The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice...

19
4 The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice-theoretical Approach Godehard Link 1 Introduction The weekly A1agac;:;ine of the German newspaper Frankfurter Zeitung regu- larly issues Marcel Proust's famous questionnaire which is answered each time by a different personality of West German public life. One of those recently questioned was Rudolf Augstein, editor of Der Spiegel; his reply to the question: "Which property do you appreciate most with your friends?" was (I) "that they are fc\\." Clearly, this is not a property of any one of Augstein's friends; yet, even apart from the esprit it was designed to display the answer has a straightforward interpretation. The phrase (I) predicates something col!ertiveli1 of a group of objects, here: Augstein's friends. As it is well knmYn, collective predication is a rather pervasive phenomenon in natural language, as the following sample of sentences shows: (2) The children built the raft. (3) The Romans built the bridge. (4) Tom, Dick, and Harry carried the piano upstairs. 1 (5) The playing cards are scattered all over the floor. ( 6) The members of the committee will come together today. (7) Mary and Sue are room-mates. (8) The girls hated each other. There a striking similarity between collective predication and predication involving mass nouns. (9) (a) The children gather around their teacher. (b) The water gathers in big pools.

Transcript of The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice...

Page 1: The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice …users.ox.ac.uk/~sfop0776/LinkPlurals.pdf · (8) The girls hated each other. There a striking similarity between collective

4

The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice-theoretical Approach

Godehard Link

1 Introduction

The weekly A1agac;:;ine of the German newspaper Frankfurter Zeitung regu-larly issues Marcel Proust's famous questionnaire which is answered each time by a different personality of West German public life. One of those recently questioned was Rudolf Augstein, editor of Der Spiegel; his reply to the question: "Which property do you appreciate most with your friends?" was

(I) "that they are fc\\."

Clearly, this is not a property of any one of Augstein's friends; yet, even apart from the esprit it was designed to display the answer has a straightforward interpretation. The phrase (I) predicates something col!ertiveli1 of a group of objects, here: Augstein's friends.

As it is well knmYn, collective predication is a rather pervasive phenomenon in natural language, as the following sample of sentences shows:

(2) The children built the raft. (3) The Romans built the bridge. (4) Tom, Dick, and Harry carried the piano upstairs. 1

(5) The playing cards are scattered all over the floor. ( 6) The members of the committee will come together today. (7) Mary and Sue are room-mates. (8) The girls hated each other.

There a striking similarity between collective predication and predication involving mass nouns.

(9) (a) The children gather around their teacher. (b) The water gathers in big pools.

Page 2: The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice …users.ox.ac.uk/~sfop0776/LinkPlurals.pdf · (8) The girls hated each other. There a striking similarity between collective

128 Godehard Link

Moreover, a characteristic feature of mass terms, their c1111111/ativc reference propertv,2

can be imitated by plurals.

(10) (a) If a is water and his water then the sum of 11 and his water. (b) If the animals in this camp arc horses, and the animals in that camp are

horses, then the animals in both camps arc horses.

All this has been observed and discussed in the literature althoug;h the noted parallelism has perhaps not been stressed too much. 3 As it can be seen from Pelleticr's 1979 rnlumc, however, there is much disagreement about the proper way or attacking the logical problems posed by plurals and mass term!>. From a semantic point of view the basic question is: what do mass terms and plural expressions denote? Some have thought that in order to be able to give a satisfactory answer to this question it is necessary Lo give up or at last extend the underlying set theory and to define new kinds of objects, tiw instance enscmhles (Bunt 1979) or K11/lektio11en (Blau 1979). I think, however, that we can retain the usual set-theoretic metalanguage and simply enrich the structure of our models as to account for properties like cumulative reference. On my view, such properties arc also not secured by defining some plural or mass term denotations out of others through sct-theoretic manipulations; they all :-.hould be recognized as simply being there. What we rather should try to discover, then, is the network of the various relations which they enter and through which they are tied together. Jn the case of group mass objects this picture naturally leads to the notion oflattice structure,-1 an idea which is, again, not new: it is inherent in mereological predicate logic and the Calculus oflndividuals as developed by Leonard and Goodman ( 1940) and Goodman md Q_uinc ( 1947). However, its possible use in the present context has perhaps been obscured reductionist ontological considerations which are, in my opinion, quite alien to the purpose oflogically analyzing the inference structures of natural language. s Our guide in ontological matters has to he language itself, it seems to me. So if we have, for instance, two expressions a and h that refer to entities occupying the same place at the same time but have different sets of predicates applying to them, then the entities referred to arc simplv not the same. From this it follows that my ring and the gold making up my ring arc different entities; they arc, however, connected by what I shall call the c1111stituti1111 rdati1111: There is exactly one portion of matter making up my ring at a time. A constitution relation C has been explicitly introduced into the discussion by Parsons ( 1979). Sharing· his intuitions on this point l shall provide a similar 2-place relation, "C', for constitutes or 11wkes up. Its semantic counterpart in the theory to be presented below, the "materialization" function h, lies at the heart of my reconstruction of the ontology of plurals and mass terms: individuals arc created by ling·uistic expressions involving different structures even if the portion of matter making them up is the same. Consider the example from Blau (1979) (imagine that there is a deck of playing cards on the table):

(11) (a) the cards (h) the deck of cards

vVhile the portions of matter denoted by (I la) and (11 b) arc the same, I consider the individuals <lS being distinct 6 (I la) refers to the pure collection of objects, and in many

Page 3: The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice …users.ox.ac.uk/~sfop0776/LinkPlurals.pdf · (8) The girls hated each other. There a striking similarity between collective

The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms 129

contexts (11 b ), too, refers just to this collection. In general, however, the introduction of a collective term like ( 11 b) is indicative of connotations being added enough for it to refer to a different individual; for instance, a committee is not just the collection of its members, etc. Note, by the way, that the transition to an function would be of no help here. There might be two different committees which necessarily consist of exactly the same members. 7

lt might be thought, then, that collective predication is just the context in which pairs of expressions like (l la, b) refer to collections and thus are eoreferential. This is not so, however, as can be seen from the following example. Imagine that there arc several decks of cards, a blue one, a green one, etc., lying on a table. 8 Then the two following sentences do not mean the same although number consecutively is a collective predicate (the German word is durchnumerieren).

(12) (a) The cards on the table are numbered consecutively. (b) The dech of cards on the table are numbered consecutively.

