The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

download The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

of 30

Transcript of The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    1/30

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    2/30Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1675583Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1675583

    2

    and state of exception along with their concrete political implications, which boosted

    the contemporary currency of Schmitts philosophy.4

    This essay focuses on another avenue of engagement with Schmitts thought,

    namely, its specific appropriation by Chantal Mouffe in her formulation of a radically

    pluralist model of liberal democracy. At first, one might wonder how it is possible for

    Mouffe to draw on Schmitts thought given the discrepancy between their political

    positions and theoretical foci. After all, Schmitt is (in)famous for being a conservative

    jurist, the theorist of sovereign power and dictatorship, and even the philosophical

    godfather of National Socialism. Mouffe, on the other hand, is a staunch advocate of

    radical pluralist democracy, the theorist of social indeterminacy and discursivity, and the

    co-author of the groundbreaking post-Marxist work Hegemony and Socialist Strategy.

    However, the fact that Mouffe has written three books and collections of essays (1993,

    2000, 2005) and edited another one (1999), all of which engage with the works of Carl

    Schmitt, proves that although the two figures are radically divergent, they are not

    incommensurable. Moreover, this very divergence attest to the multilayered character of

    Schmitts writings, which renders them available for utilization in diverse politico-

    theoretical projects and opens up new avenues for thinking about the political in our time.

    To this purpose, this essay focuses on a specific theme in Schmitts theory,

    namely, the ultimate incompatibility of the logic of liberalism and the logic of

    democracy, which Mouffe considers as the challenge of Schmitt and tries to resolve

    through a particular interpretation. Put briefly, Mouffe strives to overcome the

    incompatibility between liberalism and democracy by articulating the two in a

    4A recent work in this lane isInternational Political Thought of Carl Schmitt: Terror, Liberal war and the

    Crisis of Global Order, edited by Louiza Odysseos and Fabio Petito (2007).

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    3/30

    3

    democratic paradox, whereby the defining principles of each logic (individualism,

    deliberation, and universal human rights of the former, and homogeneity, identity, and

    exclusivity of the latter) play themselves out in an open-ended discursive struggle for the

    redefinition of the terms equality and freedom, which animates a politics of agonism in a

    radically pluralist liberal democratic system (Mouffe, 2000: 4-5). To this end, Mouffe

    draws on particular themes and appropriates particular concepts in Schmitts works, and

    modifies these as to fit her overall project. In her criticism of the universalist-rationalist

    model of liberal democracy (exemplified in the works of Rawls and Habermas), she

    summons to her aid the Schmittian notion of the political and the distinction of

    friend/enemy with a point to emphasize the irreducibly antagonistic and exclusive logic

    of democratic politics (Mouffe, 1993). As I will argue, however, in her avowed project of

    thinking withand againstSchmitt (Mouffe, 1999: 6), Mouffe omits some of his major

    concepts and drastically redefines certain others so as not to endanger the liberal and

    pluralist character of democracy she envisions.

    In what follows, I begin my exploration with an outline of the Schmittian

    concepts and themes that are central to the incorporation of a Schmittian moment in

    Mouffe. Among these, the concept of the political as friend/enemy distinction, the

    notion of the logic of sovereignty as the nexus of sovereignty-decision-exception, and

    the counterposition of liberalism and democracy will be accorded special importance.

    This outline is followed by an examination of the works of Mouffe which explicitly draw

    on Schmitt for a theory of agonistic politics in a pluralist liberal democracy. In the course

    of discussion, I try to delineate the strategic theoretical maneuvers Mouffe undertakes,

    which are geared towards the domestication of the Schmittian notion of the political by

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    4/30

    4

    transforming enemy into adversary, antagonism into agonism, and homogeneity into

    commonality. Mouffe justifies these conceptual mutations on the grounds that Schmitts

    understanding of democracy is rendered obsolete and untenable by the democratic

    revolution that has replaced the embodied forms of politics with (in Claude Leforts

    terms) the empty place of power. Consequently, although Schmitts insights are useful

    for reinvigorating democratic politics, they nonetheless have to be adapted to its modern

    conditions. I contend that it is only with these theoretical alterations of core Schmittian

    concepts that Mouffe can then construct a paradoxical articulation between liberalism and

    democracy.

    The focus of the essay then shifts to the questions and problems that arise in the

    particular course of Mouffes appropriation of Schmittian concepts. These include the

    elision of the questions of sovereignty and decision, and the banishment of the exception

    from democratic politics. These theoretical gaps emanate from a presupposition of a state

    of normalcy as the condition of possibility of the pluralist democracy, and this

    presupposition constitutes the limits of Mouffes theory. These limits become manifest in

    her silence regarding the instances where the political community comes into contact

    with its constitutive outside, and where the displaced, disavowed, and domesticated

    political returns with a vengeance. Finally, the essay concludes with a brief exploration

    into the dark side of the liberal democracy, whereby it posits the possibility of a more

    insidious and destructive configuration between liberalism and democracy, namely, their

    indistinction, which lurks beneath their paradoxical articulation.

    I. The Political and the Logic of Sovereignty

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    5/30

    5

    The major essays that Schmitt penned throughout the 1920s and early 1930s, that

    is, during the parliamentary experiment of the Weimar Republic, have behind them not a

    sheer scholarly interest of the jurist, but a political investment that was a reaction to what

    he perceived as a degenerative, decaying, and moribund political order reigning in

    Germany. The opening sentence of Political Theology (1922), Sovereign is he who

    decides on the exception (Schmitt, 2005: 5) should be read as an attempt to revive an

    idea that Schmitt observed had fallen into oblivion in the Weimar Republic. In this work,

    Schmitt develops the notion of an executive power that will intervene to secure the

    foundations of the constitutional order, a notion he first voiced in his essay On

