The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

download The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

of 27

description

Los estándares de cuidado en la negligencia

Transcript of The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 1 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    UniversityPressScholarshipOnlineOxfordScholarshipOnline

    ThePhilosophicalFoundationsofTortLawDavidG.Owen

    Printpublicationdate:1997PrintISBN-13:9780198265795PublishedtoOxfordScholarshipOnline:March2012DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198265795.001.0001

    TheStandardsofCareinNegligenceLawRICHARDW.WRIGHT

    DOI:10.1093/acprof:oso/9780198265795.003.0012

    AbstractandKeywords

    Thischapterchallengestheutilitariansclaimwithrespecttothestandardsofcareinnegligencelaw.Negligenceliabilityisthemostcommontypeoftortliabilityandisthoughttobethemostobviousexampleoftortlawsutilitarianfoundation.Iftheutilitarianefficiencytheorycannotexplainnegligenceliabilityitsprimedoctrinalexampleinitsfavoritefieldofcommon-lawliabilityitisinveryserioustrouble.Conversely,iftheequalfreedomtheorycanexplainandjustifynegligenceliability,itwillhaveclearedwhatmanyseeasthebiggesthurdleforanon-utilitariantheoryoftortliability.Negligenceisgenerallydescribedasbehaviourthatcreatesunreasonableforeseeablerisksofinjury.Almostalljuryinstructionsdonotprovideanytestordefinitionofwhatconstitutesunreasonablyriskybehavior,otherthananoftencircularreferencetotheordinarycarethatwouldbeexercisedbythereasonableorprudentpersoninthesameorsimilarcircumstances.

    Keywords:utilitarian,standards,care,negligencelaw,liability,tortlaw,equalfreedom,riskybehavior,

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 2 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    injury

    I.MoralFoundationsInaprioressayinthiscollection,IarguedthattheKantian-Aristoteliantheoryoflegalresponsibility,basedonthefoundationalnormofequalindividualfreedom,isnormativelymuchmoreattractivethanitsmaincompetitor,theutilitarianefficiencytheory.Accordingtotheequalfreedomtheory,eachhumanbeinghasanabsolutemoralworthasafreeandequalmemberofthecommunity.Thus,thecommongoodtowhichlawandpoliticsshouldbedirectedisnotthemeaninglessmaximizationoftheaggre-gateutilityorwelfareofthesocietyasawhole,asassumedbytheutilitarianefficiencytheory,butratherthecreationofconditionsthatalloweachpersontorealizehisorherhumanityasaself-legislatingfreerationalbeing.1

    Thelegaleconomistsgenerallydonotcontesttherelativenormativeunattractivenessoftheutilitarianefficiencytheory.Theyusuallyacknowledgethatutilitarianefficiencycanbeatbestasecondarygoalthatisconstrainedbydistinctmorallyjustifiablegoalsmoreparticularly,thepursuitofjustice.However,theyexplicitlyorimplicitlyassumethatthisconstraintisminimal.2Theyalsoarguethat,althoughtheutilitarianefficiencytheorymayappeartobenormativelyunattractive,itseemstobethemoraltheorythatactuallyunderliesourlawandpolitics,sinceitallegedlybest(orevensolely)explainsthecontentofourexistinglaws,particularlytortlaw.3

    (p.250) Inmyprioressay,Ichallengedtheutilitariansdescriptiveclaimprimarilyonthegloballevel.IelaboratedtheKantianconceptofRightanditscorollaryAristotelianconceptsofdistributiveandcorrectivejusticeandarguedthattheseconceptsexplain,justify,andilluminatethegeneralstructureoftortlawanditstraditionalstatusasthepreferredliabilityregimeforinterpersonalinjury.Inthisessay,Ichallengetheutilitariansclaimwithrespecttothestandardsofcareinnegligencelaw.Negligenceliabilityisthemostcommontypeoftortliabilityandisthoughttobethemostobviousexampleoftortlawsutilitarianfoundation.Iftheutilitarianefficiencytheorycannotexplainnegligenceliabilityitsprimedoctrinalexampleinitsfavoritefieldofcommon-lawliabilityitisinveryserioustrouble.Conversely,iftheequalfreedomtheorycanexplainandjustifynegligenceliability,itwillhaveclearedwhatmanyseeasthebiggesthurdleforanonu-tilitariantheoryoftortliability.

    II.TheUnworkabilityoftheUtilitarianHandFormulaNegligenceisgenerallydescribedasbehaviorthatcreatesunreasonableforeseeablerisksofinjury.Almostalljuryinstructions,thevastmajorityofjudicialopinions,andmanysecondarysourcesdonotprovideanytestordefinitionofwhatconstitutesunreasonablyriskybehavior,otherthananoftencircularreferencetotheordinarycarethatwouldbeexercisedbythereasonableorprudentpersoninthesameorsimilarcircumstances.4

    Legalscholarsarelessreticent.Thereisanalmostuniversalassumptionamonglegalscholarsthatapersonsconductisdeemedunreasonable,andhencenegligent,ifandonlyiftheforeseeableriskscreatedbysuchconductexceeditsexpectedsocialutility.5Thisaggregaterisk-utilitytestofreasonablenesswasmostexplicitlyarticulatedinJudge

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 3 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    LearnedHandsfamousformulainUnitedStatesv.CarrollTowingCo.:apersonsconductXisunreasonableonlyifPtimesLisgreaterthanB,wherePistheprobabilityofaninjuryoccurring,Listhemagnitudeoftheinjury,andBistheexpectedbenefitofengaginginconductXor,conversely,theexpectedburdenorcostthatwouldhavetobebornetoavoidengaginginconductX.6

    TheassumedprevalenceofHandsrisk-utilityformulaastheoperativetestofreasonablenessinnegligenceisdeemedtobethestrongestevidence(p.251) oftheutilitarianefficiencyfoundationoftortlaw.Undertheutilitarianefficiencytheory,conductisefficient(hencereasonableandnotnegligent)ifitmaximizesthetotalsumofexpectedbenefitsminuscosts;itdoesnotmatterwhobearsthecostsandwhogainsthebenefits.TheHandformulaseemsperfectlytoreflectthisview.However,thereareinsurmountableproblemswiththeHandformulaevenundertheutilitarianefficiencytheory.

    Theproblemsarebothdescriptiveandanalytic.Inordertoidentifytheefficientlevelsofprecaution,onemustfocusonmarginalincrementsincostsandbenefitsattributabletomarginalincrementsinprecaution,ratherthanthetotalcostsandbenefitsofsomeparticularsuggestedprecaution.7Yetitishighlydoubtfulthatcourtsengagein,orareevencapableofengagingin,suchmarginalanalysis.8

    Moresignificantly,evenpropermarginalanalysiswillnotidentifytheefficientlevelsofprecautionwhentheHandformulaisappliedseparately(asitmustbe)totheconductofthedefendantandtheplaintiff.Forexample,assumethata$100losstotheplaintiffcouldhavebeenavoidedby(1)aunilateral$40precautionbythedefendant,(2)aunilateral$60precautionbytheplaintiff,or(3)abilateral$15precautionbythedefendantand$15precautionbytheplaintiff.Asisalmostalwaysthecaseinpractice,themostefficient(leasttotalcost)optionisthethird,whichrequiresbilateralprecautionbybothpartiesratherthanunilateralprecautionbyoneortheother.Yet,applyingtheHandformulaseparatelytoeachpartysconduct,thedefendantwouldbedeemednegligentifshedidnotadoptoption(1),sinceher$40precautionwouldhaveavoideda$100loss,andtheplaintiffwouldbedeemednegligentifhedidnotadoptoption(2),sincehis$60precautionwouldhaveavoideda$100loss.Underthetraditionalnegligenceliabilityrule,accordingtowhichtheplaintiffcannotrecoverifheiscon-tributorilynegligent,thedefendantwillnottakeanyprecaution,sincesheknowstheplaintiffeitherwilladoptoption(2),inwhichcasetherewillbenolossandhencenoliability,orwillnotadoptoption(2)andbebarredfromrecoveringanydamagesduetohiscontributorynegligence.Theplaintiff,knowingthatthedefendanthasno(economic)reasontotakeanyprecaution,willadoptoption(2)i.e.,spend$60toavoidthe$100loss.UsingtheHandformulatodeterminethenegligenceofthepartiesrespectiveconductthusleadstotheleastefficientoptionbeingchosen,ratherthanthemostefficientoption.

    TheHandformulawillidentifytheefficientprecautionlevelforoneofthepartiesonlyifitisappliedusingtherisks,burdens,andbenefitsthat(p.252) wouldbeexpectediftheotherpartywereexercisinghisorherefficientlevelofprecautionasolutionblithelyassumedbythelegaleconomists.9However,thissolutionishopelesslycircular:

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 4 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    identifyingthefirstpartysefficientprecautionlevelrequiresfirstknowingthesecondpartysefficientprecautionlevel,butthesecondpartysefficientprecautionlevelcanbeidentifiedonlyifthefirstpartysefficientprecautionlevelisknown,andsoonaroundthecircle.

    Thus,fromthestandpointofutilitarianefficiency,theHandformulamustbeabandoned.NegligencemustbedefinednotasafailuretosatisfytheHandformula,butratherasafailuretoadopttheefficientlevelofprecaution.Asintheaboveexample,thisefficientlevelcanonlybeidentifiedbyconsideringalltheexpectedcostsandbenefitstothedefendantandtheplaintiff(andothers)ofallthepossiblecombinationsofprecautionbythedefendantandtheplaintiff(andothers)andthenchoosingtheleastcostoption.Yet,asHandhimselfnoted,inpracticeitwillbeimpossibletotakeintoaccountmorethanafewoptionsandtheirexpectedcostsandbenefits,andevenfortheseoptionstheexpectedcostsandbenefitsgenerallycannotbeestimated.10Attemptingtocalculateandenforceefficientprecautionlevelsbasedonsuchhighlyimperfectinformationmayverywellleadtogreaterinefficiencyratherthangreaterefficiency,evenassuming(contrarytotheusualsituation)thatsomedeterminateanswerissuggestedbytheavailable(imperfect)information.11

    III.NonutilitarianAttemptstoJustifytheHandFormulaAlthoughthelegaleconomistsaggregaterisk-utilityinterpretationofnegligence,especiallyasembodiedintheHandformula,isunderminedbymajortheoreticalandpracticalproblems,almostalllegalscholars,includingthosecriticaloftheutilitarianefficiencytheory,assumeitisdescriptivelycorrect.Criticsofutilitarianefficiencygenerallyhaveattemptedtoconstructnon-utilitarianargumentstoexplainandjustifythesupposeduseoftheaggregaterisk-utilityformulainnegligenceandothertortcases.TheyrelyexplicitlyorimplicitlyonthefundamentalKantianmoraldutytorespecttheequalabsolutemoralworthofyourselfandothersasrational(human)beings.Thisdutyisassumedtorequirethatinallyouractionsyoumustweightheinterestsofothersequallywithyourown,whichleadsimmediatelyandinevitablytotheaggregaterisk-utilityconceptionofreasonablenessandnegligence.

