i ('".~ - ('\

ARABIC TEXTS

. (S:U'. J enuntiemus , t ~,~;,~ (Y

. i .j.r\ ~ (r

. i j\ (t

.~ ~ (0

'i ~ ('. ~ 4A::.. (V

. i ~ (".~ t""';.,...u (\

. i (o.J~) (\ •

. t N;"~;' ~ ~ , it""';)' (\\

183

(YO)

.~tr~i\..0'" (\. J - (Y

. i (o.J~) (r

. i ()L.Jl Jj) ~WI (t

. ~ _ (0

. t ' ~ - ('. J quod sunt (V

(n)

J iJ!f-S" a.L..:l:-\ olA~) ('

~1 .:..U,pl If o..l>~ •JS'

Page 98: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

u.,.;}\ ~ J J~' ~ "*J ~IS'" 1~1 ' ~ ~ } \Y ~).I l!.U~

\1"J~' -~~ ~ J-lI)) : l!.U~ J~ , ~.ri ~ ~ ~IS'" .} ~.ri\t (I~«. ~

-~~ ~ ~(..lll.I» : 1:J7 \4ft" ~~ (IS" f:LI ~~ ~J .YV~ ~ 1...:;1 J,~'::/I Y-lJi .~'::/I ~J lolA ~ J.;J~ «( • ~ ~I

'::/ ,~ tyo ~ if .;.>\'~ ..b-~I ~ 1...:;1 t'-"J yo:;):-~ :.;.t~1

.0"'JS' J;o:.\,~ Jft"0 \.Jl..b-i [.1 AY -i] ~ if

• ~I:J.I J ~ G1J tlp;... \r~ ~ Gl : lJL.i:...,p ~~ . YA

~I)) : I:J} ~1:J.4 ~I J~J . i-.J.Aj L. !.I~ ..,..i J ~I YJ~

lJ~ 'lJi~ l!.UJS"" , ..b-~ 41)" -lJi t Lf"J ' ~WI J 41)'1S'" ~..ul yoJ«.~I

YJ&-:?~ ~ ~ ~ , lJ1S'" L. 0-? ' ~4 \JW,t; . Y"~!\;l.lJ\~.Y.'::/J .;.>\'I if -ri t\.Jl..b-i ~ ~!t.=.U, -~~ ,Y'Jft"~J~~ ~\ Jy411 -lJi dt:Al' ~\::S'" J i-..L4; ,Cl 0-zJ.J . ~I o.l~ if

JW,t; , Al!.U.lS'" l!.U~ lJ1S'" v'~lJ' ~~ '\ J);' ~ 0';;'" L. yo WiJ~J • ~I.lI~ & yo '::/J '~!)a...PI .;.>T J} ~J~~ ~ i;4 ~~:,sJ.I i~~ ~I;.l. ~~ ~i J,\;-ll \. J&- ..~ ~ , Oi ~~Jy41' lolA J .\;-It; , l!.U~ .fi:-J \Y'JL.a.J'::/~ \Y~~ \\~I J\tlJ~~ , ~)kl.\ ~.r ~ ~IS'" ~1 d~1 J J~~I ~)=JI ~

\0~I yo ..k....J~\ -..lJ..~ , ~)kl.1 Jr .J~ ~IS'" ~1 ~~, ~)=lI yo

Y'o~ ..\;-ll)) : I~ \:..li , \"dt:Al1 \A \:.Di ~ . \VJ:i'=lI "J

• «~~ .\;-It; 'lJ~ Y\~~

0.l;o:.~ lJi ~ ~ ~ tlJ~ Y'~I "lJl» Yl:Jj \-~ .r., t;ls"" Ao.l;o:.t .~ J d. v~J~~ .\;-ll '\l$~ wi \;,)) lJl~

~I oolA~ u IS" ~!t . « \.~~A ";-:.. -JS"" -~1)1 yoJ

184

-L>i ~ ~.J «.....1J» JI

)/1 J--olkl J~ .Ii I.iA

'i (4f.J.r~\ 0.iA ~.J~ -L>i

. t. 1'"'C''' , '-:' J.- (Y. i ()a-ll J}) (r

. '-:' Coi (t

(Y\)

. '-:' Jw'4 ( \. i - (Y

• '-:' lS;O:- ~ i lSI?,- (r

. '-:' ~..1>i (t

ARABIC TEX'rs

.t.N'lD"~M ~ '-:' ' i J~I ('". i '?.,,-II (\r

''-:'~~i~ (H(YV)

• i~;O:- (\. J quia ~ i -lJ~ (Y

• '-:' lSI):-' (r

. i - (t

~ t. "MN:l ~...... .r';II J (0

. J sit in ahero

(YA>...A.~J.\..Y~) (\

ARABIC TEXTS

" '-:' ~I ~ i. i "",\All (\\

~ t. 1:I"~rl'tD'C ~ '-:' 0& ( Y•

. J solidum

~ t. M~t"l'lD'Cn ~ '-:' ~I (Y\

. J solidum

(r')

. '-:' J'1 (\. J dicenti (Y

~ t. M~t"l'lD'CM ~ '-:' ~1 (r

. J solidum

• '-:' lJ~ (t

. J sit (0

. J concludere ~ '-:' l.$}:w ('\. '-:' o).J,r4l1i (V

....... o.1>L (A

~ t. M~n'lD'l:I ~ '-:'~ (\

,J solidum

• '-:' L>~ (\.

. '-:' ~ (0

. '-:' lS;:1:-1 ~ i lS1):-1 ( '\· i ';1..1 (V

· '-:' - (A

. i (4..,.i...~) (\

.,-:, - (\.

nT"MN ~ '-:' ~I ~ i ;._.....::11 (\ \. J solidatem ~ t. I:I"P'C

equalitatem ~ t.t"l'~C"I'lDnM (\ Y~ J

~ t. n'p:l,n ~ i ~ '11 (\r

. J contrarietatem

'-:' (KlS .;:ll. 4Ji~ Ji) <'?.J..ul (\ t

~ t. 1:I,i''C t"lT"MN ~ '-:' - (\ 0

. J soliditas

· '-:' - (\'\

equalitas et ~ t. r'~n1CMM (\ V

.J caetera

("';\All Jj«"';» ~.J) I:.::AlI (\A

185

Page 99: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

186 ARABIC TEXTSARABIC TEXTS 187

IY~ 0i <l,ji.;. \.. ,? [.J~Y ~] "":"~I ~ ~ \....cs.