    Dictatorship (1921), and formulates a tirinitarian theory of the state which hinges on the

    inextricable nexus between the concepts of sovereignty, decision, and exception. In

    essence, this nexus points to a locus that is outside the constitutional order and at the

    same time its condition of possibility. The crucial assumption that underlies this extra-

    constitutional foundation of the constitutional order is that the legal order rests on a

    decision and not on a norm (Schmitt, 2005: 10). For Schmitt, an exclusive rule of law

    was inconceivable, which was not a simple advocacy of dictatorship, but an assertion of

    the need to recognize an extra-legal, personal element of power which would provide an

    exterior support, an exoskeleton for the legal order.5In this imagery, when this external

    support is cast aside and real life situations in their radical manifoldness are tried to be

    dealt with solely by legal norms, the legal order enters a crisis (a state of emergency)

    and begins to dissolve, for the letter of law is ultimately finite and thus unable to subsume

    5This is a point that has been acknowledged by the earlier liberal thinkers who reserve a space in their

    right-based consensual politics for exceptional decisions. For an excellent essay that surveys this space in

    the political thought of John Locke, William Blackstone, and Alexander Hamilton, see Clement Fatovics

    The Political Theology of Prerogative: The Jurisprudential Miracle in Liberal Constitutional Thought.

    ADD MONK

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    6/30

    6

    life as a whole. It is at this point it becomes an imperative to step outside of law and

    temporarily and/or partially suspend its efficacy in order to secure the conditions in

    which it can operate.6This, for Schmitt, is the moment of exception, whereby the two

    elements of the concept legal order are then dissolved into independent notions (Ibid:

    12) and the legality (Legalitt) is sacrificed for the purpose of saving the order

    (Ordnung). Whereas the efficacy of law refers to its normative content, the order is the

    homogenous medium (Ibid: 13), the state of normalcy in which the norm can be

    applicable at all. The exception is positioned on the limit between law and order, and

    comprises the nexus that upholds the legal system as a whole. In this sense, exception is a

    borderline concept in that although it exists outside law, it is nonetheless belongs to it,

    which positions the sovereign who decides on the exception both inside and outside legal

    order (Ibid: 7).

    The concept of exception broaches the issue of who is authorized to decide

    whether an exceptional situation is at hand. The provisions for diagnosing an exceptional

    situation (a state of emergency) cannot be ultimately derived from the legal norm itself,

    for the exception issui generis the situation that defies subsumption under law. Thus the

    declaration of exception is not a matter of normative applicability, but reveals decision

    as the irreducible and indispensable component of the legal order. This is what leads

    Schmitt to identify the decision on the exception as the decision in the true sense of the

    word (Ibid: 6). Implied here is the idea that a decision detached from the exception

    (situation outside of law) and sovereignty (the authority unbound by law) is no decision

    6The notion that the concept of democracy can only be practiced if its ideal radical openness is subjected to

    certain degree of closure was famously elaborated by Jacques Derrida. He expounds this autoimmunity of

    democracy inRogues: Two Essays on Reason(2005).

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    7/30

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    8/30

    8

    The total exclusion of the logic of sovereignty-decision-exception12

    and the

    absolute depersonalization of politics constitute the crux of Schmitts criticism of

    liberalism. This, for Schmitt, makes liberalism a metaphysical system (akin to deism),

    which, by founding positive law on the model of natural law, banishes miracle in line

    with the Enlightenments rejection of all arbitrariness and exception (Ibid: 36, 41).

    Thereby arises the politics of immanence, which wreaks an onslaught on the political

    by reducing political problems to organizational-technical and economic-sociological

    ones, thus evading the exacting moral decision that constitutes the core of the

    political (Ibid: 65). This logic manifests itself most clearly and most decisively in

    liberalisms inability to draw lines of distinction between friends and enemies. This

    distinction is the moment when the political emerges and reveals its inherent

    relationship with the logic of sovereignty. For this distinction is not a concrete definition

    and has no substantive content but follows from a decision. A friend/enemy grouping is

    not discovered but decided on, and this decision is irreducibly sovereign, because the

    relationship between the two parties is one of existential combat (Schmitt, 1976: 32)

    and emerges at the moment of the exception. In other words, the political is not another

    domain of life such as economy, religion or morality, (though it can and does feed on

    antagonisms in these domains), but exists as an ever present possibility, a potentiality

    embedded in social life in its entirety, which is realized when the sovereign decides that

    the political system and/or the social body is lethally endangered, and that it has to be

    protected by exceptional measures. Contrary to the logic of liberalism, which strives to

    dissolve the political along a continuum between economics and ethics (Ibid: 71),

    normatively. When conceived so, the nothingness is the lack of correspondence, or the gap between the

    existing norm, and the concrete life situation it faces.12This point onwards this logic will be referred to as the logic of sovereignty.

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    9/30

    9

    political entities (friends and enemies) confront each other not as economic competitors

    or debating adversaries, but as existentially different and alien opponents who enter

    in a decisive bloody battle that involves physical killing, rather than engaging in

    mere symbolic wrestlings (Schmitt, 1976: 26-8, 33; Schmitt, 2005: 59). The extremity

    of the political and the existentiality of its stakes cannot be overemphasized in Schmitt,

    for it constitutes the nexus between the political and the logic of sovereignty that

    animates his whole paradigm.