By contrast, spatio-temporal collective predicates do refer to the pure collection, or, as 1 conceive it, the portion of matter making up the individual in question. Examples arc be-on-the-table, occupy, etc. I call such predicates invariant. So the following (a) sentences arc indeed equivalent to their corresponding (b) sentences.

(13) (a) The cards are on the table. (b) The decks of cards are on the table.

(14) (a) The stars that presently make up the Pleiadcs galactic cluster occupy an area that measures 700 cubic light years.9

(b) The Plciades galactic cluster occupies an area etc.

In the following I shall distinguish between pure plural individuals involved in ( 12) and collections in the portions-of-matter sense referred to in (13) and (14). The former 1 call (individual) sums or plural objects; they respect levels of "linguistic comprehension" as shown by ( 12). By contrast, collections do not, they typically merge those levels. Sums and collections are similar, however, in that they both are just individuals, as concrete as the individuals which serve to define them, and of the same logical type as these. The latter feature is important because there is no systematic type ambig·uity inherent in predicates like rnrry, build, demolish, defend, etc. As to the question of concreteness of sums of concrete objects, 1 agree with the intuitions of those who say that an aggregate of objects like a heap of playing cards which can be shuffled, burned, etc., is simply not an abstract entity like a set (sec Burge 1977; Blau 1979). What is more important, however, is the fact that the set approach to plural objects 10 docs not carry over to the case of mass terms, thus missing the structural analogy between the two cases. Inherent in the notions of a set is atomicity which is not present in the linguistic behaviour of mass

Before I go on to present my own approach I want to say something about what tcr Mculen calls nominal mass terms. Typical examples are stuff names like gold in sentences like gold has the atomic number 79. But there is also the time-honored sentence maier is midespread in which the term mater has apparently a somewhat different status. It seems

Page 4: The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice …users.ox.ac.uk/~sfop0776/LinkPlurals.pdf · (8) The girls hated each other. There a striking similarity between collective

130 Godehard Link

to refer to the concrete "scattered individual" that you just find everywhere, hence Quine's analysis in terms of mereology. In this sense the sentence should be synonym-ous to the water (on earth) is widespread. Of the same type is the use of gold in Amerirn's gold stored in Fort Knox. Here, ag·ain, a concrete object is referred to by . 1 / mm ca 's gold, namely the material fusion of all quantities of the US gold reserve. So there can be no doubt that some notion of fusion is needed to account for definite descriptions inrnlving predicative mass terms (the µ-operator defined below docs just this). Genu-ine stuff names, however, arc something else. Substances are abstract entities and cannot be defined in terms of their concrete manifestations. The question, then, is of what kind the connections are that are intuitively felt between substances and their quantities. Take water, for instance. A quantity is water if it displays the internal structure of water, that is HzO. But this relation is not a logical one. Or else we might look for substance properties which carry over to the quantities of the substance in question. Water is a liquid and yet, all concrete water might be frozen. So we have to go over to dispositional properties, getting more and more involved into our knowledge of the physical world ... What I am getting at is that nominal mass terms do not seem to have a proper logic. Be this as it may, this issue is completely independent of the lattice structure that governs the behaviour of predicative mass terms and plural expressions; it is only this structure that I want to address myself to in the present paper .11

Now what I am going to propose, then, is basically the following·. First of all, let us take seriously the morphological change in pluralization, which is present in many natural languages, and introduce an operator, "*", working on I-place predicates P, , , which generates all the individual sums of members of the extensions of P. Such a starred predicate now has the same cumulative reference property as a mass predicate, it is closed under sum formation: any sum of parts which arc * P is again * P. This property gives rise to the introduction of a Boolean structure on the domain of discourse, E: technically, E becomes an atomic Boolean algebra which is taken to be complete so that every subset of E possesses a sum. Now let 11 ·II be the denotation function in a model, and llPll the extension of P. Then ll*Pll, the extension of*P, can be defined in terms of llPll as the complete join-subsemilattice 12 in E generated by llPll. This construction is the mathematical expression of the closure property referred to above. The set A of atoms of E consists or the "singular objects", like this card, that deck of cards, etc. Among them are all the different portions of matter, like the water making up this ice cube.

Now, let a and h denote two atoms in A. Then there are two more individuals to be called below a+ hand a EB h, a+ his still a singular object in A, the matenaljimon o(a and h; a EB h is the individual sum or plural ob1ect of a and h. The theory is such that a + h constitutes, but is not identical with, a EB h. This looks like a wild platonistic caprice strongly calling for Occam's Razor. Language, however, seems to function that way. Take for a, h two rings recently made out of some old Egyptian gold. Then the rings, a EB h, are new, the st14f; a+ b, is old.

Sums are partially ordered through the intrinsic ordering relation "Si" on E which is expressed in the object language by the 2-placc predicate "TI". It is called the indii·idual part relation (I-part relation, for short) and satisfies the biconditional

(15) aTih <---->a E::! h = b. i

'1 ,,

Page 5: The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice …users.ox.ac.uk/~sfop0776/LinkPlurals.pdf · (8) The girls hated each other. There a striking similarity between collective

The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms 131

The semantic counterpart of (15) is the well-known Boolean relation (where LJ, denotes the join operation on E):

(16) llall S, llbll iff llall LJ, llbll = llbll Now if Pis a 1-place predicate and * P the corresponding plural predicate let Cp (the proper plural predicate of P) be true of exactly the non-atomic sums in the extension of *P. Then we can define the sum and the proper sum of the P's, raPx and a*xPx, respectively, as the supremum of all objects that are* P and c P, respectively (" 1" is the description operator):

(17) (a) axPx : = 1x(*Px ii /\y(*Pv----+ yIIx)). (b) a*xPx: = 1x(c Px r, /\y(*Py----+ yIIx)).

(J*xPx carries the presupposition that there arc at least two P's; in this case axPx and (J*xP\· coincide.

The materialfi1sion of the P's, denoted by µxPx, becomes that object which consti-tutes the sum of the P's:

(18) pxPx:=1x(.rL(JxPx)

The p-operator has the effect of merging levels of comprehension, as I called it above. Thus we "ill have pxPx = 11.rQr, if P stands for is a card of one o(the card decks, and Q for is a card deck. axPx and (JxQt· are not the same, however. If we have two decks of Bridg;e cards, for instance, axPx contains 104 atoms whereas axQr contains only 2 atoms.