    (p.253) Forexample,RonaldDworkin,whilenotexplicitlyinvokingKants(oranyother)moraltheory,attemptstoexplaintheassumeduseoftheaggregaterisk-utilityformulainnegligenceandprivatenuisancecasesbyarguingthatinsuchcasestherearecompetingclaimsofabstractright(alsomoreaccuratelydescribedasmereinterests)whichmustberesolvedbyusingthebasicprincipleofequalconcernandrespecttocompromisethecompetingclaimssoastomaximizethecollectiveutilityoftheparties.12Similarly,ErnestWeinrib,explicitlyrelyingonKantianmoraltheory,assumesthatthecategoricalimperative,whichrequiresonetoactinaccordwithamaximthatonewouldadoptasanequalmemberofthekingdomofends,forbidsanyself-preferenceinconceptionoraction.Heargued,untilrecently,thatthisallegedrequirementofcompleteimpartialityofinterestmandatesanobjectivecomparisonofinterestsconceptionofreasonablenessforbothdefendantsandplaintiffs.13CharlesFriedalsopurportstofindinKantianmoralityarequirementofcompleteimpartiality,whichheatonetimeusednotonlytojustifythe

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 5 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    aggregaterisk-utilityconceptionofnegligencebutalsotoconstructasocialriskpoolfromwhichpersonssupposedlycandraw,withincertainunclearlimits,toexposeotherstominorormajorrisk.14

    Thesearguments,althoughmeanttobenon-utilitarian,arebaseddirectlyontheutilitarianconceptionofequality,accordingtowhichtreatingpeopleasequalssimplymeanscountingeachpersonsinterestsequallywhilemaximizingthetotalsatisfactionofinterests.ThisconceptionofequalityisdirectlyopposedtotheKantianconceptionofequalindividualfreedom,accordingtowhicheachindividualmustalwaysbetreatedasanendinhimselfratherthansolelyasameanstothesatisfactionoftheinterestsofothers.KantsdoctrineofRightmandatesproperrespectfortheequalabsolutemoralworthofothersbyrequiringaslegalaswellasethicaldutiesthatresourcesbedistributedtopromoteeachpersonsequal(p.254) positivefreedom(distributivejustice)andthatconductwhichmightaffectanotherpersonsexistingstockofresourcesbeconsistentwiththatothersequalnegativefreedom(correctivejustice).Kantsdoctrineofvirtuerequiresasasolelyethicaldutyproperconcernfortheequalabsolutemoralworthofothersaswellasyourselfbymakingtheirhappinessoneofyourownends.Itdoesnot,however,requirethatyouweighothersinter-estsequallywithyourownineverythingyoudo.Sucharequirementwouldcompletelyundermineindividualautonomyandfreedom,15

    Althoughheisanon-utilitarianmoraltheorist,GeorgeFletcherusuallyequatesreasonablenessintortlawwithutilitarianefficiency.Inanearlyarticle,hearguedthatnegligenceandtortiousconductingeneralshouldbeunderstoodintermsofanon-utilitarianparadigmofnon-reciprocalrisk-creationandlackofexcuse,asanallegedimplementationoftherighttoequalsecuritythatisembodiedincorrectivejustice,ratherthanintermsoftheutilitarianefficiencyparadigmofreasonableness.16Now,however,Fletcheracceptstheutilitarianefficiencyinterpretationofnegligence.Heclaimsthatacollaborativeprincipleunderliesthelawofnegligence:Byenteringintocertainspheresofrisk-taking,plaintiffanddefendantbothcomeunderdutiestoactwithaviewtothe[aggregate]costsandbenefitsoftheiractions.Theybecomeaunit,actingunderanimplicitobligationtooptimizethe[aggregate]consequencesoftheiractionsandhaveashareddutytofindtheoptimallevelofharmfulactivities.17

    EthicofcarefeministssuchasLeslieBendertravelthesamepathasDworkin,Weinrib,Fried,andFletcher,althoughtheyseemunawareofthedestinationtowardwhichtheyaretravelingandmightbeshockedtolearnoftheirtravelingcompanions.Benderequatesthereasonablenessstandardinnegligenceand,moregenerally,theliberalconceptsofreason,autonomy,rights,equality,fairness,andjusticewithamasculineethicofantisocial,self-interested,wealth-based,dehumanizingutilitariancalculation.Sheseekstoreplacethereasonablenessstandardanditsmasculineethicwithafeminineethicofcareandconcernfortheneedsandwelfareofothers,accordingtowhichapersonincasesofbothmisfeasance(puttingothersatrisk)andnonfeasance(failuretoprotectothersfromrisksyoudidnotcreate)shouldbeheldtoalegalstandardofconsciouscareandconcernofaresponsibleneighbororsocialacquaintanceforanother

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 6 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    underthesameorsimilarcircumstances.18

    (p.255) BendersfeminineethicofcaremightwellbelesscaringthanthecompleteimpartialityrequirementespousedbyDworkin,Weinrib,Fried,Fletcher,andthe(mostlymale)utilitarianefficiencytheorists,accordingtowhichothersinterestsandwelfaremustalwaysbetreatedasbeingequallyasimportantasyourown.Recognizingthatweallcaredifferentlyforfamilyandfriendsthanwedoforstrangersandthatwecouldnotpossiblyhavetheenergytocareabouteverypersonaswedoourchildrenorlovers,Benderprescribesvaryinglevelsofrequiredcaredependingontheclosenessoftherelationship.19Yet,givenherrejectionofthemasculinenotionsofautonomyandself-interestandheremphasisonthefeminineethicofcareandconcernfortheneedsandwelfareofallothers,itisnotatallclearhowshecouldjustifysuchpreferredtreatmentforonesfamilyorfriends(oroneself).Conversely,assumingavariablestandardbasedonclosenessofrelationship,sheseemsunabletojustifyherproposedrequirementthattheconcernappropriateforneighborsandacquaintancesmustalsobeaffordedtostrangers.

    Theproposeddisplacementofthemasculineethicofreason,autonomy,rights,equality,fairness,andjusticebyafeminineethicofcareandconcernforotherswouldseemtobe,asfeministssuchasCatharineMacKinnonandMargaretRadinhaveargued,atrapforwomenespeciallysince,beingafeminineratherthanamasculineethic,itapparentlywouldonlyapplytowomen.20Inarecentarticle,Benderseemstoacknowledgethisproblem.Shenowstatesthatreasonhasitsplaceintortlaw,butthatreasonisaricheranddeeperconceptthantortlawhashistoricallyacknowledged,andsheurgestheusefulnessofthereason/careparadigminsuggestingreconceptualizationsthatmakelawmorereflectiveofhumanexperienceandmoreresponsivetoconcernsofjustice.21

    IV.TheEqualFreedomStandardsofCareIfBenderwerefurthertoinvestigateKantian-Aristotelianmoralandlegaltheory,shewouldfindapowerfulelaborationofthemoralandlegalobligationstorespectandcareforthehumanityinothersaswellasoneselfthatshehopestocaptureinherreason/careparadigm.Theseobligationsinclude(althoughtheyareoftenoverlooked)thelegallyenforceabledutiesofdistributivejusticeandthepurelyethicaldutiesofbeneficenceaswellasthelegallyenforceabledutiesofcorrectivejustice.

    (p.256) Tortlawfallswithinthedomainofcorrectivejustice,althoughdistributivejusticeconsiderationsareinterwovenincertaintortdoctrines.Correctivejustice,aimsatsecuringeachindividualspersonandexistingstockofresourcesagainstconductbyothersthatwouldbeinconsistentwiththeequalnegativefreedomofall.Onesnegativefreedomthefreedomfromunjustifiedinterferencewithonesuseofonesexistingresourcestopursueonesprojectsorlifeplanwillbecompletelyunderminedifonemustalwaysweightheinterestsofallothersequallywithonesownwhendecidinghowtodeployonesexistingresources,asrequiredbytheutilitarianefficiencytheory,theprincipleofequalconcernandrespectasinterpretedbyDworkinandothers,and

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 7 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    Bendersfeministethicofcare.Underthesetheories,nooneistreatedasadistinctpersonwithonesownlifetolead.Rathereachpersonismerelyafungibleaddendinthecalculationofsomemysticalaggregatesocialwelfare.Foranyparticularactivity,itdoesnotmatterwhoisbeingputatrisk,bywhom,orforwhosebenefit;allthatmattersisthemaximizationofaggregatesocialwelfare.Thisisthemorallyunattractivemessageandeffectoftheutilitariansconceptionofreasonableness.

    UndertheKantian-Aristoteliantheory,whichisbasedonthefoundationalnormofequalindividualfreedomratherthanthemaximizationofaggregatesocialwelfare,therespectiveweightstobegiventoanactorsinterestsandtheinterestsofotherswhomightbeaffectedbythatactionwillvaryconsiderablydependingon(amongotherfactors)whoisbeingputatrisk,bywhom,andforwhosebenefit.Forexample,giventheKantianrequirementoftreatingothersasendsratherthanmerelyasmeans,itisimpermissibletousesomeoneasameremeanstoyourendsbyexposinghim(orhisresources)tosignificantforeseeableunacceptedrisks,regardlessofhowgreatlythebenefittoyoumightoutweightherisktohim.Conversely,sacrificingyourinterestsforthebenefitofsomeoneelseisregardedasmorallymeritorious,althoughnotlegallyrequired,eveniftherisktoyougreatlyoutweighstheexpectedbenefittotheotherperson,aslongasyourexposingyourselftotheriskdoesnotconstituteafailuretoproperlyrespectyourownhumanity.

    Itistheequalfreedomconceptionofreasonableness,ratherthantheutilitarianefficiencyconception,thatisreflectedinactualtort-lawdoctrinesanddecisions.Undertheutilitarian-efficiencytheory,itisasinefficienttobeabovetheoptimallevelofcareastobebelowit:eitherformofdivergencethereforeshouldbeconsiderednegligent.However,consistentwiththeequalfreedomtheory,defendantsandplaintiffsareonlydeemednegligentforbeingbelowtherequiredlevelofcare,notforbeingaboveit.Onlywhenoneisbelowtherequiredlevelofcareisthereanimpermissibleinterferencewiththerightsofothers(defendantsprimarynegligence)orafailureproperlytorespectonesownhumanity(plaintiffscontributorynegligence).

    (p.257) Moreover,althoughtheutilitarianefficiencytheorywouldapplythesameaggregaterisk-utilitystandardofcaretoplaintiffsanddefendantsinallsituations,takingintoaccountallrisksandbenefitstoeveryone,actualtortlawconsistentwiththeequalfreedomtheoryappliesquitedifferentstandardsofcareindifferentsituations.Thisisevidentforallthreeaspectsofthestandardsofcare:theriskstakenintoaccount,theperspectivesapplied,andthesubstantivecriteriaofreasonableness.