    The contours of Schmitts conception of democracy trace the hidden lines of the

    political. This correspondence has at its core the requisite of homogeneity of the social

    body defined on the basis of a substantive equality (Schmitt: 1988: 9). Schmitt calls the

    latter political equality and opposes it to human equality which he contends is a

    liberal, not a democratic, idea (Ibid: 11-2). Liberalism does not recognize any substance

    that differentiates amongpeople, and considers all individualsto be equal on the basis of

    their abstract humanity, which disqualifies liberalism as a state form and renders it an

    individualistic-humanitarian ethic and Weltanschauung (Ibid: 13). The underlying

    principle of political equality and homogeneity is that for a polity to be a democracy, the

    people should be cohesive enough to be mobilized for existential combat (war) when the

    sovereign decides on the exception and draws the lines between friend and enemy. This

    becomes clearer in Schmitts later assertion that humanity as such cannot wage war

    because it has no enemy (Schmitt: 1976: 54). In this respect, one can argue that the

    substance of political equality is valuable not in itself, but insofar as it supplies the

    political core around which a peoples willcan cohere and recognize this core as worth

    protecting against enemies. Homogeneity is not in the natureof the substance shared

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    10/30

    10

    by the governed, but consists of the identity of the governed with the government, of

    people and state, of peoples will and law; it is, in short, politicalhomogeneity (Wiley,

    2002: 485).13

    Schmitt admits that this identity is not a palpable reality but rests on the

    recognition of identity, in other words, on identification (Schmitt, 1988: 26-7). The

    logic of identification enables Schmitt to reconcile democracy with constitutional

    dictatorship (and thus the presidential dictatorship he himself advocates), in which the

    peoples will is identified with, or rather incarnated in the state and unified in the

    executive as the exclusive bearer of sovereign power and monopoly of decision (Ibid:

    45).

    The political distinction between friend and enemy is central to Schmitts efforts

    to keep the rule (peace) and the exception (war) distinct, and render the latter temporary

    and manageable. For the decision on friend and enemy designates, or rather, creates

    definitivepoliticalentities to which antagonism is restricted. In contrast, the idea of a war

    waged in the name of humanity results in the dehumanizationof the enemy, and would

    be geared toward not self-preservation but toward the utter destruction of the enemy

    (Schmitt: 1976: 54). Here we see a glimpse into the grim premonitions on the dangers

    lurking behind the refusal to come to grips with the political dimension of life, and the

    conflation of the nonpolitical concept of humanity with the political logic of friend and

    enemy, or rather, formulating a politics out of humanitarian principles, a politics of

    humanity. It is as if the humanitarian logic of liberal individualism, which avoids the

    risks implied by political existence (risk of being called upon for taking and sacrificing

    13The substance of political equality, on the basis of which political homogeneity is erected, is thus

    context-specific, and can be associated with different physical and moral qualities in accordance with the

    historically specific political project at hand. This introduces an aspect of uncertainty into the lines that

    separate politically desirable groups from undesirable ones, the people from domestic enemies

    (Schmitt, 1976: 46).

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    11/30

    11

    life in the existential combat between friends and enemies) and entrusts the right over life

    only to the individual, points to a dark, destructive underside, where war is condemned

    but executions, sanctions, punitive expeditions, pacifications remain. The adversary is

    thus no longer called an enemy but a disturber of peace and is thereby designated an

    outlaw of humanity, and every war must turn into a crusade and into the last war of

    humanity (Ibid: 79).

    II. Domestication of the Political and Democratic Pluralism

    Mouffes engagement with Schmittian insights constitutes a central avenue of

    thought in her works The Return of the Political (1993) and The Democratic Paradox

    (2000). In these books, as well in her introduction to the collection of essays entitled The

    Challenge of Carl Schmitt(1999), the position that Mouffe accords to Schmitt is that of

    an interlocutor who, with his concept of the political, supplies Mouffe with a heavy

    hand in her criticism of the rationalist-deliberative (Haberawlsian) theories of

    democracy and facilitates her move from this critique to the formulation of a radically

    pluralist liberal democracy. Nonetheless, although Schmitt proves a useful indicator for

    diagnosing the problems of liberal thought (which Mouffe contends that still persist

    today) his staunchly anti-liberal stance ultimately proves irreconcilable with the theory of

    liberal democracy that Mouffe tries to reinvigorate, and forces her to part ways with

    Schmitt at a certain point. Mouffe accomplishes this move by subjecting Schmittian

    concepts to a series of transformations and transmutations to render them compatible with

    the specificity of modern liberal democracy after the democratic revolution (pace

    Lefort), the inattentiveness to which constitutes Schmitts blind spot (1993: 109, 121).

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    12/30

    12

    However, this strategic move broaches as many questions as it answers, and

    problematizes the position of the Schmittian moment in Mouffes thought. I will try to

    elaborate on these points below.

    Mouffe is particularly wary of the claims of a post-political age that she

    associates with neoliberal hegemony, which induce apathy toward and a retreat from

    politics. She perceives rational-proceduralist theories of Habermas and Rawls as

    complicit with this ideology due to their sublimation of political struggle to a dialogical

    network of communication, which is universally inclusive on the premise that the

    deliberating parties relegate their conflictual interests and beliefs to the private sphere.

    Mouffe resorts to two critical Schmittian insights to reveal the problems inherent in this

    approach. First, in their attempt to counter the economic- aggregative model of

    democracy with the rational-deliberative model and to infuse a democratic modus vivendi

    with a moral content of impartiality and universality, Habermas and Rawls remain within

    the political fallacy of liberalism, which totally overlooks the specificity of the political

    by moving between ethics (intellectuality) and economics (trade) (Schmitt, quoted in

    Mouffe, 1993: 140).14

    Second, in their assumption of universality and openness of

    deliberation and in their exclusion of the irresolvable (morally comprehensive) conflicts,

    they fail to see the limits and exclusions inherent in the rationalist-deliberative discursive

    space.15

    The consequent illusion of consensus and unanimity culminates in the

    repression of antagonisms in society and creates a political void which is increasingly

    14In his later writings, especially in Political Liberalism, Rawls tries to compensate for his evasion of

    politics in his earlier works. I cannot do justice to a satisfactory discussion of this issue in this essay, though

    I would like to note briefly that the intersubjective Kantian constructivism that remains the backbone of

    Political Liberalismsituates the Rawlsian understanding of politics in a position that would appear

    profoundly apolitical from the Schmittian perspective.15

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    13/30

    13

    occupied by populist and extremist right-wing movements of ethnic, nationalist or

    religious nature (Mouffe, 1993: 5-6).16 Here lies the main anxiety that animates

    Mouffes thought in these works: the return of the repressed political in forms that cannot

    be contained by the liberal democratic framework, and an explosion of antagonism that

    can tear up the very basis of civility (Mouffe, 2000: 104, emphasis added). Her whole

    endeavor is an attempt to devise a liberal democratic framework which, by

    simultaneously reinstituting andcontaining the political, facilitates cathartic discharge of

    social antagonisms and thus forecloses the possibility of vengeful return of the repressed.

