theroies of tort

download theroies of tort

of 45

Transcript of theroies of tort

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    1/45

    Theories of Tort Law

    A tort is a legal wrong. Tort law is a branch of the civil law;

    the other main branches are contract and property law.

    Whereas in criminal law the plaintiff is always the state andthe defendant, if found guilty of a crime, is punished by the

    state, in civil law the dispute is typically between privateparties (though the government can also sue and be sued). In

    the case of torts, the plaintiff is the victim of an alleged wrong

    and the unsuccessful defendant is either directed by the court

    to pay damages to the plaintiff (the usual remedy) or else to

    desist from the wrongful activity (so-called "injunctive

    relief"). Examples include intentional torts such as battery,defamation, and invasion of privacy and unintentional torts

    such as negligence. Most contemporary tort theory focuses on

    the legal consequences of accidents, where the relevant forms

    of liability are negligence and strict liability. This entry

    likewise focuses on these forms of liability.

    Misfortune happens and when it does its victims incur costs.

    Those costs can remain the burden of victims or they can beshifted to others. Sometimes the costs are borne by everyone

    (within a particular group or political community). Still other

    times those costs are borne by particular individuals, namely,

    those who are responsible for having caused them. The

    question is: Who is to bear the costs of life's misfortunes:

    victims, the community as a whole, those who are responsible

    for them, or someone else entirely? How are we to answer this

    question? What principles ought to guide the decision, andwhat institutions ought we create to realize these principles in

    practice?

    1. Introduction 2. The Difference Between Fault and Strict Liability

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/
  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    2/45

    3. Framework for a Theory of Tort Law 4. Theories of Torts: Economic Analysis 5. Theories of Torts: Corrective Justice Bibliography Other Internet Resources Related Entries

    1. Introduction

    Let's set aside for the moment the costs of misfortune that are

    borne collectively and distributed throughout the community

    through tax systems that support, for example, social welfare

    and safety net programs more generally. Of those that remain,

    the question is whether the costs are to be borne by victims or

    some other particular person or persons. Tort law is one of the

    institutions political communities develop in order to allow

    victims the opportunity to shift the costs that befall them to

    others. Insurance is another such institution. Many individuals

    purchase first party insurance to protect themselves against

    having to shoulder the full costs of some misfortunes that may

    befall them and to guard against others. Private health

    insurance provides a good example of first party insurance

    against risk to oneself. The contrast is with third party

    insurance a contract into which one enters to guard against

    shouldering the full costs of misfortune one imposes on others

    for which one is held by law to be responsible.

    Tort law and insurance are connected in the following way.Tort law establishes conditions under which victims can shift

    at least some of the costs they incur to others. All individuals

    realize that they may be subject to a judgment against them in

    torts and so many buy third party insurance to protect them

    from bearing the full costs of those judgments. In some

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/
  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    3/45

    jurisdictions purchasing third party insurance is mandatory.

    All individuals are likewise aware that they may be victims of

    another's actions and may not be able to secure a favorable

    judgment against their injurers or they not deem it worth

    the effort to pursue redress through the courts. So many ofthem buy first party insurance to guard against some of the

    costs they would otherwise have to shoulder completely.

    It is important to note that tort law provides an avenue of

    redress, not a guarantee of recovery. The victim must

    determine whether pursuing a remedy through torts is worth

    the effort and cost. Indeed, as an empirical matter most simply

    grin and bear the loss then move on. When a victim choosesthe form of redress provided by tort law she is given the

    opportunity to shift her losses to another provided the

    conditions the law sets out for doing so have been met. The

    conditions for shifting losses from victim-plaintiffs to injurer-

    defendants are expressed in liability rules . The law of torts

    distinguishes between two basic kinds of rules: those that

    impose fault liability and those that impose strict liability.

    In the next section we will characterize the difference betweenthese liability rules precisely, but for now it may be helpful to

    illustrate the underlying distinction in familiar terms that do

    not rely on the technicalities of the law.

    Suppose I made a mess of some sort on my property, then I

    turned to you and presented you with the bill for cleaning it

    up. In the absence of some prior agreement we might have

    made this would seem rather odd. After all, it is my mess, notyours. The burden, accordingly, is mine, not yours, to

    discharge. Now suppose that instead of making a mess on my

    property and presenting you with the bill, I simply move the

    mess I made to your property (or I make the mess on your

    property from the get-go), and simply walk away claiming the

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    4/45

    cleanup problem is now yours. If it was inappropriate of me to

    present you with the bill for the mess I made on my property,

    it hardly seems that I have improved matters by placing my

    mess on your property instead. It is, after all, my mess, and

    the responsibility of cleaning it up is mine. This is theunderlying thought behind strict liability. One has a duty to

    clean up one's messes, and that responsibility does not appear

    to depend on how hard one has tried not to make a mess in the

    first place.

    On the other hand, unless each of us stays in his respective

    dwelling, we are bound to make the occasional mess in each

    other's lives. You would not be justified in demanding of methat I never bump into you or make something of a mess in

    your life, nor would I be justified in making similar demands

    of you. What I can demand of you is that you take my

    interests into account and moderate your behavior

    accordingly. You need to take reasonable precautions not to

    harm me; you need to avoid being reckless with respect to my

    interests. And I am obligated to treat you similarly. That is,

    what we have a right to demand of one another is that webehave responsibly with respect to the other's interests. This is

    the underlying thought behind fault liability.

    The question is which is the appropriate standard of liability

    in torts? Most tort theorists believe that we cannot answer that

    question without first answering another namely, what are

    the goals or aims of tort law? The conditions of liability in

    torts justify imposing a duty of repair on those who satisfythem only if (a) the duties so imposed are the ones best suited

    to help tort law meet its goals, and (b) the goals are

    themselves justified. The primary focus of tort theory has

    been to identify the goals of tort law and to justify them as

    legitimate aims for the law to pursue. Once the goals are

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    5/45

    identified and justified, tort theory is then a matter of

    exploring the extent to which the conditions of liability in

    torts are appropriate instruments for pursuing them.

    Put this way, tort theory is largely a normative activity thatappears to eschew explanatory projects. Whereas explanatory

    projects in law can be pursued without raising justificatoryquestions, it is less clear that justificatory projects of this sort

    can be pursued completely independently of basic explanatory

    ones. Consider the claim that the goal of tort law is

    deterrence. The claim is not that deterrence is a legitimate

    goal for some logically possible tort law. The claim is that

    deterrence, for example, is the goal of this or that system oftort law; and making out such a claim requires showing that

    the law makes sense as the sort of thing that could pursue that

    goal or aim. That requires in turn establishing that various

    features of existing or idealized practice makes sense in the

    light of the goal one attributes to it. In that sense, the

    normative project requires that we address certain explanatory

    or conceptual questions. And so part of making the case that

    say, the efficient reduction of accident costs is the goal of tortlaw rests on showing that fundamental features of actual tort

    practice are best explained by seeing them in the light of

    efficiency.

    As noted above tort law has both strict and fault liability rules.

    Thus, we have at least two projects. The first project is to

    distinguish between fault and strict liability as conditions of

    liability in torts. The second is to explore the extent to whichthe central features of tort law including the rules of fault

    and strict liability can be explained by the putative goals of

    tort law.

    2. The Difference between Fault and Strict Liability

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    6/45

    There are three basic elements in a tort: wrong, harm and an

    appropriate relationship between the injurer's wrong and the

    harm to the victim. To harm someone is to set back a

    legitimate interest of hers. The law does not recognize all

    harms as grounds for a claim in torts. If you beat me in tennisor in competition for the affections of another, I may be

    harmed, and you may be the cause of it, but I have no claim in

    torts to repair for my broken heart or my bruised ego. Even if

    the interests harmed are protected by the law, claims to repair

    for the losses one imposes on others require more than risk

    and harm; they require a wrong the violation of a duty not

    to harm or not to impose risks of a certain kind on others. You

    have no duty not to harm me through competition in businessor the affections of another, and so in harming me you do not

    thereby wrong me. There is no overstating the importance of

    the idea of a wrong or of a breach of duty to tort law.

    The central idea in tort law is that liability is based not so

    much on acting badly or wrongfully, but on committing a

    wrong. At the same time, a victim's claim to recover for harm

    to her depends on the wrong the injurer has committed being awrong to her. It is not enough that the injurer has committed awrong and that she (the victim) has suffered as a consequence.

    The defendant's liability to the victim and the victim's claim

    against the defendant depend on the defendant's having

    breached a duty of care to the victim.

