This Article Explores the Laclau and Mouffe

17
Article Review (Muhibbuddin Murzan / 230 717 005) This Article explores the Laclau and Mouffe’s principal about hegemony and Socialist Strategy (1985) which is supported with some texts written by Laclau alone. Traditionally, Discourse theory, by using discourse analytical tools in analyzing social phenomena, aims at understanding of the social as a separated construction. Discourse theory is suitable as a theoretical foundation for different social constructionist approaches to discourse analysis because of its broad focus, presenting the discourse theoretical approach to language and extending the theory to cover the entire social field. However, the Laclau and Moffe’s text do not include so many practical tools textually oriented discourses analysis, so that it can be useful to supplement their theory with methods from other approaches to discourse analysis. To sum up, the discourse theory views that the social phenomena are never finished. It means that the social phenomena can never be ultimately fixed and this opens up the way for constant social struggles about definitions of society and identify, with resulting social effects. Toward a theory of Discourse

Transcript of This Article Explores the Laclau and Mouffe

Page 1: This Article Explores the Laclau and Mouffe

Article Review

(Muhibbuddin Murzan / 230 717 005)

This Article explores the Laclau and Mouffe’s principal about hegemony and Socialist

Strategy (1985) which is supported with some texts written by Laclau alone. Traditionally,

Discourse theory, by using discourse analytical tools in analyzing social phenomena, aims at

understanding of the social as a separated construction.

Discourse theory is suitable as a theoretical foundation for different social constructionist

approaches to discourse analysis because of its broad focus, presenting the discourse theoretical

approach to language and extending the theory to cover the entire social field. However, the

Laclau and Moffe’s text do not include so many practical tools textually oriented discourses

analysis, so that it can be useful to supplement their theory with methods from other approaches

to discourse analysis.

To sum up, the discourse theory views that the social phenomena are never finished. It

means that the social phenomena can never be ultimately fixed and this opens up the way for

constant social struggles about definitions of society and identify, with resulting social effects.

Toward a theory of Discourse

In constructing their theory, Laclau and Moffen used the combination and modification

of two major theoretical traditions namely Marxism and Structuralism. Marxism is a theory

which is focus on social while Structuralism provides a theory of meaning. Laclau and Moffe

combine these traditions into a single poststructuralist theory in which the whole social field is

understood as aweb of processes where meaning is created.

In the previous chapter, there was a suggestion toward the structuralism view of language

that can be understood in terms of the metaphor of fishing-net : all linguistic signs can be thought

of as knots in net, deriving their meaning from their difference from one to another, that is, from

being situated in particular positions in the net. The poststructuralist objection was that meaning

cannot be fixed so unambiguously and definitively. Poststructuralists agree that signs acquire

Page 2: This Article Explores the Laclau and Mouffe

their meaning by being different from each other. , but, in ongoing language use, we position the

signs in different relations to one another so that they may acquire new meanings. Thus language

use is a social phenomenon: it is through conventions, negotiations and conflicts in social

contexts that structures of meaning are fixed and challenged.

But let’s start off with Laclau. First of all we need a sense of his (and of course Mouffe’s

too) definition of discourse. For him, the intrinsic emptiness in all discourses is what constitutes

them as unstable, inessential and contingent formations. No discourse can be a complete entity –

i.e. a social construction that would be independent from all other constructions – because that

would mean that the construction would be essentially given and resistant to change. It would be

a meta-physical entity that we couldn’t even begin to understand. This is exactly the problem

with the structural linguistic theory of Saussure – from who Laclau and Mouffe starts off. In his

well known Course in General Linguistics (1974) Saussure portrayed a linguistic structure as a

system of difference where every sign gets its meaning from its relational position vis-à-vis other

signs. In such a system meaning is only constituted through difference and every sign becomes

non-essential in character, but on the other hand, the meaning of the system itself becomes

essential – something in itself as it is not standing in relation to anything at all. The relational

positions of the included signs thus become fixed – which means that meaning itself is fixed.

Meaning is still arbitrary – yes, and still relational – yes, but yet it remains fixed. Even Saussure

recognized this problem and because of that he included the time-factor in his theoretical body.

Linguistic change, he postulated, can only come from something as undefined and un-theorized

as time itself (1974: 73-74).