    With this aim in mind, Mouffe introduces the Schmittian concept of the

    political as the ontological dimension of social life (Mouffe, 1993: 3). She contends

    that antagonism and power relations are constitutive of the very social reality that we live

    in and that this antagonism hinges on an irreducible distinction between friend and

    enemy, between us and them. In contrast to the rationalist-deliberative model, she

    holds that the identities of the parties engaged in politics are not pregiven but constituted

    in and through the antagonisms, and always involve an originary exclusion (Mouffe,

    2000: 11).17

    The process of identity formation necessitates,pace Schmitt, some form of

    homogeneity that would make it possible to draw a frontier between us and them

    (Ibid: 43; Mouffe, 2000: 55). Mouffe identifies this necessity for exclusion as the

    16Such vocabulary as populism and demagogues, which Mouffe uses when referring to political

    movements that she sees as threats to liberal democracy, resonates all too well with Schmitts model of

    plebiscite and acclamation , and is an initial symptom of the divergent ways they conceive of democracy.17A point of distinction between liberal, deliberative democratic theory and radical democratic theory is the

    conceptualization of the legitimate boundaries of the democratic community. Whereas Jurgen Habermas

    builds his theory on constitutionalism, human rights and popular sovereignty on the premise that the

    legitimate borders of the polity are not only given but also beyond political debate, radical democratselevate the tension between universal impetus of human rights and the bounded scope of national, civil

    rights to paramount importance. On this issue compare Jurgen Habermas Constitutional Democracy: A

    Paradoxical Union of Contradictory Principles? (2001) and Jacques RanciereDisagreement: Politics and

    Philosophy (1995). For an excellent commentary on Habermass essay see Lasse Thomassen, A Bizarre,

    Even Opaque Practice: Habermas on Constitutionalism and Democracy (2006)

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    14/30

    14

    democratic logic of equality that makes possible political agency, and counterposes it

    against the liberal logic of liberty which rests on a fundamentally apolitical primacy of

    the individual over all forms of social and political association. Although Mouffe

    borrows this contrast from Schmitt, she does not agree with him on the ultimate

    incompatibility of these two logics, but instead argues that the logics of liberalism and

    democracy can be articulated in a democratic paradox in a politically productive way

    (Mouffe, 1993: 8). However, before Mouffe can use Schmitt against Schmitt in this

    way, it becomes imperative to perform certain transformations and exclusions on

    Schmittian body of thought.

    The first alteration that Mouffe introduces is the domestication of the political

    by transmuting the figure of the enemy into that of adversary who is thus no longer

    perceived as an opponent to be destroyed but as somebody whose ideas we combat but

    whose right to defend those ideas we do not put into question (Ibid: 102). This is a

    drastic break with the Schmittian concept of the political, in which the engagement

    between friend and enemy is one of existential combat and not mere symbolic

    wrestling (Schmitt, 1976: 32). This tension is present in Mouffes initial definition of

    enemy as someone who is perceived as negating our identity, as putting in question our

    very existence (Mouffe, 1993: 3). It is not clear whether what is at stake is identity or

    existence, but ambiguity dissipates when Mouffe states that existence of the adversary

    is legitimate and must be tolerated (Ibid: 4), which implies that her definition of

    political antagonism mainly consists of a contestation over identities. However, Mouffe

    does not completely do away with the concept of the enemy but displaces it by

    declaring it to be pertinent with respect to those who do not accept the democratic rules

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    15/30

    15

    of the game and who thereby exclude themselves from thepoliticalcommunity (Ibid).

    This statement calls forth a crucial question regarding the nature of the relationship to

    those outside the political community, which Mouffe leaves unanswered: are these people

    enemies or domestic enemies in the Schmittian sense? Or do they represent a

    nonpublic, a politically disinterested existence which place[s] [itself] outside the

    political community (Schmitt, 1976: 51)? More importantly, how does the political

    community deal with this nonpublic (Schmitt recites a series of methods including

    privileges for aliens, internment, exterritoriality, and laws for metics)? Or can democracy

    simply ignore and exclude one part of those governed [in this case, those who do not

    accept the democratic rules of the game] without ceasing to be a democracy (Schmitt,

    1988: 9)? Mouffes position on these questions is not wholly clear.

    However, what is clear is that this displacement implies a redefinition of the

    political and the political community, which hinges on the divestiture of the political of

    its existential (i.e. Schmittian) content and its domestication within the political

    community. This is reflected in the second moment of Mouffes operations of

    containment, which is the transformation of antagonism as struggle between

    enemies into agonism as struggle between adversaries (Mouffe, 2000: 102-3).

    Whereas antagonism puts at stake the self-preservation of the enemies that confront each

    other, agonism consists of an open ended and indeterminate discursive contestation over

    differential definitions and articulations of the ethico-political principles of liberty and

    equality that characterize liberal democracy. At this point, it becomes increasingly harder

    to see what remains of the political essence of Schmittian thought, for agonism appears to

    conform to what Schmitt contemptuously called an endless symbolic wrestling that he

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    16/30

    16

    associated with liberalism. This point is not an overstatement, for the third conceptual

    modification by performed Mouffe is the transformation of homogeneity into

    commonality (Mouffe, 2000: 55), which is precisely the acknowledgement of a

    common symbolic space that makes it possible to recognize ones opponents not as

    existentially different and alien enemies (Schmitt, 1976: 26) but as friendly enemies

    (which would amount to an oxymoron for Schmitt) (Mouffe, 2000: 13, emphasis

    added).18 Moreover, the relationship between friendly enemies is described as the

    struggle to organize this symbolic space in a different way (Ibid), which reconstitutes

    the political community on the basis of the process of discursive articulation and

    rearticulation of collective identities and of ethico-political principles. Finally, the

    strategic theoretical moves that are presented above reach their consummation in

    Mouffes juxtaposition of the political (antagonism inherent in human relations) and

    politics (ensemble of practices, discourses and institutions which seek to establish a

    certain order and organize human coexistence), whereby politics is identified with the

    attempt to domesticatethe political (Mouffe, 1993: 141, emphasis added), and the aim

    of democratic politics is established as the reconstruction of enemy as adversary (Mouffe,

    2000: 102).