    Just as harm without wrong is no tort, wrongs without harms

    are typically not torts either. Suppose for a moment that everymotorist has a duty to exercise reasonable care in driving his

    or her car, and that the intended beneficiaries of the duty

    include all the pedestrians and other drivers who might be put

    at risk by one's failure to drive with adequate care. Now

    imagine two people who drive recklessly and in so doing

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    7/45

    breach the duty we suppose they have, but that one motorist

    causes damage whereas the other escapes injuring anyone. By

    hypothesis, both have breached a duty to those whose security

    is put at risk, and in doing so both have committed wrongs.

    Only one driver harms someone as a result of the wrongs hecommits and thus only he subjects himself to tort liability.

    So torts require both wrong and, in most cases, harm. A

    notable exception to the harm requirement is the case in which

    injunctive relief is awarded in order to prevent harm that is

    virtually certain but yet to occur. As a general rule though

    torts require both wrongs and harms. They require more as

    well: for liability in torts can be imposed only if the harm hasbeen caused in the appropriate way by the wrong. A's wrong

    must be what the law calls the proximate cause of B's harm.

    These are the elements of a tort, but the question is how arethey represented in the context of the rules of strict and fault

    liability. On the conventional view, the difference between

    fault and strict liability is that in strict liability, but not in fault

    liability, a defendant can be liable even if he has done nothingwrong. The common understanding, then, is that strict liability

    is liability without wrong, and fault liability alone is liability

    based on the injurer's wrong. But then the conventional view

    seems incompatible with the claim that all torts involve

    wrongs.

    There is a distinction between wrongs and wrongdoings a

    difference between committing a wrong and actingwrongfully. To act wrongfully is to act without justification or

    excuse. Wrongdoing reflects badly on an agent for his actions.

    On the other hand, to commit a wrong is to breach a duty, to

    invade another's right. One can breach a duty for good reason,

    with adequate justification, or under excusing conditions.

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    8/45

    Rights in other words can be invaded innocently (or

    justifiably) on the one hand, or wrongfully (or unjustifiably)

    on the other. This distinction is sometimes expressed in terms

    of the difference between rights-infringements and rights-

    violations. Whether my action invades your right is one thing;whether, if it does, the action reflects poorly or favorably on

    me is another.

    Let's apply this distinction to the conventional understanding

    of the difference between strict and fault liability. When

    liability is imposed strictly, the question is whether the

    defendant has invaded the plaintiff's right. A plaintiff under

    strict liability does not have to establish the fault of thedefendant, though a judgment of strict liability does not

    necessarily mean that the defendant has acted innocently or

    justifiably. According to the conventional view, under fault

    liability, the plaintiff has to establish not only that he was

    wronged by the defendant but that in doing so the defendant

    acted wrongfully, that is, without justification or excuse.

    But this way of explaining the distinction between fault andstrict liability leads us even further astray. For if the victim's

    being wronged by the defendant is adequate to ground his

    claim to repair (other things being equal) in some cases, why

    is it not enough in all cases? Concern for the character of the

    defendant's action may be appropriate to the question whether,

    in addition to incurring a duty to make his victims whole, he

    should be punished, held up to ridicule or banished from the

    community. Under strict liability, the breach of the duty iswhat is relevant to the duty to repair. In other words, if a

    practice of strict liability is justified at all, then the duty to

    make repair cannot depend on whether the injurer has acted

    justifiably or not. If that is so, why should the duty of repair in

    fault liability require more than it does in strict liability?

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    9/45

    When fault is treated as an element of a tort distinct from the

    breach of duty, either fault liability requires too much or strict

    liability too little.

    The conventional understanding of the difference betweenfault and strict liability goes astray precisely because it

    distinguishes the breach of the duty from the faultrequirement. The better view is that the difference between

    fault and strict liability is a difference in the content of the

    underlying duty of care. To see this, consider the cases of

    blasting, on the one hand, and motoring on the other. In a case

    like blasting an activity traditionally falling under strict

    liability the blaster has a duty-not-to-harm-by-blasting.This is the content of the duty of care blasters owe those

    whom their blasting puts in danger. On the other hand, in the

    case of motoring a familiar example of an activity covered

    fault liability the motorist is thought to have a duty-not-to-harm-by-faultily-motoring. That these duties have differentcontent is illustrated by their respective success and failure

    conditions. A blaster fails to discharge his duty when his

    blasting, regardless of the care he takes, injures someone towhom he owes the duty. A motorist fails to discharge his duty

    when he harms another negligently, recklessly or intentionally

    through his driving. The blaster can satisfy his obligations

    only by not harming another. The motorist can meet hers

    either by not harming anyone or, in the event she harms

    someone, by not having done so negligently, recklessly or

    intentionally. And this is just another way of saying that the

    contents of the respective duties differ. The fault requirementis thus an aspect of the underlying duty, not a reflection on thecharacter of the defendant's action.

    The force the interests of others imposes on our duty to

    moderate our behavior varies with the circumstances.

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    10/45

    Sometimes, the likelihood or magnitude of harm to others is

    so great that the duty we have to others is not to harm them as

    a result of the actions we choose to undertake. At other times,

    the balance of interests indicates that we need to take

    reasonable precautions to guard against harm to others, and nomore. Understood in this way, the problem is familiar and not

    in the least unique to tort law. It is a matter of ordinary

    morality that the content of our duties to others varies as a

    consequence of a range of familiar factors. Noting this does

    not solve the problem of telling us why sometimes the duty is

    strict and other times it demands only reasonable care. But the

    difference is that between points on a continuum, and so the

    stark contrasts that are implied in the conventional view areinapt.

    3. Framework for a Theory of Tort Law

    It is customary in tort theory to distinguish substantive from

    structural and procedural aspects of tort law. The rules of

    strict and fault liability are substantive features of tort law.

    The bilateral structure of a tort suit the fact that victims suethose they identify as their injurers and do not instead seek

    repair from a common pool of resources (as is the case in New

    Zealand) is a structural feature of our tort law. The fact that

    the burden of bringing forward a claim and of making the

    prima facie case falls to the plaintiff is a procedural feature oftort law, and so on. We have already identified the most basic

    substantive concern of a tort theory, and that is to justify,

    insofar as possible, the rules of fault and strict liability. It isnot the only substantive feature of the practice that has drawn

    the attention of theorists, as the following summary of

    substantive concerns helps to make clear.

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    11/45

    Mischief, even great mischief, that does not materialize into

    harm, may be wrongful, but it is not tortuous. Similarly, a

    reckless and irresponsible defendant who is fortunate to

    escape causing major damage to others, is only liable for the

    minor damages he causes. This in stark contrast to thegenerally focused and attentive actor whose minor mischief

    occasions a great deal of misfortune. The general principle of

    tort is that both are liable for the full costs of the harms their

    conduct has occasioned. Yet, the burdens they face bear no

    relationship to the degree of their relative wrongdoing. Why

    should fortuity play so pervasive and powerful a role in tort

    law?

    A defendant judged liable in torts incurs a duty to make good

    the full costs of the harms that result from his wrong. The

    liability takes the form of the imposition of a duty of repair.

    The defendant, however, is often able to discharge his duty

    through an insurance mechanism. The contrast with the

    criminal law can be illuminating. It is unimaginable that we

    would permit individuals to purchase insurance against the

    likelihood of criminal liability. What explains the difference?

    4. Theories of Torts: Economic Analysis

    Competing theories of tort law offer accounts of these various

    features of tort law. The degree to which they illuminate our

    practice is relative to their perspective on legal practice It is

    helpful to understand tort law through the lens of a judge

    deciding cases based on prior rulings and doctrine, from theperspective of potential litigants seeking the vindication of

    claims, and from the perspective of the legal reformer trying

    to formulate the best rules for imposing liability. Economic

    analysis of law is unconvincing if its aim is to illuminate the

    law from the perspective of either judge or litigant. It is much

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    12/45

    more plausible when viewed through the lens of a particular

    kind of legal reformer. We will get the most from economic

    analysis if we remind ourselves that the economic analyst is

    asking questions of the following sort: what substantive

    liability rules are most likely to have the greatest impact onreducing the incidence of accidents at the lowest cost? What

    procedural rules at a trial are most likely to induce those with

    the most relevant information to reveal it, or most likely to

    lead to optimal investments in information or safety; and so

    on. These are the questions of a reformer less interested in the

    actual state of tort law than in how the law can be improved.

