The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

download The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

of 50

Transcript of The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    1/50

    The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics: A SymposiumAuthor(s): Atul Kohli, Peter Evans, Peter J. Katzenstein, Adam Przeworski, Susanne HoeberRudolph, James C. Scott, Theda SkocpolSource: World Politics, Vol. 48, No. 1 (Oct., 1995), pp. 1-49Published by: Cambridge University PressStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/25053951

    Accessed: 19/03/2010 11:23

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless

    you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you

    may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

    Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cup.

    Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed

    page of such transmission.

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    Cambridge University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to World

    Politics.

    http://www.jstor.org

    http://www.jstor.org/stable/25053951?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cuphttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=cuphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/25053951?origin=JSTOR-pdf
  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    2/50

    THE ROLE OF THEORY INCOMPARATIVE POLITICSA Symposium

    ByATUL KOHLI, PETER EVANS, PETER J.KATZENSTEIN,ADAM PRZEWORSKI, SUSANNE HOEBER RUDOLPH,JAMESC. SCOTT, andTHEDA SKOCPOL*

    Introduction: Atul Kohli

    THECenter of International Studies at Princeton University organized a symposium during 1993-94 on the topic of "The Role of

    Theory in Comparative Politics." The symposium seminars generatedconsiderable interest among participants, enough to lead the editors ofWorld Politics to publish this edited and condensed version of the proceedings for

    a broader audience. A group of distinguished scholars?Peter Evans, Peter Katzenstein, Adam Przeworski, Susanne HoeberRudolph, James Scott, andTheda Skocpol?responded to the mainthemes of the symposium. These themes are itemized below followedby the responses of the individual scholars. Some of the main conclusions that emerge from these diverse responses are then summarized atthe end.

    The field of comparative political analysis is again embroiled in theoretical controversy. While theoretical debates are hardly new to comparative politics (for example, no single paradigm has dominated thefield for too long, and both methodological and ideological differencesare common among comparative politics scholars), current claims andcounterclaims appear to be deeply divisive. At one end of the methodological spectrum, there are the new students of political culture, inspired by a variety of postmodern or culturally relativistic claims, whodoubt the value of causal explanations altogether and thus of conventional social science theorizing in comparative politics. The other

    *The symposium was organized under the auspices of the Center of International Studies, Princeton University. Symposium seminars were all held at Princeton University during 1993-94. Thanksare due to John Waterbury, the director of the Center of International Studies, for his encouragementand support. This edited and condensed version of the proceedings was prepared for publication inWorld Politics.

    WorldPolitics 48 (October 1995), 1-49

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    3/50

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    4/50

    SYMPOSIUM 3forces that shape the evolution of social science paradigms, I will begin

    my discussion there. Iwould then like to explain more clearlywhat Imean by the eclectic messy center, using my own work as an example.This done, I will discuss why ahistoric, asocial versions of rationalchoice or game-theoretic analysis are unlikely to overrun the center.Finally, Iwill talk aboutwhy I see the role of cultural theories as inherently partial.In thinking about the evolution of social science paradigms, it is useful to ask about microfoundations. What motivates us to undertake thekind of research and writing thatwe do?Most scholars would agreethat part of the answer is that we care about particular cases. If Iwere todo a study of inflation, for example, itmight be in part because Iwasinterested in its general parameters, but itwould also be because I happen to have friends who live in a country where inflation has run at 30percent amonth, tearing apart their lives. As long as we care about particular cases, we are compelled to do history, to try to understand specific sequences of events and to acquire the ideographic knowledge thatunderstanding specific sequences of events entails.

    There is another, even more primitive and pervasive set of incentivesinvolved inmost social science investigations. We would all like to predict when something bad or something good is likely to happen to usor, better still, figure out how to increase the likelihood of somethinggood happening. We are therefore always trying to conceptualize a particular sequence as one example of a larger set of similar sequences. Themore we know about the set, the more likely we are to be able to anticipate the outcome of any given sequence. If we can describe key characteristics parsimoniously, we can handle bigger sets and talk aboutlarger numbers of individual outcomes. The desire to predict is part ofsocial science, not because we are positivists but because social scientists share with everyone else the desire to know what is likely to happen to them and how they might be able to improve prospectiveoutcomes.

    Our interest in particular cases thus keeps pushing us in the direction ofdoing history.

    Our interest infiguring outwhat isgoing to happen to us makes even the crudest and most limited theorizingtremendously attractive. Neither motivation is likely to disappear fromthe social science scene, regardless of changes in intellectual fashion.The agenda, activity, and paradigms of the social science communityare not shaped only by the motivations of individual scholars. Nor arethey shaped only by discourse within the community itself ? laThomas

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    5/50

    4 WORLD POLITICSKuhn.2 Agendas are powerfully shaped by the demands and constraintsof consumers and patrons. Everyone, from our students to the NationalScience Foundation, is interested in having

    us elucidateparticular

    historical sequences and wants to know more about the likely consequences of social action. They provide persistent incentives, both forthe ideographic understanding of particular sequences and for predictions.Their pressure fits nicely with the kind of work that is found inthe eclectic messy center of comparative politics.

    By now, what Imean by the "eclectic messy center" should be clearer.It iswork that draws on general theories whenever it can but also caresdeeply about particular historical outcomes. It sees particular cases asthe building blocks for general theories and theories as lenses to identify what is interesting and significant about particular cases. Neithertheories nor cases are sacrosanct. Cases are always too complicated tovindicate a single theory, so scholars who work in this tradition arelikely to draw on am?lange of theoretical traditions inhopes of gaininggreater purchase on the cases they care about. At the same time, a compelling interpretation of a particular case is only interesting if it pointsto ways of understanding other cases as well, so scholars in this tradition are often chastised for "trespassing" on the historical cases of otherspecialists in their search for broader generalizations.Since I consider my own work very much a part of the eclectic messycenter, let me use it to illustrate the interplay of theory and cases. Firstof all, theory has been very important tome because it helps definewhat questions are worth looking at and, by extension, provides an external definition of what cases are most interesting to examine. Inshort, it defines "big ideas." My early work on Brazil was originally motivated by a desire to understand how the process of industrializationwas affected by the fact that economic actors from other countries wereplaying a central role in that process.3Why did I think this questionwas important? Heated general debates between proponents of economic growth and dependency theorists made my particular investigation seem relevant and worthwhile. Later in the 1980s I began to focusmore

    specificallyon the role of the state in industrial transformation.4

    Once again, the topic seemed important in part because big theoreticalassertions were being made, most prominently by neoliberal propo2 In this sense my vision of the evolution of scientific paradigms is distinctly "un-Kuhnian." Cf.

    Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962).3 See Peter Evans, Dependent Development: The Alliance ofMultinational, State and Local Capital inBrazil (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1979).4 See, for example, Peter Evans, Embedded Autonomy: States, Firms, and Industrial Transformation(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1995).

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    6/50

    SYMPOSIUM 5nents of modernized and aggressive versions of classic theories of theminimalist state.

    I should point out that in both cases, theory, in the sense of bigideas, was defined more broadly than in the Kuhnian sense of a discourse within a particular community of investigators. These theoretical debates engaged me because they resonated outside my owncommunity of scholars. The debates between transnationalism and dependency and around the modern resuscitations of the theory of theminimalist state have been driven, not only by academics, but also bypoliticians, policymakers, and even "regular" people who see these issues as

    importantto their lives.

    General theoretical perspectives have also been important in mywork as a source of tools. I draw on general theoretical frameworks tohelp me describe mechanisms that make the behavior of actors and institutions causally plausible. For example, when trying to distinguishthe behavior of multinational firms from that of local entrepreneurs, Ihave drawn (parasitically) on a rudimentary set of propositions frommicroeconomics.5 By taking the conventional theory of the firm,adding a little bit of industrial organization, a little bit of HerbertSimon, and some political arguments about issues of nationalism andlegitimacy, Iwas able to specify causally plausible mechanisms thathelped explain how these actors behaved. The result was eclectic and

    messy, but it helped illuminate the case.Likewise, in my more recent work on the state, several theories of

    how organizations work?for example, simple economic models abouthow bureaucrats function and what kind of incentive systems bureaucracies create?have again been important in trying to generate causallyplausible mechanisms. Some generic "cultural" ideas about when peopleare likely to care about what other people think of them and feel accordingly constrained have also been important. No single ready-madetheoretical model can provide all the tools necessary to explain the casesI am interested in, but an eclectic combination offers enough leverageto make a start.