    A.RisksTakenintoAccountDifferentrisksaretakenintoaccountinanalyzingtheallegednegligenceofdefendantsandplaintiffs.Theanalysisofadefendantsallegednegligencefocusesontheforeseeableriskstootherscreatedbythedefendantsconduct,ratherthantheriskstoeveryoneincludingherself,whiletheanalysisofaplaintiffsallegednegligencefocusesontheforeseeableriskstotheplaintiffhimselfcreatedbyhisconduct,ratherthantheriskstoothersaswellashimself.22Thisdifferentialtreatmentisinexplicableundertheutilitarian

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 8 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    efficiencytheory,whichviewsdefendantsandplaintiffsasmorallyandeconomicallyindistinguishablecausesoftheeffectsoftheirinteractingactivitiesandseekstoconstructliabilityrulesthatwillmaximizetheaggregatenetbenefitsofsuchinteractions,takingintoaccountallexpectedcostsandbenefitstoeveryone.23Incontrast,theequalfreedomtheoryeasilyexplainsandjustifiesthedifferentriskstakenintoaccount.AsamatterofRightorjustice,thedefendantisliableforaninteractionalinjuryifandonlyifherconductforeseeablyaffectedthepersonorpropertyofanotherinamannerthatwasinconsistentwithhisRighttoequalnegativefreedom,thusgeneratingacorrectivejusticeobligationofrectification.24Intheanalysisoftheplaintiffscontributorynegligence,aquitedifferentissuearises:whetherthedefendantsprimafaciecorrectivejusticeobligationtotheplaintiffshouldbebarredorreducedbecause,inthelightoftheforeseeableriskstohimself,theplaintifffailedtoactwithproperrespectforhisownhumanityandthusalsobearsmoralresponsibilityforhisinjury.25

    B.PerspectiveApplied(ObjectiveorSubjective)Similarly,differentperspectivesareappliedinanalyzingtheallegednegligenceofdefendantsandplaintiffs.Whenassessingadefendantsallegednegligence,anobjectiveperspectivegenerallyisapplied:thedefendantisrequiredtotakeatleastasmuchcareaswouldbetakenbythe(ideal)(p.258) prudentpersonwithordinaryphysicalandmentalabilities.Thestandardisnotloweredtoconformwiththedefendantsparticularphysicalandmental(dis)abilities.Althoughadefendantwithanobviousphysicalincapacityisnotrequiredtodowhatsheisincapableofdoing,sheisrequiredtotakewhateveradditionalprecautionsarenecessarytoreducetheforeseeableriskstootherstotheobjectivelyspecifiedacceptablelevel.Ontheotherhand,althoughitoftenisnotexplicitlymentionedbythecourts,itisgenerallyrecognizedbycourtsandcommentatorsthatamoresubjectiveperspectiveisappliedwhenassessingaplaintiffsallegedcontributorynegligence.26

    Undertheutilitarianefficiencytheory,asubjectiveperspectiveideallyshouldbeappliedtobothdefendantsandplaintiffs.Itwouldbeinefficienttorequirealldefendantsorplaintiffstoattainthesamelevelofriskreductiondespitewidelyvaryingphysical,mental,technical,andeconomiccapacitiestoachievesuchriskreduction.Instead,eachdefendantorplaintiffshouldberequiredtoinvestincareonlytothepointwherethemarginalcostofsuchcaredoesnotexceedthemarginalbenefitsinreducedrisk.Duetodifferingcapacitiesandthuscostsofcare,thispointwillvaryforeachindividual.Itisonlytheveryhighadministrativecostsofattemptingtoapplythesubjectiveperspectivethatrequireadoptioninmostinstancesoftheobjectiveperspective,whichisassumed(butnotshown)tobeasecond-bestefficientsolutionforbothdefendantsandplaintiffs.Thus,whenpersonal(in)capacitiesareeasilyascertainable,theyshouldbetakenintoaccountforbothdefendantsandplaintiffs.27

    UnderKantsmoraltheory,asubjectiveperspectivewouldberequiredifthequestionwerethemoralblameworthinessormeritofthedefendantsorplaintiffsconduct.But,whenevaluatingthedefendantsconductinatort(ratherthanacriminal)action,thatisnottherelevantquestion(unlesspunitivedamagesareatissue).Instead,therelevant

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 9 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    questionisthedefendantsmoralresponsibilityforhavingadverselyaffectedsomeoneelsespersonorproperty.Assuch,thequestionisoneofobjectiveRightratherthansubjectivevirtue.Theexternalexerciseoffreedomdependsonsufficientsecurityagainstinterferencesbyotherswithonespersonandproperty.Regardlessofmeasurementproblems,usingasubjectiveperspectivetodeterminethenegligenceofdefendantswouldmakesuchsecurityimpossible,sincetheriskstowhichonecouldpermissiblybeexposedbyothers(p.259) woulddependonthesubjectivecapacitiesoftheparticularotherswithwhomonehappens(oftenunpredictably)tointeract.Tohavesufficientlysecureexpectations,onesrightsinonespersonandpropertymustbedefinedbyanobjectivelevelofpermissibleriskexposurebyotherswhich,underthemoralcategoricalimperativeanditscorollary(thesupremeprincipleofRight),mustbeequallyapplicabletoallandobjectivelyenforced.Thus,anobjectivestandardoflegalfault(moralresponsibility),ratherthanasubjectivestandardofmoralfault(blame),isrequiredwhenconsideringlegalresponsibilityfortheadverseeffectsofadefendantsconductonthepersonorpropertyofothers.28

    Whenthecontributorynegligenceofaplaintiffisatissue,thequestioniswhethertheplaintiffsrecoveryfromadefendantwhoinfringedhisrightsbynegligentlyinjuringhimshouldbebarredorreducedbecauseoftheplaintiffscontributiontohisowninjury.Sinceweareconcernedwithaninjurytotheplaintiffhimself,ratherthananinjurytothepersonorpropertyofothers,noissueofRightimmediatelyarises.Insteadtheissueiswhethertheplaintiff,byexposinghimselftotheparticularrisk,failedtoproperlyrespecthisownhumanityandthusshareswiththedefendantmoralresponsibilityforhisinjury.Whenassessingtheplaintiffsmoralresponsibilityforhisowninjury,thereasonjustgivenfordepartingfromthesubjectiveperspectiveofmoralfaultorvirtueandinsteadapplyingtheobjectiveperspectiveoflegalfaultorRighttothedefendantsconductdoesnotdirectlyapplytotheplaintiffsconduct.Rather,theissueofRightarisesindirectlyandappliesinamuchmorelimitedmanner.Properregardfortheequalfreedomofthedefendantsuggeststhattheplaintiffsconductbedeemednegligentandaffecthisrightofrecovery,evenifitwassubjectivelyreasonableinthelightofhisphysicalandmentalcapacitiesandbeliefs,ifitwasunforeseeablyidiosyncratici.e.,ifitfelloutsidethe(broad)rangeofforeseeablebehaviorforthegreatmassofpersonsinsimilarsituations.Thus,theplaintiffsconductshouldbejudgedbyalimitedsemi-subjectiveperspectiveratherthanafullysubjectiveperspective.29

    (p.260) C.TheSubstantiveCriteriaofReasonablenessFinally,differentcriteriaofreasonablenessareusedinevaluatingtheallegednegligenceofdefendantsandplaintiffsindifferentcontexts.Contrarytowhatiscommonlyassumed,thecourtsrarelyusetheaggregaterisk-utilityformulaoranyotheruniformdefinitionofreasonableness.Rather,differentfactorsaretakenintoaccountanddifferentweightsaregiventothosefactorsdependingonanumberofconsiderationsthatarehighlyrelevantundertheequal-freedomtheorybutirrelevantundertheutilitarianefficiencytheory.

    Inanarticlepublishedin1915thatisoftencitedaspresagingJudgeHandsformula,HenryTerrynotedfivefactorsthatmayberelevant,including[1]theprobabilityand[2]

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 10 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    themagnitudeofanyinjurythatmightresultfromtheconductatissueand,insomecases,atleast,[3]theprobabilityand[4]themagnitudeofthebenefitexpectedtobeattainedbysuchconductdiscountedby[5]theprobabilitythatthebenefitwouldbeattainedintheabsenceofsuchconduct.30In1927,WarrenSeaveywarnedagainstassum[ing]thatwecanrelyuponanyformulainregardto"balancinginterests"tosolvenegligencecases,andhestatedthattheutilityofthedefendantsconductusuallyisnotconsideredorisweightedverylowwhenthedefendantforherownbenefitputsanotherspropertyorespeciallypersonatrisk,orintentionallyinterfereswiththepersonorpropertyofanother.31JudgeLearnedHandhimself,theauthoroftherisk-utilityformula,notedthattheformulasfactors

    arepracticallynotsusceptibleofanyquantitativeestimate,andthesecondtwo[LandB]aregenerallynotso,eventheoretically.Forthisreasonasolutionalwaysinvolvessomepreference,orchoicebetweenincommensurables,anditisconsignedtoajurybecausetheirdecisionisthoughtmostlikelytoaccordwithcommonlyacceptedstandards,realorfancied.32

    Similarly,afterelaboratingtheusualacademicaggregaterisk-utilityinterpretationofreasonableness,JohnFlemingwarns:

    Butnegligencecannotbereducedtoapurelyeconomicequation.[I]ngeneral,judicialopinionsdonotmakemuchofthecostfactor[ofeliminatingtherisk],andforgoodreasons.Foronething,ourlegaltraditionintortshasstrongrootsinanindividualisticmoralitywithitsfocusprimarilyoninterpersonalequityratherthanbroadersocialpolicy,[T]hecalculusofnegligenceincludessomeimportantnon-economicvalues,likehealthandlife,freedomandprivacy,whichdefycomparison(p.261) withcompetingeconomicvalues.Negligenceisnotjustamatterofcalculatingthepointatwhichthecostofinjurytovictims(thatisthedamagespayable)exceedsthatofprovidingsafetyprecautions.Thereasonablemanisbynomeansacaricaturecoldblooded,calculatingEconomicMan.33

    Verylittlescholarlyattentionhasbeenpaidtothecriteriaofreasonablenessthatareactuallyappliedindifferentsituations.Intheremainderofthisessay,Iattempttobegintofillthisgap.Thedifferentsituationswillbedistinguishedprimarilybywhoputwhomatriskforwhosebenefitandbywhetherthepersonputatriskconsentedtosuchriskexposure.Morespecifically,Iexaminethestandardsofcareinthefollowing(non-exhaustive)contexts:(1)defendantstreatingothersasmeans,(2)defendantsengagedinsociallyessentialactivities,(3)defendantoccupierson-premisesrisks,(4)defendantsactivitiesinvolvingparticipatoryplaintiffs,(5)paternalisticdefendants,(6)plaintiffsself-interestedconduct,(7)plaintiffsself-sacrificingconduct,and(8)defendantsfailuretoaidorrescue.