    The economic approach to tort law, like the economicapproach to law more generally, attributes a particular goal to

    the law: namely, efficiency. In the case of tort law, efficiency

    is understood as optimal cost reduction. The aim of tort law is

    to minimize the sum of the costs of accidents and the costs of

    avoiding them. This is to be accomplished in part by creating

    a system of incentives adequate to induce individuals to invest

    appropriately in determining what the optimal precautions are

    and to take them.

    The distinguishing feature of economic analysis is the account

    it provides of fault: the formula it offers for determining

    whether an actor has adequately taken into account the

    interests of others. In general, to be at fault in torts is to fail to

    take others interests appropriately into account and to adjust

    one's conduct accordingly. Reasonable persons take the

    interests of others appropriately into account and adjust theirbehavior accordingly. To be at fault is to fail to behave as

    would a reasonable person of ordinary prudence. It is a failure

    to accord others the appropriate level of care to guard against

    harming their interests.

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    13/45

    Economic analysts focus primarily on the concept of

    negligence. Negligence is the failure to take adequate care and

    adequate care consists in taking cost-justified precautions.

    Precautions are cost-justified whenever their cost is less than

    the costs of the harm risked (by not taking precautions)discounted by the probability of the harm's occurrence. Once

    we understand negligence as the failure to take cost-justified

    precautions we need to ask what justifies imposing liability on

    those who have failed to take appropriate precautions.

    From an economic point of view, the costs of the accident for

    which one is responsible are sunk. There is nothing to be done

    about them. All that we can do is shift the costs from thevictim upon whom they have fallen to someone else. From the

    economic point of view, such a decision must be based on the

    impact of cost imposition on the incentives of individuals to

    invest appropriately in safety. Individuals ought to bear sunk

    costs only if imposing those costs on them will have the

    desired impact on the reduction of costs in the future. The

    responsibility relationship is backward looking; the cost

    reduction aim is forward looking. It may turn out that havingthe property of being responsible for a harm may be reliably

    connected to the property of being an effective cost-avoider.

    Even in that case, being responsible for a loss is not the

    groundof liability, but is instead a reliable indicator that theinjurer possesses the property that is the ground of liability.

    Beyond that, if having the property of being responsible for a

    harm is a reliable indicator that one has the property of being

    a good cost-avoider (even of harms of the particular sort forwhich one is responsible), it does not follow, without more,that one should be held liable for the particular harm for

    which one is responsible. One could just as well be held to

    bear the costs of a similar injury, or one could be held to bear

    the costs adequate to induce investments in cost reduction

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    14/45

    and those costs may or may not coincide with the costs

    associated with the harm for which one is responsible. So it

    cannot be part of an economic argument that the party who is

    at fault must pay for the costs of harms that are his fault

    because he is responsible for them. Rather, liability isimposed on those at fault in order to put in place the right

    incentives on the defendant and those similarly situated.

    If we assume that actors are fully rational and informed,

    imposing liability on those at fault will have the desired effect

    on others. Here's the argument. If we assume that agents are

    fully rational, then under the economic conception of

    rationality it follows that they will maximize benefits orminimize costs. If agents are fully informed, they know the

    costs of liability and the costs of precautions. Ex ante, all

    agents will choose the lesser of these costs. The relationship

    between precaution costs and potential liability based on fault

    is as follows. An agent will be at fault only if the costs of

    precautions are less than the costs of the harm discounted by

    the probability of occurrence. To avoid being at fault the

    rational agent takes the precautions, which, in addition, are thelesser costs he faces. If the costs of precautions exceed the

    cost of the harm discounted by the probability of its

    occurrence, then he will not take precautions, but then he will

    not be negligent either. Should harm to another result, he will

    not be required to shoulder the victim's costs. That will be for

    the victim to do (an important consequence of fault liability to

    which we shall return below.) So the rational and informed

    agent will take precautions whenever it would be efficient forhim to do so, not otherwise.

    In contrast to fault, strict liability is imposed whether or not an

    agent ought to have taken precautions. Why might we want to

    hold someone liable who has in fact invested in cost-justified

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    15/45

    precautions? The economic answer to this puzzle in effect is

    that there is more than one way to skin a cat. Skinning a cat,

    in this context, amounts to inducing individuals to take cost-

    justified precautions.

    An agent subject to strict liability has to bear the full costs of

    his activities the costs to him of engaging in it and thecosts his engaging in it imposes on others. All the costs are

    his. The question he faces, then, is whether there is anything

    he might do to reduce the costs he faces. That depends on

    whether there are precautions he can take, their costs and their

    expected effectiveness. In other words, if the costs of

    precautions are less than the harms likely to occur discountedby the probability of their occurrence, then he will take the

    precautions. He does so because these costs are lower than

    those he would otherwise expect. Notice that those

    precautions are in fact the cost justified ones. And so under

    strict liability the rational and informed agent will also be

    induced to take all and only cost justified precautions. In this

    respect fault and strict liability give the same results. The only

    difference between the two is that under fault liability thecosts of accidents not worth preventing are borne by victims,

    whereas under strict liability, those same costs are borne by

    injurers. In fault liability, the costs of accidents that are no

    one's fault are the burden of victims; in strict liability, they are

    the burden of injurers.

    If strict liability can induce efficient investments in safety,

    why would we have a rule of fault liability? If fault liability iscapable of inducing individuals to take optimal precautions,

    why impose strict liability? The two rules have different

    distributional consequences. From the economic point of

    view, the distributional consequences are not important in

    their own right, but they can be important because of their

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    16/45

    impact on activity levels. The choice of strict or fault liability

    is in one sense a choice between making activities more or

    less expensive relative to each other. Take ranching and

    farming for example. A rule of strict liability imposed on

    ranchers for the damage their straying cows impose on corncrops makes ranching more expensive relative to farming.

    This means that even if, at any level of ranching and farming,

    both strict and fault liability could be efficient in reducing

    accidents at that level, a rule of strict liability will makeranching relatively more expensive and reduce the overall

    level of it (in relation to farming). This means more farming

    and more farming accidents and fewer ranching related

    accidents. And so on. If efficiency depends on activity levels,then fault and strict liability need not be equally efficient. Or

    put another way, because fault and strict liability have

    differential impacts on activity levels, they can be used

    differentially whenever appropriate to secure an efficient

    overall allocation of risks.

    The implications of fault and strict liability are more

    complicated once we distinguish between one and two partyaccidents. A one party accident is one in which in order

    optimally to reduce the probability of its occurrence only one

    of the parties to the accident need take appropriate

    precautions. In contrast, in a two party accident, securing the

    optimal reduction in the probability of the accident's

    occurrence requires that both parties take appropriate

    precautions. Setting aside the problem of activity levels, we

    can be taken to have shown that in the case of one partyaccidents both strict and fault liability can be efficient. Thesame is not true in the case of two party accidents, where

    strict liability is not efficient. In strict liability, the victim is

    always compensated his full damages and therefore has no

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    17/45

    incentive to invest in precautions, yet the situation requires

    him to do so.

    In contrast, the rule of fault liability is efficient in the two

    party case in that it induces both injurers and victims to makeoptimal investments in safety. The rule of fault liability

    imposes liability on the injurer only if he is at fault. If theinjurer is rational, he will always take the cost justified

    precautions. We established this result above in the discussion

    of the one party accident case. Thus, the rational injurer will

    never be at fault. If people are always rational, then the costs

    of whatever accidents occur will fall to their victims.

    Victims must assume, then, that the costs of all accidents will

    be theirs to bear. Notice that this puts the victim in the exact

    position the injurer is in under strict liability. On the

    assumption that the injurer will never be at fault, the victimwill always be responsible for all of his costs. And just like

    the injurer in strict liability, the victim must decide which, if

    any, precautions to take. Whenever precaution costs are lower

    than the expected costs of the harm victims will opt for them,otherwise not. In precisely the same way that strict liability

    encourages injurers to take optimal precautions, fault liability

    encourages the victim to do the same.