There is a second ordering relation, called the material part (m-part) rela1i1111 and denoted by "T". It establishes a partial order on portions of matter, but only a preorder, called S 11,, on the whole domain of individuals. Objects which are m-parts of one another are materially equi11a!e11t in that they have the same portion of matter constituting· them. If a is an i-part of h then a is an m-part of h; symbolically:

(19) aIIh Tb

In order to explain the meaning of "T" more precisely let me supply the remaining concepts of the model structure to be defined below. In addition to the domain of individuals, E, there is a set D which is endowed with a join operation "LJ" making D into a complete, but not necessarily atomic, join-semilattice. D is partially ordered by its intrinsic ordering relation, S, defined by

(20) x s y iff x LJ y = y

D represents the set of all individual portions of matter in the model, and as such, it is considered as a subset of A, the set of atoms of E. The relation (20) stands for a material part-whole relation. 13 It can be used to order the individuals of E materially. For this I postulate for every model the existence of a semilattice homomorphism h from E \ { 0}

Page 6: The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice …users.ox.ac.uk/~sfop0776/LinkPlurals.pdf · (8) The girls hated each other. There a striking similarity between collective

132 Godehard Link

to D such that h is the identity function on D and commutes with the supremum operator. Then h is order preserving, i.e. we have

(21) .r<::;,y =? h(x)Sh(y)

for all x,y E E with x # 0. I can now define the relation <::; 111 mentioned above by

(22) x <::; 111 y iff h(x) <'.'. h(y) (x,y EE\ {O}).

Sm is the semantic counterpart of "T". Obviously, <::;, is coarser than <::; 111 , a fact that is syntactically expressed by ( 19). In its intended interpretation, then, which is formally implemented into the model structure, a Tb can be read as follows: "the portion of matter constituting a is m-part of the portion of matter constituting h''.

One-place predicates are interpreted as subsets of E \ { 0}. (Herc, the null clement 0 is assigned the role of a dummy object to which no predicate applies and which can take care of denotation gaps arising in our description theory; for details see I ,ink ( 1979, 5.2).) If Pis a mass term the extension llPll of Pin a given model should be a set of portions of matter which is closed under joins. So llPll becomes a subsemilattice of D. This completes the informal description of the Boolean mode/ s/ruc/ure@ = \E, A, D, h) and of the LPM-model M = \@, 11 ·II). For precise definitions sec below.

If Pis a predicate we can introduce its mass term correspondent, called '"P; if llPll is the extension of P in a model, define

(23) ll 111 Pll: = {x E Dix<'.'. suphlllPllJ}

If Pis already a predicative mass term we have, by this definition, llPll C ll 111 Pll. Mass term correspondents occur in natural language. 14 Consider

(24) (a) There is apple in the salad. (b) V.rC Px A Q.x)

(24 b) is a formalization of (24a), with P for is an apple, m P for is apple, and Q for is in Lhe salad. From this we can infer, intuitively as well as formally:

(25) (a) There are apple parts in the salad. (b) VxVy(*Px 11yTx 11Qy)

We have, in fact, the following theorem (cf. (T. 14) below):

(26) '"Pa_, Vy(*Pv11aTy)

Returning now to the model structure consider once again the extension of a 1-placc predicate P. It can contain atoms as well as proper i-sums. This general case of a mixed e.rtension is exemplified by predicates like ca1-rJ1 the piano: think of Tom, Dick, and Harry (together), Obelix (all by himself), etc. Common nouns and intransitive verbs like die, however, seem to admit only atoms to their extension. l call such predicates dislribu! ive:

Page 7: The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice …users.ox.ac.uk/~sfop0776/LinkPlurals.pdf · (8) The girls hated each other. There a striking similarity between collective

The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms 133

(27) Distr(P) ----1 /\x(Px ----1 At x)

(here the predicate At stands for the property of being an atom in the model). To illustrate take the intuitively valid inference from (a) to (b) in (28).

(28) (a) John, Paul, George, and Ringo are pop stars. (b) Paul is a pop star.

This inference can be formally represented if we consider pop star as a distributive predicate P in the sense of (27). In this case the extension of* P is closed under non-zero i-parts (see theorem (T. 10) below), so every atom of an i-sum which is* Pis itself * P, hence it is a P. In symbolic form the inference (28) looks like this.

(29) (a) * P( a E9 h E9 c E9 d) (b) Distr(P) (c) b Ila ffi h E9 c EB d (d) *Ph (e) Pb

In a similar way we have the following valid inference with the distributive predicate Q for die (P stands for animal):

(30) (a) The animals died. So every animal died. (b) *Q(a*xPx) :=;. /\x(Px ----1 Qx)

For non-distributive predicates we have, of course, no such result, witness carrv: 11 H-1 h might be in the extension of carrv while a or h alone is not. Notice that these predicates enter formalizations unstarred. To illustrate,

(31) (a) The children gather around their teacher (b) Q(a*xP.r) (with Q for gather etc.).

think there is no harm in accepting this systematic difference: i.e. distributive predicates wor1..ing on plural terms have to be starred, all the other predicates must not be. For distributivity seems to be a lexical feature. If we have a formal translation procedure the predicates have to be subcategorized accordingly.

There is one more operator, 'ff", in the logic LPM to be presented below. Tp, for a predicate P, is to be read as partakes in P. I introduce this operator in order to be able to distinguish between the plural terms the children and all the children. It seems to me that in all the children huill the raft it is claimed that every child took part in the action whereas in the children built the raft it is only said that the children somehow managed to build the raft collectively without presupposing an active role in the action for every single child. This intuition enters the formalization of the two phrases given below. I want to stress, however, that the operator ,ff,, can only be partially characterized in view of the essentially pragmatic nature of its intended interpretation. So let me formulate just the following meaning postulates for ,ff,, which seem to be plausible:

Page 8: The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice …users.ox.ac.uk/~sfop0776/LinkPlurals.pdf · (8) The girls hated each other. There a striking similarity between collective

134 Godehard Link

(32) (a) (b)

T Ar( Px ____, Vy(xIIy /\Py)) T Distr(P) ----+ Av( Px ----+ Px)

I conclude the informal part of the paper with some more formalizations of natural language sentences i1wolving plurals and mass terms. Most of the principles governing their logic that have been mentioned in the literature come out valid in the system LPM below. Some of them are instantiated here, like Massey's plural-ity principles of symmetry, expansion, and contraction (sec Massey ( 1976 )). What I did not treat in LPJ\1, however, are any "downward" closure properties that arc somehow felt to be present in the behavior of mass terms ("a part of water is still water"). Such principles can be added when a careful linguistic analysis has suc-ceeded in giYing them a form that takes care, in particular, of the problem of' minimal parts (is every m-part of lemonade really lemonade again?). For some discussion of downward closure properties see, e.g., Bunt (1979) and Hocpelman and Rohrer (1980).