    My attempts to investigate big questions or to work through the implications of plausible causal mechanisms have always been tied to particular cases. I end up presenting complicated pictures of institutionalconfigurations that are very much rooted in particular historical settings. Nevertheless, I have always felt that, if they were to be useful,

    51 say "parasitically" because Imake no claim to be a contributor to the development of this body oftheory.

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    7/50

    6 WORLD POLITICSthese configurations had to be conceptualized inways that were potentially separable from the settings inwhich theywere originally derived.In order for my efforts at deciphering particular historical sequences tobe worthwhile, they have to speak to other cases as well. The generalideas I derive from a particular case may or may not fit other cases, butthey should at least seem worth applying.The notion of "dependent development," which I found useful insummarizing some key features of Brazils post-World War II development trajectory, is a good example. After working on Brazil for a number of years, I became interested inEast Asia. I began by examining theapplicability of dependent development and found that itdid not apply.Figuring out why that was so not only helped my understanding ofEast Asia but also led me to reformulate my earlier ideas of what wasdistinctive about Brazil.61 would like to think that every time I gain abetter understanding of a particular historical sequence, the process willalso generate some ideas that will be useful in other cases, useful notonly to me but to others as well.Given my sense of the character of work in the eclectic messy center,it should be clearwhy I feel it isunlikely that the centerwill be overrun.The absence of well-defined consensus on methodological models ortheoretical propositions may appear to be a source of vulnerability, butit also makes it easier to absorb new ideas. The persistent movement

    between cases and theories makes it hard for any particular theory togain dominance and makes it easier for the tradition to speak to a broadaudience.

    In my own case, the absence of threat is probably most obvious in thecase of the recent offshoots of microeconomics. It is hard to see theseapproaches as undercutting my work. To the contrary, as a potentialparasite, I hope, for example, that people working on principal-agenttheories can come up with simpler and more powerful ways of describing how firms and bureaucracies behave. I could certainly use bettertools.

    Some might say that I am na?vely underestimating the natural imperialism of strategic actor models, that formal models are already encroaching on an ever-wider range of political behavior, and willcontinue to do so until they constitute an all-encompassing paradigminstead of simply a set of tools. Frankly, I think there are several reasons

    why this is not going to happen. First, it is very difficult to aggregate6See Evans, "Class, State, and Dependence in East Asia: Some Lessons for Latin Americanists," inFrederic Deyo, ed., The Political Economy of theNew Asian Industrialism (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell Univer

    sity Press, 1987).

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    8/50

    SYMPOSIUM 7from microfoundations without changing your style of analysis and exposition. Indeed, it isnot just difficult, but inefficient. Trying to explaininstitutions by aggregating individual rationalities is like trying to explain chemical reactions by using propositions from subatomic physics.It may be possible in principle, but it is neither efficient nor effective.

    Equally important is the fact that rational choice theorists are notimmune to the pressures of providing a comprehensible understandingof particular sequences. Consumers and patrons will push them to domore history. Once they do, their work will begin to involve an increasing amount of detailed analysis of particular institutions and look morelike work in the eclectic messy

    center. As sophisticated understandingsof game-theoretic models become more widely diffused among newgenerations of researchers, the novelty of asocial and ahistorical modeling will pale. The tendency for game-theoretic elements to become embedded in historically and institutionally complex arguments willincrease and the approach will become progressively less threatening tothe messy eclectic center.

    There is one other reason why I am less worried about the expansion of rational choice theorizing than I might have been some yearsback. Over the last ten years theoretical work at the core of economics,in both trade and growth theory,7 has opened up space for multipleequilibria and path dependence. These new theoretical approaches aresaying that even in principle, formal theoretical models cannot providedeterminative answers without knowing something about individualsequences of events. There has to be an element of path dependence,which is to say history. So even as the economistic models are makingtheir forays into other social science disciplines, the theoretical redoubtsfrom which they came are changing in ways that are much morefriendly to the kind of work which goes on in the messy eclectic center.But what about new forms of cultural analysis? Like rational choiceand game-theoretic approaches, cultural approaches have certainly experienced a boom in recent years. Might they overrun the eclectic

    messy center? Anyone who doubted that culturally oriented approachesmight be used to address core issues of comparative politics was certainly forced to reassess his or her views when confronted with a recentarticle by that hard-nosed veteran of the field, Samuel Huntington, inwhich he argued that world politics was entering a new phase, wherein

    7See, for example, Paul R. Krugman, Rethinking International Trade (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1990);Paul Romer, "The Origins of Endogenous Growth,"JournalofEconomic Perspectives 8 (Winter 1994);and Brian W. Arthur, "Positive Feedbacks in the Economy," Scientific American (February 1990),92-99.

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    9/50

    8 WORLD POLITICSthe dominant sources of conflict would be culturally based, that is,based on a politics of identity and culturally distinctive values ratherthan on the politics postulated by conventional theories of politicaleconomy.8 Not only did Huntington make the argument, but his articlewas touted inForeign Affairs as the "X" article of the post-cold war era.The article, although fascinating, is also a good illustration of thelimits to the ascendance of culturally based arguments. In it,Huntington conjures up aworld in which a "Confucian-Islamic connection"confronts "theWest." Imagining such aworld may be a nostalgic tripfor those who miss the old clarity of global communism versus the free

    world, butas a

    plausible description of the contemporary world it simply does not fly.The extent to which the vision is misguided is most obvious whenyou look at the Confucian end of this connection. In constructing hisconnection, Huntington makes much of the fact that the Chinese were

    willing to make some money by selling missiles to some not very pricesensitive customers in the Middle East. Iwould agree that the transaction is indicative of behavior at the "Confucian" end, but it is not aboutcultural affinity, it is about sharp business practice.The forces that are reshaping China today are much more about selling Nike shoes to the U.S. than they are about selling missiles to theMiddle East. InEast Asia it is the politics of growth and accumulationthat is delivering the goods. Interest-based political economy arguments are becoming more, not less, relevant. Ifwe are looking for plausible causal mechanisms in the world's most populous and rapidly

    growing region, it is time to "round up the usual suspects" of politicaleconomy. Some combination of markets, bureaucracies, and informal

    mechanisms in the pursuit of power and conventional material gainsmakes sense both to political leaders and to people in the street.As long as we live in aworld where the normal, interest-based logicof political economy remains plausible to policymakers and to the people in the street, cultural analysis is not going to overrun the eclectic

    messy center. Obviously, we should use the analysis of discourse, values,and symbols to modify, complement, and contextualize conventionalpolitical economy arguments, but we are not likely to get very far byconstructing an alternative worldview that completely bypasses oldfashioned power and interests.

    Advocates of cultural analysis may protest my using the work ofHuntington as an example, since he is hardly in the vanguard of post

    8The reference is to Samuel Huntington, "The Clash of Civilizations," Foreign Affairs 72 (Summer1993).

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    10/50

    SYMPOSIUM 9modern thinkers. I would respond that more sophisticated ways of analyzing discourse and symbols do not escape the problems that I haveraised in relation toHuntington, and they have additional problems oftheir own. Insofar as they are indeed anticausal, they must fly in theface of one of the two generic social constraints that I outlined at thebeginning. The consumers and patrons of social science want help infiguring out what is likely to happen to them if they take one course ofaction rather than another. Individual practitioners who refuse to deliverpredictions and are onlywilling to discuss theways inwhich sociallife is inherently inchoate and unpredictable are unlikely candidates forestablishing hegemony.One important caveat is in order. People want prediction becausethey are looking for better outcomes. Persistent bad times, whether explicable or not, bring disillusionment with theories that claim to enhance predictability. The conventional logic of political economy hasfailed to deliver for a large share of the world's population and has little prospect of delivering for them in the future. Those living on theother end of Huntingtons Confucian-Islamic connection are a case inpoint. On the Islamic end of the supposed connection, there is a regionand people that have long suffered political humiliation and, over thelast ten to fifteen years, have suffered from declining growth and tradeas well. It is hardly surprising that under such circumstances movements based on identity and culturally distinctive values should gainstrength. To the extent that they do, the causally plausible microfoundations of conventional political economy become increasingly lesscompelling.