    If fault liability is efficient, so too is strict liability with thedefense of plaintiff or contributory negligence. Here is anothersimple proof. This proof relies on the fact that the rule of fault

    liability imposed on defendants can be redescribed as the rulethat victims are strictly liable for the costs of harms that befall

    them unless they can establish the fault of their injurer. What

    we call fault liability can just as easily be characterized as

    strict liability for victims with the defense of injurer fault. But

    if this rule is efficient, then so too is the rule of strict (injurer)

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    18/45

    liability with the defense of victim fault. They are the same

    rule. All that changes is that every occurrence of victim is

    replaced with injurer and vice versa. One rule is efficient if

    and only if the other is. The rule of fault liability is efficient,

    and therefore the rule of strict liability with plaintiff fault mustbe as well. In those cases in which both rules are efficient, the

    choice between the two depends on other features of the rules:

    in particular, costs associated with their administration.[1]

    Notwithstanding the fact that it illuminates important features

    of legal practice and remains an invaluable tool in the

    assessment and reform of the law, economic analysis has

    spawned considerable criticism. Let's begin with twostraightforward objections. Economic analysis reduces

    reasonable risk taking to rational risk taking. In doing so, it

    treats the care I owe you as identical to the care I would owe

    myself. Suppose I engage in an activity whose benefit to me is

    100 and whose costs to me varies. Whenever the costs to me

    are under 100 it will be rational for me to absorb the costs and

    continue on. As soon as the costs to me exceed the benefits, it

    will no longer be rational for me to engage in the activity.

    Economic analysis draws no distinction between the case in

    which the costs and benefits are mine alone and the case in

    which the benefits are mine to enjoy and the costs yours to

    endure. But what is reasonable to expect of me when all the

    costs are mine to bear may not be what is reasonable to

    demand of me when the benefits are mine to enjoy and the

    costs yours to bear. To be sure, there is no difference betweenthese cases from the point of view of collective rationality, but

    that is just the point. There is no reason to identify the

    reasonable with the rational in the torts context, where one

    party (the injurer) secures the benefits (in the form of freedom

    from the costs of precautions) and the other party (the victim)

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/notes.html
  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    19/45

    bears the costs (in the form of the costs of injuries more likely

    to occur). Economic analysis in effect imposes the fungability

    of costs on the practice of torts without showing that in fact

    the practice treats costs in this way. That is one reason for

    thinking that economic analysts are reformers, not analysts oftort law.

    Now the economic arguments we have considered talk loosely

    of fault and strict liability, but nowhere invoke the notion of a

    duty. As we have already seen, the duty element of a tort has

    two dimensions. The first concerns those to whom I owe a

    duty of care; the second concerns the content of that duty. As

    we noted above, the fault standard is part of the content ofsome of our duties to others; it does not mark out the class of

    individuals to whom I have a duty. The distinction between

    the scope and content of the duty of care is central to the

    American tort case, Palsgraf v. Long Island R.R.. Famously,Judge Cardozo argued that each of us has a duty to moderate

    our actions by taking into account only the interests of those

    who fall within the ambit of foreseeable risk. I have to guard

    against injuring those who fall within the zone of dangerassociated with my conduct. Others may be injured by what I

    do, and what I do may have been lamentable or mischievous,

    but those who fall outside the ambit of foreseeable risk have

    no claim in torts against me. They have no claim, not because

    I did not act badly or carelessly. Ex hypothesi, I have. Theyhave no claim against me because I did not wrong them. I did

    not wrong them because I had no duty to take their interests

    into account in regulating my conduct. This point cannot beemphasized enough. The only individuals who can in tortshave a claim against me are those to whom I have a duty of

    care. It is only with respect to those individuals that I must

    exercise reasonable care.

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    20/45

    The problem for economic analysis is that the duty restriction

    on liability is incompatible with the goal of inducing

    individuals to take appropriate precautions. In order to

    encourage injurers to take appropriate precautions, each must

    face the full costs of his activity. But the duty requirementallows injurers to displace at least some of the costs of their

    conduct, costs that efficiency requires them to internalize.

    This is one reason that economic analysis has no place for the

    duty requirement.

    Relatedly, tort law imposes the costs associated with the

    actual causal upshots of an individual's action. From an

    economic point of view, it is the risk of harm and not actualharm that should matter. One has to be careful not to

    misunderstand this point. Harms are of interest to the

    economic analyst. But the harms that matter from an

    economic point of view are the ones that have not yet

    occurred the ones that can be optimally avoided by

    inducing individuals to take proper precautions and not the

    harm that occasioned the case at hand. If what matters is

    reducing the incidence of future harms, then the main concernof economic analysis should be conduct that risks harm. Some

    conduct that risks harm actually causes harm as well, but not

    all conduct that risks harm does. Harm that has occurred is of

    interest only insofar as it provides reliable evidence of

    riskiness of the underlying conduct. In our tort practice,

    however, harm, not the risk of it, is a ground of liability and

    not merely an epistemic convenience. To the extent that the

    fact of harm is central to the practice of tort law and not anartifact of our limited epistemic capacities, the economicanalysis falls short.

    Finally, let us turn to the structure of tort law. Tort law has a

    bilateral structure. If the victim of another's mischief brings an

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    21/45

    action in torts, he brings it against the person he alleges has

    harmed him. In making out his case, the plaintiff argues that

    the defendant breached a duty of care owed to him, and that

    the breach has resulted in the harm of which he complains.

    From the normative point of view, the most basic relationshipin torts is that between the injurer and the victim whom he has

    wronged. From the economic point of view, the most basic

    relationship is that between each litigant, taken separately, and

    the goal of minimizing the sum of accident and accident

    avoidance costs. That is, economic analysis separates the

    injurer from the victim. The relevant normative questions are:

    (1) what is the relationship between the injurer's conduct and

    the goals of tort law (cost reduction), and (2) what is therelationship between the victim's conduct and the goals of tort

    law?

    The relationship between particular victims and injurers

    matters to economic analysis only insofar as features of it

    might provide evidence of the ability of either to reduce

    accident costs. Since the aim of accident law is optimally to

    reduce accident costs, the loss should be imposed on thatindividual who is in the best position to reduce costs at the

    lowest cost. This means that from an economic point of view,

    there is no reason why the victim should be suing the person

    he alleges injured him.

    5. Theories of Torts: Corrective Justice

    According to the principle of corrective justice, an individualwho has wronged another has a duty to repair the wrongful

    losses occasioned thereby. The corrective justice account thus

    illuminates not just the bilateral structure of tort litigation, but

    tort law's emphasis on harm caused rather than harm risked.

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    22/45

    Arguably, central to tort law is the moral notion of

    ownership , not the moral notion of blame . Tort law picks

    out a particular way of recognizing one's ownership of some

    of the untoward outcomes for which one is responsible. It

    does this by imposing a duty to make good the costs one'swrongs have imposed on those one has wronged. And so,

    rather than trying to determine whether the injurer has

    satisfied the conditions that would warrant blaming him for

    what he has done, tort law inquires into whether the injurer

    has satisfied conditions necessary to impose on him a duty to

    repair the plaintiff's loss. In short, the law asks whether the

    loss is attributable to him as his doing: whether, to use the

    currently fashionable phrase, he is outcome responsible forit. In the prevailing view, to be outcome responsible, the

    outcome must be foreseeable and avoidable.[2] This emphasis

    on the ascription of responsibility for outcomes rather than on

    ascriptions of blame or culpability makes sense within the

    corrective justice account of tort law in ways in which it

    would not within a traditional retributive view.

    According to economic analysis, all liabilities are simply oneor another cost. There is no significant normative difference

    among punishments, sanctions, duties of repair and taxes. All

    that matters is the way in which each impacts rational

    decision-making. But there are important normative

    differences among these kinds of costs that this crude picture

    misses. Tort law imposes a duty of repair, and while it is true

    that a person who is under a duty to act is constrained in the

    set of actions open to him, duties are neither punishments norsanctions. In contrast with tort law, criminal wrongdoers aresubject to punishment for their crimes, and while this means

    that they are not at liberty to prevent others from punishing

    them, they have no duty to be punished or to permit others to

    punish them.

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/notes.html
  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    23/45

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    24/45

    repair, not the duties of care that are the bases of those duties

    of repair. Though it grounds duties of repair, it does not

    mandate a mechanism by which those duties are to be

    discharged.

    It is tempting to think of corrective justice as a goal of tort law

    in the same way that economists think of efficiency or optimaldeterrence as a goal of tort law. The better view is that

    corrective justice is not a goal of the law in the way in which

    efficiency might be. Rather, corrective justice itself is a

    principle of justification; it seeks to articulate grounds upon

    which a certain category of duties rest. It claims that certain

    duties of repair or repayment are grounded on one'sresponsibility for them. The grounds of the duty to repair are:

    (1) the fact that one has a prior duty to take into account the

    interests of another and to mitigate one's own conduct

    accordingly; (2) the fact that one has failed to do so; (3) the

    fact that one's failure to do so results (in an appropriate way)

    in harm to another; and (4) the harm that results is one for

    which can be charged to an agent as his doing, or, in the

    contemporary jargon, for which he is outcome responsible. Noone claims that these grounds must be satisfied if ever an

    agent is to have a duty of repair or repayment. Corrective

    justice grounds some, but, very likely, not all of our duties of

    repair.