0i \11 ' 10~ I!..\l~ ,yo Jw'4 \t ~.r;a;.l\. , 1"'4):-\ ..:..\..-.illl

~ 0\S"" 01.J. i:;lSJ4 IV~I t)) ,)~J)'~ I'r-.,A:JI ~ ~ .l>~

[.JAr' i] YI..:..~\ ~ Y·\:--.i I~\..J.~ II\~ ..J;~II\ I:J_ eHt:.....\.....:.-l tY' r~ '1''''~ ,~ 4..':ill1 o.i...A \:..cs. ~.J n~~

'I' \:r..4:I\ J.J~ -0i ..J~ \:.A if-' . i.,?!)1 ts,)4 J J 'J ~k.,.;4 ,.~ I!..\l~

, 'I'\s?i 0"'; ,:r J -~I ,:r Y'~l ..:..\..-.illl oolA J~i J i:;lSJ4

-~I "-?~ -0~ ~ ,)..uJ\ O,).JJ..~ t,.,~i ~ !JJ~ L..:jl-~I 0\S"" ~1

.Yt' 44 -Jil~ . \A~.J ~I Pi lolA if ~:} ~ '-:t L..:il. ..lW -~I if Y~~I YI\~..aAl1

~I .Yt'.J ' ~~\ i.,?;.:.:."1::.. ~~ YI-4! 'A ~ I Lt.J .f'~ '1t ,)~J)'\ ~ J&- '"~.4:I1 JW,\ ~ L..:il) : Jli , JWI ~4

~..all (,,)"'\:Al4 J~ '1 0\S"" ~ , -§J « • .kAt 0c:?~~ t (,,)"'I:A!I ~

. '-:' l:->\ ( yt

. J veritatis (Y 0

.r~ 4:;i ('"o '-:' ~i (YV

o '-:' J..4Al1 ~ r ~W, (Y"

. '-:' ~4 (YI\

(r\)

~ t."nm '0':1' ~ '-:' ~ ( \

. J imaginati sunt

. '-:' '-4! (Y

. t. "Z"l'l:llltM (r

. J , t. ' '-:' - (t

t. ",,:lM' Z"l'''~':1Z''lMM' (0. J advertentiae

. '-:' J'J ('\

~ t. C1"~Z"lm'l:lM ~ '-:' .;..~\ (\ \

oJ solida

.r k (\Y

oJ expertae ~ '-:'- ~ r~p::ll (\ ro t.,"lIt:1:1 ~ '-:'~~4~ (\ t

ot.-(\O. J praevii apparatus (\ '\

. J veritatis (\ V

veritatis de ~ '-:'~ ~ (\ ". J umversalitate

JI «L...t.s>>> rY J! L. JS') (\ 1\

.J - (<<r~t»

: '-:' l:-> (Y'

.t. Q"~Z"l'l'''l:lM ~ '-:' ';"~I (Y \

.r ;j~';"~ (n

or ~ (yr

, (,,)"'~ I\ij.... !J\:.A 0.J~ ')ij 4ji~ i.".wl v0~ 0i ~) , ~I

if ,.~ J 1u ~~ ~ if o~ 0i~ ~f'1 ~\::S"" ~ 0~ ~.~ t.~L... ~WI ';".J..\>. 0~.J ' 4..-..x..l.\

~UI oolA J yo I.J ,~...t.,a;ll J Jw'1 ~f \.. ~ ..w .fY. J.tJ:.1 J ;I:A!I t p.l:2.i 4A '" .r:-4l1 ·0i Lf , J~I J ,.~'11 'I'~

<I. \it ~ .jl ~1A;.i\.1>lJ'-J. ."

~~ ~1I I..:..IA:.A1\ J I Jy4l1 Jl ~ 0i lolA ~ ~ ..Ii.J .ff

"'41 -J d' ..:..1A:.A1\ oolA.J . ~~I if 'I'~ \.. )...li. J.J cY..Jli4• f. • .....1.:~ r 4:.J\)

4 i ~I if ~lt o~ t~.J Jl4l1 ¥ ~ <,>. v~ U. J~.J ~ -~ ,j->" 0L..i)'1 '~

,~...t.,a;ll ".Ji '·":"'1~'14 ~~UI I\[.G...l::...-\ ~.J <Y>~~ ~.J-} I'"..:..'1l.-.4i1 CUI ~ J ~ 0i IYy..

,.(V . '-:' lJ~ (Vo'-:'''~

oJ praevius apparatus (" .J aliquod quod doceatur (". '-:' .;,:MWI (1\ (rY)

. J affectum ( \ . or (o.)~) (\

J' «~» rY J! L. JS') (\\ . J simile et conforme (Y

. r <'.J~UI J «~Y!» . t 'Z"lOMM'I' ~ r ~I (r

(«~..l.,4j))JI<<y..».:r-J! L. JS') (\Y oJ simile et conforme (t

.;..~\ W:.~ J~ lJi y.. (rr)

~,mM ''l:l~ \ '-:' ,,~..l.,4j ~y. ()a..J1 Jj «J\ J ».1) .;..~ (\

\ t'lN'l:llltn :1"',n" Z"l""'~M . rProut possible est in veri- or~ (Y

ficatione audientis affec- ll.:lli (r. r .tus, cogens eius verifica- o'-:' ~ (t

.J tionem ......~ (0

'Jl..4i1 (\r o'-:'~ ('\. r

Page 100: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

[j; 1\'r \] 'i lolA.J .~ .Ji .j.",:- .Ji '0 4.1-) .Ji H~ ,y

. ~..l..a:ll JI ~W)'I Wu ~i .;AU; t~i

Y'p ~4 ~~.J' '''(4.ll:1 J~.J\;)r~ '\:,~LlI J:.c. \.. I.....J <or>n·;....J ""4.4HAlI .;hAJ1 jAi"".J "'~l:fj)rl ~ W1 rA.} -~i rA• y \..r".J:.:J~~ LS"" Yi , yo ('ili. ~ I$"")/.J ,.l..!t i$ i.r. y\.r":;~ rly.. "~\i ,Yllo~.J J.JAlI ":.i -.,>lll ..,-)rl yv~ I~.J < t >, ..~.aJ~.J . ~1 1"'J:..i ~\ ..:..;1$"" ,1'"~ ~ , J.JAlI

1°, .wI l.l...,.A, I. ;"1 ~ 1"t W .4' ,1"1" ~ ~. 1"Y •• (J'":'- •• I......~.......r-' J'....r---> '$'"