    The global political economy includes regions inwhich states andmarkets are delivering and regions in which they are not. To analyzesuch aworld, one must combine conventional political economy kindsof analysis, which focus on how people get what they want, with cultural approaches, which help us understand the nature of the preferences themselves. And, of course, this combining of conventionalpolitical economy with approaches that focus on the origin and natureof

    preferencesthemselves is

    preciselythe sort of eclectic work that the

    center of comparative politics has practiced for a long time.Let me sum up. First, individual and societal incentives push us toward the detailed examination of individual cases, toward history. Atthe same time, they demand guidelines to future outcomes?that is,prediction. The character of work in the messy eclectic center is an effective response to these pressures. Second, rational choice and gametheoretic approaches are less threatening to the messy eclectic center

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    11/50

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    12/50

    SYMPOSIUM 11provided me with a distinctive perspective. Contemporary research oncomparative and international issues increasingly calls for blurring thedistinctions between political economy, security, and culture. And thereis a growing need to erase the barriers between comparative politics?of which American politics is a part?international relations, and political theory. My own research has taught me that the state is not aunitary actor and that the origin of political preferences?and hencehistory?matters. But most importantly, I have learned that you haveto ask important and interesting questions. That is the hardest thing todo and the hardest thing to teach. We can teach paradigms, analyticalperspectives, and methods by taking them off the professional shelf andtransporting them to the classroom. What we cannot teach so readily ishow to ask important and interesting questions, the hallmark of superior research and great teaching.What do we mean by comparative research? To this question I offerthe answer I learned in graduate school, for it is still useful and plausible: comparative research is a focus on analytical relationships amongvariables validated by social science, a focus that ismodified by differences in the context inwhich we observe and measure those variables.

    My church of scholarship is a cathedral not a chapel; hence I subscribeto an expansive notion of "social science." The church of scholarship accommodates many different sects often bent on fighting holy wars: behavioralists and nonbehavioralists then, rationalists and interpretivistsnow. In my view international research should focus on internationaland global phenomena, including the relations between states andtransnational processes and structures that occur either outside oracross societal and state boundaries.

    As I look at the intellectual vicissitudes of the comparative and international fields, they appear to move in cycles. In the field of international relations, for example, one cycle started in the 1960s, when muchoriginal and imaginative work was done on strategic theory and national security. In the 1970s the innovative scholarship in internationalrelations moved toward the field of political economy and eventuallybranched off in two directions. The first branch focused on qualitativeresearch, with the state and other institutions as its main analyticalfocus.The second branch developed along rationalist lines by focusingon international regimes and other international institutions. As comparative and international political economy were becoming establishedareas of scholarship, security studies in the early and mid-1980s experienced an intellectual renaissance led by a new cohort of scholars. This

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    13/50

    12 WORLD POLITICSgroup, farther removed from active policy engagement than its predecessors of the 1950s and 1960s, was committed to applying standardstructural or rationalist explanations to contemporary and historicalcases of security conflicts between states. With the end of the cold wartheir concentrated focus on questions of military security, as well astheir statecentric perspective, has provoked vigorous debate. It is generating a new corpus of scholarship that will substantially expand thefield of security studies not by replacing strategic studies but by complementing itwith a broader view of security and by going beyond thestate-centered perspectives of the mainstream.These two

    cyclesare now

    movingto

    productivenew intersections?

    for even ifworld revolutions do not change the habits of scholars, boredom does. First, scholars interested in security or political economy areseeking to apply the insights of one field to the other. Furthermore, ascultural and rationalist perspectives direct our attention to new questions?and, one hopes, new insights?in the fields of security and political economy, there is less interest in the predictable disagreementsbetween realist scholars of security who favor structural explanations andliberal scholars of political economy who favor rationalist explanations.

    Comparative work in recent decades has witnessed a move awayfrom political culture and political sociology and from styles of analysisthat tended to disregard institutions. Critics ofthat literature havepointed out that it typically treated culture as little more than a residualvariable. This focus was replaced by a renewed attention to the role ofinstitutions in politics. The new institutionalism took two forms,"thick" and "thin." The "thin" version offers a rationalist style of analysis. Derived from transaction-cost analysis and public choice theory, ittakes the role of institutions seriously as facilitating solutions to coordination problems. The "thick" form is concerned with both states and social structures, not with just one of them, and it looks at social sectors,

    political coalitions, political institutions, and ideological constraints.These two movements in comparative studies were mutually rein

    forcing and confronted somewhat related problems. For thick institutional analyses the problem was one of disaggregation. This researchtradition does a good job of illuminating a broad variety of political settings, but it is less successful at connecting what it has to say aboutstates, social structures, political coalitions, and ideologies to individualdecision makers. Conversely, thin institutionalism confronts the problem of aggregation. Done carefully, thin institutionalism tells us muchabout the microfoundations of individual policy choices and politics,but it ismuch weaker in generalizing from the specific to the general.

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    14/50

    SYMPOSIUM 13Because corresponding problems continue to bedevil both types of institutional analyses, scholarsworking inboth traditions typically shouldbe cautious about touting the virtues of their favored approaches.

    The renaissance of sociological and cultural studies was a second development that came later to the comparative field. With its focus onthe institutionalization of meaning, some of this research was evidentlyinfluenced by the work of the previous decade. Here too there is a bifurcation between what Iwould call, for lack of a better term, the objective versus the subjective move. I will put aside the subjective move,by which I have inmind postmodernism in its various guises. It isdeeply influenced by intellectual

    currents inEuropeas

    they apply in thehumanities and in cultural studies, as well as in anthropology, to a variety of texts and are often directed to the analysis of a very expansive notion of politics. Much postmodern scholarship rejects the social scienceenterprise as I understand it here, submitting competing truth claimsto empirical tests rather than simply offering playful illustrations.The objective move is concerned with identities and norms. Normsare understood in the sociological tradition as areas of intersubjectiveagreement, that is, as dealing with objective reality not with subjectivefactors. This conception of culture differs from that of the 1960s, whichfocused on individually held values. Obviously there is a relationshipbetween intersubjectively shared norms and deeply held subjective values. But compared with psychologists, political scientists are less wellequipped to understand these relationships. This sociological version ofcultural studies is important for comparative analysis because normsand identities often get institutionalized. The two research programs,institutionalism and objective cultural studies, are thus as intimately related to one another as are rationalism and culturalism, economics andsociology.The debates between realism and idealism in the 1940s and 1950sand between quantitative-behavioral and qualitative-historical approaches in the 1960s were followed in the 1980s and 1990s by the"third debate" in international relations. It has raised ontological, epistemological, and methodological issues that make mainstream realistand liberal scholars uncomfortable because they are not particularlywell equipped to handle them. Typically, such discussions occur only atthe margins of the field of comparative politics. Scholars of comparativepolitics have by and large shied away from extreme versions of a nomothetic and typically rational choice approach, as practiced in some specialized subfields of international studies. Similarly, comparativepolitics scholarship has taken a centrist approach to cultural studies, ac

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    15/50

    14 WORLD POLITICScepting the insights of both cultural and rationalist styles of analysis.There is a very good reason for this centrism. Many strands of interpretivist research rely on methods that tend toward historical reconstructions or genealogical excavations rather than hypothesisformulation and testing. But interpretive social science is particularlyhelpful formaking us think about issues of identity that evidently havebecome more important in the contemporary analysis of comparativepolitics than they were two or three decades ago. Rationalist theorieshave to date been unable to shed significant light on the processes bywhich identities are built up or down. Conversely, these approaches arewell tailored to the analysis of choices of individual

    orcorporate

    actorswhose identity is assumed. In brief, between the false extremes of bothrational and cultural approaches, comparative analysis continues to explore a world of power and institutions in which cultural norms andidentities interact with interests.

    As is true of most other scholarship in political science, internationaland comparative research, too, is driven by real-world events. This doesnot mean that we study only the present, for as Schopenhauer has reminded us, newspapers are the second hands of history?they alwaystell the wrong time. But real-world events spark our imagination, send

    ing us back to the past, which we can then see in very different terms.Rethinking the past in light of the present and conversely rethinkingthe present in light of the past are productive ways of searching for important and intriguing questions. The momentous political upheaval ofthe last decade has spurred renewed interest in history in both comparative and international studies, as scholars in both fields turn to the pastfor insights and categories of analysis thatwill help us get our bearingsin a present that is in flux.