Because of this theoretical problem Laclau and Mouffe introduced several notions,

among them their concept of the “field of discursivity” (1985/2001: 111) – a field in which every

discursive formation partakes in and which they cannot fully master. The field of discursivity is

characterized by infinitude, i.e. by the multitude of meaning that every object/sign/element can

take. This field conditions every object as discursively constituted, while at the same time it

prevents every attempt to fix their meaning, since they can always be put in new relational

constellations, which would assign them new meanings. Every discourse thus becomes a semi-

stable fixation of the field of discursivity and there is always something outside every discursive

formation – structure in Saussure’s terminlogy. This ‘outside’ makes every discourse into a non-

Page 3: This Article Explores the Laclau and Mouffe

complete entity, which allows us to theorize about structural change. But it also allows us to

theorize about power – and it is for that latter analysis that the concept of empty signifier is of

the utmost importance.

The field of discusivity allows us to understand the non-complete character of meaning,

but it doesn’t allow us to understand how a semi-stable meaning actually is constructed. As

Laclau and Mouffe says: “Even in order to differ, to subvert meaning, there has to be a

meaning.” (1985/2001: 112), and how is this meaning constructed? How is it that certain

elements in the field of discursivity actually become connected to one another and thus turn

themselves into a chain of relational positions (which is Laclau and Mouffe’s definition of

discourse)? This is where the empty signifier comes into play. The empty signifier is the

discursive centre, what Laclau & Mouffe calls a nodal point, i.e. a privileged element that

gathers up a range of differential elements, and binds them together into a discursive formation.

But it is only by emptying a certain signifier of its content that this process can be achieved. Its

emptiness makes it possible for it to signify the discourse as a whole. The power of a certain

signifier is therefore coterminous with its emptiness. It is only through this emptiness that it can

articulate different elements around it, and thus produce a discursive formation. (As David wrote

in his Notebook entry on Rauschenberg’s “Mother of God” (notebook): The centre is at the same

time both brilliant and actually pretty much nothing at all). With this emptiness the nodal point

becomes universal in its scope, but it cannot be completely universal, since it is only given

meaning by the particular elements, which it stands in relation to. Rather it is becomes a signifier

of an absent universality – of a lack within the discourse’s core. It becomes:

”… present as that which is absent; it becomes an empty signifier, as the signifier of this

absence” (Laclau, 1996: 44)

The centre’s emptiness is what makes discourses possible, but at the same time they

condition every discourse as empty – as a non-complete formation. The discursive centre, far

from being an identifiable centre with a given – positive – content thus becomes a function of

negativity, i.e. a function of something that the discourse lacks, to use Lacanian terms.

We can now begin to understand how this emptiness is related to power, not only the power to be

able to construct a discursive formation, but also as a power-struggle between formations. For

Page 4: This Article Explores the Laclau and Mouffe

Laclau, the empty, incomplete character of every discourse is the driving factor behind politics as

such. Politics, looked at from this perspective, then becomes a struggle to fill the emptiness with

a given content – to suture the rift of the discursive centre and to create a universal hegemony.

The political struggle is therefore a struggle of identification, of obtaining a

full/complete/positive/essential identity. An impossible project, but nevertheless a project that

political discourses undertake. It would be a project aiming at the end of meaning and at the end

contingency; towards “… the realization of a society fully reconciled with itself” (Laclau, 1996,

69). Given the impossibility of this project, antagonisms are introduced as the ”… symbol of my

non-being” (Laclau & Mouffe, 1985/2001: 125), of what keeps the political project from

realizing itself, i.e. from obtaining a positive identity and thus establish hegemony. So the

antagonistic relationship – what keeps us from Ourselves (with a capital O) – is the only type of

identity we can obtain. Partial, yes, but at least semi-stable.This is exactly what privileges the

antagonistic relationship in Laclau’s body of theory, because it constructs the antagonistic

relationship as the moment of individuation, as constitutive of the discursive formation, using

Torfings wording:

”… the outside is not merely posing a threat to the inside, but is actually required for the

definition of the inside. The inside is marked by a constitutive lack that the outside helps to fill.”