(33) (a) (b)

(34) (a) (b)

(35) (a) (b)

(36) (a) (b)

(37) (a) (b)

(38) (a) (b)

(39) (a) (b)

(40) (a)

(b) ( 41) (a)

(b) (42) (a)

(b) (43) (a)

(b) (44) (a)

(b)

A child built the raft Pr: x is a child Vx(Px ,\Qr); Qr: .v built the raft Children built the raft. V.r(Px /\ Ql·); Pr, Qr: dto. The child built the raft. Vy(J' = lx:Px 11 Qy); Pr, Qr: dto. The children built the raft. V_J°'()' = r:r*xPr t.Qy); P.r, Qr: dto. Every child saw the raft. /\x(Px __,_ Qr); Pr: dto.

Qr: .r saw the raft All the children built the raft. /\y(v = r:r*xPx ----+ Qy); Pr, Qr as in (33)

Q: = Ax(Qr A A:::.(:::.II.r ___,·i·Q;;:;)). Tom and Dick carried the piano upstairs. P(a Efi /!); a: Tom, b: Dick,

Pr: x carried the piano upstairs Tom and Dick carried the piano upstairs, so Dick and Tom carried it upstairs. P(a 123 b) ==? P(b E.B a) (sy111111etrv)

John and Paul are pop stars and George is a pop star, so John, Paul, and George are pop stars. cP(a EB b) fl Pc ==? cP(a dj b c) (expansion) John, Paul, George, and Ringo are pop stars, so Paul and Ringo are pop stars. (see (28)) cP(a Efi b tB c tB d) ==? c P(b d) (rn11tractio11) (All) water is wet. /\x(P.r ____,Qr); Px: x is (a quantity of) water The water of the Rhine is dirty. Q({txPx); Px: .r is (a quantity of) Rhine water

Page 9: The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice …users.ox.ac.uk/~sfop0776/LinkPlurals.pdf · (8) The girls hated each other. There a striking similarity between collective

The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms 135

( 45) (a) This ice cube is water. (b) Pzx(xLa); a: this ice cube

Px: as in ( 43) (46) (a) The gold in Smith's ring is old, but Smith's ring is not old.

(b) Qix(Px 1\ .1· La)/\ /Qa; Px: xis gold Qr:: \' is old a: Smith's ring

2 The Logic of Plurals and Mass Terms (LPM)

LP!\1 is a first order predicate calculus with the usual logical constants "/", "v", "11", "--+", "--+ ", "V", "/\", the description operator denoted by "i", and the abstraction operator "A". 15 The syntactic variables are, for formulas of LPM, "qJ", "1V', "x"; for individual terms, "a", "b", "c"; for variables, ".r", "y", '';:;";for (I-place) predicates, "P", "Q'. These symbols can also appear with primes and indices. For metalinguistic (definitional) identity the symbol ",,:,", (": =") "ill be used. The set of I-place predicate constants contains two specified subclasses: the set f\1T of predirntivc mass terms and the set DP of distrihutii•e predicates. MT and DP arc taken to be disjoint sets.

As special primitive S)'mhols of LP!\1 we have a I-place predicate symbol "E", three 2-place predicate constants, "II", "T", "L", and two operators on I-place predicates,"*" and "T". The intended interpretations are the following. Ea stands for "a c.rists "; all h for" a is an indh•idual pa rt (i-part) of/!''; a Th for "a is a material part ( m-part) of h", a J, h for "a constilutcs or makes up h"; *P for "the plural predica!e of P"; Tp for "par!akcs i11 P".

Now I introduce a number of expressions.

General first order ahhrez•lations. Let P, Q be I-place predicates, R a 2-place predicate, and a an individual term.

(D.l) PC Q --+ /\x(Px--+ Qr) (D.2) P=Q --+ PcQ11QcP (D.3) P E9 Q : = lr(Px v Qr) (D.4) !" : = lx(x =a)

Furthermore, the usual definitions for the following formulas imolving R arc assumed: Refl (R) ("R is reflexive"), Trans (R) ("R is transitive"), S)'m (R) ("R is symmetric"), Antisvm (R) (''R is antisymmetric"). We then have, with PrO (R) for "R is a preordering relation", PO (R) for "R is a partial ordering relation", and Equ (R) for "R is an equivalence relation":

(D.S) (D.6) (D.7)

PrO(R) PO(R) ElJu(R)

Refl(R) A, Trans(R) /\ Trans(R) r, Antis)'ln(R)

Refl(R) ,\ Trans(R) A, Svm(R)

Page 10: The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice …users.ox.ac.uk/~sfop0776/LinkPlurals.pdf · (8) The girls hated each other. There a striking similarity between collective

136 Godehard Link

2 Defined predicate constants. With two individual terms a, b, let a = b stand for "a equals h", a rv b for "a ism-equivalent to b", At a for "a is an atom", and Mpa for "a is a portion o( matter". Define

(D.8) a=b H aIIb 11 hIIa (D.9) (/CV b H aTb11bTa

(D.10) Ata H /\x( xIIa ___. x = a) (D.11) Mpa H a La

3 Defined predicate operators. Let P be a I-place predicate and a an individual term. The proper plural predicate CP of P and the mass term rorre.1pondent to P, '"P, arc then defined as follows.

(D.12) Cpa H *Pa:, nAt a (D.13) "'Pa <---+ Vy(* Pv 11 a T fr:(z Ly)).

4 Defined individual terms. With I-place predicates P and individual terms a, h, define the /-sum of the P's, the proper i-sum of the P's, the i-sum of a and b, the material fusion of the P's, and the rnaterial .fl1sio11 of a and h, respectively:

(D.14) CJxPx ·- ix(* Px /\ /\y(* Pv -> y II .r)). (D.15) CJ*xPx ·- lx(cPx 11 /\y(* Pv <---+ y TI .r)). (D.16) a rf: b ·- CJ.r:(/11 ffi ft, )x (D.17) pxP.r ·- ix(x L CJxP.r) (D.18) a+h ·- px(J" EfJ ft, ).r

5 Special abbrcviati11e formulas. Let P be a 1-place predicate.

(D.19) (D.20) (D.21)

Distr(P) <---+ /\x(Px <---+ At.r) hf(P) <---+ /\x(P.r _, Mpx)

/Jw(P) <---+ 1\x/\y(x cv y---+ (P.r H Pl')).