    1.DefendantsTreatingOthersasMeansThefirstcategory,theinvoluntaryDPDcategory,encompassessituationsinwhichthedefendant(D)puttheplaintiff(P)atrisktobenefitthedefendant(D)orsomethirdparty,andtheplaintiffdidnotseektobenefitdirectlyfromthedefendantsrisk-creatingactivity.

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 11 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    Recently,afewscholarshavenotedthattheactualtestofnegligenceinsuchcasesisnottheutilitariansaggregaterisk-utilitytestbutrather(consistentwiththeequalfreedomtheory)thedefendantscreationofasignificant,foreseeable,andunacceptedrisktothepersonorpropertyofothers.34Ariskissignificant,andhenceunreasonableunlessacceptedbytheplaintiff,ifitisalevelofrisktowhichanordinarypersonwouldbeunwillingtobeexposedwithouthisconsent.

    ThebestknowncaseofthistypeistheBritishHouseofLordsdecisioninBoltonv.Stone,inwhichtheplaintiff,whilestandingintheroadinfrontofherhouse,wasseriouslyinjuredwhenshewasstruckbyaballthathadbeenpropelledbyanexceptionalhitoutofthenearbycricketgroundsoveraninterveninghouseandintothestreet.35EachoftheLawLordsassumedthatthedefendantcricketclubwouldbeliableinnegligenceiftheriskwereforeseeableandofasufficientlyhighlevel,regardlessoftheutilityofthedefendantsconductortheburdenofavoidingcreatingtherisk.Eachlordconcludedthattherisk,althoughforeseeable,wasnotofasufficientlyhighleveltobedeemedunreasonableasamatteroflaw,giventheverylowprobabilitiesofaballsbeinghitintotheroadandalso(p.262) hittingsomeoneonthelittle-usedresidentialsidestreet.LordReidwasthemostexplicit.Hestatedthatinordertobenegligent,ariskmustnotonlybeforeseeablebutalsobeonethatareasonableperson,consideringthematterfromthepointofviewofsafety,wouldconsidermaterialorsub-stantial:

    InconsideringthatmatterIthinkthatitwouldberighttotakeintoaccountnotonlyhowremoteisthechancethatapersonmightbestruckbutalsohowserioustheconsequencesarelikelytobeifapersonisstruck;butIdonotthinkthatitwouldberighttotakeintoaccountthedifficultyofremedialmeasures.Ifcricketcannotbeplayedonagroundwithoutcreatingasubstantialrisk,thenitshouldnotbeplayedthereatall.Idonotthinkthatareasonablemanconsideringthematterfromthepointofviewofsafetywouldorshoulddisregardanyriskunlessitisextremelysmall.36

    Inasubsequentcase,theLawLordssittingasthePrivyCouncilinaCommonwealthcaseonappealfromAustralia,TheWagonMound(No.2),heldthat,evenwhentheforeseeableriskisinsubstantial(small),thedefendantwillstillbeheldnegligentif,butonlyif,theriskwasrealratherthanfar-fetchedorfantasticandthedefendanthadnovalidreasonforfailingtotakestepstoeliminateit.Avalidreasoncouldbethatitwouldinvolveconsiderableexpensetoeliminatetherisk.[Thedefendant]wouldweightheriskagainstthedifficultyofeliminatingit.Boltonv.Stone,thecourtsaid,hadinvolvedsucharealbutinsubstantialrisk.But,thecourtreiterated,iftheriskwererealandsubstantial,itwouldbeunreasonablenottotakestepstoeliminateit,regardlessoftheutilityoftheriskortheburdenofeliminatingit.37

    TheWagonMound(No,2)issometimesmisreadasabandoningBoltonv.Stonessubstantialriskcriterionandreplacingitwiththerisk-utilityformula.ButthePrivyCouncilclearlystatesthattherisk-utilityformula,ratherthanbeingtheuniversaltestofdefendantsnegligence,isapplicableonlyinthosesituationsinwhichtheriskordinarilywouldbeconsideredinsubstantial.Iftheriskissubstantial,theutilityofthedefendants

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 12 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    conductisirrelevant.Therisk-utilityformulaisusedtoexpandthedefendantsliability,toencompasssituationsinwhichtheriskordinarilywouldbedeemedinsubstantialbutisneverthelessdeemedunacceptablebecauseitisreal,ratherthanfantastic,andthecostofeliminatingitwouldbesimilarly(p.263) small(noprecisequantitativebalancingofriskandutilityseemstobefeasible,impliedorjustifiedeveninthesesituations).38

    AlthoughnotusuallyemployinglanguageasexplicitasLordReidsinBolton,anddespitesometimesemployingbalancinglanguage,courtsintheUnitedStatesandelsewheregenerallyalsofindadefendantnegligentifshecreatedaforeseeablesignificantunacceptedriskofinjurytothepersonorpropertyofothers.39Aswepreviouslynoted,juryinstructionsonadefendantsnegligencerarely,ifever,refertotheaggregaterisk-utilityformula,focusinginsteadonthecareexpectedofthereasonableordinaryorprudentpersonwhoactswithproperconcernfortheeffectsofheractivityonthepersonsandpropertyofothers.Courtshaveupheldjuryfindingsofnegligenceeventhoughthejuryhasspecificallyfoundthatthebenefitsasawholeofthedefendantsconductoutweighedtherisks.40Inacareful,documentedstudyofallnineteenthcenturyCaliforniaandNewHampshireappellatecourtdecisionsontortliability,GarySchwartzreports:

    Thefactorofprivateprofitwasseenasareasonforbeingskeptical,ratherthanappreciative,oftheproprietyofriskyactivityengagedinbyenterprise.Ingeneral,theNewHampshireandCaliforniaCourtswerereluctanttofindthateconomicfactorsjustifiedadefendantsrisktaking.NeitherCourtevenonceheldmeremonetarycostsrenderednonnegligentadefendantsfailuretoadoptaparticularsafetyprecaution.41

    Defenselawyerscarefullyavoidmakingargumentstojudgesorjurorsthatseektojustifyrisksimposedontheplaintiffbyallegedlyoffsettingenhancementsofthedefendantsutility.Defendantsthatarethoughttohavedeliberatelymadesuchrisk-utilitydecisionsareoftendeemedbyjuriesandjudgesnotonlytohavebeennegligent,butalsotohavebehavedsoegre-giouslyastojustifyaheftyawardofpunitivedamages,asoccurredintheFordPintoandasbestoscases.42

    (p.264) 2.DefendantsEngagedinSociallyEssentialActivitiesWhilethepurelyprivateutilitytothedefendantofhisconductisrarelytakenintoaccount,thesocialutilityofthedefendantsconductistakenintoaccountinsomesituations,althoughnotthroughautilitarianbalancing.AcoupleofthesesituationsarethesubjectoftheWisconsinSupremeCourtsillustrationsofappropriatebalancingofthesocialinterestsinnegligencecasesunderanordinarycarejuryinstruction:

    Onedrivingacarinathicklypopulateddistrict,onarainyday,slowlyandinthemostcarefulmanner,maydoinjurytothepersonofanotherbythrowingmuddyorinfectedwateruponthatperson.Societydoesnotholdtheactorresponsiblebecausethebenefitofallowingpeopletotravelundersuchcircumstancessofaroutweighstheprobableinjurytobystandersthatsuchconductisnotdisapproved.Circumstancesmayrequirethedriverofafiretrucktotakehistruckthrougha

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 13 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    thicklypopulateddistrictatahighrateofspeed,butifheexercisesthatdegreeofcarewhichsuchdriversordinarilyexerciseunderthesameorsimilarcircumstances,societyweighingthebenefitsagainsttheprobabilitiesofdamage,inspiteofthefactthatasareasonablyprudentandintelligentmanheshouldforeseethatharmmayresult,justifiestheriskandholdshimnotliable.43

    Thecourtsfirstillustrationreflectsthefactthatinanysocietycertainriskssuchasthoseposedbyproperlyconstructed,maintained,andoperatedelectricalgenerationandtransmissionfacilities,dams,trains,automobiles,andplaneswillbeunavoidableaspectsofactivitiesessentialorimportanttoallpersonsinthesociety.UnderthesupremeprincipleofRight(universalizableequalfreedom),allmembersofsocietywillbedeemedtohaveacceptedsuchactivitiesandtheirunavoidablerisksasbeingreasonable(butnotnecessarilyasbeingimmunefromstrictliabilityfordamagescausedtothosenotseekingtodirectlybenefitfromaparticularriskyactivity).Yet,astheWisconsincourtnotes,thesociallyimportantactivitymustbeoperatedinthemostcarefulmannertominimizetheriskstoothers,andtheactivitywillbedeemedreasonableonlyiftheriskstoothersarenottooserious(intheillustrationtheyaredeminimis)andaregreatly(notmerelymarginally)outweighedbytheactivityssocialutility.

    TheWisconsincourtssecondillustrationinvolvestheoperationofpublicemergencyvehiclesbydefendantsseekingtoalleviateseriousthreatstopeopleslivesorproperty.Insuchemergencysituations,thedefendantis(p.265) heldtobejustifiedinengaginginpractices(e.g.,drivingathighspeeds,onthewrongsideoftheroad,andthroughtrafficsignals)thatordinarilywouldbedeemednegligent,butonlyifsheundertakesadditionalprecautionsorwarnings(suchasslowingdownatintersections,soundingsirens,andflashinglights)sothatthosetherebyputatriskcan,withoutsignificantinterferencewiththeirlegitimateactivities,avoidbeingexposedtoasubstantialorsignificantrisk.44Defendantsinemergencysituationsarethustreatedsimilarlytodefendantswithphysicalincapacities,whoaswehavenotedarenotrequiredtodowhattheyareincapableofdoingbutarerequiredtotakeotherstepstoavoidexceedingtheobjectivelyacceptablelevelofrisk.45

    3.DefendantOccupiersOn-PremisesRisksInafewsituations,wherethedefendantsownrightsaredirectlyimplicated,thedefendantsprivateutilityistakenintoaccountandasemi-subjectiveperspectiveissometimesapplied.Oneofthesesituationsinvolvesrisks,topersonswhocomeonthedefendantsproperty,thatresultfromactivitiesorconditionsontheproperty.Whetherformulatedasdistinctdutiesorasasingleall-encompassingdutyofreasonablecare,thestandardofcarevariesaccordingtowhethertheplaintiffwasabusinessinvitee,asocialguest,alicensee,achildtrespasser,oranadulttrespasser.46Thehighest,objectivestandardofcareisrequiredforbusinessinvitees,whilethelowest,semi-subjectivestandardofcareisrequiredforadulttrespassers.Ofthevariouscategoriesofon-premisesplaintiffs,onlybusinessinviteesareaffordedapproximatelythesameprotectionasoff-premisesplaintiffs.47

    Thesedistinctionsarefairlyeasilyexplainedandjustifiedundertheequalfreedom

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 14 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    theory,whichwouldnotrequirethedefendanttosignificantlysacrificeherownintereststoprotectfromon-premisesrisksthose(especiallyadults)whohavewrongfullytrespassedonherproperty,ortogobeyondprovidingwarningsandmoderatesafeguardstomakethepremisessaferforlicenseesorsocialgueststhansheiswillingandabletomakeitforherself.Thisequal-freedomreasoningappearsofteninthecases.For(p.266) example,intheHouseofLordsdecisioninBritishRailwaysBoardv.Herrington,LordReidstated:

    Normallythecommonlawappliesanobjectivetest[todefendants].Ifapersonchoosestoassumearelationshipwithmembersofthepublic,saybysettingouttodriveacarortoerectabuildingfrontingahighway,thelawrequireshimtoconducthimselfasareasonablemanwithadequateskill,knowledgeandresourceswoulddo.Hewillnotbeheardtosaythatinfacthecouldnotattainthatstandard.Ifhecannotattainthatstandardheoughtnottoassumetheresponsibilitywhichthatrelationshipinvolves.Butanoccupierdoesnotvoluntarilyassumearelationshipwithtrespassers.Bytrespassingtheyforceaneighbourrelationshiponhim.WhentheydosohemustactinahumanemannerthatisnotaskingtoomuchofhimbutIdonotseewhyheshouldberequiredtodomore.