• 1"0 t.1?-)l1 ~....,"'o <" >. 1"iwb,+~1 ~.J <, >

• 1"1I~;JI 1"V--.J;.;JI I' <V>. • ~ . • ",",".J. t'~~ll" 1"\/~\ \+-~ <1\ >

. t'~~)rl I+--i' <~ >ttJ~ t1"~1 w· -II J.:tl LAS ty~ c· ~i \.... <,. >. ~:r-!J 'r' • . ~ "t"":'

..,-i tY' ~ ti~ J.- '~~1 i.J.J. -.,>lll ..,-)r\ .:l~.J top

A~ t .....I. tll,,~ tv· i ,: . '•.~. "'.J4' ~.J .'T~.J ~ .....J .........;r-

t.. • \.'. .~ .1\.A....1 o'J' \;)rl ~ LO' I' <" >~.J "t"""' ..I'::"" .J •.J •.T ",",".J

J>.:li ~I J oolA.J ,~...lj1A.. Jt-i.J ~ o'..I~ \.. ~.J~

. ~~I J I+--. ~)\>. ,y ";11 w~1 [.J ~f ,-;,,] ~ 0.1...

~l:.i1 Y..L.Ai 1...:;1 ~i I+-- .#' J ..,-)rl 'J~i ,y ~ y..J .ft

.0olA J J.JA; ~.J . ~\b. ~ ~~ .?: ..u '+~ J.J ' 1".kAt

<o,)\fJJI>,\.. .J'!- ;./' .tkl:-~ ;;.:l~1" . ;;.:l~1 Yy. 4..,- u.~i ',y.J .f"

,y p)rl" , ~I" ,y pi .Ji 1" (~I" ~ ~.J~I ~~ ~i (.1 ' .;fl"

188

, J purificatio (Y I+.

. '-:" ':'>4 (Y~

, t.") (",.

, J declivis (""

. i ()a..J1 Jj) ("'Y

. t. - ~ i~ ("''''. '-:" ..:..A ("'t

,~~~, ~ '-:" - ~ i t.1,.;.:-)l1 ("'0

et de illis sunt ~ t. T1::1pM. J conciones...... ..:..1..lA~\ (""

, J supplicatio ~ t. ::1~"M ("'V

. J , t. ' '-:" - ("'I+.

t""::1'~::1 "M""n ~ '-:" l$~I ("'~

. J fideiussio ~ t.

':'>~':'>I~•.J) n'llt,r'll"I "::10' (t·

I~;!I. 4....\SJI 4I:) vl:..!' o..lA

.J pignoratio ~ t.(~JI

ARABIC TEXTS

'n',~ ~'-:" ~ ~ i.u~ (,t. J dolore ~ t.

· t. '::1'''?~ ~ '-:"~) ('°• '-:" o..lA ("

· J declinare faciat (' V

. '-:" ~L.l1 ('I+.

u...I:Cl' ULCL (' °''-:'' .. . i· . -..,-:" J~ (y.

C1"::1,mMl"I ~ '-:" $}il ~ i~.))/I (Y'. J proclari intellecto , t.

~ '-:" L2!Al\ J:Ul1 J--i (n

~ t. M::1,m~l"I M,,":r"M "m~llt

.J viri nobilis educationis

. '-:' 1$ (Y'"· J utitur ~ t. ,":a,l"I (H

. J perversus ~ t. .,':lM (Y°. J , t.' '-:" - (n

. t. "")l"I (YV

ARABIC TEXTS

~ t. ,llt.,., llt, ~ '-:" ~ (0'

; J detegat

("'t)

. i J'!.JI ('

.,-:" ~ (Y

.,-:,,~ ('"

("'0)

JI «.J".J» .J" 4W:-' o..L...) ('

(..:..lc-:;1IJ~~lo,)~I.

C1M~ M:I"'~ pTM .,n,"l"I~'

vehemen- ~ t. n",l"I ,,,~,

tiore gradu istorum, qui

. J est ipsa attestatio

• '-:".$"'" (Y

. i..1>lJ ('"

Et de illis est ~ t.' '-:" - (t,solitude in eremo et tolle­rantio laborum et vita

. J monastica

• '-:" .:.>§... (H

(I ~I. I.,:;t ~.J) 4..io.:ll (t'".,-:"

.,-:" Y: (H

. '-:" J:'; (to

. '-:" ':'>1 (t,. J pallescit et erubeseit (tV

. '-:" ' i ~ (tl+.

'i u1&. (t~

depravatio sermonum et (0'

. J ipsorum declinatio

189

Page 101: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

190 ARABIC TEXTSARABIC TEXTS 191

(rA)

('(Y(r

,~~ ~~. 'Y 4s:.k \,)~ -U.J t".J"'2>~. °4s:.k t0~ -U ~!J

~~I ,.~)rl if 0.J~!J ,41~ (.1.J ~~ (.1 ~ ~I ,.~)r!J

:.r...?- Ij~ 0i \ (.1.J [.JAt i] A lA;'-:"'i ~~..ul t" !,~ 0i v(.1(.1 ~ p.~\ ~~\ ,.~)r!J ' Xi .J\ -Jii } ('"~ <:.r..> J;I if

0\..)1 J 0~ 0i (.1.J ~ ~ -~ r-3 \\~\.. 1~J'"i 1'0~ 0i10~ ItU~ I\"0 ~ \Y ,("t .....;\.,l\

, ,~~ J-

, oJJ~ 'Y.J ~:i J~~ ',.~ ~ ,lAl:....-i JI ,.~)rl (.b ,y""\

r+;t;, ~~..ul ~UI \"~i ~ u'Y.#\ J r)r\ ·Y0.J~ 0i y ~ ~jS"'.J

0i ~ ..w J~I ~ (.b ,u'Y.JA.J.\ ~ ~l:...., J .k:;~ 0i

~s::.t4 ~~ .)\ ~\kll t~.(W1 o..u..J . T..l:.i1 ~:i o,)\~1 JttA;~.; J:f-.J t>J~1 ,);'.J.J r-3 W1 0.J~ ~fU 0 J !J~ r-3 8. ~i rf

Gb 0 ~L4l.1 ~.; ~fU J ~\ J ..lW 'tJ\;j1 O,)~' ~J It' \ I .. 0 A·- .11 .';~. ·ll V~~~lt 1I

.~,) ~.J*' ~.,--~ '-'.J~ '-? ....... u:z

. i Ii- ('0 . i iJ~ (t

(r,) oJ universitas (0

oJ immorandum ~ t. i'~Il'l:l~ (' . '-:"' iJj§.... ('oi - (Y J' G 1,.1 B~ J! I,. JS" 4o-;.}J) (V

. i Jil (r (~ Ji- G~.;>T :r». J invenimus , i ~ (t aut narrant illas quas

°i~ (0 viderint, aut narrantquae

radieibus ~ t. M"t1M m,;p (' oJ audiverint ab aliis

legis super attestione legis . ,-:", t.~\ (/\

oJ . i (O)~) (-.