6

Distr (P) is to be read as "Pis distrlbuti1·e" (i.e. Pis true of atomic individuals only), M (P) as "Pis a material jJredicatc" (i.e. it is true of portions of matter only); Inr (P) means: "P is an in<'an1111t predicate" (i.e. it is closed under substitution of m-equivalent terms).

"T" /l!Ieaning postulates for .

(MP.I) (MP.2)

/\x(1 Px Distr(P)

Vy(x Ily ;., Pl')). /\x( T P.r <----> P.v)

i.e. for all .r, if x partakes in P, then x is an i-part of a y which is P (1\1P.1 ); if Pis distributive, then for all r, x partakes in P just in case x is P (MP.2).

Page 11: The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice …users.ox.ac.uk/~sfop0776/LinkPlurals.pdf · (8) The girls hated each other. There a striking similarity between collective

The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms 137

The sernantlcs o( LP M. I shall employ the usual set-theoretic terminology (sec, for instance, Eberle (1970), Link ( 1979), with for set inclusion and ''.fl YJ" for the/.:. image {f(x) I .r E Y} of Y X under the function f: X -> Z. Moreover, some elementary notions of lattice theory are needed (see, e.g., (1971 ), Sikorski (1969) for their definition) partial ordering relation, partially ordered se! ("poset"), 1-elernent, 0-elernent, atom, semi-lattice, join-semllattlce, lattice, s11blat1ice, ideal, principal ideal, complete lattice, Boolean lattice (algebra), a tornic lattice, (semi) lattice homomorphism. The supremum of a subset Y of a poset X, relative to its ordering relation<:::, if it exists, will be denoted by Y, the principal ideal generated by an clement x E X, where X is a lattice, by (x]. So we have (x] = {y EX I y <::: x}. If Xis a complete (semi)lattice, and Y X, then [ YJ denotes the complete sub(semi)latticc generated by Y.

I now provide a model-theoretic interpretation of the formal system LPM.

(D.22) A Boolean model structure !Pith homogeneous kernel ("boosk") is a quadruple @ (E,A, D, h) such that

E is a complete atomic ( c.a.) Boolean alg-ebra, with join operation LJ, and the intrinsic ordering relation <'.'.'.,;

2 A E is the set of atoms in E;

4 D A is a complete join-scmilattice with join lJ and ordering relation <'.'.'.; h: E\ {O} ->Dis a semilattice homomorphism such that (i) h2D,,:, zdD, i.e. h(x),,:, x for all x E D;

(ii) for all B E\{O}.

It follows from this definition that we have, in particular, for all x, JI E £\ {O}:

(47) h(xU,JI) (48) x <'.'.'.,JI

h(x) lJ h(y) lz(x) <'.'.'. h(y)

The homomorphism h induces a second ordering relation on E\ {O} which will be called the material part relation on £\ { 0} and denoted by <::: 111 :

(D.23) x <::'. 111 y iff /z(x) <'.'.'. h(J') (x,y E E\{O})

<'.'.'.,,, is only a preordering relation. It gives rise to an equivalence relation, defined by

(D.24) x "',,, y iff x <'.'.'.,,, y and y Sm x (x,JI E E\{0}),

and thus to a partition of E\ { 0} into equivalence classes each containing all the individuals that are made up by the same portion of matter.

In the following definition of a model for ] ,PM I am going to interpret only I-place predicates, for simplicity (except for the special 2-place predicate constants). All the other many-place predicates receive their usual first order interpretation.

(D.25) A mode/for LPM is an ordered pair II· 11) such that @ (E,A, D, h) is a boosk (£is the domain o(zndividuals in M, "i the set ofa111111s in A1, D the set o(portions of matter in AI, and h the "materiali.;:,alion jimction" in A1);

Page 12: The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice …users.ox.ac.uk/~sfop0776/LinkPlurals.pdf · (8) The girls hated each other. There a striking similarity between collective

138 Godehard Link

2 II· II is a first order assignment of denotations to the primitive expressions of LPM such that

(i) llall E E if a is an individual constant; (ii) llPll E\ {O} if Pis a I-place predicate constant;

(iii) llPll A if P E DP; (iv) llPll is a complete subsemilattice of D if P E MT;

T (v) II Pll {x E Elx # O&=:Jy E llPll such that x S1y}; (vi) llTPll===llPll if PE DP.

The model is such that predicates are interpreted in the non-zero clements of E (condition (ii)). Conditions (iii), (iv) guarantee the special properties of the distributive and mass predicates, respectively. (v) and (vi) are designed to validate the meaning postulates (MP.I) and (MP.2) above, respectively.

Let NI= (@,II · II) be a model for LPM. The usual first order semantical recursion rules are assumed, where quantification is taken to run over the non-zero elements of the domain of individuals only. The truth and denotation conditions for the special primitive symbols of LPM are defined as follows ("I" stands for "true"; bivalencc is assumed):

(D.26) llPall===I iff llall E llPll; (D.27) llixPxll===d iff d # 0 and llPll==={d}, and 0 otherwise; (D.28) llEall===I iff llall # 0 (D.29) llaIIhll===I iff llall # 0 and llall <:'.'., llhll; (D.30) llaThll===l iff llall, llbll # 0 and

h(llall) <:'.'. h(llbll); (D.31) Ila L hll ===I iff llhll # 0 and llall===hCllhll); (D.32) 11 * Pll ===r llPll J, (the complete LJ,-subsemilattice

generated byllPll);

A number of semantical facts can now be derived that g·ive truth and denotation conditions for all the defined symbols of LPM.

(49) llP C Qll===I iff llPll llQll (50) llP = Qll===I iff llPll===llQll ( 51) llP E9 Qll ===llPll U llQll (52) ll!"ll==={llall} (53) Ila= bll===I iff llall, llhll # 0 and llall===llhll (54) Ila rv bll=== I iff llall, llhll # 0 and h(llall)===h(llhll) (55) llAtall,,:, I iff llall EA (56) llJ\!Ipall===I iff llall ED (57) ll*Pll ,,:, {x E El=:JX llPll &X # 0 s.t. x===sup1X} (58) llCPll ,,:, ll*Pll\A (59) ll"'Pll === E Dix<:'.'.