    Furthermore, my intuition tells me that real-world events are drivingscholarship in a second direction. With the collapse of bipolarity contemporary events are moving us to aworld of regions and a new kind ofarea studies that connect comparative and international research. Sincethe late 1960s traditional area studies has been criticized relentlessly,and often justifiably, for its lack of attention to explicit comparisons andtestable propositions and for its proclivity for analysis that privileges apresumed and insufficiently analyzed cultural uniqueness of a particularcountry or region. The new kind of regional studies that I envisionwould connect expertise in language and familiarity with culture andhistory with a cast of mind interested in either testing the plausibilityof different propositions or analytical perspectives against a body ofempirical evidence or illuminating that evidence with a variety of in

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    16/50

    SYMPOSIUM 15terpretive methods. It is worth pointing out explicitly that sincethe coding of cases and variables that precedes the testing of hypotheses is often itself an act of interpretation, the two activities are closelyrelated.

    With the collapse of the bipolar structure of power there are manygood reasons why we are moving toward aworld of regions. This is notaworld sensibly thought about only in the categories of the 1930s and1940s. For in this world of regions there exist two noteworthy globalprocesses?the legacy of two hundred years of Anglo-Saxon imperialism?that are no longer tied firmly to territorially anchored states. Thefirst diffuses technologies through markets; hence, states

    nolonger fullycontrol global profits, even though they may contest that fact. Thesecond diffuses human rights and international law; also politicallycontested by states, this process, too, has had profound political conse

    quences in recent years. Thus, states will rarely give up their sovereignrights, but their sovereignty is nevertheless affected by processes thatthey no longer fully control. In turn these processes will reknit the relationships between regions and states in novel ways. This creates a newarena for politics, one that did not exist fifty years ago. Although hegemons sought to dominate their regions and international markets wereencroaching on state prerogatives, global processes touching the rationalist realm of profit and the cultural realm of identity did not have thepolitical prominence then that they enjoy now. Today sworld regionsand the states that inhabit them have to respond to these globalprocesses.

    To recognize and understand or interpret these processes requiresbridging the world of comparative and international studies. A sharpdistinction between a nomothetic and an idiographic social science,more recently between rationalism and culturalism, will do little to helpus recognize andmake intelligible this world of regions. For anybodyseeking to answer an important and interesting question would be afool to sacrifice the insights that can be gleaned from either perspective.Although it is true that among the blind the one-eyed isking, it isalso true that good depth perception requires two eyes.The new regionalism creates local processes of political mobilizationand demobilization around internationally and regionally induced political struggles over power, markets, and identities. The intersections of

    global and local processes and the connections between regional contexts and national states may give us a sense of some of the newlyemerging processes and structures as we witness the collapse of some ofthe old.

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    17/50

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    18/50

    SYMPOSIUM 17mentally, to look for a case that is exactly like Chile in all aspectsother than its regime and, possibly, its rate of economic growth?a"Chile 1985" that is democratic?and then to compare the authoritarianChile with the democratic "Chile." Ifwe then find that this democratic "Chile 1985" has a positive rate of growth, we conclude thatdemocracy is good for growth. If decay ismore profound, we discoverthat democracy is bad for growth.And this is indeed what we do.We try to emulate experiments byfinding "matches," cases that are "comparable." The logic is the samewhether we have just one such pair or many. When doing comparativeresearch, we are told that one should find cases that are as similar aspossible, in as many aspects as possible, and then find a crucial difference that can explain what one wants to explain. We have this notion ofthings being "comparable" as if comparability were an intrinsic characteristic of our objects of investigation rather than a result of our judgments. A comparison of Sweden and Denmark is acceptable. However,ifwe compare Sweden with Chile or Kenya with Argentina, we are toldthat this is not a legitimate operation, that this is like comparing applesand pears. Note that the entire organization of our discipline?the institutional structure of political science departments, of professional associations, and of the Social Science Research Council?is organizedalong geographical lines. I think the underlying construction is precisely this emphasis on quasi experimentation, that is, having cases thatare comparable so we can control aspects that are common and thenmove step by step, variable by variable.Let me broaden the range of examples. We ask questions about effects of coups on poverty, about the impact of trade policies on economic performance, of electoral systems on political participation, ofrevolutions on social change, or of class structure on the emergence ofdemocracy. These research questions share the same logic and we approach them the same way, that is, we find matching cases. We take

    Germany versus England or Japan versus China, and then we compare.Now, to apply this procedure to my question, that is, the impact of

    regimeson economic growth, Iwill take 139 countries, between 1950or the year of independence and 1990 or the last year for which data areavailable. I classify their regimes as democracies or dictatorships. If Ithen calculate means, Iwill find that democracies during this periodhad an average annual rate of growth of 2.44 percent per year, whereasauthoritarian regimes grew at a rate of 1.82 percent per year. If I alsodo regression analysis, it will reveal a significant, positive effect of

    democracy. One may then conclude that regimes matter for growth:

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    19/50

    18 WORLD POLITICSdemocracy promotes development. Much of comparative analysis proceeds in the manner just delineated: what Imean by comparisons is thisprocedure of matching cases.

    Suppose, however, that the fact that Chile was a dictatorship in 1985is not independent of its economic growth. There are several possiblereasons for this: first, growth may affect the survival of regimes; second,there may be other underlying factors, such as the level of development,that affect both regime selection and rates of growth; third, there maybe some unobservable factors (including errors in measurement) thatare common to both variables. Whatever the underlying mechanism,and I will focus on the first, what are the implications for comparativeanalysis? The main result will be that there will be cases in our samplewithout amatch and our inferences will be biased.

    Let me explain. Suppose that democracies that experience an economic decline of 5 percent in a particular year die instantaneously,while dictatorships survive or die independently of economic conditions. We will then observe dictatorships over a full range of exogenousconditions, but democracies over only a part of that range. There willbe dictatorships facing adverse conditions, for which there will be nomatch among democracies. The observable population of democracieswill be a biased sample of all the potential conditions.

    Indeed, I think that we have to think about the world in this way, orat least suspect the world of being endogenously produced. If we believe that the conditions under which we live are somehow created bypeople in pursuit of their ends, then the social world which we observearound us is not given, that is, is not independent of our actions, andnot independent of various outcomes that we try to explain. We thusmust treat the observable world as having been produced by "us," thatis, as having been generated endogenously. More specifically, an additional powerful intuition is that the world nurtures successes and eliminates failures. If so, one suspects that there should be more successes to

    be observed than failures. Iwant to emphasize immediately that I amnot talking about samples here; this is not a question of sampling fromavailable observations. Sampling by the dependent variable is elementary textbook material and it is not what is at stake. The issue rather isthat the observable world is not a random sample of the possible underlying conditions. If we want to compare, we must process the impact of independent variables?in my case, democracy and dictatorship,or in other cases, parliamentary and presidential systems, revolution orno revolution, landlord domination versus bourgeois domination?

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    20/50

    SYMPOSIUM 19across some range of similar conditions. But we cannot expect to findobservations across the same conditions.

    Let me provide one piece of evidence to buttress the point I am making. Dictatorships in which per capita income declines have an ex

    pected life of forty years. Dictatorships that are growing economicallycan expect to live fifty-three years. Democracies, by contrast, have anexpected life of eighteen years when the economy declines and an expected life of sixty-eight years when the economy grows. Democraciesare thus much more vulnerable to economic crises than dictatorships.In order to assess the impact of regimes on growth, therefore, you haveto take into account the fact that these observations are not exogenously produced. Given endogeneity, you are unlikely to observe pooreconomic performance in democracies, particularly poor democracies.Now we are in a position to discuss the relationship between comparisons and counterfactuals. Let us put together two assumptions. Supposethat on the average regimes do not make a difference for economicgrowth: for any regime during a particular year the growth rate is equalto 2.09, which is the world average during this whole period, plus orminus a random error.We also already know that democracies are morelikely to die when they do badly. Pause to thinkwhat we are then goingto observe in the real world if these two assumptions hold: regimes haveno effect on growth but democracies die when they perform poorly.The answer is that ifwe take the observations as they are given andcalculate the average rates of growth for democracies and dictatorships,we will find that democracies do better in promoting economic growth.When democracies face bad economic conditions, they die, and we donot observe them anymore: if a democracy does poorly, it becomes adictatorship, so that in the observed population we are going to observethat democracies do better. Yet this finding results not because democracy has any effect on economic growth, but because democracies aremore sensitive to economic crises. The fact that the world is not exogenous leads to invalid?specifically, biased and inconsistent?inferences.What we are observing here iswhat the statistical literature calls a"selection bias." Indeed, I am persuaded that all the comparative work

    we have been doing may suffer potentially from selection bias. We cannot do good comparative research unless we worry about selection, thatis, until we ask each time how our observations are produced. Is themechanism by which our observations are produced independent of

    what we want to explain or not? Unless we pass that test we will bemaking biased inferences.