. '-:"' ~UzlI (V . '-:"' iJ§.... (' .secta autem, ~ t.M~'1I)n;~ (/\ .,-:", ~. ("oJ quae Deum cognoscit 0,-:", J'1 ('Y

oi ~";)' (-. . '-:"' iJ§.... ("". J lateant ~ '-:"' ' i ~~ (H

'~~;IlM1I) l"I'l:l l"I);IlM M~Mn

quando excedit una ~ t.universitas aliam, et magis

sunt adepti excellentium

oJ illius, quod attingerunt

o t. '~"~OM , i ),.;:...-' (H

aut difficile Foret ~ i - (' 0

. J illos confundere

rora ~ t.M"t1M ~ '-:"' ~1fl.1 (". J in scriptura sacra

°i JAoJ aliquo modo

,~;;p ~~~~M M1I)'C ~ '-:"' ~

Moses principis ~ t.0,;11)1"1

prophetarum, supraipsum

. J sit pax

oJ SinaH e~"o ~ '-:"" i- (t

oJ Horeb ~ t. ~"M (0

(rv)

in nar- ~ t.,,1l0M' t1,,;pm ( ,

ratione autem et attes-

oJ tione

. J - (Y

, t.M~'~ ~ '-:"' ..u.~ 'i ..u.~ (r

. J videmus

oJquod fortificetur ~ '-:"'i~ (t

o t. ~rJ~ , '-:"' ...l:$' ( 0

o i iJA (1

oJ fidei sunt quae (V

o t. - (/\o '-:"' r3 (-.

o -:' l.:j! (, •~~ ~ i t.r> .:f.;.. '1 ~~ (";tM ~~ ,;p ~, ;Mp ~ '-:"' t.~innumerabilis , t. ,,1l0;

oJ universitas

o '-:"' !,>I ('"M~M ;";~M C10'~1l) M~;~ (' r

Page 102: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

'y'.,l.,Q.::l1 -0i ~ Y'J . ~.J,J~ <\;"J \':'..I..u~ ~ J,)\.,.all -0!! ~ ~~ ~

'~..uJ . ·UJ-I \.r \':'..I.iJ~ v'1ji~ 1"::1 '4....~\ )y~I' ,)~J~

..:..\.....~I ,)~.,<~ 'y'..l.,Q.;:!1) ~J • L. LJ-~ ,...loU L. Gb- ~..loU ~

"uJ . ~ -I' L. .? ~i "WJ J! ·..,J-I :r ..h.4t ":"I.1J~ ~

'\~JJ~ J~\Y ~ U"'~I :r ul..u~ ..:..\....~I ~~ ~i ~I J.a-s:JWI ~J""" ~ ~ '1 ~I \'1 ' ,,. 0~ <\li , .~ ~b- IJA -0i

'" -. ":"\ll~ •d"\J:1

\:J 0\S'" [J ~ t ,-;,,] '1J '1; •~ ~ ~I 4....~1 .JY~I G~ .'"'~YP \A,)~~ ~I ~ ..li '~1i 'U"'~ \A,)~J ~~,)1 J1 J~

..Y~I t J&- ~ ,.../' L. J&- \A.J~~ \:J J~ ..li ~i Lf·Ji~\ Js­\A:,~i ~ '-'; 0i·~ ~ ~~i •..,J-~ 0-'; ~ 01J oJA J~i .~j

~ "Y' U"'\:.ll ~ ;s-~\ ...\:.&. 'y'..l.,Q.;:!1 IJA eY-liJ . v~~ •J~ L. }

..;,Jl. U. I•• I!.JJ~ -0i ··...11·....~ "~I ,. l>~tl \ -I-IIv:;. iJ" If.. v u· . .J. )!J J':J"

Ji~1 J&- ,,.)~~, n JAJ <\J ~ ~i .;J::! L. @ ~i J..l.,a.ll ·0~

."w -II 1.,L..,.i" ..:..G...J.I '0 -. L. ;"":" \t, I"• 'f" ...... . . ~ ,.... ..s-

"~ ~~J ..,.;~~ l$lll '0:..AJ1 lJA J~ J ~I G~ .t­

t·..,J-1 ,-;,,\::5" J J:i ..loU 'r-W1 IJA ,.J ~ ~.})I i;4 L: ~~ i,)~ v.J~~1 J!Jk~ 0i!y~ 'i.} '1-4! ~ oo.J. U"'r~~, W; J J:a.~. 4:;1) : !,J\i ,tJ~ t "Wi . ":"lllI~ ~I ~

L. ,)~ ,. 4A 0\S'" } ~1i ' ~ 4kJ~ oJAJ ((. li...\:.&. ~~ ~ 01J

\to .\.1\ ~U.~I ,,. L..:.\A:j --l n. c.iJi ~ LAo<::. "..:..Illl. [ 1\0 ]!lr _ ~ I' I.!~ - ~. • J i, ~ W....A.i.Y.J .~ 0i .:f-l ,)..wl IJA "015JJ '.:r.~1 ,o,)..l~ J.1~ 0i~ '''i~ W ~llJ . J!)I ~ 4~) U4J], o~1 J!