    One may be tempted to ask the question, How can Mouffe still claim to draw on

    Schmitt after she has hollowed out the radical political content of his concepts by turning

    enemy into adversary, antagonism into agonism, homogeneity into commonality, thus

    reducing the political to a mere semblance of what it originally was? Secondly, on what

    theoretical grounds are these conceptual enervations justified? Mouffes justification is

    18It is also remarkable that the term adversary that Mouffe chooses to designate the agonistic parties is

    used by Schmitt for referring to the parties involved in liberal-parliamentary discussion the the debating

    adversary (Schmitt, 1976: 28).

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    17/30

    17

    based on her diagnosis of what she considers to be Schmitts blind spot, that is, his

    inability or refusal (Mouffe is unclear on this) to come to terms with the novelty of

    modern liberal democracy that has emerged in the wake of the democratic revolution

    (Mouffe, 1993: 109, 121). At the core of this argument is Leforts thesis that after the

    collapse of the embodied politics of the Ancien Regime the locus of power becomes

    an empty place that no individual or group can ultimately occupy and be consubstantial

    with (Lefort, 1988: 17).19Modern democracy rises on a fundamental indeterminacy as to

    the basis of power, law and knowledge, and as to the basis of relations betweenselfand

    other, which follows from the dissolution of the markers of certainty (Ibid: 19). It is

    on the basis of this radical indeterminacy that Mouffe refutes Schmitts notions of

    homogeneity and enemy: under conditions of modern democracy, one cannot maintain

    the notion of the political as a friend/enemy distinction based on the substantive equality

    and homogeneity of political identities, for these identities are now constructed in and

    through dynamic processes of discursive articulation and rearticulation, and comprise not

    so much the starting point as the outcome of political struggles (Mouffe, 2000: 55-6).

    Mouffe augments this argument by invoking the Derridean concept of the constitutive

    outside, which enables her to uphold the notion of some form of homogeneity that is

    indispensable for an agonistic friend/adversary distinction (Mouffe, 2000: 55), while at

    the same time revealing the radical undecidability of the constitution of us in relation to

    19According to Lefort, the disembodiment of power at the moment of the kings decapitation gives rise o

    the body politic of the people upon which political power falls. Here Lefort echoes Tocqueville, who

    writes that democracy comes into being in the wake of the collapse of social and political

    hierarchies that give way to the idea of equal freedom (Tocqueville, 1990: 8-10). Being thrown back onnothing but the norm of equality, the occupation of the empty place of power becomes a heavily contested

    issue, because [i]t remains quite uncertain what it actually means for the people to rule. Democracy is

    defined instead by the corrosive logic of social and political equality (Keenan 2003: 5, emphasis added).

    Within daily politics, the regularity of elections, i.e. the reoccurring vacationof the place of power is taken

    to denote the emptiness of democratic sovereignty.

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    18/30

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    19/30

    19

    challenged by the liberal discourse of universal human rights. This paradox makes both

    perfect equality and perfect liberty impossible, but viewed from another perspective, it

    impedes both total closure that can result in totalitarianism and total dissemination that

    breeds political apathy and hands politics over to neoliberal governance (Ibid).

    III. The Crisis of Pluralist Democracy

    In the course of examining Mouffes appropriation of Schmitts theory, a

    peculiarity quickly stands out: absence of even a marginal engagement with the logic of

    sovereignty. One cannot come across the term exception even once in her work, and

    the concepts of decision and sovereignty are deployed very sparsely and marginally, and

    even then only in the context of the critique of rational-deliberative approach. Especially

    in her discussion of the Rawlsian model, one witnesses references to Schmitt in

    conjunction with such statements as question of sovereignty is evacuated (Ibid: 49),

    the question of sovereignty is evaded (Ibid: 113), a process of deliberation

    which eliminates the moment of decision (Mouffe, 2000: 57), and bringing a

    deliberation to a close always results from a decision which excludes other possibilities

    (Ibid: 105). Strangely enough, Mouffe never elaborates on either of the terms, which

    seem all the more curious in the face of the fact that Schmitt is first and foremost the

    theorist and the champion of sovereign decision. The only instance when she invokes

    popular sovereignty as a positive principle is, ironically, when she contends that in

    modern democracy popular sovereignty is exercised within a symbolic framework

    informed by the liberal discourse (Ibid: 2).