(2004: 11)

So the discursive centre is empty and needs to be filled, this is the very notion of politics

that Laclau has brought us. A notion that always produces antagonisms, since Laclau’s notion of

politics determines that the emptiness within needs to be filled with a given content. What keeps

us from performing that operation (which is actually the field of discursivity) is symbolically

articulated as an antagonism. So the only identity that we can obtain, according to Laclau, is this

antagonistic version of being kept from Oneself.

But what if we could portray that inherent emptiness in other terms, terms that would still

address discourses as lacking identity, but not necessarily illustrate their centres as something

that needs to be filled/mastered by political projects – or even identified as possible to be filled

for that matter – which would inevitably produce a symbol for that project’s failure (the

antagonistic other)? What kind of effects would that reformulation have for the analyses of social

Page 5: This Article Explores the Laclau and Mouffe

relations and of processes of identification? Instead of focussing à priori on one type of

relationships, we would have an abundance of relationships – all part in processes of

identification and the moment of individuation. Such a reformulation would widen social space –

such as it is portrayed by traditional anglo-saxan discourse theorists, and open up for a more

nuanced and valid discourse analysis – more in tune with the social. Or at least, that’s what I

feel.

Critique of Marxism

Marxism and Communism have done better as social movements than as parties in power. As

movements, they have been able to excite and galvanize the opposition. As parties in power, they

have resorted to terror and dictatorship to stay in power. When they have been democratic, they

have been overthrown by the capitalist powers. The only communist regimes, which have

successfully survived, are those, which have become capitalist. Since the collapse of communism

in the East, the left in the West has also died along with it. Those who have chosen social

democracy and reformism have increasingly become institutionalized and centrist so much that

they are indistinguishable from the powers that be.

Marxism has served as a kind of “alter ego” of modern capitalism. As long as capitalism has

continued to grow and evolve, Marxism has been there to provide a critique of it. In order for

capitalism to wipe out Marxism, it would first have to destroy itself. Then Marxists would have

nothing about which to write. Or would they? Despite its vicissitudes, capitalism does not seem

to be going away anytime soon. Its socially and environmentally destructive tendencies are only

outmatched by its adaptability and tremendously productive capacities. The belief that

civilization is on the verge of collapse (á la Žižek) echoes of hopes in the eschatological end of

times. Neither the Messiah nor the Revolution has come. Belief in the apocalypse is based on a

combination of anxiety and wishful thinking. More likely is that “the crisis of crisis

management” will be managed. As much profit can be made out of helping the environment as in

destroying it. Or, first we make money by destroying the environment so we can then make

money by saving it.

Page 6: This Article Explores the Laclau and Mouffe

In an Orwellian logic, if we do not have an enemy we would have to create one. With the

collapse of the Soviet Union, neo-conservative Samuel Huntington was all too eager but to point

the way. For the right wing in the Judeo-Christian West, the new enemy is Islam. Arms

contractors, oil companies, (along with Halliburton, Bechtel and Blackwater) have been all too

eager but to get it on what has mounted to a low grade endless wars- wars that cannot be won

and which we do not want to win- on fear that we will lose our contracts. War is more profitable

than peace. The underlying logic of the Obama administration is that the way to keep the

military-industrial complex quiet (that is for the Democrats to have their support) is to keep them

busy. If there is a desire to end a war due to its political and financial costs, it is only to free up

resources for the next one.

The Socialist, Communist, and Anarchist movements in the 19th and 20th century have not

simply waned because of the collapse of the Soviet system; they have declined due to their own

orthodoxy. Historical materialism and critical theory should be a living breathing framework,

which constantly has to renew and modify itself to address changing conditions on the ground. In

order for it to do so, it must engage in self-critique. Marx, wrote that “the premise of all criticism

is the criticism of religion.” Conservative critics have accused Marxism of being a secular

religion- a secularization of Judeo-Christian Messianism. This poses a paradox. On the one hand,

it has provided hope in something better. On the other hand, it has been delusional. Rather than

denying this, historical materialism must critique the theological residues within it so that it can

once more become a vibrant social science. Only when this occurs, can it provide a truly critical

understanding of existing social conditions and thereby provide any chance on making them

better.