192

. '-:' J'1 ~ i - (y

~ ":"~ ~ i (I} ~i~•.Ji) lJ" (rfabrieatum ~ t ;,~~~ tot'1;''tl)

. J. '-:' - (t

)z-ll J; ~I ~~) .r. (0

.JpenetreH-,-:,~~r(~~

. J penetrat ~ ":" .r.. ~ r~ ('\. '-:' ~ (V

. i (~~) (/\~ t t'1'1''1t'1;, ~ '-:' .J\;ll (~

. J legibus

~ t O"''1rlC;' ~ r .f'?- '11 <". J historiis

·J,t''-:'-(\\

ARABIC TEXTS

rem sen- ~ t 'tl)M'1'C;' j"~';' ('\

. J satam

.t ;''C t'1,":l" ;':'Mt'1 ~ '-:' '1J (V

«~llfD<Y J! \..J5'~) (/\~J «.;..1.1J4 J...d: • JI~ «.;..1'; ... .;..L.J-'""<">D

~I 0..LA ~J\jJ ~l!1

.r (~J;:

.t '1~'l:l'C "i'El~'tl) (~

.t '1~'l:l'C "i't~ tl~;, (,.

per imagina- ~ '-:' ~ ("

. J tionem

.r ~ (H

. i J4 (,r(r~)

. J , t - ('

ARABIC TEXTS

. J - ~ r (O)"'.f,..) J4 (\\. J veritas essentialiter (' Y

~ t t'1"'C ;''';''' \ '-:' j".;~ (' r. J se exeederunt

~ t O""''1t'1M ~ '-:' e}L.:I.1 (' t

. J res divulgate

• '-:' ..\:so ('0

{( ~lSJJ D,f a...l:-I 0..lA ~..J) (' '\: c:f" .r.i:. ~. «J~I D JIEt possibile esset quod hie

numerus esset proportio­

natus et eonstaret multi­

tudo veri et paucitas sunt

<:ompositae ex eombina-

. J (tionibus

·t-(W~ t '1'''t'1'tl);,m ~ r f"') (' /\

. J innituntur

193

.r (eJ"'.f,..) (' Y. J historia ~ t l"I'i:lMM (' r

. t." tot, ~ '-:'~ '1 (H. '-:' tt- <' 0

suam ~ t. t'1"'p'l:lM Ot'1:lC (' '\

. J eausam aeeidentalem

(t·)

.r (~~) <'.t. ;,~;, ~"~":l ( Y

.t j'C ~ '-:' ,f (r

. '-:' ·~I! (t

. t ''1~'~'1 (0

. '-:' ,.;~ ('\

. J historia ~ t ;,.,:lM (V

. t ..,'tl)tot~'1 ~ ":" o.J (/\.r ~§... (~

~ t '1:'tot~m M'D ~ '-:' ~ l.. (,.

.J si esset aliquis numerus

Page 103: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

<~~I ~...J'>

'C:.p~ ~~ J "l~i f)/lj ~.PJ.\ \V:....J~ .)\~'1\ G1.t\~.,,; 0.)~'1~ t\~ ~-rJ1 ~i ,f ~ O!.~I ,f ~ l.t l".:,sJ"0...l4::N ili~1 \- . II .~ ~i;.u A.~ (.e""" Vl.S' ~..il . '1(..t>

!J •• ' J'::"""Y ./JJ::'-' '.J" 'J ,

• ~ \Yr-+~ J~ \Y ':1 .:"ljI?

: ~li , Yl"~ yy~ "'~ y,~\ ~ ~ lkJ ";' \~;I,,::l\ JYA~ ,.!.U~ ~lS'" YVI~lJ « • Y\:.r.:.4:1\ .w-.~ ~i yo4 J";' :f yt J »

ol-AJ . ":"1.lJ~ ~I ~ J~ ~ '1J Y~ .k~ S\~i .1..;. \+~

1"\ 1.'<". .,6:."./\ l. ;'> . ..:..\.)I.••• tI 1"- L>)/Il_.~ ...~ L..:;\ ~UI"t""" J. ,. ,,j.4 ,+"",!J J . ~ "

'1 l.-. ~.;J -Ji)/\ J&- 1"1".,6:.~ I"Y k;lt . -jail YOJ ' 4;s--i I"Y

,~i ~l:..,.., I"t~j

<t.~)'I>

fi J&- t~jk~.J UI.\ ~i I"J\.£j1 yo ',?..ill Yt.k-)'I \G1 .n~ 0 W.J . ~~ r.! t..rJ' o.)~; t.1:J)'1 J ~i o.x.W Ul.1 J\'..l&t>. .Y.1\' «. ~)~ \.r~ V t.k-)' I '1J)\>. -~b : I"jli ,\~ i"';

\1"~ \Y~.;::J4..;..m1 "~l::S"' Jji J t.k-)'I J ~I \~ C~ ..u.A l. Ie. \A-'..w ' -' .-J w.Gl» : "Jlj . \O~..,\j,11 \t ')l...'1\

J ~ • ~ I ~!J i«( • t.k-)'I

194-

(1 ')

. J Statuorum , ~ - ('

, J , t.. - (Y,~J~ (f

quo evenit de illis verifi- (1

catio, est ipsorum consue-

,J tus usus

: (I J)) )a-l\ J}J) ~~~I (0

, i (~~~I c.i"'-,~I...\...o ('\

,~~ 'i ~ (V, t.. '1'C , i II (/\

.~ ~ (\

:lM~'C ,~ .Jl:-!I 'r .Jl:-!I (,.. J consuetudine , t..

,~0J..lA:.U ("

"'1j1'1 ,~ ~~ iJi .J..lA; ('", t.. l:l""~'~ C'l''Il)~

ARABIC TEXTS

. J legibus , t.. rl.,.,.,rl (' \veritas quae non sint (Y­

. J necessariae

. J - ('".J-'~~'i~ (H

, J , i - (Yf

. i - (Y1

,~ r¥J"; 'i (t,.2..l?) (yo

. t.. l:lj1'1~~rl. J veritas essentialiter (Y '\

JI « I~!,,)) ,y '+IS"' ~I o.k) (YV

. J - «I ul.lJ4 ))

. i ()a-ll Jj) (Y/\

• ~ j,~ (Y\

, J historia , t.. M')MM (f'

. i ()a-ll Jj) I+,:i ~Y. (f'

. t.. - (fY

. i ()a-ll J}) ~Y. (f.f

.~~ (f1

ARABIC TEXTS

Abulhamadh 't.. ''OM. J autem Algazel

, t...,~o (", ~ ~)::ll.) (' Y

'i0!('f, t.. l:l'l~olt''O'Il)'1M 'i i ')\...1 (H

. J Mauros

, t.. l"li":"~~" , ~ ~~)1 (' 0

. J AmazonidesJI « Jli ) ,y~~I o.k) (\'\

o.k .AA:J J-oill .) (I t..to-:~I ))

:~!~~~J~I.)~I

~I ..u~I '0i .!.U~J ))

~' ~ c..~ .;JI j,J.rJ1 .)