    If this is the way to think about corrective justice, how ought

    we think about its relationship to fault and strict liability? The

    question is whether the duties of repair and the conditionsunder which they arise in tort law are ones which are by and

    large grounded in the principle of corrective justice so

    conceived. As I argued above, both strict and fault liability in

    torts involve wrongs, that is, the breach of an underlying duty

    of care. The fault in fault liability is not a modifier of the

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    25/45

    character of the injurer but a constraint on the content of the

    underlying duty of care he owes the plaintiff. The difference

    between fault and strict liability standards is a difference in

    the nature of the content of the underlying duties we owe one

    another.

    In strict liability, the defendant is thought to owe the plaintiffa duty of the form A not to harm by X-ing. It is natural to

    think that the duty is absolute or unconstrained. But it is in

    fact constrained in several ways, and in each of the ways it is

    constrained, the duty in strict liability resonates with the

    conditions of a duty of repair in corrective justice. The blaster

    is liable strictly, not to everyone who is injured by hisconduct, but only to those to whom he owed a duty not to

    harm by blasting: those who fall within the ambit of

    foreseeable risk. Second, he is not liable to all those that he

    injures because he blasts, but only to those that are injured in

    the appropriate way by his blasting. In strict liability, there are

    the requirements of a wrong to a plaintiff (class), a harm, the

    appropriate causal connection between the two, and other

    elements of responsibility for the outcome, includingforseeability and avoidability.

    These same elements are present in all the classic cases of

    fault liability. The only difference, as we have noted, above is

    that in fault liability the content of the underlying duty not to

    harm differs from the duty in cases of strict liability. In fault,

    the duty is not to harm faultily, that is, negligently, recklessly

    or intentionally. In both the duty of repair requires the breachof a duty (a wrong), and responsibility for the outcome (the

    injury or harm being caused in the appropriate way by that

    aspect of the conduct that made it a wrong). Arguably, the

    duties imposed in tort law are paradigmatically duties of

    corrective justice. The bilateral structure of tort law and the

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    26/45

    pattern of practical reasoning embodied within it is

    transparent under the light of corrective justice, while cloudy

    at best, and mysterious at worst when viewed in the dim light

    of economic analysis. Moreover, the same principle explains

    both the structure and substance of tort law, and thus providesexplanatory economy as well as consistency.

    The corrective justice approach to tort law has been the object

    of serious criticism. I want to focus on three of the most

    important kinds of these. The first set of objections focuses on

    the concept of wrong at work in the principle of corrective

    justice. The second raises questions about the claim that

    corrective justice is a matter of justice. The third raisesbroader doubts about the claim that the goal or purpose of tort

    law is to achieve corrective justice. Let's consider these in

    turn.

    As I have characterized it, corrective justice sets out grounds

    upon which a certain category of duties of repair or repayment

    are justified. One of the grounds of a duty to repair is the

    existence of a wrong, that is, the breach of a duty of care toanother. One might say that whereas corrective justice

    theorists have been extremely concerned to specify

    appropriately the conditions under which it is fair to impose

    duties to avoid or prevent untoward consequences, they have

    offered precious little guidance regarding the actual duties to

    avoid or prevent harm that we owe to one another. This

    complaint has been expressed in two slightly different forms

    of criticism. The first is that to the extent that correctivejustice offers only an account of what ought to be done when

    some individuals wrong others and not an account of what

    constitutes a wrong in the relevant sense, the principle of

    corrective justice is empty or merely formal. The second is

    that since the principle of corrective justice appears to leave

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    27/45

    open what counts as a wrong, it may be that the wrongs that

    give rise to a duty of repair are merely the failures to take cost

    justified precautions, in which case the principle of corrective

    justice collapses into the principle of efficiency.[3] A related

    objection is that corrective justice offers us no way ofdetermining when a rule of strict liability is appropriately

    imposed and when a rule of fault liability is. In other words,

    corrective justice may tell us that strict and fault liability both

    involve the breach of a duty of care and that the difference

    between them concerns the content of the relevant duty, but it

    offers us no guidance as to why some activities call for the

    duty of care typified by strict liability whereas others call for a

    duty of care of the sort associated with fault liability. Ifnothing else, the economic analysis, as we have seen above,

    gives very clear guidance on this question.

    In one form or another, the first objection is by far the most

    pervasive objection to corrective justice accounts of tort law.

    Were it a sound objection, it would be devastating. In fact, it

    is not a serious objection, and rests on an important

    misunderstanding. There is in morality, as elsewhere, asignificant, if limited, division of labor. It is not the burden of

    corrective justice to explain the content of our duties not to

    harm others or to determine their scope. It is instead a

    principle that grounds some of the duties we incur in the event

    that we fail to comply with our duties not to harm others. We

    have a responsibility in general to mitigate our conduct by the

    impact it is likely to have on the interests of others. This is a

    matter of common sense morality and simple fairness. Thisgeneral duty we have to others is not itself a matter ofcorrective justice. Nor are the specific duties we have to

    particular persons to take into account the impact of our

    conduct on their interests in concrete ways matters of

    corrective justice. It is a good question of morality, just what

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/notes.html
  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    28/45

    it is we owe one another concretely in order to discharge our

    general obligations of fairness to one another. How must I

    mitigate my conduct in the light of your (presumably,

    legitimate) interests? And which of those interests must I take

    into account?

    One can hold the view that drawing up a list of such concreteduties is the task of moral philosophy. Others may hold that

    moral philosophy is unlikely to be able to provide us with a

    definitive list, that at least part of duties we have to others will

    depend on the practices we happen to have. In any case, these

    underlying duties are not themselves duties of repair; they are

    duties of care. It is not a burden of corrective justice toidentify or ground them.

    Quite the contrary, in fact. Once we have concrete

    requirements to take the interests of others into account in thisor that way in regulating our own affairs, we face the

    altogether different question of whether, and in what ways,

    the breach of these duties impacts the normative relationships

    between the parties . What, in other words, are the normativeconsequences of a breach? Here is where the principle of

    corrective justice makes its claim. It holds that in the event

    certain conditions attend the breach, a second order duty of

    repair exists. Whereas the underlying duties of care establish

    in part normative relations between the parties, the breach of

    such a duty creates a different but related normative

    relationship. Or so the principle of corrective justice claims

    We could adopt practices in which the losses suffered by

    victims as the result of the breach of some are to borne

    collectively by us all; or we could adopt practices in which the

    victims are left to bear their own costs. Or we could adopt a

    practice in which particular wrongdoers have the duty to make

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    29/45

    good the costs they have imposed. Or we could adopt some

    mixture of these responses, and others as well. In fact that is

    precisely what we do. If we adopt a practice of imposing a

    duty of repair on wrongdoers, such a practice is (were other

    conditions satisfied) defensible as a matter of correctivejustice.

    It is a further question whether commitment to the principle of

    corrective justice demands that we have such practices. It is

    one thing to claim that our practices of tort law the ones we

    actually have and not all logically possible ones are

    usefully or even best illuminated by a principle of corrective

    justice; quite another to claim that corrective justice requiresthat we have an institution of tort law that is, an institution

    that imposes legally enforceable duties of repair that could be

    defended on the grounds of corrective justice. The principle of

    corrective justice justifies some of the legally enforceable

    duties to repair we might incur. It does not claim that we

    suffer an injustice in the event we do not recognize such

    duties in our legal practices. So, for example, there is no

    reason to suppose that a no-fault scheme of liability foraccidentally imposed losses that distributes the costs of

    accidents through general tax coffers would be incompatible

    with corrective justice. Such an institutional arrangement is

    best seen as reflecting the idea that we are less concerned with

    the source of misfortune than with the urgency such

    misfortunes create for those who bear them.

    To be sure, there are differences between these cases. In theformer, no one may be responsible for the misfortune one

    suffers; in the latter case, someone is. Corrective justice

    embodies important moral values for it emphasizes not only

    the notion of misfortune and loss, but the idea that we owe

    duties of care to one another and the fact that some of the

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    30/45

    misfortunes that others suffer are our doing. Corrective justice

    connects us to our actions and the impact our actions have on

    others in ways in which other principles of justice, for

    example, distributive justice, do not. In arguing that corrective

    justice does not mandate a system of tort law I am not sayingthat nothing would be lost from the moral point of view.