    Soitappearstomethatanoccupiersdutytotrespassersmustvaryaccordingtohisknowledge,ability,andresources.Ithasoftenbeensaidthattrespassersmusttakethelandastheyfindit.Iwouldrathersaythattheymusttaketheoccupierastheyfindhim.

    [Theoccupier]mightoftenreasonablythink,weighingtheseriousnessofthedangerandthedegreeoflikelihoodoftrespasserscomingagainsttheburdenhewouldhavetoincurinpreventingtheirentryormakinghispremisessafe,orcurtailinghisownactivitiesonhisland,thathecouldnotfairlybeexpectedtodoanything.Butifhecouldatsmalltroubleandexpensetakesomeeffectiveaction,Ithinkmostpeoplewouldthinkitinhumaneandculpablenottodothat.

    Itwouldfollowthatanimpecuniousoccupierwithlittleassistanceathandwouldoftenbeexcusedfromdoingsomethingwhichalargeorganisationwithamplestaffwouldbeexpectedtodo.48

    Moresuccinctly,LordPearsonstated:Thereisalsoamoralaspect.[T]respassingisaformofmisbehaviour,showinglackofconsiderationfortherightsofothers.Itwouldbeunfairiftrespasserscouldbytheirmisbehaviourimposeonerousobligationsonothers.49

    Undertheutilitarianefficiencytheory,itwouldseemthat(contrarytothecases)defendantlandownersshouldbeatleastasconcernedabouton-premisesrisksasoff-premisesrisks,regardlessofthestatusoftheplaintiff,andindeedarguablyshouldbesubjecttogreater(strictorabsolute)liabilityforon-premisesrisksastheusualcheapestcostavoider.Thelegaleconomistsattemptstoexplainthedefendantlandownersgreatlyrelaxeddutyofcaretotrespassersasplaintiffsand,conversely,therelatedstrict(sometimespunitive)liabilityoftrespassersasdefendants,relyonaconvolutedandad

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 15 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    hocencouragingmarkettransactionsrationalethatisriddledwithexceptionsforallegedinfeasiblebargainingsituations.50

    (p.267) 4.DefendantsActivitiesInvolvingParticipatoryPlaintiffsAnothermajorcategoryofnegligencecases,theVoluntaryDPPcategory,encompassessituationsinwhichthedefendant(D)puttheplaintiff(P)atriskatleastpartiallytobenefittheplaintiff(P),andtheplaintiffsoughttobenefitdirectlyfromthedefendantsriskyactivity.Thiscategoryincludessituationsinwhichtheplaintiffswerecustomersof,participantsin,orwillingspectatorsofthedefendantsriskyactivity.Inthesesituations,theriskwillbedeemedreasonableevenifitwassubstantialifitwasonethattheplaintiffimplicitlyacceptedasbeingworthwhilegiventhebenefitsheexpectedtoobtainfromtheriskyactivity(includingthebenefitofnothavingtopayanyincreasedprecautioncoststhatwouldlikelybepassedontohim).Hence,inthiscontextatypeofrisk-utilitytestisproperundertheequal-freedomtheory.Butthebenefitstakenintoaccountarelimitedtothoseexpectedbythetypicalplaintiff,ratherthanalsoincluding(astheutilitarianefficiencytheorywouldmandate)anyindependentutilitytothedefendantoraggregatesocialutility.Moreover,thecomparisonofriskandutilityisnotasimplequantitativecomparisonofnon-weightedfactors,asisassumedbytheutilitarianefficiencytheory.Dependingonthevaluesinvolved,thecomparisonmaybequalitativeratherthanquantitative,ormayinvolveweightedorlexicallyorderedfactors,orboth.Forexample,rarely,ifever,wouldseriousriskstolifeorhealthbedeemedoutweighedbymereeconomicbenefits.

    Therearemanyexamplesofcasesinthiscategory.Amongthemostcommonnowadaysaresuitsbyaproductpurchaseroruserallegingdefectivedesignbytheproductsmanufacturer.Acommon(butnotexclusive)testofdefectorreasonablenessinsuchcasesisanexplicitrisk-utilitytest,whichinallbutahandfulofcasesfocusessolelyontherisksandbenefitstothetypicalconsumer,ratherthanonanyindependentutilitytothedefendantoraggregatesocialutility.51Inatypicalnon-productliabilitycase,theplaintiff,apassengeronthedefendantstrain,apparentlyfaintedinawashroomandreceivedsevereburnsonherfacewhenitcameintocontactwithanexposedheatingpipeunderawatercooler,whichpipecouldonlybereachedbypersonskneelingorlyingdownonthefloor.Assumingthatfailingtoguardagainstsuchanoccurrencewouldbeunreasonableifitwerereasonablyforeseeable,thecourtheldthatitwasnot.52Theriskconced-edlywasforeseeableandperhapscouldhavebeendeemedsignificant(reasonablyforeseeable).Yet,giventheverysmallrisk,itisunlikelythatthe(p.268) typicalpassengerwouldhavebeenwillingtopay,throughincreasedticketprices,thedistributedcostsofeliminatingtheriskbyshieldingthepipesineverywashroomoneverytrain.

    5.PaternalisticDefendantsAdistinctandinfrequentlyencounteredcategory,theinvoluntaryDPPcategory,encompassessituationsinwhichthedefendant(D)puttheplaintiff(P)atriskforwhatthedefendantconsideredtobetheplaintiffs(Ps)bestinterest,buttheplaintiffdidnotconsenttoorseektobenefitfromthecreationoftherisk.Consistentwiththeequal-

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 16 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    freedomtheorybutcontrarytotheutilitarian-efficiencytheory,defendantsgenerallyarenotallowedtodothiswithouttheplaintiffsconsent,eveniftheexpectedbenefitsallegedlygreatlyoutweightherisks,unlesstheplaintiffisincapableofgivingconsentandthereisauthorizedsubstitutedconsent.

    Themostcommoncasesinvolvemedicaltreatment.Althoughsomejurisdictionsleavetothemedicalprofessionthejudgementofwhatrisksshouldbedisclosedtothepatient,manyUnitedStatesjurisdictionstodayfollowthepatient-centeredstandard,accordingtowhichthephysicianhasthedutytodiscloserisksthatwouldbedeemedmaterialbythetypicalpatient,orwhichthephysicianotherwiseknowsorhasreasontoknowarematerialtotheparticularpatient.53Thepatient-centeredstandardhasalsobeenapprovedbytheHighCourtofAustraliaandtheSupremeCourtofCanada,54andwasfavoredbyLordsScarmanandTemplemanintheBritishHouseofLordsdecisioninSidawayv.BethlemRoyalHospital,55

    However,abaremajorityoftheLawLordsinSidawayaffirmedtheCourtofAppealsadoptionofthephysician-centeredmedical-practicestandard,basedonEnglandsmorepaternalisticapproachtodoctor-patientrelationsandaconcernthatthetransatlanticapproachwasbothimpracticalandwoulddonothingforpatientsormedicine,althoughitmightdoagreatdealfprlawyersandlitigation.56Nevertheless,themajorityintheHouseofLordsagreedwiththeminoritythatthedoctorsjudgementonproperriskdisclosurewouldhavetogivewaywhen(p.269) necessarytorespondfullytoapatientsqueryabouttherisksinvolved.57Moreover,LordBridge,joinedbyLordKeith,statedthat,whiletheissueofproperriskdisclosureistobedecidedprimarilyonthebasisofexpertmedicalevidence,exceptionalcasesmightarise:

    [T]hejudgemightincertaincircumstancescometotheconclusionthatdisclosureofaparticularriskwassoobviouslynecessarytoaninformedchoiceonthepartofthepatientthatnoreasonablyprudentmedicalmanwouldfailtomakeit.ThekindofcaseIhaveinmindwouldbeanoperationinvolvingasubstantialriskofgraveadverseconsequences.Insuchacase,intheabsenceofsomecogentclinicalreasonwhythepatientshouldnotbeinformed,adoctor,recognisingandrespectinghispatientsrightofdecision,couldhardlyfailtoappreciatethenecessityforanappropriatewarning.58

    Despitethedisagreementsonthedoctor-centeredversuspatient-centeredstandardfordeterminingwhichrisksarematerialtothepatient,itisuniversallyrecognizedthatthepatienthastheright,regardlessofthedoctorsopinion,todecidewhetherornottoundergosomemedicaltreatmentandthatthedoctorhasacorrelativedutytodisclosematerialriskstothepatient.Thisrightanddutyseemobviousundertheequalfreedomtheory,buttheyaredifficulttoexplainundertheutilitarianefficiencytheory.

    Thelegaleconomistmightarguethatthemedicaltreatmentcasesarelowtransaction-costsituationsinwhichthedoctorshouldbeprecludedfrombypassing(fullyinformed)marketbargainingbyfailingtodiscloseriskinformationthatisknowablyorforeseeablymaterialtothepatient.59Butapatientsrefusaltoundergosometreatmente.g.,a

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 17 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    refusaltoacceptbloodtransfusionsbecauseofreligiousbeliefsorotherreasonsmaygreatlyendangerhishealthandlife,therebycreatingsubstantialexpecteddisutilitynotonlytohimselfbutalsotootherseconomicallyoremotionallydependentonhim.Thetransactioncostsofnegotiatingwithsuchaffectedthirdpartieswillgenerallybeveryhigh,yetthecompetentpatientsrighttorefusetreatmentremainsclear,eventhoughundertheutilitariansimpartialcalculustheaggregatebenefitstothepatientandothersofgoingaheadwiththetreatmentmightbethoughttogreatlyoutweighthepsychicand/orreligiouscoststothepatient.