«t..~'i l )) t...)J) , i (I( t..\:i'i l~J Mtl::lCi'1j1~ 4.0-:;..} 1"~PM ~ 0;:; 0i

•(~ LS"" ~l"li'j1

. i 4=;i (\V

. t..- ('/\

195

(H)

at..~)),y~ ;'1...J:.1 o.k .::J:) ('

:~;f~a~4))JI

Convenimus etilm per-

suasioni attestionis legis,

decori, et conventioni

virorum legalium de ali-

. J (qua re ipsius legis

,t..1"~~M (Y

• ~ JlA;\ , i..;..z;1 (f

, '-' ~ -..sklf ' i ~If (1. t.. ":'1l:~''Il)

. t.. ..'Il) .,.,~,~., (0

. t.. '~"::l'll)'C1tJ , ~ 0» ('I

. t.. ~MPl"l (V

at.. to-:~I))JI (I~)),y J! L. JS") (/\«t..~'i l )) t...)J) 'i (J--Ill').) LS"" 1"~i'M ~ ;.;..,;..

. t.. (Y r-i.J ~lJ.1

. t.. ."El::l" , ~)~ (\.,~~ , ~ »-Y.' ~ i »- 0!1 (, •

Page 104: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

196 ARABIC TEXTS ARABIC TEXTS 197

<'i..bdl)

l",:?~\ <Ut:.ii ·iJi '11 . Y~~4 iJ~ ..w ,\~·.~11 (.1.t\"

~ ~i v($) J' .).".-)/1 t.S".J ' 'I~~ °J):L:I t~~ iJ~ ~..lll

, "~!iJ1 ~~ I:.j ~J-All ~IS' iJ1.J , ~i ~I tf II~ . ?I ~cl...,.;j .... lli\ IY~I.AJ •• 1:.1\. .Co ~ ..l..4J ':J [J; 1\0 ] ~li, • ~. ~ • l.f"' ,j->.J~ • • • i ..

~\I'I 10~1::S"" J. 1t..Lol> 'y'i c~ .At.J. 'l"~':J1 .r)/I iJlS' 1~1

Js- 1,\~\ ~~ IVJ--')~ iJW.)f\» : Jli) 1'1 \-4~ lJ"1.k-.4J4• •• 1_ y.. ·,C.l I~ IY:!- yo v"'~\ ~> iJ1.J '~.)K. ~.r yo iJ~\ 4.C".)"

«• llA [.J "0 <...;J]

y~ ·A JI Yt.S" ~.)\:L:' .).".-)/1 tf \ IA\;.)·~ JI o~ .tt .

L.:i1.J . 0 ~1:.i1 -~-~ ,~~ ;t... (.10• t~ ~ l"J..a.s: ~i

\.. •.:'A~l .j~ .At ~;)/ t:...\Aj ·~1 olA tf ~..;.i 'I;~11 ~IS'

<~\f:i~l)

o($i., t.J l"~~I .j y~.r .0 ~j 1 (,:1 ,~) (.1 .to

.j ~ lllA~1 .)~I J~I vJ '" W1 .':..Il~~1 olA 'I ~~ ·iJi

Abuhamadh ~ t ''l:lM 'I~~ (H (U') . J - (a ~.)b:. » . J ignotis esse (V. J Aigazel ·J contentiones ~ t ''IM~~M (\ 'i J."..i (yr ignotum ~ i e':Jl 4 .;f (/\

• t .,ElC (\0 ·Jin differentiisverborum (y .~ 'i~ (Yt . Jesse. J inscripta circa haec (" ·J contentiones ~ t ''IM~~n (r . J , t'~ - (yo •~ iJ~ ~ i iJ~ (\

. J simpliciter (\ Vde ~ t MT ;~~ ~ ~ p~' (t usi sunt ~ t l:In~ 'I'Il)'l:lt'1'1l)~m ( Y'\ . J prestantia ~ t t'1'1~~mM (\.

~t M~;ElM ~~ ~I (\/\. J lasso .J . J loquentis (\ \

. J lassi. J scindente ~ t ""'I'~ . Jvia ~ t'''' ~ ~~> (YV • t 'I'Il)'Dt'1m~ (\ Y(0

. i 0J~.) (\ \

promisiones ~ t t'1'1~'I'Il)C'1n ('\ . J veritatis ~ t t'1~NM (y/\ .tMT'I (\r~ t l:I~"~''DM ~ i ~, (y.

. J legis (to) . i l?.illi (H. J loquentes

.~ ~ (V .Jexquo~ t ..m "'I~~ M~M (\ . t ~'Il)n'll) (\0(U)

. ~ §"':J• t l:IM3,,'l:l ~ i 4-:~ (Y .t n~;~ (\'\

. i !+i,)·-.U> (\ (/\. J veritate (r • t 'Im'l:lC'1'1l)~ (\V

• ~ I.S'" (Y . J agens (\. J- (t . t M~;~ (\/\

'i~ (r 'i - (\..~~ (0 • ~ ";"b~ (\\

-; J veritas ~ t r'I'l:l~ (t ~t t'1'1~~t'1'l:lM ~ ~ ~~I (\\ oppor- ~ t 'OU'll) ~ i ..~ ('\ . J judiciis ~ t 1:I~~~' (y.Rhetorica autem residui (0 . J maxime enormis . J tunitas accidiH t t'1'1~~TM l:IM~ M"P~ (Y\

. J huius est nota • t '1t'1;"'El~ (\ Y ·t- (V . J disputatio de illis~ J signa ~ t l:I~:l'l:lCM ('\ .~ ~':JI (\r • t 1:I~"~'~ 1:IC'1'1~ (/\ JI «..~» ,j" ~ L-o JS') (n

Page 105: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

.1i lYu!r.> ~i " @I '-, _<:.L \. "1 i:,.)\ ~I "8·1-\ ~I..,;,~\i 'to. r-;. 1$ • ')& .'f:" •

u!r.> ~i \I"i@\ ~ ~ JI ~.)~~\ ..~~\ .::..;\S'" 0..1 ' J.Jf­

~.1 ~\.J..\ 0Lojl \t J.1 <\j\~ J 0W~ ~.Y. Lo 4:--0 <, > J.1f- }

J ~\.J..\ 0Lojl J ~.Y. Lo 4:--0.1 <y >- , \0 J~I~)~ JL.a.AlI ..I"

JA=-ll J ~ \A~'y' Lo ~ <"'> - , IVJ..w~ "Jyl;\ yo ~~.1 0;',;;.Y\'~~\ Y\~ Y'J.1~\ c..i - o).,Q.l~ Wl:.!1 JY~\ ..I" cit; \".1

~\;ll c..b ' Y'lo.r.-W\~ YO~;l~ll [.1 '" i] nc..b·, Y\"~)\:J.IY" G...I.o.1 !.IJ~YA oA Lo -~ ,- . YA 0W~ I 0\S'" _ wi:, WI • •.