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    21/50

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    22/50

    SYMPOSIUM 21cal distribution to generate the counterfactuals. We must proceed lessformally. But I offer a suggestion that I have found fruitful in playingmental experiments: Write up your cases, say South Korea and Brazil,and then use the "search and replace" function on your word processor totranspose the names of countries. Does the story still make sense? Brazilnow has access to the U.S. markets. Does it adopt the export-orientedstrategy? And if it does, is it successful? The new story may readsmoothly, and you will be satisfied. But you may discover that?holdit?the level of relative wages in Brazil may have been too high to export even if the U.S. market were open, the protected sectors were tooentrenched politically to tolerate a neutral exchange regime, and so on.Clearly, this isnothing but amental experiment guided by intuition. ButI think this procedure should be a standard protocol for case studies: wemust worry about selection and this is at least away of coping with it.To conclude, if the observed world is not a random sample of the possible worlds, then inferences from the observable cases, one or all, will beinvalid. Comparisons must then entail counterfactuals. We must worryabout selection mechanisms, identify their effects, and correct for them.

    These conclusions add up to an antiexperimental posture. Our effortshould not be to match, since we cannot match when the world doesnot generate all the pairs we need. Indeed, matching the observablecases may just exacerbate the selection bias. Instead, we must theorizeabout the mechanisms by which the observations are generated andthen use this knowledge to compensate for the nonrandom nature ofthe observable world.

    Susanne Hoeber RudolphTo pairWeber and Foucault in an essay on the comparative method, asI do here, may appear odd to some. But the contrast (and overlap) provides a vehicle for discussing what stance we shall take to the comparative enterprise?and to the social sciences more generally. Thequotations adduced below are offered as a scaffold for the report of mytravels from Weber toWeber via Foucault. The encounter with Foucault was more in the nature of a sideswipe than a full-scale encounter,but it ledme to readWeber differently.Weber figures in the story because he was a central figure, albeit in mediated form, in defining thecomparative enterprise for persons studying the non-Western world inthe 1950s and 1960s. I use him and his American progeny as the mainfigures against whom and with whom to define a stance toward thecomparative enterprise.

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    23/50

    22 WORLD POLITICSAn intellectual stance is the fruit of our historical life situation and o.

    the way the knowledge worlds of our disciplines impinge on us.Whenin the course of the essay several Weber quotations appear,these are

    meant to convey not that there is an essential, definitive Weber butrather thatWeber is subject to different readings. We can understandhim as one of the most important of the modernists, but also as a postmodernist. That puts me in the camp with those who see a text, not ashaving a determinate meaning, but as having a meaning that emergesas a collaboration between reader and author and that is in turn embedded in history. Such an approach to meaning presumes that thephenomenal is constructed; not only texts but also social categorieswithin which we live are constructed. Yet even as we construct the

    world, we cannot simply construct any world we want to?to refashiona useful Marxism for our times.The following are the quotes to be considered. First Weber:A product of modern European civilization, studying any problem of universalhistory, is bound to ask himself towhat combination of circumstances the factshould be attributed that inWestern civilization, and inWestern civilizationonly, cultural phenomena have appeared which (aswe like to think) lie in a lineof development having universal significance and value.10

    And Foucault:The project of a total history is one that seeks to reconstitute the overall form ofa civilization, the principle, material or spiritual, of a society, the significancecommon to all the phenomena of a period, the law that accounts for their cohesion ... [but] the possibility of a total history begins to disappear.... In place ofthe continuous chronology of reason, which was invariably traced back to someinaccessible origin, there have appeared scales that are sometimes very brief, distinct from one another, irreducible to a single law.11

    These quotations are cited in tandem for an obvious reason. The introduction to the Protestant Ethic that harbors the Weber quote waspart of an ambitious architectural edifice, what Foucault would call atotal history, tracing the evolution ofWestern and world civilizations asa continuous chronology of the progress?or failure?of rationalizationin the world. The quote represents one side ofWeber, that part of himthat still thought it possible to carry on the kind of world-encompass

    10Max Weber, The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, trans. Talcott Parsons (New York:Charles Scribner's, 1958), 13.11Michel Foucault, The Archaeology ofKnowledge and theDiscourse on Language (New York: Pantheon Books, 1972), 8-9.

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    24/50

    SYMPOSIUM 23ing projects favored by so much of nineteenth-century social science,especially inGermany. Despite the deep differences between Weber,

    Marx, Durkheim, and others, their projects were energized by a common enlightenment perspective. Itwas the world moving on an upwardtrajectory toward its future, driven by an inner reason that movedstraight or dialectically toward a climactic condition, with theWest inthe vanguard.12The Foucault quote is the marker of a contrary tendency, to dismantle wholes, to disrupt the consistency of large schemes and powerful determinacies; to focus on anomalies; to cut up wholes into discontinuouspieces

    whoseopposing

    tendencies can be examined, rather than subsumed as anomalies in holistic schemes; to prefer representatives thatbuild in their own contestation rather than offering a smooth, impenetrable face to the world.

    The tendencies highlighted in theWeber quote were picked up, rationalized, amplified, and systematized by the structural-functionalismthat animated the comparativists of the 1950s and 1960s. Modernization theory elaborated paradigms to deal with political and economicdevelopment thatwould allow the field tomove from, asGabriel Almond put it, "an 'area studies' approach to the study of foreign politicalsystems to a genuinely comparative and analytical one."13It was Talcott Parsons who led the new analytic; he more than anyother occasioned the reception ofWeber in the United States. The social world, he affirmed, could be understood through the pattern variables, a series of oppositional diads: ascription/achievement; affectivity/affective neutrality; collectivity orientation/self-orientation; particularism/universalism; diffuseness/specificity. As the usage of the patternvariables evolved, the items on each side of this dichotomous construction were seen to be systemically related. Thus, affectivity, collectivityorientation, particularism were joined by an inner logic and were mutually constrained; to be oriented toward human beings was to be oriented toward collective obligations and to care about particular personsor objects rather than general principles and so forth.14 And affective

    12For an illuminating philosophical and historical perspective on the modern project, see StephenToulmin, Cosmopolis: The Hidden Agenda ofModernity (New York: Free Press, 1990).13Gabriel Almond and James Coleman, The Politics of theDeveloping Areas (Princeton: PrincetonUniversity Press, 1960), vii. Parenthetically, this quotation was characteristic of most comparative studies in the way it conceived the project as something carried on by a community ofWestern viewerslooking at the "foreign." The creation of multinational and transnational social science communities inthe 1990s, as "native" social scientists have broken theWestern monopoly, compromises the idea of the"foreign" and has softened the imperialism of categories typical of the 1960s.14Talcott Parsons and Edward Shils, Toward a General Theory ofAction (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1951), 77. It is not self-evident that Parsons and Shils themselves, in this essay, saw the