    Whether something is lost depends on whether we elsewhere

    express in our institutional life and practices the moral values

    that are embodied in the principle of corrective justice. Those

    values can be expressed adequately in a range of formal and

    informal practices. They need not be expressed through a tort

    law. For what a tort law does is express those values in a

    particular way. It ties together one's duties to take into accountthe impact of one's conduct on others and one's responsibility

    for what happens to others in the event one fails to do so in a

    particular way, namely, by imposing a duty to make good the

    loss. We could separate the former from the latter, however.

    We could have practices of making formal apologies, of

    offering services or other forms of aid or restitution, while at

    the same time allocating the costs of misfortune more

    efficiently through a general tax coffer. If we have a tort

    system, it is not because such a system is mandated by

    corrective justice. If such a system it is defensible it is

    because, on balance, such a practice is a defensible way of

    expressing the values embodied in corrective justice and of

    doing so in ways that are cost effective and accident costavoiding, and so on.

    The second objection was that if the principle of corrective justice is compatible with an economic theory of theunderlying wrongs or duties of care we owe one another, then

    corrective justice is reduced to economic analysis. Whereas

    no set of underlying duties falls out of the principle of

    corrective justice, the principle constrains the set of duties that

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    31/45

    can be protected or secured by it. The general form of the

    constraint can be put abstractly. The underlying claims of

    right and duty sustained by the principle of corrective justice

    must be such that the imposition of a duty of repair

    occasioned by their breach are requirements of justice and notmerely something that we can provide good instrumental

    reasons for.

    It may be helpful to illustrate the general point by considering

    a different, and less controversial example (at least in this

    regard): that is, the relationship between criminal punishment

    and retributivism. Retributivism can only be plausible as an

    account of criminal punishment if the crimes identified by thelaw are the sort that makes it in general clear why punishing

    someone for them would be deserved. If, for example, there

    were no excuses in the criminal law if all liability to

    criminal sanction were strict in that sense and if only the

    most trivial offences were crimes, retributivism would be an

    implausible account of our criminal practices. The plausibility

    of retributivism as an account of criminal punishment depends

    on the conduct deemed criminal by the law and the conditionsof responsibility for those crimes being appropriate to an

    attribution of culpability or blame. This example illustrates

    two important points. First, no one criticizes retributivism as

    empty because it does not provide a full accounting of the

    wrongs for which punishment would be deserved. Second,

    even though it does not provide an accounting of the

    underlying wrongs for which punishment would be

    appropriate, it does constrain membership in that set.

    The same is true of corrective justice. While corrective justice

    is not a theory of the wrongs it rectifies, it can only make

    sense of tort law if in general the kinds of wrongs identified in

    torts are ones that must as a matter of justice be repaired.

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    32/45

    Another way to put this point is to say that even though

    corrective justice does not have nor must it provide a theory

    of the wrongs that are identified in torts, it in fact sets out

    what are the clear or paradigmatic cases of such wrongs. It

    clearly meets that requirement, for the wrongs it picks out asparadigmatic trespass against property, the intentional torts

    of battery and assault, negligent regard for the interests of

    others, and so on are the bread and butter of tort law.

    We can draw three conclusions from this discussion. First,

    corrective justice is not empty. It relies on the basic notion of

    a division of labor in moral theory. Within its domain, it is as

    substantive a principle as one can find. Second, it is notcompatible with all underlying theories of wrong. In fact it

    imposes significant constraints on what can fall within the

    class of wrongs for which repair can be a requirement of

    justice. Finally, it does not require another full theory of

    underlying wrongs in order to fill out its content. That is,

    because corrective justice identifies a set of paradigms of

    wrong compatible with it, the content of corrective justice

    does not depend on a full moral theory of wrongs. Rather, thenotion of a wrong compatible with corrective justice may be

    filled out by our practices of corrective justice including

    tort law.[4]

    We turn now to the question of whether corrective justice is

    an independent ideal of justice. Here the worry is that what

    makes corrective justice seem like a principle of justice

    undermines its claim to independence, and whatever supportsits independence undermines its claim to being a principle of

    justice. Corrective justice is a principle that requires

    correction in an underlying distribution of holdings. The

    wrongs that are the concern of corrective justice, one might

    think, are violations of duties we owe one another to respect

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/notes.html
  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    33/45

    the rights we have in those holdings. If those holdings are just,

    then corrective justice requires us to protect it. But in doing

    so, it does no more than return individuals to the positions to

    which they were entitled as a matter of distributive justice.

    Understood in this way, corrective justice is the ex postcomponent of distributive justice. That is, the claim to repair

    is a requirement of distributive, not corrective, justice. Or, put

    the other way, there is no independent principle of corrective

    justice. On the other hand, if the underlying distribution is not

    just, then corrective justice can sustain, enforce or entrench

    unjust distributions of resources. In that case, corrective

    justice is an independent principle, but it seeks to impose

    duties to support unjust institutions. Independent, yes, aprinciple of justice, no.

    In meeting this objection, corrective justice theorists have

    typically taken either of two approaches. The first is to

    identify the domain of distributive justice with the initial or

    underlying distribution of holdings and corrective justice with

    the norms governing the ex post transfer of those holdings.

    Corrective justice is a matter of transactional justice in thissense. Whatever the underlying distribution of holdings may

    be, we recognize legitimate and illegitimate means of

    transferring them. These are separate, if related, concerns. If

    agreement or gift moves resources from one person to

    another, that is a legitimate form of transfer. If the result is a

    more uneven or unfair overall distribution of resources, that is

    a concern of distributive, not transactional justice. Similarly,

    if fraud or force moves resources from one person to another,that is an illegitimate form of transfer. If the result is moreequitable from the point of view of distributive justice, that

    does not mean that the benefits and costs of the fraud ought

    not to not be annulled. They must be as a matter of

    transactional justice. And so on.

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    34/45

    One problem with this line of argument is that it explains the

    sense in which corrective justice is a principle of justice by

    drawing what may well be an artificial distinction between

    transactional and distributive justice. On most plausible views

    of distributive justice, it concerns the mechanisms andinstitutions of resource allocation including markets, and

    non-voluntary transfer practices. In other words, the

    mechanisms of transfer are part of distributive justice. So the

    distinction between the transactional and the distributive may

    be artificial at best.[5]

    The second solution is based on a distinction between the

    justice of a distribution and its legitimacy. A legitimatedistribution of resources may fall short of being a fully just

    one. While it may be true that no one can have a moral duty to

    repair losses when doing so merely entrenches a patently

    unjust distribution of resources, it is also not true that an

    individual can have a duty to repair losses only if doing so

    protects a less than fully just distribution of resources.

    Individuals can have duties to repair losses that support

    legitimate institutions for distributing holdings, and a systemof holdings can be legitimate even if it falls short of the

    demands of justice.

    Whereas a legitimate distribution of resources is adequate to

    confer on each individual a right against others for repair in

    the event of wrongful harm to his share, the legitimacy of the

    system of holdings does not confer on each individual a right

    against the government to prohibit redistribution. Indeed, thegovernment always has a right, indeed one could argue that it

    has a duty, to redistribute holdings if justice requires doing so.

    If a distribution is not just, the state can redistribute for the

    purposes of achieving justice without triggering claims to

    repair by those whose interests it hinders or harms. But a

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/notes.html
  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    35/45

    distribution that is legitimate if not fully just is adequate to

    ground private remedies in order to sustain the interests

    individuals have in their holdings and to secure their

    expectations accordingly.

    It is a further question what the standard of legitimacy is.

    What must be true of a distribution of holdings beforeprotecting or securing it by coercive rectificatory practices is

    permissible as a matter of justice? This is too big a topic to

    address here. We can say, though, that the notion of

    legitimacy I have in mind is the same as that which generally

    justifies coercion e.g. in the name of the criminal law in

    legitimate but not fully just states. If these conditions are notmet, we might nevertheless endorse practices of repair that

    protect holdings, but not as a matter of justice. Rather doing

    so might be desirable to increase security or as a step along

    the way to institutions that offer a legitimate promise of

    prosperity and equality, or the like. Duties of repair are always

    matters of correction , but they are not matters of corrective

    justice unless the conditions of legitimacy in the institutions

    of resource allocation are satisfied.[6]

    We come finally to one last objection to the corrective justice

    account of tort law. Here the worry is that if achieving

    corrective justice were the concern of tort law, then

    prosecuting wrongful conduct would be the province of the

    state. In fact, the state's role in torts is primarily a passive one.