One thing that a Marxist, historical materialist or a critical framework can provide is a

better understanding of religion. There is a tendency of many social scientists to avoid dialectical

frameworks for understanding social reality because of its political associations. Any association

with Marxism gives most social scientistsUnbehagen. Marx did not invent dialectics nor was he

the first to apply it to history, but he was the first to do it in a materialist manner, that is,

supposedly devoid of theology. The roots of dialectics go back beyond Hegel and Kant to Plato

and Aristotle. Dialectical frameworks still provide a useful tool in understanding the dynamics of

historical processes. One of these dialectical frameworks is class analyses. However, it too often

applied in a rigid manner. There are never just two classes but more complex divisions,

Page 7: This Article Explores the Laclau and Mouffe

subdivisions, and overlapping boundaries. Class is only one line along which conflict takes

place. There others including race, ethnicity, nationality, gender, sexual orientation, etc. Many of

these conflicts have an economic basis. Neither Marx nor the Frankfurt School was the first to be

critical. Preceding them were the Young Hegelians and Immanuel Kant. To be critical is not

simply to negate but it is stems from the desire to make things better.

There is a tendency for most analyses of religion in the last few decades to engage in an

empathetic understanding. While affirming freedom of belief and religious pluralism, we should

not be afraid to criticize it. Religious beliefs need to be crosschecked with their relation to

reality- whether literalist interpretations of the Bible, terrorism in the name of Jihad, or the

delusions of the end of times. Individuals must have the right to religious freedom but we must

challenge religious ignorance, Thanatos, and lack of self-reflection.

To understand the religious conflicts in the modern world, we need to use a critical

framework, which selectively appropriates elements from its intellectual past. The framework is

self-reflective;  critique turns back in on itself. Through critique, we can reach higher levels of

understanding. Religious conflict is a process of interaction, and like all interaction, it has a

dynamic. The pattern is not a cycle or a pendulum but rather a spiral (a dialectic). There is a

tendency of sectarian religious movements to become institutionalized into churches. Social

movements, if they survive, become institutionalized into NGOs or political parties. These

institutions become increasingly ossified only to give rise to the need for new religious and

secular movements. In the sphere of religion, the process with its periodic “revivals and

routinization” is a dialectical one of religious rationalization and secularization.

Critical theory needs to reevaluate its relationship to positivistic social sciences. It should

make use of all methodologies available to it including quantitative, qualitative, and historical

methods. A critical approach to religion will not be likely to attract institutional funding.

Religious institutions and religious sympathetic foundations, especially conservative ones, are

likely to be uninterested or even hostile. This is the problem of the left. Unlike our conservative

and mainstream counterparts, we do not have much of an economic base. This, however, should

not stop us. A critical approach to religion will help us better understand not only the roots of

religious conflict, but also how it unfolds. It may help us make better sense of the religious right,

Page 8: This Article Explores the Laclau and Mouffe

of fundamentalisms and orthodoxies of all kinds, which stand in the way of progressive social

change.

Antagonism and Hegemony

This article examines the implications of the introduction of the category of

'heterogeneity' in Ernesto Laclau's most recent work. Laclau's theory of hegemony and discourse

theoretical approach to ideology is often associated with the category of 'antagonism'. I argue

that heterogeneity should be the central category of hegemony and discourse analysis, and that

antagonism can be seen as a strategy of ideological closure. In addition, heterogeneity—

understood as the simultaneous condition of possibility and impossibility of hegemonic

articulation—renders the theory of hegemony closer to Derridean deconstruction. Hegemony

analysis and deconstruction are often presented as different and complementary theoretical

moves. I argue that this is not the case, and that they can instead be seen as dealing with the same

issues of the conditions of possibility and impossibility of the discursive constitution of ideology

and identity.

 As having shown in Hegemony and Socialist Strategy, to be able to envisage negation in

the mode of antagonism requires a different ontological approach where the primary ontological

terrain is one of division, of failed unicity. Antagonism is not graspable in a problematic that sees

the society as a homogeneous space because this is incompatible with the recognition of radical

negativity. As Ernesto Laclau has stressed, the two poles of antagonism are linked by a non-

relational relation, they do not belong to the same space of representation and they are essentially

heterogeneous with each other. It is out of this irreducible heterogeneity that they emerge. In

order to make room for radical negativity, we need to abandon the immanentist idea of a

homogeneous saturated social space and acknowledge the role of heterogeneity. This requires

relinquishing the idea of a society beyond division and power, without any need for law or the

state and where in fact politics would have disappeared.