    Pondering over Mouffes constant elision of the issue of the sovereign logic

    (except for when it comes out to bash Rawls) might prove insightful for sketching the

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    20/30

    20

    limits of her theory of pluralist democracy. In my outline of Schmitts theory, I tried to

    show that the political is intimately linked with the logic of sovereignty because the

    distinction between friend and enemy in which it manifests itself always follows from

    sovereign decision that declares the self-preservation of the legal system and/or the

    political body to be at stake, and an existential battle to be at hand. As demonstrated

    above, Mouffe circumvents this entire configuration by replacing it with an agonistic,

    adversarial model of politics. However, if one recalls her remarks about the displacement

    of the enemy onto those who refuse to play by the rules of the liberal democratic game,

    one can catch a glimpse of the specter of Schmitts notion of the political occupying the

    subterranean yet central position in Mouffes model. For this displacement signals a

    relationship that lacks a common symbolic space, a third grammar which is neither

    liberal, nor democratic, and which, by defying articulation, points to the limits of the

    pluralist democracy. Mouffe seems to have precisely this problem in mind when she

    contends that the institutionalized achievements of the democratic revolution (a

    distinction between public and private, separation of Church and State and of civil and

    religious law) cannot be called into question in the name of pluralism (Mouffe, 1993:

    132).20

    It is highly significant (and even more so when seen from the present situation)

    that Mouffe points to Islam as a religion that does not recognize these achievements, and

    her following remark is even more problematic: The relegation of religion to the private

    sphere, which we now have to make Muslims accept (Ibid, emphasis added).21 This

    20In view of Mouffes celebration of these achievements, the absence of the sovereign logic in her theory

    becomes more intelligible. For these achievements, as Mouffe herself acknowledges, are the contributionsof liberal thought and belong to the Enlightenment tradition, both of which Schmitt holds responsible for

    the banishment of miracle from theology and exception (i.e. sovereign decision) from politics (Schmitt,

    2005: 36, 41).21Mouffe starts with Islams rejection of the public/private distinction (which is quite problematic to begin

    with) and, in one huge sweep, grafts this stigma onto all Muslims without the slightest hesitation. This is

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    21/30

    21

    statement evokes a series of liminalquestions for Mouffes pluralist democracy: Who is

    this we? The liberal democrats? The non-Muslims? The demos? And who are we

    to make Muslims accept the relegation of religion to the private sphere, that is, where do

    we derive our authorityfrom? From popular sovereignty? Are the Muslims living with

    us not a part of the populus? Moreover, how are we going to accomplish this? By

    agonistic-adversarial struggle (or are the Muslims incapable of understanding the rules

    of the game so that we have to stop the game and suspendsome rules in order to teach

    them before they can join in)? Or are the Muslims not adversaries but (displaced)

    enemies? At this point Mouffes pluralist democracy comes into contact with its

    constitutive outside, and because the outside has to be incommensurable with the

    inside (Mouffe, 2000: 12), it cannot deal with the latter on discursive terms. And it is at

    this very moment that the Schmitts question of Who decides? returns with full

    vengeance. Who decides that the achievements of the democratic revolution are in

    danger, and that the very existence of the pluralist democratic order is at stake? This is

    fundamentally a question on the exception, and within its liberal democratic confines,

    Mouffes theory cannot answer this question, for it rests exclusively on the

    presupposition of astate of normalcy: exclusion of political violence, adversarial respect,

    human rights, secularism, public/private distinction, all of which are institutionalized and

    legally protected by a state which rests on the ethico-political principles of equality and

    liberty but which is at the same time benevolent enough to refrain from imposing a

    an extremely telling symptom of the limits of her theory as one of the contingent, decentred andradically indeterminate identities. Rebounding off these limits, Mouffe falls back to a position which she

    criticizes in Rawls and argues for the relegation of controversial, morally comprehensive (in this case,

    religious) beliefs to the private sphere. This is all the more problematic for Mouffe than it is for Rawls, for

    it is harder to sustain a clear notion of private sphere in Mouffes theory, for the latter asserts the decentred

    and discursively constructed nature of the public/private distinction.

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    22/30

    22

    substance on these principles.22

    In other words, the political unity that is created and

    sustained by hegemonic articulation enters a crisis when the exception appears on the

    horizon.

    Put differently, the limits of the pluralist democracy run parallel to the problems

    that arise in Mouffes attempt to domesticate the political by externalizing it.23

    Mouffe

    deploys the philosophy of concrete life in Schmitt (that legal order must be based on

    human action) as a wedge with which to open up the disembodied, rational and uniform

    political action envisioned in the deliberative theory to the embodied, dynamic and

    antagonistic human agency. However, her desire for infusing liberal politics with a

    democratic lan vital is quickly overshadowed by her preoccupation with keeping it

    under control.24

    No sooner the power of the people makes its appearance than it is

    subjected to exercise through a liberal symbolic framework (Ibid: 2). Human action or

    real life (with the correlate dimension of physical violence) appears in Mouffes theory

    only for an instant before it is absorbed and dissolved into a post-materialist discursive

    network.25This inability or refusal (Mouffes own blind spot, if you will) to think of

    22The position of the state is also undertheorized in Mouffes work, especially when one considers that the

    figure she draws on is one of the staunchest champions of executive state power. Although Mouffe concurs

    with Schmitt that the state is not just one association among others but has primacy over them (Mouffe,

    1993: 99, 131), she never delves into the question of what it is, except for distinguishing it from the

    neutral state in liberal theory, by furnishing it with the ethico-political principles of liberty and equality,

    and designating it as their guarantor. This reluctance explore the problem of the state is reflected in

    Mouffes incorporation of Western political history into her theory, whereby she narrowly focuses, pace

    Lefort on the democratic revolution and the radical indeterminacy it has brought about and neglects the

    enormous shift of power and legitimacy from legislatures to executives that accompanied the 20th

    -century(Wiley, 2002: 485).23

    This gesture ironically resembles Rawlss banishment of the comprehensive political doctrines (that is,

    differences that can culminate in violent antagonism) from political liberalism.24

    There are potential insights to be gained from a comparison of Mouffes strand of radical democratictheory with other such theories as articulated by Sheldon Wolin and Jacques Ranciere. See, among others,

    Ranciere,Disagreement: Politics and Philosophy (1995) and Wolin, Fugitive Democracy (1996).25

    From the Schmittian perspective, this dissolution positions Mouffe alongside Habermas and Rawls in

    that she ultimately sublimates concrete human action to discursive contestation, if not to rational

    deliberation. This, coupled with her non-substantive definition of political equality and the fundamental

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    23/30

    23

    human action except as the animator of the discursive makes her theory stutter in the face

    of the real life that emerges in the exceptional situation (for example, regarding the

    problem with the Muslims, she diagnoses a problem which will not be easily solved

    and suggests that we now have to make them accept [the liberal values], but does not

    offer an idea as to how this can be accomplished). For real life is outside discourse (just

    as the exception is outside the legal order), nonetheless, in its muteness, it comprises the

    constitutive outside and the very condition of possibility of discourse (again, just as the

    legal order ultimately hinges on the exception). Expressed in political terms, it is the

    presence of the enemy outside the borders of the political community and the possibility

    of antagonistic struggle (or rather, the impossibility of discursive engagement) with it

    that makes possible to have agonistic (that is, discursive) relationship with adversaries

    within the political community.