    Tort law gives victims an option to pursue redress. The law

    does not aim to achieve justice; it merely provides amechanism for victims to pursue redress. If tort law meant to

    promote justice, it would more actively pursue wrongdoers

    and prosecute cases against them. Victims would be

    encouraged to appear as witnesses in such prosecutions, and

    because they have an interest in having the prosecutions

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/notes.html
  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    36/45

    succeed, they would do so. But victims are the prosecutors in

    torts, not witnesses for the prosecution. On this view, if we

    want to understand tort law, we need to uncover the reasons

    we might have for providing victims with opportunities for

    pursuing the particular form of redress tort law gives.[7]

    This is an interesting line of argument, and I cannot give it thecare it warrants here. I would note, however, that one

    response would begin by acknowledging that at bottom tort

    law provides victims with a form of redress. The particular

    form of redress it provides, however, is what one would

    expect as a matter of corrective justice. Beyond that, the

    reason the law does not prosecute on a victim's behalf or onthe behalf of the principle of corrective justice, may have

    more to do with considerations of personal autonomy and

    privacy than it has to do with the underlying aims of tort law.

    That is, there are constraints on political power that limit the

    authority of the state to sue on behalf of an unwilling victim.

    It may be that the most the state can do consistent with respect

    for personal autonomy and privacy is to provide victims with

    the opportunity to seek repair and to insure that warrantedclaims to repair are enforceable by the law. Lastly, we want to

    distinguish between the claim that the law of torts embodies a

    principle of corrective justice and the very different claim that

    tort law aims to achieve or pursue corrective justice. Tort law

    may have no such aims; it may have no aims at all. But it

    would be a mistake to infer that tort law does not embody a

    principle of corrective justice, or that it is best explained,

    therefore, by the principle of corrective justice.

    Bibliography

    Abel, Richard, 1990, "A Critique of Torts." UCLA LawReview 37, 785.

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/tort-theories/notes.html
  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    37/45

    Benson, Peter, 1995, "The Basis for Excluding Liabilityfor Economic Loss in Tort Law." PhilosophicalFoundations of Tort Law. Ed. David G. Owen. Oxford:Clarendon Press.

    Calabresi, Guido, 1975, "Concerning Cause and the Lawof Torts." University of Chicago Law Review 43, 69-108.

    ------, 1970, The Costs of Accidents: A Legal andEconomic Analysis. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    ------, 1961, "Some Thoughts On Risk Distribution AndThe Law Of Torts." Yale Law Journal70, 499.

    Calabresi, Guido, and A. Douglas Melamed, 1972,"Property Rules, Liability Rules and Inalienability."

    Harvard Law Review 85, 1089. Calabresi, Guido, and Jon T. Hirschoff, 1972, "Toward a

    Test for Strict Liability in Torts." Yale Law Journal85,1055.

    Chapman, Bruce, 2001, "Pluralism in Tort and AccidentLaw: Towards a Reasonable Accommodation."

    Philosophy and the Law of Torts. Ed. Gerald Postema.

    New York: Cambridge University Press. ------, 1995, "Wrongdoing, Welfare, and Damages:

    Recovery for Non-Pecuniary Loss in Corrective Justice."

    in Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law. David G.

    Owen (ed.), Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Christie, George C., 1995, "The Uneasy Place ofPrinciple in Tort Law." in Philosophical Foundations ofTort Law. David G. Owen (ed.), Oxford: Clarendon

    Press. Coleman, Jules., 1982, "Corrective Justice And Wrongful

    Gain."J. Legal Studies 11, 421-440. ------, 1988, Markets, Morals, and the Law, Cambridge:

    Cambridge University Press.

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    38/45

    ------, 1992, "The Mixed Conception Of CorrectiveJustice."Iowa L.Review 77, 427.

    ------, 1982, "Moral Theories of Torts: Their Scope andLimits: Part I."Law and Philosophy 1, 371.

    ------, 1995, "The Practice of Corrective Justice." inPhilosophical Foundations of Tort Law. David G. Owen(ed.), Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    ------, 2001, The Practice of Principle, Oxford: OxfordUniversity Press.

    ------, 1987, "Property, Wrongfulness, and the Duty toCompensate." Chcago-Kent L. Rev 63, 451.

    ------, 1992a, Risks and Wrongs. New York: CambridgeUniversity Press.

    ------, 1992b, "Tort Law and the Demands of CorrectiveJustice,"Indiana Law Review 67, 349.

    ------, 1992c, "Tort Law and Tort Theory: PreliminaryReflections on Method." in Philosophy and the Law ofTorts. Gerald Postema (ed.), New York: CambridgeUniversity Press.

    Coleman, Jules, and Arthur Ripstein, 1995, "Mischiefand Misfortune," McGill Law Journal41, 91.

    Cooper-Stephenson, Ken, 1993, "Corrective Justice,Substantive Equality, and Tort Law." in Tort Theory.

    Ken Cooper-Stephenson and Elaine Gibson (eds.),

    Toronto: Captus Press.

    ------, 1993, "Economic Analysis, Substantive Equality,and Tort Law." in Tort Theory. Ken Cooper-Stephenson

    and Elaine Gibson (eds.), Toronto: Captus Press. Englard, Izhak, 1995, "The Idea of Complementarity as a

    Philosophical Basis for Pluralism in Tort Law." in

    Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law. David G. Owen

    (ed.), Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    39/45

    ------, 1993, The Philosophy of Tort Law. Aldershot:Dartmouth Publishing Company.

    Epstein, Richard A., 1979, "Causation and CorrectiveJustice. A Reply to Two Critics."J. Legal Studies 8, 477-

    504. ------, 1973, "A Theory of Strict Liability." J. Legal

    Studies 2, 151-204.

    Finnis, John, 1995, "Intention in Tort Law." inPhilosophical Foundations of Tort Law. David G. Owen(ed.), Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Fletcher, George P., 1972, "Fairness and Utility in TortTheoery,"Harvard Law Review 85, 537.

    Gardner, John, 2001, "Obligations and Outcomes in theLaw of Torts." in Relating to Responsibility: Essays for

    Tony Honore. Peter Cane and John Gardner (eds.),Oxford: Hart Publishing.

    Geistfeld, Mark, 2001, "Economics, Moral Philosophy,and the Positive Analysis of Tort Law." in Philosophy

    and the Law of Torts. Gerald Postema (ed.), New York:

    Cambridge University Press. Goldberg, John, 1997, "Misconduct, Misfortune, and Just

    Compensation: Weinstein on Torts." Columbia Law

    Review 97, 2034.

    ------, 2002, "Twentieth Century Tort Theories." Geo.Law Journal90.

    Goldberg, John, and Ben Zipursky, 1998, "The Moral ofMacPherson." University of Pennsylvania Law Review

    146, 1733. ------, 2001, "The Restatement (Third) and the Place of

    Duty in Negligence Law." Vanderbilt Law Review 54,657.

    ------, 2002, "Unrealized Torts." Virginia Law Review 88,1625.

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    40/45

    Gordley, James, 1995, "Tort Law in the AristotelianTradition." in Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law.David G. Owen (ed.), Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Green, Leon, 1960, "Foreseeability in Negligence Law."Columbia Law Review 61, 1401.

    Honore, Tony, 1995, Foundations of Tort Law. Oxford:Clarendon.

    ------, 1995, "The Morality of Tort Law Questions andAnswers." in Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law.David G. Owen (ed.), Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    ------, 1995, "Necessary and Sufficient Conditions in TortLaw." in Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law. David

    G. Owen (ed.), Oxford: Clarendon Press. Kaplow, Louis, and Steven Shavell, 2002, Fairness

    versus Welfare. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Keating, Gregor, 2001,. Social Contract Concept of the

    Tort Law of Accidents. in Philosophy and the Law ofTorts. Gerald Postema (ed.), New York: CambridgeUniversity Press.

    Keeton, Robert E., 1962, "Creative Continuity in the Lawof Torts,"Harvard Law Review 75, 463.

    Kress, Ken, 1995, "The Seriousness of Harm Thesis forAbnormally Dangerous Activities." in Philosophical

    Foundations of Tort Law. David G. Owen (ed.), Oxford:Clarendon Press.