=== x E Dl=:Jy E ll*Pll such that r <:'.'. h(l')}

. I

Page 13: The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice …users.ox.ac.uk/~sfop0776/LinkPlurals.pdf · (8) The girls hated each other. There a striking similarity between collective

The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms 139

(60) llO"xPxll - sup, llPll, with sup,0,,:,0 (61) llO"*xP.rll - llO"xPxll if llPll has 2': 2 elements, and 0 otherwise (62) Ila EB bll - llall LJ, llbll (63) ll/trPxll - sup,,,hlllPllJ if llPll #- 0, and 0 otherwise (64) Ila+ bll - h(liail) LJ h(ilhll) if llali #- 0 #- llhll

Let the notion of truth in a given model be defined in the usual way. A formula is Dalld if it is true in every model.

I now give, in a loose order, a list of theorems of LPM that come out valid under the above interpretation. I may mention, in particular, the homogeneous reference prnperties (T.11 ), (T.12), and the existence and identity criteria for the O"- and /Herms, (T.16 )-(T.21 ).

(T. l) (T.2) (T.3) (T.4) (T.5) (T.6) (T.7) (T.8) (T.9)

(T.10) (T.11) (T.12) (T.13) (T.14) (T.15) (T.16) (T.17) (T.18) (T.19) (T.20) (T.21) (T.22) (T.23) (T.24) (T.25) (T.26) (T.27) (T.28) (T.29) (T.30) (T.31) (T.32)

a = b ---+ aIIh fl b Ila a IIh ---+ a Th a= h ____, aTbAhTa Equ( = ) /\ Equ( ,....., ) PO(l1) /I PrO( T) Distr (P) ---+ Ar(Px ---+ Jc Px) Pc *P /\x(Atx---+ (Px---+ *Px)). /\x(* Px ____, xIIO"xPx /\ Vy(P)' Ayllx)). Distr(P) ---+ /\x/\y(* P)' /\ xIIy ---+ * Px) /\x /\]'( * Px A* Pv ---+ * P.r EB y) /\x/\y(P.r A Py ---+ Px + y) for P E MT M(P) ---+ P c 111P Mpa ____.("'Pa---+ Vy(*Pyfl.aTy)). VxPxAP C Q---+ *Q(O"xP.r) VxP.r ---+ EO"xPx V xPx ---+ Ep:>.:P:x EO"*xPx ---+ VxVy(Px fl Pv fl x #- y) P = Q ---+ O"xPx = GxQx Dzstr(P) /\ Distr(Q) ____, ( O"xPx = GxQr ---+ P = Q) P = Q ---+ pxPx = pxQr Ata---+ a = O"x(x =a) .Mpa ___, a = JLX(x = a) /t.rP:x = ix(Px /\ /\y(Py ---+ y T x)) a,--., h---+ px(.r =a)= 11.r(x = h) /txPx = ix(.r £ ftxPx) Mp(pxPx) a L h ---+ Mpa /\a ,....., b pxPx ,....., O"xPx O"xPx = O"xQr ___, /txPx = /t.rQr /\x/\y(xIIy ---+ x rCB y = y) /\x/\y(xTy x + y = y)

for PE MT

Page 14: The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice …users.ox.ac.uk/~sfop0776/LinkPlurals.pdf · (8) The girls hated each other. There a striking similarity between collective

140 Godehard Link

3 Applications to Montague Grammar

I ,et the basic syntax be as in PTQ 16 The category CN of common noun phrases has to be subcategorized into MCN (mass noun phrases), SCN (singular count noun phrases), and PCN (plural count noun phrases). The quantifiers discussed are a, 0p1, some, the, all the, flJery, all; they are of category T /CN with suitable subcat-egorizations (term formation is <lone compositionally). We have the obvious plural rule

(65) ( E Pscv =} (p1 E Ppc\

hand becomes hands, (..:..._ child, children, etc. The logic of PTQ TITL, is extended as follows. TITL', or extended TITL, contains

as new symbols all the special symbols of LPM. Additional mea11111g/iil expressions arc: (i) *(, c(, T( E MEp, and "'( E MEp for T = e(r E TJ1pe, or HI, ( E MEp); (ii) rrurp, rr*uq>, 1u<f> E ME1 , and pu<f> E ME, (r E Type, u E Varr, </> E ME1);

(iii) cdljj E il·1E1 and (/. ffi () E MEr (TE Type, u.,(J E MET); (iv) u.T/), (/. rv fi, u. L fJ E ME1, and u. + /5 E ME" (u., fJ E ME,,).

The semantics for TITL' has to specify the "boolification" of the sets of possible denotations since the i-sum operation applies to expressions of any type (m-sums are formed on level e only). Let E be a c.a. Boolean algebra, /, J sets, and K = I x J. A Boolean hierarchy o( possible denotations over E mi th re.1pect to K is a family of sets (Dr,£, F·JrE Trpc defined as in PTQ, but endowed with a c.a. Boolean structure for every Dr as folio\\ s: (i) The sets De = E and D1 = 2 arc already c.a. Boolean algebras; (ii) J; g E D,r; then: (( U,r g)(k): = /(k) Ur g(k)(k E K), similarly for the other operations; (iii) /; g E D,n; then (( IJ"r g)(x): = /(x) Ur g(x) (x E D" ), similarly for the other operations. The resulting structures arc c.a. Boolean.

An inlerpretation for TJTL' is a 7-tuple 11·11) such that (i) (E, A, D, h) is a boosk, (ii) K = I x J is as in PTQ and (iii) II· II is the interpretation function that naturally emerges from a combination of TITL and LPM. As rules of" truth and denotation provided by an appropriate recursive definition let me mention the following: (i) characteristic function of l{x E E MEr1); (ii) the characteristic function of [ {.r E Drl 1} lur (( E /HE,r1, k EK); (iii) nr1 X'1r: where ( E /11E,1, Ar the set of atoms in Dr, X Jr the characteristic function of Ar, and "'" the Boolean complement; (iY) (k) nu x'1r(( E it1Em,k EK); (v) with an<l rru</>11 if ll)_u<f>ll has more than one element, and 0 otherwise; (vi) iff ll:xll :::;r 11/Jll and llu.11 i= 0 (u., /5 E MEr, and :::;, the intrinsic ordering relation of D,); (vii) llu. ffi Ur 11/Jll(u.,jj E MEr). The remaining basic symbols are characterized as in LPM.