    In light of the discussion above, the position of Schmitts thought in Mouffes

    theory can be restated as follows. When one examines the Schmittian moment withinthe

    pluralist liberal democracy, one finds its main arguments domesticated and its concepts

    hollowed out to such an extent that it is no longer possible to recognize any Schmittian

    content in it, but only an empty shell.26

    There are no more enemies, but adversaries; no

    more substantive homogeneity, but symbolic commonality; no more existential

    antagonism, but respectful agonism; no more concrete human struggle, but discursive

    contestation. Even the concept of the political, which is at the core of Mouffes

    appropriation of Schmitt, is admitted in on the condition of its subjection to politics

    indeterminacy of the ethico-political pillars of her concept of pluralist democracy, renders her theory a

    highly formal one.26As though someone had painted the radiator of a modern central heating system with red flames in order

    to give the appearance of a blazing fire (Schmitt, 1988: 6).

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    24/30

    24

    that domesticates it. When one looks for the Schmittian moment around the pluralist

    democracy, that is, in its relationship to its perceived enemies, one witnesses that the

    domestication of the Schmittian thought has ironically deprived it of the theoretical tools

    with which to define this relationship. With an introverted focus on adversariality and

    agonism, it has grown myopic with respect to antagonism and enmity. It is not clear

    whether the ethico-political principles of liberty and equality constitute a political core

    that people can (pace Schmitt) identify with and thus form a collective will for the

    protection of the regime that represents these values. More importantly, the ultimate locus

    of political unity for Schmitt, that is, the question Who decides? (whether the pluralist

    democracy is lethally threatened, for example) is utterly absent in Mouffes theory.

    Exception is banished from political life, though this time not by a universalist-rationalist

    exorcism, but by a radically decentred and indeterminate discursivity. The real challenge

    of Carl Schmitt to political theory has been the question of the sovereign decision on

    the exception, and in the end it appears that Mouffe does not take up this challenge.

    Conclusion

    If my critical take on Mouffe appears unduly intense, it is not because I think she

    does injustice to Schmitts work, and even less because I advocate Schmittian

    decisionism against pluralist democracy. Rather, the intensity emanates from a concern

    with grimmer political configurations that might arise from the coexistence of liberalism

    and democracy, which Mouffes exclusive focus on their articulation might render one

    blind to. One such possible relation can be conceived as the indistinction of liberalism

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    25/30

    25

    and democracy, and I would like to conclude this essay with a brief speculation on its

    implications.

    Schmitt had already observed the beginnings of a fusion between classical

    liberalism and mass democracy in what he termed the total state (Wiley, 2002: 485),

    and his appeal to maintain the distinction between friend and enemy, and state and

    society was in part a reaction to this development. However, under conditions in which

    the liberal principle of universal humanity and the democratic principle of political

    inclusion/exclusion begin to shade into each other, it becomes harder do sustain the

    distinction between nonpolitical rights of humanity and political rights of citizenship, and

    the loss of ones citizenship status reveals the inalienable rights of man as lacking

    every protection and reality at the moment in which they can no longer take the form of

    rights belonging to the citizens of a state (Agamben, 1998: 126). In other words, ones

    human value is not recognized as such unless ones life is politically relevant for a

    state or a political community. Mouffe locates the contemporary expression of Schmitts

    concept of political equality in citizenship (Mouffe, 2000: 40), and argues that under

    modern conditions the individual and the citizen do not coincide because private and

    public have been separated (Mouffe, 1993: 113), however, her lack of elaboration on

    what kind ofpolitical relationship is or ought to be between the citizen as the subject of

    political rights and the individual as the bearer of human rights is worrying. The dearth of

    thought as to what the political community, that is, the body of citizens should do with

    those who place themselves outside it attests to this gap in her theory. Do these

    politically disinterested people, as Schmitt puts it, lose their citizenship rights? Political

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    26/30

    26

    theory urgently needs to think this relationship aloud so that the human rights are not

    silently abandoned to the question of the political relevance of ones life.

    Moreover, this problem is further aggravated by discourses on theproperpolitical

    existence today, which is increasingly located in First World lives (Butler, 2003: 12).

    Capitalized tropes of Civilization, Democracy and Freedom constitute a discursive matrix

    which differentially distributes political value or relevance of lives over the world, which

    translates into a global geography of differential humanity.27 This was most clearly

    evidenced in the fact that their citizenship in their respective political communities did

    not protect hundreds of thousands of Afghan and Iraqi lives from being destroyed under

    the rubric of collateral damage, which is utterly unthinkable with respect to their First

    World counterparts. The term and the practice of civilization work to produce the

    human differentially and a Western civilization defines itself over and against a

    population understood as, by definition, illegitimate, if not dubiously human (Ibid: 91). I

    think Mouffes assertion that to belong to the political community what is required is

    that we accept a specific language of civil intercourse, while not directly evoking a

    civilized/uncivilized binary, leaves open the question of how the constitutive outside of

    the political community is defined in terms of civility (Mouffe, 1993: 67, emphasis

    added).28

    This silence, coupled with her designation of Islam and Muslims (and one

    should also add ethnic, nationalist, religious, and populist movements) by definition

    27

    Butler convincingly shows the relationship between depoliticization and dehumanization around theproblem of violence. That the Palestinian Intifada cannot be conceived as but terror, while Israeli state

    violence against the Palestinians is understood as self-defense or military operation rests on the

    definition of the Other as lacking a political capacity that We have, which renders the violence it bears

    irrational, uncivilized, inhuman, and bestial (Butler, 2003: 88). The depoliticization of the Other renders itshumanity precarious, and creates conditions in which the Other can be stripped of its humanity (and thus

    human rights) at the moment it is perceived as a threat.28

    This civil language constitutes not an identity but an articulating principle (a grammatical rule) that

    tends to disallow certain articulations and actions, thus rendering certain voices inaudible (Keenan, 2003:

    117, 120, 132).