    Owen, David G., 1985, "Deterrence and Desert in Tort:A Comment." Cal. L. Rev. 73, 665.

    ------, 1989, "The Moral Foundations of PunitiveDamages."Alabama Law Review 40, 705.

    ------, 1995, "Philosophical Foundations of Fault in TortLaw, in Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law. David

    G. Owen (ed.), Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    41/45

    ------, 1995, "Why Philosophy Matters to Tort Law." inPhilosophical Foundations of Tort Law. David G. Owen(ed.), Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Perry, Stephen, 1992, "Comment on Coleman:Corrective Justice,"Indiana Law Journal67, 381-409.

    ------, 1996, "The Distributive Turn: Mischief,Misfortune, and Tort Law," Quinnipiac Law Review 16,

    315-38.

    ------, 1988, "The Impossibility of General StrictLiability, Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 1,147-71.

    ------, 1993, "Loss, Agency, and Responsibility forOutcomes: Three Conceptions of Corrective Justice." inTort Theory. Ken Cooper-Stephenson and Elaine Gibson(eds.), Toronto: Captus Press.

    ------, 1992, "The Mixed Conception of CorrectiveJustice," Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy 15,917-38.

    ------, 1992, "The Moral Foundations of Tort Law,"IowaLaw Review 77, 449-514.

    ------, 2000, "On the Relationship between Correctiveand Distributive Justice," in J. Horder, ed., Oxford

    Essays in Jurisprudence, Fourth Series, Oxford:

    Clarendon Press.

    ------, 2001, "Responsibility for Outcomes, Risks, and theLaw of Torts," in Postema 2001 (see below).

    ------, 1995, "Risk, Harm, and Responsibility." in

    Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law. David G. Owen(ed.), Oxford: Clarendon Press. ------, 1996, "Tort Law." in Companion to the Philosophy

    of Law and Legal Theory. Dennis Patterson (ed.),

    Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    42/45

    Polinsky, A. Mitchell, and Steven Shavell, 1994, "ShouldLiability Be Based on the Harm to the Victim or the Gain

    to the Injurer?" Journal of Law, Economics, andOrganization 10, 427-437.

    Posner, Richard A., 1981, "The Concept of CorrectiveJustice in Recent Theories of Tort Law," Journal ofLegal Studies 10, 187.

    ------, 1972, "A Theory of Negligence." J. Legal Studies1, 29.

    ------, 1995, "Wealth Maximization and Tort Law: APhilosophical Inquiry." in Philosophical Foundations of

    Tort Law. David G. Owen (ed.), Oxford: Clarendon

    Press. Postema, Gerald, ed., 2001, Philosophy and the Law of

    Torts. New York: Cambridge University Press. Rabin, Robert, ed., 1995, Perspectives on Tort Law. 3rd

    ed. Boston: Little Brown.

    Ripstein, Arthur, 1994, "Equality, Luck, andResponsibility."Philosophy and Public Affairs 23, 3-23.

    ------, 1998, Equality, Responsibility, and the Law.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    ------, 2002, "Private Law and Private Narratives."Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 20, 683-702.

    ------, 2000, "Three Duties to Rescue." Law andPhilosophy 19, 751-779.

    ------, 2001, "Torts." The Oxford Handbook ofJurisprudence and Legal Philosophy. Jules Coleman and

    Scott Shapiro (eds.), Oxford: Oxford University Press. Ripstein, Arthur, and Benjamin Zipursky, 2001,

    "Corrective Justice in an Age of Mass Torts." in

    Philosophy and the Law of Torts. Gerald Postema (ed.),

    New York: Cambridge University Press.

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    43/45

    Schwartz, Gary T., 1978, "Contributory and ComparativeNegligence: A Reappraisal." Yale Law Journal87, 697-727.

    ------, 1983, "Deterrence and Punishment in the CommonLaw of Punitive Damages." Southern California LawReview 56, 796-852.

    ------, 1990, "The Ethics and Economics of Tort LiabilityInsurance." Cornell Law Review 76, 313-365.

    ------, 1997, "Mixed Theories of Tort Law: AffirmingBoth Deterrence and Corrective Justice." Texas LawReview, 75, 1801-1834.

    ------, 1994, "Reality in the Economic Analysis of TortLaw: Does Tort Law Really Deter?" UCLA Law Review42, 377-444.

    ------, 1981, "The Vitality of Negligence and the Ethicsof Strict Liability." Georgia Law Review 15, 963-1004.

    Shavell, Steven, 1980, "An Analysis of Causation andthe Scope of Liability in the Law of Torts." Journal of

    Legal Studies 9, 463-516.

    ------, 1998, "Causation and Tort Liability." in The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics and the Law. PeterNewman (ed.), New York: Stockton Press.

    ------, 1987, Economic Analysis of Accident Law.Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    ------, 1984, "Liability for Harm versus Regulation ofSafety."Journal of Legal Studies 13, 357-374.

    ------, 1980, "Strict Liability versus Negligence."Journal

    of Legal Studies 9, 1-25. ------, 1983, "Torts in Which Victim and Injurer Act

    Sequentially." Journal of Law and Economics 26, 589-612.

    Simons, Kenneth W., 1995, "Contributory Negligence:Conceptual and Normative Issues." in Philosophical

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    44/45

    Foundations of Tort Law. David G. Owen (ed.), Oxford:Clarendon Press.

    ------, 1990, "Corrective Justice and Liability for RiskCreation: A Comment," UCLA Law Review 38, 113.

    ------, 1996, "Deontology, Negligence, Tort, and Crime."Boston University Law Review 76, 273.

    ------, 1992, "Jules Coleman and Corrective Justice inTort Law: A Critique and Reformulation," HarvardJournal of Law and Public Policy 15, 849.

    Stone, Martin, 2001, "The Significance of Doing andSuffering." in Philosophy and the Law of Torts. Gerald

    Postema (ed.), New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Street, Thomas A., 1999, The Theory and Principles ofTort Law. Washinton, D.C.:Beard.

    Weinrib, Ernest J., 1980, "The Case for a Duty toRescue." Yale Law Journal90, 247.

    ------, 1987, "Causation and Wrongdoing," Chicago-KentLaw Review 63, 407.

    ------, 1992, "Corrective Justice," Iowa Law Review 77,403

    ------, 1995, "The Gains and Losses of CorrectiveJustice,"Duke Law Review 44, 277-97.

    ------, 1995, The Idea of Private Law. Cambridge:Harvard University Press.

    ------, 1989, "Right and Advantage in Private Law,"Cardoza Law Review 10, 1283.

    ------, 1988, "The Special Morality of Tort Law," McGill

    Law Journal34, 403. ------, 2002, Tort Law. Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing. ------, 1989, "Understanding Tort Law," Valparaiso Law

    Review 23, 485.

    Williams, Bernard, 1995, "What Has Philosophy toLearn From Tort Law?" inPhilosophical Foundations of

  • 8/7/2019 theroies of tort

    45/45

    Tort Law. David G. Owen (ed.), Oxford: ClarendonPress.

    Wright, Richard W., 1985, "Causation in Tort Law."California Law Review 73, 1737-1828.

    ------, 1995, "Rights, Justice, and Tort Law." inPhilosophical Foundations of Tort Law. David G. Owen(ed.), Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    ------, 1995, "The Standards of Care in Negligence Law."in Philosophical Foundations of Tort Law. David G.Owen (ed.), Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Zipursky, Benjamin, 1998, "Rights, Wrongs, andRecourse in the Law of Torts." Vanderbilt Law Review

    51, 1-100.

    Other Internet Resources

    Tort Law & Unjust Enrichment, Links to relevant articlesfrom the Encyclopedia of Law and Economics, supported

    by the Economic Institute/CIAV of Utrecht University

    and the Department of General Jurisprudence and

    History of Law, University of Ghent.

    Related Entries

    causation: in the law |justice: distributive | legal philosophy:

    economic analysis of law | privacy

    Copyright 2003 by

    Jules Coleman

    http://allserv.rug.ac.be/~gdegeest/tablebib.htmhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/legal-econanalysis/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/privacy/http://plato.stanford.edu/info.htmlhttp://plato.stanford.edu/info.htmlhttp://plato.stanford.edu/info.htmlmailto:jules.coleman%40yale.eduhttp://plato.stanford.edu/info.htmlhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/privacy/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/legal-econanalysis/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/legal-econanalysis/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/justice-distributive/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/causation-law/http://allserv.rug.ac.be/~gdegeest/tablebib.htm