The Act of Being - Christian Jambet - Preface to the English Edition

9
The Act of Being The Philosophy of Revelation in Mullā Sadrā by Christian Jambet Preface to the English-Language Edition When a philosophical work written by a Westerner attempts to articulate the essential elements of a philosophical system con- structed by an Iranian Shi'ite of the seventeenth century, the potential reader has the right to ask: For what reasons has the author of this book spent so many years reading the works of this man who will always remain a foreigner, whose very face he will never know, and whose beliefs belong to the intellectual universe that came to an end, in the West, with the mathematization of physical space, with the end of political theology, and with the great revolutions that radically modified the image of reason? Rarely does such a question fail to become an objection. After reading The Act of Being, an erudite and attentive friend, who had long before included my first work on Islamic philosophy in the series he was then editing, 1 wrote to me in all honesty that for us today there is not much to learn from my dear Mulla Sadra. Working before the age of modern science, deeply rooted in the soil of metaphysics, subject to the demands of religious revela- tion, Sadra, like all the thinkers of Islam, is merely an object of learned study and of the history of philosophy, a kind of scholarly curiosity or even an antiquated exhibit fit for a museum. This objection is not entirely without merit. I would even like to add a few arguments to it, in order to see whether it is possible to refute it in a serious manner. The first argument against such an undertaking is of a historical 1

Transcript of The Act of Being - Christian Jambet - Preface to the English Edition

Page 1: The Act of Being - Christian Jambet - Preface to the English Edition

The Act of BeingThe Philosophy of Revelation in Mullā Sadrā

by Christian Jambet

Preface to the English-Language Edition

When a philosophical work written by a Westerner attempts to articulate the essential elements of a philosophical system constructed by an Iranian Shi'ite of the seventeenth century, the potential reader has the right to ask: For what reasons has the author of this book spent so many years reading the works of this man who will always remain a foreigner, whose very face he will never know, and whose beliefs belong to the intellectual universe that came to an end, in the West, with the mathematization of physical space, with the end of political theology, and with the great revolutions that radically modified the image of reason?

Rarely does such a question fail to become an objection. After reading The Act of Being, an erudite and attentive friend, who had long before included my first work on Islamic philosophy in the series he was then editing,1 wrote to me in all honesty that for us today there is not much to learn from my dear Mulla Sadra. Working before the age of modern science, deeply rooted in the soil of metaphysics, subject to the demands of religious revelation, Sadra, like all the thinkers of Islam, is merely an object of learned study and of the history of philosophy, a kind of scholarly curiosity or even an antiquated exhibit fit for a museum.

This objection is not entirely without merit. I would even like to add a few arguments to it, in order to see whether it is possible to refute it in a serious manner.

The first argument against such an undertaking is of a historical nature. The interest that Western culture has shown for Islam, for its thinkers, poets, and mystics, has its own history. Roughly speaking, this history has had three major phases since the eighteenth century: first there was the "Oriental Renaissance," as Raymond Schwab has called it.2 Then, in response to the positivism of Ernest Renan, there was the discovery of the great spiritual figures of Islam, as part of a quest aimed at starting a dialogue between the mystics of the three religions of the Book —Judaism, Christianity, and Islam. Finally, today, the intent is no longer to gain self-knowledge in proximity with Islam, but rather to come to know Islam in its foreignness, or even its fundamental hostility toward ourselves. A concern

1

Page 2: The Act of Being - Christian Jambet - Preface to the English Edition

no longer for the same, for similitude, but for the other, for difference, for the absence of any common space. This more recent perspective, which is eager to take up the vocabulary of war ("clash of civilizations," and so on) is the unreflective response to the political emergence of Islam at the present moment of world history.

The first phase can be associated with the names of Goethe and Hegel, the second with those of Louis Massignon, Henry Corbin, Richard Walzer, and Seyyed Nasr. The third phase, our own, is seen as the time of the sociologists and the political scientists. The history of this research would thus show that the period when Orientalism was closely linked with the colonial era, and with that of the emancipation of colonized peoples, has ended. The present is seen as a time involving the reciprocal criminalization of the West and the Islamic East, the hegemony of "revolutionary" doctrines in Islam, and the ruin of all "dialogue" between the peoples of the Book. The major conflicts centered in the Middle East are said to overwhelm a more spiritual Islam, drowning it in blood — a spiritual Islam whose death knell was rung during the Islamic revolution in Iran.