The notion of distributivity introduced above can be extended to class-denoting expressions of any type. Call a ( E MEr1 distributive if it can be true of atoms of type T

only:

(66) DISTR(() ,___. Ax[((x) _r'lt(x)I

Page 15: The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice …users.ox.ac.uk/~sfop0776/LinkPlurals.pdf · (8) The girls hated each other. There a striking similarity between collective

The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms 141

Most of the basic count nouns like child are taken as distributive, similarly IV phrases like die or see. In accordance with what I did above the translation rule T4 involving distributive expressions has to be such that their translations always enter this rule under the star operator. While this seems to me the correct move from a technical point of view lam aware that it carries the empirical prediction that distributivity is a lexical property.

I now give translations for the quantifiers. Let U be the translation relation, and P: = ),y[P(y) /\ !\xlxil)' --+rP(x)]].

a,0p1,some u xlQ(x) /\ P(x)] 2 the u /\. !\x[Q(x) ----:_ xIIy] /\ P(y)J 3 all the u = a*xQ(x)--+ P(y)] 4 every, all u )"QP!\x[Q(x)--+ P(x)l

a applies only to singular count noun phrases and </Jp! to PCN phrases. The quantifiers some and the, with one and the same translation, apply to both singular and plural phrases. As can be seen from 5 through 8 below it is only the incoming CN phrase which differentiates between the appropriate singular and plural readings. While this is obvious with some, a comment on the transformations under 7. is in order. The conjunct !\xlQ(x) --+ xIIyl in the translation of the asserts maximality which is needed for the intended sum formation in the extension of* Q. At the same time, however, it generalizes the usual uniqueness condition for definite descriptions. This comes out when the is applied to a singular count noun like child: The i-part x ofy in 7. cannot be 0, andy is an atom because of DISTR (chzld'); so x equals y. l think this is a nice instance of strict compositionality in times in which this principle has come under heavy fire in view of all sorts of recalcitrant data (see below). Finally, 9-11 show that universal quantification is as in LPM where, again, the difference in meaning between the children and all the children is only partly characterized (P being defined in terms of "T").

5

6 7

8

9 10 11

a child } some child some wMer (some) children the child

the clzlldren

all the chlldren Cl\ery child all water

U PVxlchild'(x) 1\ P(x)]

U PVxlwater'(x) 1\P(x)] U PVxl Cchlld' (x) /\ P(x)J U PVy[child'(v) /\ !\ .r[child'(.r) ____, xIIy] .'\ P(J')]

= PVylchild'(J')!\xlchild'(x)--+ x = y] /\P(J1)] = PVyjy =ix chlld'(x)/\P(J')J

U PVy[Cchlld'(v) 11 !\ xl Cchild'(x)--+ xIIv] /\ P(v)l = PVyly = a*x cltild'(x) /\ P(11)]

C P!\yly = a*xchild'(x)--+ P(v)] U P !\xlchild'(.r) --+ P(x)J U P !\.rlmater' (x) --+ P(.r)l

l may mention here that the incorporation of numerals like one, Imo, three, into the fragment is straightforward. The extension of three men, for instance, is the set of all i-sums in which contain exactly three atoms. Sentences like three men ment to monJ a meadow receive a translation of the form V.:::l(three men)'(z) .l\Q(.:::)].

Page 16: The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice …users.ox.ac.uk/~sfop0776/LinkPlurals.pdf · (8) The girls hated each other. There a striking similarity between collective

142 Godehard Link

The final topic 1 want to say something about is the vexing problem of relative ' clauses with more than one head noun. 17 Call those structures hi1drae. Let me consider restrictive relative clauses only. First of all, there is a rather friendly type of hydra, like the following.

(67) the German or Austrian John met yesterday (68) the cabinet-member and mafioso who was deeply involYed in the scandal

PTQ style relatiYization, i.e. CN modification, takes care of these pets yielding the obvious representations for (67) and (68), respcctiwly:

(67') the ((German or Austrian) such that John met him yesterday) PVy[/\ x [German' tP Austrian'(.\') A ¢L.\'J +--+ .r = y J A P(J') J

(68') the ((Cabinet-member and mafioso) such that he was deeply involved in the scandal PVy[/\ x [Cabinet-member' 0J 11111/ioso'(.\') A 1/t[x] .,__, x = y[ 11P(J1)J

Here,¢ and t/t are the translations of the relative clauses of (67) and (68), respectively; furthermore, (EB IJ A.r[((.r) v 11(.r)J is the Boolean join and ( 1:J 11 Ax[((.\·) I' r1(x)I the Boolean meet of (and 17. This case is simple because CN conjunction does not lead to plural structures, and there is only one determiner present. 18

Next, let us conjoin two singular count nouns to form a plural phrase. Examples arc man and moman, hoy and girl, husband and mifi:, landlord and tena11t. Such phrases can be true of a sum of two individuals one being of the first and the other being of the second kind. An appropriate translation, therefore, is of the form

(69) ((and17) U l::V.\Vy[('(x)1117'(J1)11.:::=x,fiyJ

\Vith this sentences like .John awl Mar)' are hushand and 17'/fe can be handled in a first approximation while the non-symmetric features of this sentence have to be taken care of by other clues. This is because the predicate ( 69), by itself, is necessarily symmetric reflecting the fact that pluralization has the force of group formation which typically gives rise to symmetric constructions. 19 Such is the following CN phrase:

(70) boy and girl who dated each other

With (69), the standard PTQrule yields for this:

(71) A::-.V.rVy[boy'(x)11girl'(J1)11;::: = x y11dated-rncli-othcr'(.:::)J

Now term formation with one and the same determiner for both head nouns is again standard if we decide to have it distributed over the two nouns in a kind of copying process. So, for instance, a boy and a girl n,/w meet becomes

(72) a ((hoy and girl) such that they meet) U PVz[VxVy[boy'(.\·) 11glrl'(v) 11::-.=.reiy11meet'(.::-.)J11 P(.::)]

Page 17: The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice …users.ox.ac.uk/~sfop0776/LinkPlurals.pdf · (8) The girls hated each other. There a striking similarity between collective