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    27/30

    27

    anti-secular (and thus illegitimate) leads one to wonder whether Mouffe is leaving too

    wide a leeway for differential understanding of proper political existence, and unwittingly

    participating in the discourse of Civilization. The problem is further exacerbated by the

    radical indeterminacy of political identities, and the contested definitions of citizenship

    and human rights (instigated by the democratic revolution), which render the lines that

    separate politically relevant from irrelevant lives (thus humanity from less-than-

    humanity) fluid and shifting.29 In a crisis situation (a state of emergency), the

    citizenship rights of certain groups can radically fall into question, dragging along the

    protection of their human rights, as demonstrated by the exposure of the Muslims citizens

    and residents in the Western countries to the constant threat of arbitrary detention and

    interrogation in the aftermath of the 9/11.

    What we witness in this picture of the marriage of liberalism and democracy is far

    from a vibrant clash of democratic ideas but a precariousness of human life that verges

    on the brink of falling outside of the political community and thus outside of humanity. It

    appears that the articulation between the liberal logic of universal human rights and the

    democratic logic of political inclusion/exclusion has a dark underbelly wherein the two

    logics enter a zone of indistinction (which flashes for a moment in Mouffes expression

    of contamination). In this zone of indistinction, sovereignty is exercised in the name of

    protecting humanity by deciding on and eradicating the nonhumans that threaten it;

    the preservation of peace becomes inseparable from the incessant war against the

    disturbers of peace; and one cannot quite tell whether one is living under rule or under

    29Keenan observes this in terms of problem of the unqualified equation of radical openness and democracy

    in Mouffes work, and warns that there is no guarantee that the open symbolic space will not be

    articulated in non- or anti-democratic ways (Keenan, 2003: 112). As he rightly asserts, for democracy to

    mean anything certain things have to be decided, however, this point is overlooked by Mouffes

    undertheorization of decision (Ibid: 138).

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    28/30

    28

    exception. The political situation of our times chimes too well with the premonition that

    Schmitt posited at the end of The Political Theology: war is indeed condemned, but extra-

    legal detentions (Guantanamo), tortures (Abu Ghraib) and executions (Afghanistan, Iraq,

    and now Afghanistan once again) remain. The adversary is no longer called an enemy but

    a terrorist and is thereby designated an outlaw of humanity. And the War on Terror

    that has been reigning for the past 8 years has already turned, in its avowed intention to

    rage until the last one of the terrorists is killed, into a crusade and into the last war of

    humanity. Perhaps it is indeed time to face the challenge of Schmitt.

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    29/30

    29

    Bibliography

    Agamben, Giorgio (2005) State of Exception. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    _______________ (2000) Means without End. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota

    Press.

    _______________ (1998) Homo Sacer: Sovereign Power and Bare Life. Stanford:

    Stanford University Press.

    Butler, Judith (2004) Precarious Life: The Powers of Mourning and Violence. London:Verso.

    Derrida, Jacques (2005) Rogues: Two Essays on Reason. Stanford: Stanford University

    Press

    Dyzenhaus (1998) Law as Politics: Carl Schmitts Critique of Liberalism. Durham, NC:Duke University Press.

    Fatovic, Clement (2008) The Political Theology of Prerogative: The Jurisprudential

    Miracle in Liberal Constitutional Thought. Political Theory 6: 487-501.

    Habermas, Jurgen and William Rheg (2001) Constitutional Democracy: A ParadoxicalUnion of Contradictory Principles? Political Theory 29 (6): 766 781.

    Keenan, Alan (2003) Democracy in Question: Democratic Openness in a Time of

    Political Closure. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Lefort, Claude (1988) Democracy and Political Theory. Minneapolis: University ofMinnesota Press.

    McCormick (1997) Carl Schmitt's Critique of Liberalism: Against Politics as

    Technology. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Mouffe, Chantal (2005) On the Political. New York: Routledge.

    _____________ (2000) The Democratic Paradox. London: Verso.

    _____________ (1999) The Challenge of Carl Schmitt. London: Verso.

    _____________ (1993) The Return of the Political. London: Verso.

    Schmitt, Carl (2005) Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty.Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

  • 8/13/2019 The Return of the Schmittian- Radical Democratic Theory at Its Limits, 30p, 09

    30/30

    ___________ (1988) The Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy. Cambridge, MA: The MITPress

    ___________ (1976) The Concept of the Political. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers

    University Press

    Ranciere, Jaques (1995) Disagreement: Politics and Philosophy. Minneapolis: Universityof Minnesota Press.

    Schwab, George (1970) Challenge of Exception: An Introduction to the Political ideas of

    Carl Schmitt between 1921 and 1930. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Thomassen, Lasse (2006) A Bizarre, Even Opaque Practice: Habermas onConstitutionalism and Democracy, in Lasse Thomassen (ed) The Derrida-Habermas

    Reader. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Tocqueville, Alexis de (1990) Democracy in America. New York: Westvaco

    Wiley, James (2002) The Impasse of Radical Democracy. Philosophy and SocialCriticism 28: 4.

    Wolin, Sheldon (1996) Fugitive Democracy, in Seyla Benhabib (ed) Democracy and

    Difference: Contesting the Boundaries of the Political, Princeton: Princeton University,pp. 31 - 45