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    25/50

    24 WORLD POLITICSneutrality, self-orientation, universalism were similarly thought to bejoined.The two sides of the pattern variables were the framework within

    which one could understand the march of history, a process in which"growing" and "developing" meant moving from the left side of the dichotomies to the right. The ideological cast of the framework mandated movement toward a necessary future. The march of historyoffered only two possible routes: one the high road and one a cul-desac. Nobody drove this agentless process. The analytic promised closure, confidence that all of the possible permutations of action had beenaccounted for: "We maintain that there are only five basic pattern variables, and that, in the sense that they are all of the pattern variableswhich so derive, they constitute a system."15Parsons (and Shils) set out to produce a more parsimonious, moreconsistent summary of the theoretical oppositions of tradition and rationality embedded in theWeberian architecture. It was a totalizingproject in the Foucaultian sense. As Parsons told the Faculty Committee on Behavioralism at Harvard in 1954: "A long-term program ofscholarly activity which aims at no less than a unification of theory inall the fields of the behavioral sciences is now envisaged."16 Because theelements were systemically related, the system could only be disruptedas awhole, not in parts. It did not accommodate the possibility that social actors could, as itwere, mix and match, take elements from opposite sides of the variables to create new mixes. No hybridities. If socialactors or institutions mixed features, they were "transitional," on their

    way to the predetermined future or lamentably unable to make it.Weber had laid the basis for the theoretical framework that surmiseda fatalistic and passive East lurking behind Parsonian-based modernization theory. Weber's dichotomizing project sorted civilizations on either side of a great divide: those civilizations inwhich humans were theinstruments and tools of God and those inwhich humans were the vessels of God; on the one side the ethical religions, which led to this

    left and right side of pattern variables as displayed above systematically related. However, the examplesin the essays?which are few?suggest such a grouping (p. 79). Francis Sutton and Fred W. Riggs developed systematic models, complete with presumptions that history was moving from one set of characteristics to another. Sutton is so cited inAlmond. For Riggs, see "Agraria and Industria: Toward aTypology of Comparative Administration," inW. J. Siffin, ed., Toward a Comparative Study ofPublicAdministration (Bloomington, 1957), 23-116. Almond, in his introduction to The Politics of theDeveloping Areas (fn. 13), explicitly avoids such "unfortunate theoretical polarization" and stresses the embeddedness of traditional inmodern structures (p. 23).15Parsons and Shils (fn. 14), 77.16Report by the Faculty Committee, The Behavioral Sciences atHarvard (Cambridge: Harvard University, June 1954), 114.

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    26/50

    SYMPOSIUM 25worldly asceticism and the accompanying urgency to remake the world;on the other side exemplary religion, otherworldly asceticism thatshunned activity and accepted the cosmos, that is, fatalism.The first "field trip"onwhich Lloyd Rudolph and I embarked beganto unravel this inherited apparatus. The sheer noisy, shouting nature ofthe data encountered flew in the face of the dominant dispositions oftheWestern social science by which we as observers were then constituted. The experience not only created our first book but also engendered an enduring suspicion of a social science that could so mislead.Looking for "voluntary associations," which we believed to be criticalto the civil society necessary for pluralist democracy,

    we stumbled overcaste. That most ascriptively based, hierarchical, diffuse, particularisticinstitution of Indian society, said to be generative of the fatalism of theEast, had spawned/was spawning an adaptive social hybrid that satcomfortably on the divide between "modern" and "traditional."

    What Lloyd Rudolph and I encountered was amost inventive mixture of pattern variables?ambitious lower-caste persons who were remaking their social fate by working through an adapted version oftraditional collectivities?in other words, grasping their fate in theirhands. In its democratic incarnation, caste itself was deeply disruptiveof caste hierarchy. To account for the phenomena we were seeing, wehad to break up the totalistic, systemic nature ofWeberian and Parsonian structures.17 We elaborated the idea that the world of social changewas badly imagined when itwas confined within oppositional categories and systemic theories. Much change seemed to proceed by adaptations not captured by the oppositions. Adaptations were created outof mixes of features lying on one or the other side of the pattern variables or the activist and fatalist civilizational line. Dichotomies werelogical structures that suppressed the intervening ground on whichmost of the phenomenal world exists. The categories that constitutedthe "modern" were not systemically or organically related, asWeber andParsons and Marx thought, and they were not and would not be universal. They had become related in the specific history of theWest andwould take as yet unknown shape in the future of the "East." Othermodernizers would figure out different constellations of relationships.The Foucault quote cited here is a critique of total history, exemplified in the hypersystemic side of theWeberian project and by its Parsonian variant. Instead of total histories, singular and ideological,

    17We did so in Rudolph and Rudolph, The Modernity of Tradition: Political Development in India(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1967,1984,1996).

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    27/50

    26 WORLD POLITICSFoucault intimates multiple and open histories, providing space for alternative social destinies. His is also a critique of the understanding,embedded inmodernization theory, that change, or "development," wasdriven by a continuous chronology of reason. My interest in the Foucaultian suggestion of discontinuities and disruptions is not about suspending comparison, generalization, and explanation; it is about dismantlingthe all-encompassing formats that have imprisoned us and the non

    European societies we were trying to explain. Discontinuous, nonholistic projects make it more possible to represent the contested nature of"reality," to avoid subsuming contradictions to "larger" truths or suppressing

    themaltogether

    in the interest of"consistency." Disrupt

    meansbreak and challenge: as we construct a story we do so not in the tones ofthe omniscient observer, of objective truth, of absolute certainty, but ina voice that recognizes we are both partial and partisan and that we express half-truths?which indeed may be the only truths there are.18 Itmeans a less enthusiastic embrace of attributes regarded as academicvirtues, such as consistency, objectivity, parsimony.

    Weber, surprisingly, offers us considerable support in developing adifferent, more contingent stance to knowledge. The quotation featuredat the beginning of this essay embodies his attachment to a totalistic,ideological, universalizing, dichotomizing project. But embedded inthat quote there is an anomaly: In the midst of a confident assertion ofthe universal significance ofWestern culture, he emits a kind of episte

    mological hiccup: ". . . inWestern Civilization, and inWestern Civilization only, cultural phenomena have appeared which {as we like tothink) He in a line of development having universal significance" (emphasis added). It is that self-doubt, that sudden pause in confidence,that begins to suggest the "other Weber."Weber moves in aworld inwhich reality is not "there" in any transparent fashion but is constructed out of the situation of the observer."All knowledge of cultural reality," he writes, "is always knowledge fromparticular points of view."19 Reality is so infinite, so comprehensive, thatthe human mind must make severe compromises to grasp it at all, andthese compromises arise out of the observers situation: "The way whichlife confronts us in immediate concrete situations, it presents an infinite

    multiplicity of successively and coexistently emerging and disappearingevents."20 And the "scientist" "selects from an absolute infinity a tiny18For a discussion of types of voice and their relationship to truth claims, see Donald N. McCloskey,

    IfYoure So Smart (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1990).19Max Weber, " 'Objectivity' in Social Science and Social Policy," inWeber, TheMethodology of theSocial Sciences, trans, and ed. Edward A. Shils and Henry A. Finch (New York: Free Press, 1949), 71.20Ibid., 72.

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    28/50

    SYMPOSIUM 27portion with the study of which he concerns himself."21 "Accordingly,cultural science in our sense involves 'subjective* presuppositions insofaras it concerns itself only with those components of realitywhich havesome relationship ... to events to which we attach cultural significance."22

    For Weber, reality is clearly not an unmediated, unproblematic concept. He never tells us there is no reality; he does not refrain from usingthe word; and he does not put it in quotation marks, the postmodernconvention for signaling skepticism.23 Yet by representing reality to usas infinite and ungraspable, he comes very close to a similar position:"coexistently emerging and disappearing"; "infinite multiplicity." Theseare not phrases that signal certainties. He then suggests that the only

    way to come to grips with "reality" is in fact through acts of construction.We cut out pieces of the infinite flow in light of our subjective interests. The ideal type allows an unnatural freezing of a moment of"reality" and the possibility of extracting and addressing it.Iwould interpret the "subjective"here to refer to the individual whodwells within social and historical contexts on the one hand and paradigm communities on the other that suggest the range of what is of"cultural significance." (InWeber this "I"?the lonely individual whomust choose from among contending possibilities without the guidanceof any absolute standard?is unconstructed.) And which of the piecesextracted from the flow is "true"? Weber suggests that contradictorycuts may have truth value. At the end of the Protestant Ethic, he offersa disingenuous denial: "But it is, of course, not my aim to substitute fora one-sided materialistic an equally one-sided spiritualistic causal interpretation of culture and history." And then he tells us, "Each isequally possible."24 Indeed, Weber the culturalist constantly invokesmaterialist interpretations. He refuses exclusive commitment.This denial would clearly place Webers work in a more contingentrelationship to truth than the totalizing projects discussed above?projects that aspired to encompass all truths in a single systematic formulation and that subsumed all anomalies as exceptions that prove the rulerather than as ruptures. It would place him on the other side not merelyof his own more holistic, macrotheoretical self but also of, say, Parsons,

    21Ibid., 82.22 Ibid.23The career of the inverted comma in academic disciplines isworth a biography. It is the cautionlight on the road to cognition, warning the unwary that aword may not be what it seems, telling thereader that she should walk all around "sovereignty" or "growth" and have a conversation with it aboutits provenance before incorporating it. Note thatWeber does put inverted commas around "Objectivity" in the above-cited article (fn. 19).24Weber (fn. 10), 183.