The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms 143

In a further step we admit conjunction of plural nouns. This move doesn't really add any new difficulty so I can write down an example immediately. Let() be the trans!Jtion of the phrase students and professors who had met in secret:

(73) 0 -'- l .. h *professor'(y) t.:::. = x y h

Adding a determiner as before, say the definite article, we get the term

(74) the students and the professors who had met in secret U PV:::. = u*xO(r) r. )I

The present conception of conjunction of two CN phrases ( and 17 is such that the extension of ( ( and I]) contains i-sums of objects which are of kind ( and I/, respect-ively. Unlike the Boolean join this carries the presupposition that both sets of objects be non-empty. I think this is as it should be. Notice that in this case the overall sum is the same as the one which is formed in terms of the Boolean join, i.e. we have O".r((' 17 1)(x) = O".r(( and ry)'(r). What is not captured in either approach, however, is the proper pair reading which is dominant in sentences like landlords and te11a11/s Jl'ho hate each other mill a/Jpays find something lo argue about. I find these constructions hard to treat at the moment though I am confident that they will finally lend themselves to an analysis which is compatible with the present framework. \Vhat is needed here is some notion or ordered pair in the object language, apart from the symmetrical sum

20 I . 1 . 1 h id. . 1 . . h . operator. t 1s on y wit l sue an a( 1t10na mstrument, 1t seems to me, t at \ve can, m a close-to-language treatment, attack the most dangerous hydra lurking in the realm of pair reading and branching quantification. 21

The last type of hydra I want to address myself to shows up in a sentence like the following

(75) all of the students and some of the professors who had met m secret were arrested after the coup d'etat.

From a purely syntactic point of view it might look natural to try a T-S-analysis here: first conjoin the t\\o unrelativized terms all the studrnts and some of'tlze professors and then modify the conjunct by the relative clause. Hov.ever, I agree with Janssen (1981) in his sceptical attitude towards the semantical soundness of this approach in general, and the present case, I think, is apt to confirm these doubts. Even a generalized quantifier account along the lines of Barwise and Cooper (1981) is not eaS) to gi\T because the set of properties denoted by the subject term of (75) is not the obvious intersection of two property sets. The point is that the collectiYe predicate 111eet-li1-seaet does not distribute O\er the conjuncts.

Now there is no reason to lea\e the approach taken so far, it seems to me. \Ve already ha\-c a clear understanding of the meaning of the plural CN phrase s111de11ts a/Iii pnd('ssors mlw had met in secret which is expressed by the }-term 0 of (73). So in terms of this, what is the meaning· of the above NP? Well, the set of properties that all the students of the gnmp of students and professors who had met in secret and some of its professors share. This set can be formally represented in TITL'. From the above

Page 18: The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice …users.ox.ac.uk/~sfop0776/LinkPlurals.pdf · (8) The girls hated each other. There a striking similarity between collective

144 Godehard Link

group of individuals we have to pick out again the students and the professors, respectively, which is done by means of the Boolean meet r;); we can then write (with and

(76) all the students and some of the professors who had met in secret U P[!\y[y = <r*x(rx 8)(x) ----+ P(y)] 11Vy[(/l1:18)(v)1\ P(y) 11

In the syntax, then, we have to introduce the determiners all and some simultaneously. 1 hope that a rule to this effect does not look too outlandish to the eye of the syntactieian.

Let me summarize what I consider to be the virtues of the present approach to plurals and mass terms. (1) The logic of plurals and the log·ic of mass terms share a common lattice structure the only difference being that the former leads to an atomic structure while the latter does not. (2) By means of the star operator pluralization and term formation involving· plural constructions can be treated compositionally. (3) Plural terms (the cards) and collective terms (tlze deck of cards) arc equivalent in that they are interchangeable in invariant contexts; this does not make them corcfercntial, however, in contrast to systems of the reductionist lot. ( 4) Collective predication becomes possible in a unified way accounting for the fact that many predicates (e.g. cany) are not marked with respect to distributivity and can, therefore, have mixed extensions.

Notes

The basic i<lea lea<ling to the present approach grew out of a seminar on the semantics of mass terms which I held in the 'um mer of 1980. !vi can while I had the opportunity to <liscuss various stages of the paper with a number of people "horn I wish to thank here for helpful comments, hints, an<l criticisms as well as for general support. Among these I shoul<l like to mention in particular Ulrich Blau, Paul Gochct, Barbara Partee, Christian Rohrer, Peter Stau<lachcr, Arnim v. Stechow, Alice ter 1\'lcukn, 1\latthias Varga v. Kibcd, an<l Dietmar Zacfferer.

Massey's example; see ""fasscy ( 1976). 2 Sec Quine ( 1960, p. 91 ); Dunt ( 1979). J The main source for mass terms is Pelletier ( 1979); furthermore, sec Bennett ( 1980), Dunt ( 1979),

and tcr Meulen (1980, 1981). For the treatment of plurals and collective terms, sec Massey (1976), Burge ( 1977), Blau ( 1979), Hoepelman and Rohrer (1980), .rn<l Scha ( 1981 ). The parallelism referred to is explicitly expressed in Dunt ( 1979).

4 Recrnth, Keenan and 1altz (1978) and Keenan (1981) advanced a "Boolean approach" to the semantic, of natural language. I feel very sympathetic "ith this en tcrprisc which, unfortunately, 1 became aware of only a \Tar ago Oanuary 1981). It is reassuring to sec similar technique» be successfully ,lpplied in other areas of semantics, too. I have to defer a concrete eyaluation of these ideas to another occasion.

5 On this point I agree with tcr Mculen (1981), l think. But I <lo not follm\ her in the conclusions she draws from thi» observation. The inherent lattice structure is indcpen<lcnt of the philosophical motiYes th,lt g;a\'e rise to the construction of mercolog;ical systems. For the rok of nominal mass noun denotations sec the remarks below, also note l l.

6 I guess that in German, \Yi th die Kar/I'll vs. das F:arte11sp1cl, the point might come out more clearly. 7 The point \\as <lpparentlv made first b; Davi<l Kaplan as Bennett ( 1980) reports. 8 This is the situation originally analyzed by Illau in hi» 1979 paper. 9 This is Burg·e's example, sec Burg-c ( 1977).

Page 19: The Logical Analysis of Plurals and Mass Terms: A Lattice …users.ox.ac.uk/~sfop0776/LinkPlurals.pdf · (8) The girls hated each other. There a striking similarity between collective