    6.PlaintiffsSelf-interestedConductWeturnnowtotheplaintiffscontributorynegligence.Theprincipalcategory,thePPPcategory,encompassessituationssuchasCarrollTowinginwhichtheplaintiff(P)puthimself(P)atriskforhisown(Ps)benefit.60Sinceweareonlyconcernedwiththerisktheplaintiffimposedonhimself,(p.270) noissueofRightisdirectlyinvolved,butratheronlywhethertheplaintifffailedproperlytorespecthisownhumanityandthusalsoismorallyresponsibleforhisinjury.Whenengagedinsuchpurelyself-interestedbehavior,itwouldbeirrationalforapersontoexposehimselftoriskswhichsubjectivelyexceedtheexpectedbenefits.

    AsintheVoluntaryDPPdefendantcategory,thisrisk-utilitytestreflectstheequal-freedomapproachratherthantheutilitarianefficiencyapproach.Onlyrisksandbenefitstotheplaintiffaretakenintoaccount,ratherthan(asrequiredbytheutilitarianefficiencytheory)allrisksandbenefitstoanyonewhomightbeaffectedbytheplaintiffsconduct.Therisksandbenefitsareevaluatedfromthesubjectiveperspectiveoftheplaintiff(aslongasthatperspectiveisnottooidiosyncratic),ratherthantheobjectiveperspectiveoftheidealprudentperson.Andthecomparisonofrisksandbenefitsisnotaquantitativemeasurementandbalancingofmarginalrisksandexpectedutilities,butratheracommon-senseassessmentoftherelevantrisksandutilities,whichmaybeandoftenareassessedqualitativelyorlexicallyratherthanquantitatively.61

    7.PlaintiffsSelf-SacrificingConductThispenultimatecategory,thePPXcategory,encompassessituationsinwhichtheplaintiff(P)puthimself(P)atriskforsomethirdpartys(Xs)benefit.Undertheutilitarian-efficiencytheory,theplaintiffshouldbedeemedcontributorilynegligentiftheriskstotheplaintiff(andothers),objectivelyconsidered,outweightheexpectedbenefittothethirdparty(andothers).Undertheequalfreedomtheory,however,theplaintiffswillingnesstosacrificehisownintereststobenefitsomeoneelseisconsiderednotonlyreasonable,butalsomorallypraiseworthy,evenif(undertheutilitariancalculus)theriskstotheplaintiffseemmuchgreaterthantheexpectedbenefittothethirdparty,aslongastheplaintiffsconductdoesnotconstitutelackofrespectforhisownhumanity.

    Theequal-freedomtheoryisconsistentwiththecases,whiletheutilitarian-efficiencytheoryisnot.Probablythemostcommonsituationiswhentheplaintiffputshimselfatrisktorescuesomehelplesspersonwhohasbeenputinseriousdangerbythedefendantsnegligence.Intheserescuesituations,courtsholdthat,nomatterhowmuchtheriskto

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 18 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    theplaintiffmayseemtoexceedtheexpectedbenefittothepotentialrescuee,theplaintiffsconductismorallymeritoriousratherthanmorallyblameworthyorunreasonableunlessitwasfoolhardy,wanton,rash,orreckless.62(p.271) Whenthelifeofthepotentialrescueeisatissue,therisktotheplaintiffisconsideredfoolhardyorrashonlyiftherewasnorealchanceofsavingthepotentialrescuee.

    OneofthebestknowncasesisEckertv.LongIslandRailroad63whichwas(mis)usedbyTerrytoillustratetheutilitarianbalancingofthefivefactorsthatheidentifiedasbeingrelevanttoadeterminationofadefendantsorplaintiffsnegligence.64TherescuerinEckertjumpedinfrontofthedefendantsnegligentlydriventraintosaveachildonthetracks,pushingthechildoffthetracksjustbarelyintimebutbeinghitandkilledhimself.Ifweplausiblyassumethatthelives(L)oftherescuerandthechildwereequallyvaluable(althougheconomistsmightconsidertheremaininglifeofthepresumablyproductiveadulttobemorevaluablethanthatoftheasyetunproductivechild),theprobabilityoftherescuersbeingkilledwasatleast75percent,theprobabilityoftherescuersrescuingthechildwasatbest25percent,andtheprobabilityofthechildremainingonthetrackswithoutanyrescueattemptwasaround90percent,thentherisktotherescuer(0.750L)greatlyexceededtheexpectedbenefittothechild(0.25x0.9L=0.225L).Thecourtneverthelessheldthattherescuersconduct,ratherthanbeingcontributorilynegligent,wasmorallymeritorious,andthatitwouldbecontributorilynegligentonlyifitwasrashorreckless.65TheutilitarianefficiencytheoristsignoretheEckertcourtsrashorrecklesslanguageandimplausiblyassumethattherisktotherescuerwaslessthantheexpectedbenefittotherescuee.66

    8.DefendantsFailuretoAidorRescueThelastcategory,thenonfeasanceDPDcategory,isthereverseofthePPXcategorythatwehavejustdiscussed.Itencompassessituationsinwhichthedefendantfailedtoaidapersonwhoneededherhelp,butthedefendantsfailuretoaidwasnonfeasanceratherthanmisfeasancesincethedefendantdidnotcreateorworsentheplaintiffsneedycondition.Thedefendant(D)didnotputtheplaintiffatriskforthedefendantsbenefit,butratherlettheplaintiff(P)remainatriskinordertoavoidaburdentoorlossofbenefitbythedefendant(D).Insuchsituations,thegeneralcommonlawruleisthatthedefendanthasnolegaldutytoaidtheplaintiff.Incivil-lawjurisdictionsandafewcommon-lawjurisdictions,thereisalimitedlegal(criminallawandsometimesalsotortlaw)dutyofeasyrescuei.e.,adutytorenderaidinemergencysituationstoapersonwhoselifeorhealthisseriouslythreatened,iftherescuercandosowithoutexposingherselftosignificantrisksorburdens.Thegeneralno-dutyruleincommonlawjurisdictionsisriddledbyanexpandinglistofcategoriesofpersonsheld(p.272)subjecttoadutyofeasyrescue,usuallybutnotalwaysbasedonsomespecialrelationshipwiththeplaintiffortheplaintiffsassailant.67

    Althoughitmightseemefficienttoimposeadutytoaidwhenevertheexpectedbenefitstotheplaintiffoutweightheriskorburdentothedefendant,ifappliedgenerallythisdutycouldpromoteinefficientgenerallaziness(theeconomistsmoralhazardproblem).Thus,utilitarianefficiencytheoryprobablywouldrejectageneralmoralorlegalobligation

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 19 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    ofbeneficenceorcharity,andlimitthedefendantsdutytoemergencysituationsinvolvingsignificantriskstotheplaintiffslifeorhealth.Ithasbeensuggestedthatutilitariansmightalsoexcludeaspracticallyunenforceable(andhenceeconomicallywasteful)anyrequirementthatthedefendantimposeonherselfasignificantrisktoherownlifeorhealth.68However,thisexclusionwouldconcedethelackofacceptanceoftheutilitarianmoraltheory,sinceunderthattheoryadefendantshouldwillinglyincursuchariskifitwereoutweighedbytheexpectedbenefittotheplaintiff.Inanyevent,utilitarianefficiencytheorywouldrequireadefendanttoimposesignificantnon-healththreateningburdensonherselfinemergencysituationsinvolvingsignificantriskstotheplaintiffslifeorhealthiftheexpectedbenefitstotheplaintiffexceededtheburdensonher.69Yetnojurisdictionimposessuchadutyofnon-easyrescue.

    LandesandPosnerputforthvariousefficiencyargumentstotrytoexplainthelackofageneraldutytoattemptrescue.Oneargumentisthatacausation(misfeasance)requirement,althoughusuallyirrelevanttoefficiencydeterminations,isneeded(forunexplainedreasons)inthisonecontexttoavoidexcessiveadministrativecostsinidentifyingwhowouldhavebeenefficientorcheapest-costrescuers.Anotherimplausibleargumentisthatadutytorescuewouldinefficientlyreducethenumberofpotentialrescuersbecausepeoplewouldavoidactivitieswhichmightgiverisetoadutytorescue.Yetanyactivitymightgiverisetoadutytorescue;tocompletelyavoidsuchadutyonewouldhavetoceasetoexist.Conversely,giventherareoccurrenceofemergency-rescuesituations,evenadutyofnon-easyrescueshouldhavelittleimpactonpeopleschoiceofactivities.Athirdimplausibleargumentisthatadutytorescuewouldcreateamoralhazardproblem:that,relyingonthedutytorescue,peoplewouldtakeinsufficientprecautionsfortheirownsafetyorevenplacethemselvesinexigentcircumstancesinordertobeabletosuefornon-rescue.70

    Thelackofalegaldutyofnon-easyrescueiseasilyexplainedandjustifiedunderKantianmoraltheory.Nopersoncanbeusedsolelyasameansforthebenefitofothers,whichmeansthatnoonecanbelegally(p.273) requiredtogobeyondtherequirementsofRight(correctivejusticeanddistributivejustice)ifsuchanobligationwouldrequireasignificantsacrificeofonesautonomyorfreedomfortheallegedgreatergoodofothers.Correctivejusticedefinesthescopeofonesequalnegativefreedomnottohaveonespersonorexistingstockofresourcesadverselyaffectedbyothers.Itisthuslimitedtosituationsinvolvingmisfeasance,inwhichthedefendantsconducthasputthepersonorpropertyoftheplaintiffinaworsepositionthanifthedefendanthadnotbeenpresent.Althoughdistributivejusticeobligatespersonswithmorethantheirjustshareofsocietysresourcestoredistributethatexcesstothosewhohavelessthantheirjustshare,thesedistributivejusticedutiesgenerallyaremultilateralratherthanbilateralandthusarenecessarilyorbestimplementedthroughlegislativeandadministrative(re)distributionschemes.71InadditiontotheserequirementsofRight,Kantspecifiesadutyofbeneficenceasoneoftheprincipaldutiesofvirtue,butheinsiststhatthisissolelyanethicaldutybecauseitisonlyspecifiableasanindeterminatebroadduty,whichvariesdependingoneachwould-bebenefactorsownresourcesandneeds,ratherthanasadeterminate(andhencelegallyenforceable)Strictduty.72

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 20 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    ThusKantianmoralphilosophy,whilerecognizingalegaldutyofdistributivejusticeandapurelyethicaldutyofbeneficence,rejectsagenerallegaldutyofnon-easyrescueorbeneficence.Itisoftenthoughttogofurtherandtosupporttheno-dutyrule,rejectingevenadutyofeasyrescue.73Yetthisisfarfromclear.Kanthimselfneveraddressedtheissueofalimitedlegaldutyofeasyrescue.AlthoughKantsometimessaidthattheissueofneedisirrelevanttoRight(legalobligation),hesaidthisinthecontextofdistinguishingthesolelyethicaldutyofbeneficence.74GivenKantsfundamentalfocusonequalindividualfreedom,bothnegativeandpositive,itwouldseemthatKantsmoralphilosophywouldsupport(indeedrequire)alegaldutyofeasyrescue,whichbydefinitionwouldnotentailanysignificantburdenonthedefendantssubstantivefreedomandyetwouldbeessentialtotheplaintiffscontinuedfreedom,ifsuchadutycouldbedeterminatelyspecifiedandpracticablyenforced.Thislegaldutycouldbebased,giventheexigentcircumstances,eitherondistributivejusticessecuringof(p.274) equalpositivefreedomordirectlyontheunderlyingfoundationalnormofequalindividualfreedom.