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    29/50

    28 WORLD POLITICSEaston, Kaplan, andWaltz, whose theoretical formulations strive to encompass and subsume the relevant phenomenal world within a singlesystem.Let me sum up then why we can readWeber, who is generally assimilated to the realm of the modernists, as a postmodernist. The caserests?rst on emphasizing themultiplicities with which he continuallyundermines the universal propositions he puts forward, on his propensity continually to disrupt his own holistic architectonic; secondon hisprofound ambivalence about the enlightenment project, about themarch of rationalization in human history, which he sees as a destruction of all that is intentional and sensitive and varied and centrallyhuman, the world as iron cage; and third, his belief in themultiplicityand simultaneity of "truth," his epistemological polytheism?combinedwith an absolute conviction, ungrounded, that persons must choose.This last point deserves emphasis. In the face of the ambiguity and si

    multaneity of truths that is a significant part of the postmodern project,people tend to be overcome by a fear of falling.Where all is in flux,what certainty is there? There is none, saysWeber, and adds, with absolute but convincing inconsistency, the person of integrity mustchoose, must act.

    And why should we readWeber as a postmodernist, and what has itto do with comparative method? My story has given me the opportunity to consider, as a comparativist who lived through the era of holistic, macrohistorical social science and was seduced by it,where we arenow, and why I think "now" is better. I do not believe that macrosocialtheory necessarily or merely entailed a colonial project of knowledge aspower, although that was an aspect of it. But because the macrosocialprojects of the 1960s were holistic, theywere under a logical and intellectual compulsion to suppress alternative truths, to imagine thatWestern history was world history and suppress the possibility of multiplehistories. Those projects prepared a culturally narcissistic mirror for theWest. Disrupting such a perspective prepares the ground for scholars tooperate as agents in the field of an open history.

    James C. ScottI am not very good at capturing in the abstract how I practice theoreticalwork in comparative politics. I am better at doing it than at discussing how to do it.With a figurative pistol to my temple, I didactually sit down and write an important maxim of comparative workthat derives from theway I do comparative politics. Iwill be happy to

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    30/50

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    31/50

    30 WORLD POLITICSof firewood fetching a certain price. Missing, of course, is everythingelse about the forest?all those trees, bushes, and plants?that hold little or no potential for state revenue. Missing as well are all those aspectsof trees, even of revenue-bearing trees, that might be useful to the population but whose value is not convertible into fiscal receipts. Here Ihave in mind the uses of foliage as fodder and thatched roofs, as foodfor domestic animals and people, trees and branches as bedding, fencing, hop poles, kindling, bark, roots for medicine and tanning, sap forresins, and so on. The actual tree with its vast number of possible usesis replaced by an abstract tree representing a certain volume of firewood. From the

    perspectiveof a naturalist, of course, most of the forest

    is also missing. Gone are the vast majority of flora, the grasses, theflowers, the ferns, the mosses, the shrubs, the vine; gone also are thereptiles, birds, amphibians, and insects. And from an anthropologist sperspective, nearly everything touching on human interaction with theforest is also missing. Except for its attention to poaching that impingeson the states claim to revenue and wood or its claim to royal game, thestate typically ignores the vast and complex negotiated social uses of theforest for hunting and gathering, pasturage, digging minerals, fishing,charcoal making, trapping, food collection, magic, worship, and refuge.You could say that the utilitarian state cannot see the real existingforest for the commercial trees. Its partial and abstract view of forest ishardly unique. This is the discourse of natural resources; it is the samediscourse that makes the plants we are interested in into crops and theinsects that ingest the crops that we are interested in into pests. It is thesame logic that turns animals we are interested in into game or livestock and those that compete with or prey on them into predators andvarmints. However, it is not the abstract and utilitarian logic which thestate applies to the forest through its officials that is distinctive; rather,what is distinctive is that the state can make these categories stick andcan impose them?at least to a certain extent?on the reality that it isobserving and manipulating.The invention of scientific forestry inGermany at the end of theeighteenth century was originally motivated by the need to rationalizeprincely finances. The forests played avery important role in all of this.The earlier system had been quite crude; it entailed simply dividing upthe domanial forests and either felling portions or letting the rights tofell portions of it. Since the trees of great value were never randomlydistributed, given the varying ecological zones of the forest, the actualrevenue tended to fluctuate enormously. There was thus an effort toprevent that from happening. The inventors of scientific forestry spent

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    32/50

    SYMPOSIUM 31a great deal of time selecting what they thought was a representativeplot, quite a large plot, and then set about conducting a complete inventory of this plot. It involved getting some twenty people abreast insight of one another with great trays carried around their necks, eachtray with five bins, each of the bins carrying a known number of nails ofa designated color, corresponding to a certain size class of trees thatthese surveyors had been trained to recognize. At each tree, they wouldput in a nail designating the size class ofthat tree. At the end of the exercise, one counted the remaining number of nails and arrived at acomplete inventory of how many trees of each size class were in the forest. On the basis of assumptions about rates of maturity and growth,one could then divide up the forest into a set of subterritories thatwereexploitable year by year and, as much as possible, even out the amountof wood that could be taken. There was no way of quite controlling themarket price for wood, but at least the amount of wood, assuming constant prices, would be roughly the same from year to year.There were also other efforts to determine exactly how much commercial wood was in a tree of a given size class. In a series of experi

    ments, they would take one such tree, cut it up into tiny pieces, andcompress it into cubes so that it could be measured to get the exact volume of wood. Or theywould throw thewood into in large bins filledwith water; based on the amount of water that was displaced, theycould determine the exact volume of wood in one of these trees. Theachievements of German forestry science in standardizing techniquesto calculate sustainable yield of commercial timber were very impressive in this respect.

    What is decisive for our purposes is the next logical step in forestmanagement. That was to create, through careful seeding, planting, andcutting, a forest that was easier for state foresters to count, manipulate,

    measure, and assess. The fact is that forest science and geometry,backed by the state, had the capacity to transform the disorderly andchaotic real forest into a forest more closely resembling the administrative grid of its techniques. Thus the underbrush was cleared, a numberof plant species were reduced, often to monoculture, planting was donesimultaneously and in straight rows for large tracts. They went somedistance toward creating a "normal" forest and aNormalbaum in theseforests.

    The creation of a simplified, legible forest was only the imminentlogic of its techniques. It was not and could not ever be realized inpractice, because both nature and the human factor intervened. The existing topography, the vagaries of fire, storms, blights, climatic changes,

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    33/50

    32 WORLD POLITICSinsect populations, and disease obviously conspired to thwart forestersin their efforts to shape the actual forest. Also not insignificant were theinsurmountable difficulties of policing large forests; for 250 years themost popular crime inEngland was poaching. And by popular, Imeanin both senses of the word: most common and most beloved. Given thedifficulties of policing large forests, therefore, adjacent human populations also typically continued to graze animals, poach firewood andkindling, make charcoal, and generally make use of the forest in waysthat thwarted the realization of forest management plans.The administrators forest cannot be the naturalist s forest. Even if allthe ecological interactions

    atplay in the forest

    wereknown, they wouldconstitute a reality so complex and variegated as to defy shorthand de

    scription. The intellectual filter necessary to reduce this complexity tomanageable dimensions was provided in this case by the state's interestin commercial timber and in revenue. You could say that the naturalworld?or as Iwill go on to argue, the social world?is simply too unwieldy and too complex in its raw form for direct administrativemanipulation. That is, in its natural or social context reality is bureaucratically indigestible without this abstraction. I now propose to applythe forestry metaphor to land tenure, by giving a hypothetical description of customary forms of land tenure. Though hypothetical, however,this description is realistic; that is, I have read about or actually seen allof the practices I am about to describe.Let us imagine a community in which families have user rights toparcels of cropland during the main growing season. Only certain crops

    may be planted, and every seven years use rights are redistributedamong families according to family size and the number of able-bodiedadults. In the closed corporate communities of Russia, Java, portions of

    Central America, and Vietnam, this was common. After the harvest ofthe main season crop, all cropland reverts to commons, such that anyfamily may glean, graze its fowl and livestock, and even plant quick

    maturing dry-season crops. Edible wild plants growing on the marginsof fields or along water courses are available to be gathered. Treesknown to have been planted, together with their fruit, are the propertyof the family that planted them, not the property of the people onwhose land they happen now to be located. Fruit fallen from such trees,however, may be gathered by anyone. When a family fells one of itstrees orwhen it is felled bywind, the trunk belongs to the family, thebranches to the immediate neighbors, and the tops, twigs, fronds, andleaves to any poor villager who carries them off. Certain plots of landare designated for use or lease by widows with children or by depen

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    34/50

    SYMPOSIUM 33dents of conscripted males. Use rights to land can be let to anyone inthe village, but only if no one in the village wants to take it can itbe letto anyone outside the village.