_ .T I.T.r 0'" & .1 .J.1 ~..... 1:.>-~\ o..l-A .; G<t>kJ:\ 1"\ I. \i~l 1'" L_~.... Lo\"" .:.\11.1 • ,-:?. (J..1 c.r--- ~.1..;--I!

~ l+~ JI ~~~I \"0.1 I"t0;j~1 \"\"~~l J ~) I"Y U ' ~".>\=ll

~~ J J.;.. Lo -ri ~I"V oolA y ..~ ..~ J 1"'\8 01 0\-;)'1

I"\)W)'1 \"AJ~ ~ ~\ ,~U\ \"voolA -..l>- '.. ~.llJ ...~I

\.. -fi ~ t\~):-I JY~\ ~ ..~ ..~ J t· t.\:.i)'l JtA! 0i ~

o n~\:..p ~ ..~I ~~ J ,§.t.o Y~\S'" \ lolA J \ W';' ~ 01:.1i ,:?jJ~ .f,

'"

198

.J. i c..~ ~}\:... c..~ (H

. '-:" ~~\ (yo

. J judicialis ~ t. t'I"I""eM (n

. t. t'I"I~:VM ~ '-:" ~.>rJ.1 (YV

. J quomodo (YA

. t. "''l:IMM (Y\

. J Quod autem fiant (Y'"

. '-:" ~li\'1 (Y"\

. J exposuit ~ t. ,llt:1 (Y"Y

. J tradendo (Y"Y"

. t. C""OM (Y"t

. '-:" J (Y"o

.0t. C'lltM 'Y"''''' , i r:? (Y'"

. i - (Y"V

. '-:" .>~ (Y"A

. t. t'I"I""I~lltM (Y"~

ARABIC TEXTS

. i ~I)-I (~

. i ~..lJi (\ •. J judicium ~ t. 'C~"'l:IM (\ \

JI «..:;..~» ,f J! \.. JS") (\ Y

. i - (<<..:;..~ ~I»

. J decernit ~ t. t:l~"'l:IM (\ Y"

\.. DJI «,,h B ,f o~ \.. J5') (\t

'i - «(~y.

. t. t'I"I.,t'lM~M' (\ 0

.J equitas ~ t. ,"'"M (\'. J et iniquitas ~ t. ,':VM' (\ V

. i~.i (\A

. '-' ~ (\~

. i J}JI (y.

'i~ (Y\. t. M'1)M ( YY

demonstrativa, t.t'I!'M''l:lM (YY"

ARABIC TEXTS

. i JIS" (Y

Lit>'i (<< ifu B .:...? JW) (\

~J,t.''-:''-

199

. i e~1 (t·

. i ~I)-I (t \

:J suam naturam ~ t."I:V:1'C (t Y

(t,. t. - (\

Page 106: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries
Page 107: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

1"~ ~ y~ ~Jjy JUlii u"; ,4~1 JUli)/\ 'L..~ .,Ji ' ..~I ~ ~.)I ~' 0~1 t~.r::J L..! ~J JJAl~ ..~IW!J . J~I J ,:?.1l1 "';\j;;jlU ..k.4; v~1)J1 } 4.l )~)'\ [J ~i ~]

(;l "L. -0i If" .1'~ - ·i "0 c· .!.U.1 -0)/ ~. ~~ J.. ~ i.Y" . 'J)Y .

~ lA.r.f-J 11"~~j1 4?1;....£ 4..-.,J1 )y)/\ ~ ~l&.UI if IY AS'JI l\kJli)/1 .!.U.15"' ,4..-.,J1 If [j; Ai i] )y)/\ ~IJ if'

. .vI'; "~ 10 JI JUli)/\ if'~ ..~I P

aut fugens enormitatem ('\

.J, I ;. • I :1\, • I :11 (V. u- ~:r' . i ~-:r'

. t... t"l'~"i't"lMM'Ji .;:..1.iJ ~ , '-:' ' i ';1.iJ~ (A

. t... t"l'~'" ~". i 0~ (~. i 'Y.;:i (,.. '-:' <f ("

. J in maiore parte (' Y

. J picturae , t... l"1"'i''Il)r.lM (' r'

. i 1I (' t. i - ( «( .vI';~ JI ))) (' Cl

. J intelligitur , Ji ~~ (' '\

: 0!PJ1

. J - (', '-:' JS"..,;i ~J ~I ~J (Y· J - , t...., '~''Il)~ ,,~, ,~,

· t... C~"<"''Il»M C~'r.l~r.l~ (r'

('). t... ,,~, <'

~.iJ1 '~I J I~) v-=:ll (Y

C;I) ,~':J yj ...D,...

.J~ .li .,jYJ ' , d" ~I

~ «( Ji )) j..j4 •~I 1.1l.

. (1.1l.

.Ji 'i J:;i (r'

. t...l"1"~t"l~ , '-:'~~ (t

·J rem , t..."~'M , '-:' .. -.s~1 (Cl

203

Page 108: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

'~~ O~r$- t~ I"~ ~ (.1 ,Y~~ lu')'~~ . Y

I'~\ ~. " 4:;i L__ A.b:.'&.l vJl.,> (.1 v , ~I ~ ..l>L• ~ ~ J. • J ., "Jr .

if"!iJ1 ($t if ~I "'JA» : "1:Jy4S' Oj~')'~ ~.yll ~ J; ~';J

4&-WI o.1A "~i ~ JAJ . o~ ~~} ~ II"u,),~1 o.1AJ ~ ( ~I

"~ .u §J .~ ~~I 4:;t J; 10~~\ u')'~ It.b:.t ~

IA~~I 4:;i J;IA ~~I J~ IV~J.b:.Y ~,; J U"'1;.l1 if -#'~'d'}i\ ""J.r ~t ~, ~L. "'J ~.) Y'~\ J'; ~ I~~~~\ ~ J~ YI"u.b:.f 1';1 u')'~\ o.1A J~ wlJ . I+:i~ Jo.1A Y~..kl;u L.. YA 'c"'t . YV~I "'~.c yo4.J yt::.,. J

JV J ., :r-.. .Yo r-~

} 1"1" ~')'~ I"Y \11 1"1j~ •.a"j ~i ~.: ')' JI ~~~\ J 1"' u')'~1

j~ ~i j~ ')' J ,~I l'to-#, oLA ':"li ' lAj~ J""""!

l'A \~ ~!,l\ ~il"v§JJ . ~j\;.:. ')'J ~WI J>b 1"'')' 1"0 (~."..