    Theprimaryobjectiontoadutyofeasyrescue,evenbyardentlibertarianssuchasRichardEpstein,hasbeenthesupposedindeterminatenessandimpracticalityofimplementingsuchaduty.Epsteinsuggeststheintractabledifficultyofdecidingwhoshouldbeheldliablewhenmanypeoplewerepresentwhoeasilycouldhaveaidedtheplaintiff.75Yetdoctrinessuchasjointandseveralliabilitycanbeusedhereasinothermultipledefendantsituations.Epsteinalsosuggeststhatitisdifficultifnotimpossibletodistinguisheasy-rescuesituationsfromnon-easy-rescuesituations.Forexample,hearguesthatadutyofeasyrescuewouldrequiremostpersonstorespondaffirmativelytoacharitableappealfor$10tosavethelifeofsomestarvingchildinacountryravagedbywar.76Butthisisnottrue:ifonehadsuchaduty,onewouldbeforcedtorespondtorepeatedindistinguishableclaimsthatwouldquicklyadduptoasignificantburden.Thefeasibilityofimplementingalegaldutyofeasyrescueseemstobedemonstratedbyitsactualimplementationincivil-lawjurisdictions.

    Nevertheless,thereisalegitimateconcernthatnolegaldutytorescueshouldbeimposedinnonfeasancesituationsthatwouldsignificantlyinterferewiththedefendantsRightofequalfreedom.Ibelievethisconcernjustifiesapplyingasubjectiveperspectiveandraisingtheburdenofprooffromapreponderanceoftheevidencetoclearandconvincingevidencewhendeterminingwhethertherescueattemptactuallywouldhavebeeneasy(i.e.,wouldnothavebeenasignificantintrusiononthedefendantsautonomy).Inaddition,Iacknowledgesomedoubtsaboutthejusticeofimposingextensivetortdamageswhichmightbankruptthedefendantwhenthedefendantisbeingchargedmerelywithnonfeasance(failuretobenefitsomeoneelse)ratherthanmisfeasance(affirmativelyputtingsomeoneelseatrisk).Suchdoubtsmightsuggestthatonlyminorcriminalpenaltiesorsignificantlyrestrictedtortdamagesbemadeavailableforbreachofthedutyofeasyrescue.

    V.ConclusionTheKantian-Aristoteliantheoryoflegalresponsibility,whichisbasedonthenormatively

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 21 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    attractivepremiseofequalindividualfreedom,explains,justifies,andilluminatesthevariousaspectsofthemultiplestandardsofcareinnegligencelaw.Ontheotherhand,theutilitarian-efficiencytheory,whichtreatsplaintiffsanddefendantsasindistinguishableandfungible(p.275) addendsinthemaximizationofaggregatesocialwelfare,isacompletefailure.Itnotonlyisnormativelyunattractive,assometimesisconceded,butalso,contrarytowhatisgenerallyassumed,failstoexplainorjustifyanyofthevariousaspectsofthestandardsofcareinnegligencelaw.Thisfailureisacriticalonefortheutilitarian-efficiencytheoryoflaw,whichgenerallyhasofferedtortlaw,andmoreparticularlynegligencelaw,astheprimeillustrationofthetheorysownutility.(p.276)

    Notes:(1)See,RichardW.Wright,Right,JusticeandTortLaw,thisvolume.

    (2)See,e.g.,GUIDOCALABRESI,THECOSTSOFACCIDENTS:ALEGALANDECONOMICANALYSIS(1970),2433,291308;WILLIAMM.LANDES&RICHARDA.POSNER,THEECONOMICSTRUCTUREOFTORTLAW(1987),1,89,14,1823,3123;RICHARDA.POSNER,ECONOMICANALYSISOFLAW(3dedn.,1986),113,216.

    (3)See,e.g.,LANDES&POSNER,supra,note2;A.MITCHELLPOLINSKY,ANINTRODUCTIONTOLAWANDECONOMICS(1983);STEVENSHAVELL,ECONOMICANALYSISOFACCIDENTLAW(1987);GuidoCalabresi,ConcerningCauseandtheLawofTorts:AnEssayforHarryKalven,Jr.,43U.CHI.L.REV.69(1975);RonaldH.Coase,TheProblemofSocialCost,3J.L.&ECON.1(1960).ButseeCALABRESI,supra,note2,at23987(criticizingtortlawasinefficient).

    (4)Themajorexceptionistheconsumer-orientedrisk-utilitytestfordefectiveproductdesigns.Seeinfra,textatnote51.

    (5)SeeRESTATEMENT(SECOND)OFTORTS(1963),2913(butseeinfra,note43);JOHNG.FLEMING,THELAWOFTORTS(7thedn.,1987),1028(butseeinfra,textatnote33);3FOWLERV.HARPER,FLEMINGJAMES,JR.&OSCARS.GRAY,THELAWOFTORTS(2dedn.,1986),46782;W.PAGEKBETON,DANB.DOBBS,ROBERTE.KEETON&DAVIDG.OWEN,PROSSERANDKEETONONTHELAWOFTORTS(5thedn.,1984),1713[hereinafterPROSSER&KEETON].

    (6)159F.2d169,173(2dCir.1947).

    (7)SeeJohnPratherBrown,TowardAnEconomicTheoryofLiability,2J.LEGALSTUD.323,3324(1973).

    (8)SeeMarkF.Grady,ANewPositiveEconomicTheoryofNegligence,92YALEL.J.799,8069,8219(1983).

    (9)SeeLANDES&POSNER,supra,note2,at8791.

    (10)SeeMoisanv.Loftus,178F.2d148,149(2dCir.1949);infra,textatnote32.

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 22 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    (11)SeeLANDES&POSNER,supra,note2,at201,24;Brown,supra,note7,at3334,3401,3434.

    (12)SeeRONALDDWORKIN,TAKINORIGHTSSERIOUSLY(rev.edn.,1978),934,98100,3068.Dworkinnownotesthatadutyalwaystoweighothersinterestsequallywithyourownwouldcompletelyunderminepersonalautonomyandisnotanacceptedpartofordinarymorality.Yethecontinuestoassertthatsuchadutyexistsinnegligenceandnuisancecases,whichallegedlyinvolveconflictsinindividualsabstractlegalrightsthatmustberesolvedbyapplyingthepreferredconceptionofequalityofconcerntodefineindividualsconcreterightsinparticularinteractions:seeRONALDDWORKIN,LAWSEMPIRE(1986),291312.

    (13)SeeErnestJ.Weinrib,TowardAMoralTheoryofNegligenceLaw,2LAW&PHIL.37,40,4955&note27(1983).WeinribrecentlyhasbeenpersuadedthatEnglishandCommonwealthcourtsusuallyignoretheutilitysideoftherisk-utilityformulaandfocusonthecreationofsignificantforeseeableunacceptedriskstoothers:seeErnestJ.Weinrib,UnderstandingToriLaw,23VAL.U.L.REV.485,51819&note61(1989),citingStephenR.Perry,TheImpossibilityofGeneralStrictLiability,1CAN.J.L.&JUR.147,16970(1988);seealsoRichardW.Wright,AllocatingLiabilityAmongMultipleResponsibleCauses,21U.C.DAVISL.REV.1141,117981(1988).

    (14)SeeCHARLESFRIED,ANANATOMYOFVALUES:PROBLEMSOFPERSONALANDSOCIALCHOICE(1970),414,18391,196200.

    (15)SeeWright,supra,note1;infra,note72andaccompanyingtext.

    (16)SeeGeorgeP.Fletcher,FairnessandUtilityinTortTheory,85HARV.L.REV.537,53743,550,5567,560,56971(1972).

    (17)SeeGeorgeP.Fletcher,CorrectiveJusticeforModerns,106HARV.L.REV.1658,1677,1678(1993).

    (18)LeslieBender,ALawyersPrimeronFeministTheoryandTort,38J.LEGALEDUC.3,31(1988);seeidat25,28,3036&n.113.

    (19)Seeid.at32.

    (20)SeeFeministDiscourse,MoralValuesandtheLawAConversation,34BUFF.L.REV.11,208,734(1985)(remarksofCatharineMacKinnon);MargaretJ.Radin,ThePragmatistandtheFeminist,63S.CAL.L.REV.1699,1699701,171219(1990).

    (21)SeeLeslieBender,AnOverviewofFeministTortsScholarship,78CORNELLL.REV.575,580(1993).

    (22)SeeRESTATEMENT(SECOND)OFTORTS(1963),283cmt.f,463&cmt.b,464cmt.f;FLEMING,supra,note5,at96,242.

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 23 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    (23)SeeCoase,supra,note3.

    (24)SeeWright,supra,note1.

    (25)Seeinfra,textatnotes289.

    (26)See,e.g.,Sniderv.Callahan,250F.Supp.1022,1023(W.D.Mo.1966);GUIDOCALABRESI,IDEALS,BELIEFS,ATTITUDES,ANDTHELAW(1985),247,323,4654,147note131;FLEMING,supra,note5,at1024,25860;3HARPER,JAMES&GRAY,supra,note5,at38793,42166;4id.at33442;GaryT.Schwartz,TortLawandtheEconomyinNineteenth-CenturyAmerica:AReinterpretation,90YALEL.J.1717,17437,17502,17613&note333(1981).Amoresubjectiveperspectiveisappliedtodefendantsinsituationsinwhichthedefendantsownrightsaredirectlyatissue.Seeinfra,textatnotes469andfollowingnote70.

    (27)SeeLANDES&POSNER,supra,note2,at1236.

    (28)Kantsdoctrineofvirtue,whilespecifyingobjectivemoraldutiesbasedonthecategoricalimperative,assessesthemoralblameormeritofconductintermsofonessubjectivecapacityandeffortinattemptingtoascertainandsatisfythoseduties.KantsdoctrineofRight,ontheotherhand,directlyappliestheobjectiverequirementsofthecategoricalimperativeindeterminingonesmoralandlegalresponsibilityfortheadverseeffectsthatonecausestothepersonorpropertyofothers.Thus,asKantrepeatedlyemphasizes,anactionslegalityisjudgedbyitsexternalconformitywiththeobjectiverequirementsofRight,whileitsmoralityisjudgedbyonesinternalsubjectivecapacityandeffortstoconformonesconducttotheobjectiverequirementsofthecategoricalimperative,whichgroundsalldutiesofRightandvirtue:seeIMMANUELKANT,THEMETAPHYSICSOFMORALS(MaryOregortrans.,1991)(1797);*214,21832,312,382n.*,37980,3813&n.*,38994,401,4045,4467,463;Wright,supra,note1.