    Let us also imagine that fishing rights are distributed so that anyonemay fish by net or by hook and line from canals and streams. In floodedfields, however, while anyone may fish with a hook and line for smallfish, the larger fish, taken usually when the field is drained (withwetrice, for example), belong to the owner of the crop growing in the field.I could easily elaborate on what happens to land rights and to the distribution of crops and their proceeds. That, however, is not necessary. Icould also make this

    descriptionmore elaborate because it is, in itself, a

    simplification. I also distort by describing these practices as if theywerelaws, when in fact they are a living, negotiated tissue of practices that isnever static, and that is constantly changing according to new ecological and social circumstances, including, Imust add, power relations.

    Imagine awritten system of positive law that attempted to representthis complex skein of property relations and land tenure; that is, imagine a state that wanted to respect customary forms of tenure by codifying them and representing them in positive law.The mind fairlyboggles at the number of clauses and subclauses and sub-subclausesthat would be required to represent these practices. In principle, if theycould be codified, the result would necessarily sacrifice much of theplasticity and subtle adaptability of practice; itwould freeze a livingprocess. Moreover, changes in the positive code from time to time toreflect evolving practice would, at best, represent a very jerky mechanical adaptation. And what of the next village? After this imaginary codegiver had finished representing customary land tenure in village A, heor she would have to start from nearly zero in village B because itwould have different ecological conditions, a different cropping history,a different social structure, and so on. No matter how devilishly clever,meticulous, and respectful of customary law such a state was, it simplycould not represent each village with its own particular ecology, history, cropping patterns, kinship alignments, and economic activity. Itwould require a different set of regulations, a different positive codefor each village, making for at least as many legal codes as there werecommunities.

    Administratively, of course, this is a nightmare. But notice whosenightmare it is?certainly not that of the people whose particular customs are being represented. Local practice in land tenure is completelycomprehensible to the inhabitants who livewith it day in, day out. Itsdetails may often be contested and far from satisfactory to all of its local

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    35/50

    34 WORLD POLITICSpractitioners, but there is no doubting its familiarity. They know itssubtleties andwhile theymay dislike it, they know how tomanipulateit for their own purposes as well. The nightmare in question, then, isthat of the state officials who want a uniform administrative grid of landtenure that will represent the situation in awhole region or for that matter in awhole nation. The very concept of the modern state is hardlyconceivable without a vastly simplified and uniform property regimethat is legible and hence manipulable from the center. And, of course, amajor driving force behind this legibility is the question of taxes.The next step for all modern states is, of course, to measure, codify,and simplify land tenure in much the same way that scientific forestryreconceived the forest, since the state cannot begin to incorporate theluxuriant variety of customary land tenure. The historic solution, forthe liberal state anyway, has been the heroic simplification of individualfreehold tenure. Land is owned by a legal individual who disposes ofwide powers of use, inheritance, or sale and whose ownership is represented by a uniform title deed, enforced through the judicial and policeinstitutions of the state. Just as the flora of the forest are reduced to

    Normalb?ume, so were the complex tenure arrangements of customarypractice reduced to freehold transferable title. In an agrarian setting, theadministrative landscape was blanketed with a uniform grid of ho

    mogenous land, each parcel of which had a legal person as owner,hence, taxpayer. The modern land register and its tax roll were thus theequivalent for land tenure of the scientific forester's table of timbergrowth and yield. A central consequence of its imposition was that itradically devalued local knowledge and autonomy, and this specializedknowledge, backed by state authority, changed the balance of power between the locality and the state.

    Again, like the forest, land tenure never quite measured up to theutopia envisioned by the people who did the settlement reports and thetaxation maps and who issued title deeds, because a whole series ofpractices, including resistance, went on in spite of what the paperworksaid. One of the important things about the modern state is that mostof its officials are of necessity usually at least one step, and often severalsteps, removed from direct contact with the reality and the citizens theyadminister. They observe and assess the life of their society by a seriesof simplifications and shorthand fictions that are always some distancefrom the full reality these abstractions are meant to capture. The functionary of any large organization actually sees the human activity of interest to him or her largely through the simplified approximation ofdocuments and statistics and tax proceeds.

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    36/50

    SYMPOSIUM 35The simplified facts of the administrator are necessarily of a certain

    type?static?even when they are a series of facts that give a time sequence of different observations. A series of individual, static facts cannever tell you what happened between observation A and observationB; that is, a straight line drawn between the two observations is notnecessarily an accurate representation of events. The facts have to bestandardized, because if they are not they cannot be aggregated and assembled in away that allows for an overall view. The facts also have tobe stylized to simplify a reality out there.Thus, if the objective is to divide the population into the employed and the unemployed, then onemust simplify awhole series of intermediate statuses that represent thereal life of the many thousands who are unemployed or employed incomplicated ways that defy easy categorization; they must be sortedinto one bin or the other because the exercise requires that the population be divided into these categories. The people who actually make theassignments to these categories know the fictional and arbitrary qualityunderlying each of these decisions and know that they hide awealth ofproblematic variation.Once these categories are established, of course, they operate ineluctably as if all cases classified together are, in fact, homogenous anduniform. All Normalb?ume in a given size range are exactly the same forthe purposes of statistical manipulation. All auto workers, ifwe areclassifying by industry, are the same.All Catholics, ifwe are classifyingby religious faith, are the same. Students of bureaucratic behavior understand that central coordinating schemes do their work most effectively under conditions where the task environment is known andunchanging, and where it can be treated as a closed system. What Iwant to argue about state simplification is that the modern state,through its official attempts and with varying success, creates a population with those standardized characteristics because itwill be easier to

    monitor, count, assess, and manage. That is a little bolder than Iwouldlike to state it and itmisses the fact that these efforts fall enormouslyshort. However, I think there is an effort by officials either to transformor to represent as transformed the population, space, and nature undertheir jurisdiction into a closed system, without the surprises that frustrate their ability to control and observe it.This often provides for someenormous surprises when things do not work out as well.The important thing about the state in this context is that it in particular has the capacity to make its categories and simplifications stickbecause it can insist on treating people according to its categories. Ifyou want to defend your claim to real property, you are normally

  • 8/8/2019 The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics

    37/50

    36 WORLD POLITICSobliged to defend itwith a property deed and in the courts and tribunals created for that purpose. If you wish any standing in law, youmust have the documents?the birth certificate, passport, identity card,and so on?that officials accept as proof of citizenship. The categoriesused by state agents are not merely ameans to make their environmentmore legible, they are also an authoritative tune to which the population has to dance, at least some of the time.If I had more time, Iwould make the argument that these simplifications become deadly in combination with other factors. One of themost important of these is an ideology of high modernism, that is, thenineteenth-century worldview, with its supreme self-confidence aboutthe inevitability of linear progress, the development of scientific andtechnical knowledge, the expansion of production, and, most important, the rational design of the social order, the growing satisfaction ofhuman needs, and, not least, an increasing control over nature, including human nature (also including eugenics, commensurate with scientific understanding of natural laws). It seems to me that highmodernism at its flood tide is an ideology that requires an enormously

    powerful state?it has obviously and straightforwardly authoritarian aspects to it.According to high modernism, there is only one answer toalmost any social problem, and that is determined by the technicians,engineers, and social analysts who