It could be argued that the strategy of exodus is the reformulation in a different vocabulary of the

idea of communism as it was found in Marx. Indeed there are many points in common between

Page 9: This Article Explores the Laclau and Mouffe

the views of the Post-Operaists and the traditional Marxist conception. To be sure, for them it is

not any more the proletariat but the Multitude which is the privileged political subject but in both

cases the State is seen a monolithic apparatus of domination that cannot be transformed. It has to

‘wither away’ in order to leave room for a reconciled society beyond law, power and

sovereignty.

If our approach has been called ‘Post-Marxist’ it is precisely because we have challenged

the type of ontology subjacent to such a conception. By bringing to the fore the dimension of

negativity which impedes the full totalization of society, we have put into question the very

possibility of such a reconciled society. To acknowledge the ineradicability of antagonism

implies recognizing that every form of order is necessarily a hegemonic one and that

heterogeneity cannot be eliminated; antagonistic heterogeneity points to the limits of constitution

of social objectivity. As far as politics is concerned, this means the need to envisage it in terms of

a hegemonic struggle between conflicting hegemonic projects attempting to incarnate the

universal and to define the symbolic parameters of social life. Hegemony is obtained through the

construction of nodal points, which discursively fix the meaning of institutions and social

practices and articulate the ‘common sense’ through which a given conception of reality is

established. Such a result will always be contingent and precarious and susceptible of being

challenged by counter-hegemonic interventions. Politics always takes place in a field

crisscrossed by antagonisms and to envisage it as ‘acting in concert’ leads to erasing the

ontological dimension of antagonism (that I have proposed to call ‘the political’) which provides

its quasi-transcendental condition of possibility. A properly political intervention is always one

that engages with a certain aspect of the existing hegemony in order to disarticulate/re-articulate

its constitutive elements. It can never be merely oppositional or conceived as desertion because it

aims at re-articulating the situation in a new configuration.

Another important aspect of a hegemonic politics lies in establishing a ‘chain of

equivalences’ between various demands, so as to transform them into claims that will challenge

the existing structure of power relations. It is clear that the ensemble of democratic demands that

exist in our societies do not necessarily converge and they can even be in conflict with each

other. This is why they need to be articulated politically. What is at stake is the creation of a

Page 10: This Article Explores the Laclau and Mouffe

common identity, a ‘we’ and this requires the determination of a ‘they’. This again is missed by

the various advocates of the Multitude, who seem to believe that it possesses a natural unity

which does not need political articulation. According to Virno, for instance, the Multitude has

already something in common: the general intellect. His critique (shared by Hardt and Negri) of

the notion of the People as being homogeneous and expressed in a unitary general will which

does not leave room for multiplicity and is totally misplaced when directed to the construction of

the People through a chain of equivalence. Indeed in this case we are dealing with a form of

unity that respects diversity and does not erase differences. As we have repeatedly emphasized, a

relation of equivalence does not eliminate difference- that would be simply identity. It is only as

far as democratic differences are opposed to forces or discourses that negate all of them, that

these differences can be substituted for each other. This is why the construction of a collective

will requires defining an adversary. Such an adversary cannot be defined in broad general terms

like ‘Empire’ or for that matter ‘Capitalism’ but in terms of nodal points of power that need to be

targeted and transformed in order to create the conditions for a new hegemony. It is a ‘war of

position’ (Gramsci) that needs to be launched in a multiplicity of sites. This can only be done by

establishing links between social movements, political parties and tradeunions. To create,

through the construction of a chain of equivalence, a collective will, to engage with a wide range

of institutions, with the aim of transforming them, this is, in my view, the kind of critique that

should inform radical politics.

Contingency and permence

Contingency theories are a class of behavioral theory that contend that there is no one

best way of leading and that a leadership style that is effective in some situations may not be

successful in others.

An effect of this is that leaders who are very effective at one place and time may become

unsuccessful either when transplanted to another situation or when the factors around them

change.

This helps to explain how some leaders who seem for a while to have the 'Midas touch' suddenly

appear to go off the boil and make very unsuccessful decisions.