    (29)Yettherangeofbehaviordeemedreasonableunderthemoresubjectiveperspectiveappliedtoplaintiffsissometimesverybroad,especiallyincasesinvolvingreligiousbelief:seeCALABRESI,supra,note26,at4654.

    (30)SeeHenryT.Terry,Negligence,29HARV.L.REV.40,424(1915)(emphasisadded).

    (31)SeeWarrenA.Seavey,NegligenceSubjectiveorObjective?,41HARV.L.REV.1,8note7(1927).

    (32)Conwayv.OBrien,111F.2d611,612(2dCir.1940),revdonothergrounds,312U.S.492(1941).

    (33)FLEMING,supra,note5,at1089(citationsomitted).

    (34)Seesupra,note13.

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 24 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    (35)[1951]A.C.850,8512.

    (36)Id.at864,8678;seeid.at8589(LordPorter),8613(LordNormand),863(LordOaksey),868(LordRadcliffe).

    (37)OverseasTankship(U.K.)Ltd.v.TheMillerS.S.Co.(WagonMound(No.2)),[1967]11A.C.617,633,6414(P.C.),perLordReid.LandesandPosnerignorethesestatementsinBoltonandTheWagonMound(No.2).SeeLANDES&POSNER,supra,note2,at99.AlltheDPDcasestheydiscussasallegedillustrationsoftheHandformulaactuallyturnonthesignificanceoftheforeseeablerisk:seeid.at96100.

    (38)Cf.LucyWebbHayesNatlTrainingSchoolforDeaconessesandMissionariesv.Perotti,419F.2d704,711(D.C.Cir.1969)(althoughriskofmentalpatientsjumpingthroughwindowinunsecuredareaofhospitalmayhavebeenverysmall,itremainedunreasonableandaproximatecauseofpatientsdeathiftherewasnogoodreasonforallowinghimtobethere).

    (39)See,e.g.,Brownv.Kendall,60Mass.(6Cush.)292,296(1850):[O]rdinarycaremeansthatkindanddegreeofcare,whichprudentandcautiousmenwoulduse,suchasisrequiredbytheexigencyofthecase,andsuchasisnecessarytoguardagainstprobabledanger.Tomakeaninevitableaccident,itmustbesuchanaccidentasthedefendantcouldnothaveavoidedbytheuseofthekindanddegreeofcarenecessarytotheexigency.SeealsoDepuev.Flateau,111N.W.1,2(Minn.1907)(statingasimilarcomprehensiveprinciple);infra,textatnote52.

    (40)See,e.g.,Curtisv.Stateexrel.DeptofTransp.,180Cal.Rptr.843,8536(Cal.Ct.App.1982).

    (41)Schwartz,supra,note26,at1757(footnotesomitted);seealsoGaryT.Schwartz,TheCharacterofEarlyAmericanTortLaw,36UCLAL.REV.641,6413&note8(1989).SchwartzsstudiesdemolishPosnersefficiencyinterpretationofnineteenthcenturytortlaw.

    (42)SeeGrimshawv.FordMotorCo.,174Cal.Rptr.348(1981);Jacksonv.Johns-MansvilleSalesCorp.,781F.2d394,399409&n.12(5thCir.1986);GaryT.Schwartz,TheMythoftheFordPintoCase,43RUTGERSL.REV.1013,10358(1991).

    (43)Osbornev.Montgomery,234N.W.372,376(Wis.1931).SeealsoRESTATEMENT(SECOND)OFTORTS(1963),291,whichinterpretsreasonablenessintermsofarisk-utilitybalance,butemphasizesincommentdthatthelegalratherthanthepopularevaluationofthesocialvalueofthecompetinginterestsgovernsandincommentethat[t]helawattachesutilitytogeneraltypesorclassesofactsasappropriatetotheadvancementofcertain[public]interestsratherthantothe[private]purposeforwhichaparticularactisdone,exceptinthecaseinwhichthepurposeisofitselfofsuchpublicutilityastojustifyanotherwiseimpermissiblerisk.

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 25 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    (44)Inmanyjurisdictions,evenoperatorsofemergencyvehiclesarenotallowedtodepartfromtheordinaryrulesoftheroadintheabsenceofexplicitstatutoryauthorization,andtheymuststrictlycomplywiththeadditionalprecautionsspecifiedinthestatuteasaminimumrequirementforavoidingbeingheldnegligent:seeJ.H.Cooper,Annotations,82A.L.R.2d312(1962)(firedepartmentvehicles),83A.L.R.2d383(1962)(policevehicles),84A.L.R.2d121(1962)(ambulances).

    (45)Seesupra,textatnote26.

    (46)Asmorethanonecourthasnoted,thevaryingstandardsofreasonablecarewithrespecttoon-premisesrisksdonot,asissometimesassumed,constitutedeparturesfromorlimitationsonthegeneraldutyofreasonablecare,butratherareelaborationsofthisgeneraldutyinthecontextofthedifferenttypesofsituationsthatmayarise:see,e.g.,Dillonv.TwinStateGas&Elec.Co.,163A.Ill,113(N.H.1932).

    (47)SeeFLEMING,supra,note5,at41753;PROSSER&KEETON,supra,note5,at386434.

    (48)[1972]A.C.877,8989;seeid.at9367(LordDiplock).

    (49)Id.at925;seeid.at90910(LordMorris),916&91921(LordWilberforce),9247(LordPearson),9367&9413(LordDiplock).SeealsoSchwartz,supra,note26,at17667&nn.366&367(notingtheAmericancourtsattentiontosuchequalfreedomconcernsinnineteenth-andtwentieth-centuryon-premisesinjurycases).

    (50)See,e.g.,POSNER,supra,note2,at467,1589,1701;cf.infra,textatnote59.

    (51)SeeRESTATEMENT(THIRD)OFTORTS:PRODUCTSLIABILITY(TentativeDraftNo.2,1995),2cmt.eat24(listinganumberofconsumer-relatedrisksandbenefitsasrelevantfactors,andstatingitisnotafactorthattheimpositionofliabilitywouldhaveanegativeeffectoncorporateearnings,orwouldreduceemploymentinagivenindustry);id.at27.

    (52)Hauserv.Chicago,R.I.&P.Ry.,219N.W.60,62(Iowa1928).

    (53)See,e.g.,Canterburyv.Spence,464F.2d772(D.C.Cir.1972);Cobbsv.Grant,502P.2d1(Cal.1972);cf.Mohrv.Williams,104N.W.12(Minn.1905)(battery).Iftherewasnoconsentatalltothemedicaltreatmentoriftheconsentwasinvalid,abatteryactionisappropriate.However,iftheplaintiffwasawareofthenatureofthetreatmentandfreelyassentedtoit,butwasnotinformedofattendantmaterialrisks,anegligenceactionisappropriate:see,e.g.,Sidawayv.BoardofGovrsofBethlemRoyalHosp.&MaudsleyHosp.[1985]A.C.871,883,885,892,894;Reiblv.Hughes(1980)114D.L.R.3d1,1011(Can.);Minkv.UniversityofChicago,460F.Supp.713(N.D.111.1978).

    (54)SeeRogersv.Whitaker,109A.L.R.625(Austl.1992);Reiblv.Hughes(1980)114D.L.R.3d1,1213(Can.).

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 26 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    (55)[1985]A.C.871,882,88590,9035.

    (56)Sidawayv.BethlemRoyalHosp.Govrs,[1984]1AllE.R.1018,1027(C.A.)(DonaldsonM.R.);seeid.at10301(DunnL.J.);affd.[1985]1A.C.at8905(LordDiplock),895901(LordsBridgeandKeith).

    (57)See[1985]1A.C.at895(LordDiplock),8989(LordsBridgeandKeith).

    (58)Id.at900;accord,Blyv.Rhoads,222S.E.2d783,787(Va.1976).

    (59)Cf.supra,textatnote50.

    (60)InCarrollTowing,theplaintiffsemployee,asaresultofhisabsenceforsomeunknownpurpose,puttheplaintiffsbargeatriskofbeingdamagedorsunkthroughnegligentmishandlingbyothers:seeUnitedStatesv.CarrollTowingCo.,159F.2d169,1734(2dCir.,1947).

    (61)Seesupra,textatnotes229,32,512.

    (62)See,e.g.,Bakerv.T.E.Hopkins&Son,Ltd.[1959]3AllE.R.225(C.A.)(wantonorfoolhardy);FLEMING,supra,note5,at1557(utterlyfoolhardy).

    (63)43N.Y.502(1871).

    (64)SeeTerry,supra,note30,at424;supra,textatnote30.

    (65)43N.Y.at5056.

    (66)SeeLANDES&POSNER,supra,note2,at1001;Terry,supra,note30,at434.

    (67)SeePROSSER&KEETON,supra,note5,at3737&nn.21&31.

    (68)SeeErnestJ.Weinrib,TheCaseforaDutytoRescue,90YALEL.J.247,2806(1980).

    (69)SeePOSNER,supra,note2,at174.

    (70)Seeid.;LANDES&POSNER,supra,note2,at1436.

    (71)SeeWright,supra,note1.

    (72)Howfar[theduty]shouldextenddepends,inlargepart,onwhateachpersonstrueneedsareinviewofhissensibilities,anditmustbelefttoeachtodecidethisforhimself.Foramaximofpromotingothershappinessatthesacrificeofonesownhappiness,onestrueneeds,wouldconflictwithitselfifitweremadeauniversallaw.Hencethisdutyisonlyawideone;thedutyhasinitalatitudefordoingmoreorless,andnospecificlimitscanbeassignedtowhatshouldbedone.Thelawholdsonlyformaxims,notforspecificactions:KANT,supra,note28,at*393;seeid.at*390,4524.

  • The Standards of Care in Negligence Law

    Page 27 of 27

    PRINTED FROM OXFORD SCHOLARSHIP ONLINE (www.oxfordscholarship.com). (c) Copyright Oxford University Press, 2015.All Rights Reserved. Under the terms of the l icence agreement, an individual user may print out a PDF of a single chapter of amonograph in OSO for personal use (for details see http://www.oxfordscholarship.com/page/privacy-policy). Subscriber: PontificiaUniversidad Catolica del Peru (PUCP); date: 30 April 2015

    (73)SeeErnestJ.Weinrib,LawasaKantianIdeaofReason,87COLUM.L.REV.472,4889(1987).

    (74)See,e.g.,KANT,supra,note28,at*230.

    (75)SeeRichardA.Epstein,CausationandCorrectiveJustice:AReplytoTwoCritics,8J.LEGALSTUD.477,491(1979).

    (76)SeeRichardA.Epstein,ATheoryofStrictLiability,2J.LEGAL.STUD.151,1989(1973).

    Accessbroughttoyouby: PontificiaUniversidadCatolicadelPeru(PUCP)