.~I,",=,,\::S"'JIIil~1

I-~IL LAl\ l" L_·.~ Y~ LlJ '.:....i1S' ':"I J 4&-1:....a.l1 o.1AJ .f~.U"'. V-- ... •

~~ ~ ~4 ~I:i CyJ; t..:.,I._-:..1 ~ J ~ "~ u tf ~ ')'J

.i . \:....4. 0 I . • • • ~1 ..kl;JI·($r ~ . ~J~ ..:..;IS' ';1 Y~l:.iJ1 ~ 4&-1:...aJ1 o.1A I~ ".:"i($1 0. ~j~ • t

, 1"!J;l~ JtAJI yiJ o.)~\ ')' } \L. ~r$- .)~I yi j~' U"'"A; !J.r€

'¥ o~ ~ ~ ~ P .:"i ~W)l\ tj~ .~ ~I jJ'"~1 .)"~

JI 4&-1:....a.l1 if r=J1 4&-1:..,., .:,,~ . v~~1 ~,; J~ L. "ri J;I'u')'lf" o.1A §J .~~ L. ~"r\ ~~ P:.:"i ':"L..i)ll Aj~ ~

. JL..i)l1 "'Jj~1 "JI$JI c:.r ~j\;.:.

YJ ~ ~J ~J\i~' o.1A J o~ L. ~ if 1a..J;.1 J;JI .0

J!...t..a::ll J~ J; "Y t~f J;t I"~ .:"i ~i ~4 4t.;M

204

. J erat ("

. J sumuntur (' V

.,-:, - ('A

. i - ('\.,-:, ~ (Y'

. '-:' J ~i (n

. '-:' - (n

. J sumuntur (Yf

. i .Jy. (H

.Ji ''-:' ~ (Yo

.t f"l';'l:l~ ~ '-:' ....;.J~ (n

. J assimilationis (YV

. J maior autem pars (YA

. Ji 'i ~ (Y\similitudines sit quando (f'

sumuntur secundum mo-

. J dum permutationis

. '-:' .)~ (f'

. J , t - (fY~...... I '''Yt.> ~ L,"Yl..1 (ff'f'. i't" ..

.t OM~ l''l'l:l,n

ARABIC TEXTS

. Ji ':;""Y~1i ~ i - (' (Y)

duae species ~ t O"~"'l:l "~m (Y.J

. J assimilat ~ t M'l:l'" (f

(<<~\DJ\ «~»~J. \.. JS"') (1

res alicui rei per ~ i~una dictionarum assimi-

. J lationis

. t ,~,n ~ Ji .-fJ1 (0

. t '~'M ~ Ji •-.s:J4 ('aut simulacrarum sump- (V

. J tuarum

. J - ~ ,-:,.1>,; (A

.J essentia ~ t OZ, ~ Ji .:;.,\'; (\.J assimilati ~ i J:> (,.

• '-:' 417 ~ i - ("terrae ~ t - ~ Ji d')~\ J.r (' Y

. J sudor est

. J industriae (' f

. J sumat (\1

. J - ('0

ARABIC TEXTS

. t- (f

. J valet ~ t;~''l (1

'i A (0

· Ji 'i~ ('. t - (V

. J estimat ~ t "m" (A

· t n''l:l;m~ (\. i 41lf" (, •

· t n''l:l;mM (". J - ~ (i ~~I4iIl:.A) (H

concludendo autem dici- (' (0)

. J mus quod

. '-:' - (Y

; J instituat (f

. J - (1

205

. '-:' #' ~ Ji ' i op (f1

. '-:' .)~.".. ~ Ji ' i - (fo

• '-:' ·"Yl (f'

'; '-:' J"Y ~ Ji ' i,§..1 (fV

. i 0-4! (fA(f)

·t''-:'- ('. Ji 'i~ (Y

· i J-:-! (f

· t Mm,n (1': t n''l:l,nMM' ~ '-:'~), (0

(1)

· Ji 4..i\:... ('

~ t ",:11'1 ~ Ji 'i "l;.,J1 (Y. J necessitatis

Page 109: Three Short Commentaries on Aristotle'sTopics Rhetoric and … · 2019-07-19 · E.yen. tbose still attracted to the philosophy of Aristotle are little inclin.ed tostudythecommentaries

206 ARABIC TEXTS

~ (oW 0W)'1 0~ i:~ \jrJl ~ 4./' 4i)1 oJAJ '\ . o.)~~

)2:J1 J~ y. .. Wi "JI.f' 01S'" 010W)'1 -0!i . ~)rl vJ~1 ~

"(';1 )..illl' "I-4~ ,JJ~ (oW~ )..illl \-4~ 01S"'J' J J.)\~\

";:;)1 ..:iI~ • ~)rl \TJ~\ ~ (.M:-o 4J. 0~ JI 4i)1 J J~,,. \__ II. .....,::--

l:I'1";l l~":lM 0":1 p,m; r,;Ml"ltl~m "ml"l '11)'", "m";m':1m, l"l~1:I' c"Eb~ l"l'll)1:IM,:ll"l" M''':I"M 'O,El, M"m,''''M~ M:I,"m "1:1' ", ~1:I:I',

'''~'O''':':IMM'T 1'11:1,'11) "\:1 ~'T:P

M":I oml'1 ,,,., M'OCP'C:I

Excellus autem : J JJ ~

Deus est, qui est Deus

adiutor, et sustenens, et

non est Deus nisi ipse qui

semper laudetur. Amen.

. t - (0

In hac autem arte est ('\

. J honor et prestantia

. t l"l~'r.l'mM (V. t 'n~tl,m (A

. Ji lo\ (~

• '-:' o~ (,.

. t ,'c" (". t l"l'1:;mM (' Y

: lolA ~ t JJ ~ '-:' '-:'~ (''''o,~, ,~, M'Ml"l Cl,m~~ Cll"l'~""MM l"l~~''l:l ,,:11' c,m~