The second argument is closely related to the first. Islam, it is said, is above all a political religion and gives rise essentially to political theologies, such that the only reason to study its ideologues would be to illuminate this politics, identified entirely with the "struggle on the path of faith." The philosophers, mystics, and poets should be placed on the shelf of curiosities because they lack any concrete effectivity and reflect a scholarly culture cut off from the popular masses who make history. This observation is not false. The works of a thinker such as Sadra, like those of Avicenna, al-Farabi, and Ibn Hanbal, remain unknown to the people and are of interest only to scholars. The separation between philosophy, spirituality or Qur'anic studies, and popular culture obviously promotes a religion for simple, ordinary people characterized by a naive adherence to the letter of the Qur'an, to traditional customs, and to the teachings of local preachers, who may be more or less well informed. The simplicity of Wahhabism no doubt partially explains its success, and it promotes the expansion of the Islamist political ideologues. These considerations certainly do little to weaken such an argument.

Let us remark, however, that the culture of religious scholars is more consequential than is often acknowledged. In Iran, and more broadly in the Shi'ite world, the actors on the political stage use the discourse of classical philosophers or theologians, citing it and adapting it for their own purposes. It suffices to recall the example of the Ayatollah Khomeini, or one of his successors. If Khomeini turned his back, in a way, on Mulla Sadra's thought, he nevertheless knew it very well, and his political gesture cannot be explained without taking into account his internal dialogue and his critical relation with the great Iranian mystic and philosopher. You turn your back

2

Page 3: The Act of Being - Christian Jambet - Preface to the English Edition

only on someone who rules over you — and who for that reason influences you in the very gesture of separation.3 In the Sunni world, the rupture between mystical religion and political religion is in itself a major historical fact that only the study of the spiritual philosophy of Islam allows us to illuminate in a satisfactory way.

It therefore seems to me that the doubts and confusions can be dispelled if we examine their presuppositions.

The first objection to there being any present interest in studying the philosophies of Islam emphasizes the irreducible fracture that separates the Western system of thought based on thediscourses of Descartes, Locke, and Kant from the system of thought that finds its completion and fulfillment in seventeenth-century Iran. Islamic metaphysics is said to have only a single virtue, namely that it transmitted Aristotle to the Latin Middle Ages, despite which it subsequently lost itself in the sands of perpetual commentary and sterile repetition. To the extent that Western metaphysics arrives at an end with German Idealism in the nineteenth century, it would be doubly useless to search for any living truth in the books of the Muslim philosophers. If there is any truth, it can only be modern, stripped of metaphysical illusions or else located in the deconstruction of the truths of metaphysics. Only those amateurs of mystical sentiments, who have no ambitions to attain the concept, could find any interest in these "Oriental" thinkers.

An attentive examination quickly undermines such certainties. It is now well established that the flourishing of philosophical thought in Islam did not come to a halt in the thirteenth century. The image, presented by Ernest Renan in his well-known work on Averroes, of a Muslim philosophy disappearing after the immense work of the Andalusian commentator, no longer exerts as unchallenged a seduction today as it used to.4 On the contrary, reasonable scholars will admit that one cannot treat Islamic thinkers after the thirteenth century as if they were simply "mystics" or "spiritual masters" devoted entirely to an inner salvation devoid of any conceptual intelligence. One goal of the present work, among the other purposes it attempts to serve, is to show how a number of discourses, including metaphysics, the exegesis of the Qur'an, the sciences inherited from the Greeks, Sufism, and morality, were progressively constituted into coherent systems. The internal movement of the spirit toward its perfection, in the form of the spiritual worship offered to God, and the work of the concept in no way exclude one another but rather express one another — to the point that this form of knowledge was able to actualize the ontological wealth of the Islamic religion, and that it did so in the work of Mulla Sadra, which I attempt to study here. The interest one may bring to these thinkers is therefore not simply an

3

Page 4: The Act of Being - Christian Jambet - Preface to the English Edition

antiquarian passion. It is a matter of discovering not an old and worn-out artifact but rather what Islam says about being as being. It is also a matter of knowing what Islam says about its own being, its own decision concerning being, in the way it conceives the physical universe, man, destiny, moral obligations, and the relation between concrete existents or intellectual realities and their ultimate foundation. It is a matter of understanding the ontology of Islam in both senses of the expression: the doctrine of being that Islam slowly brought to completion, and that which constitutes the being of Islam itself, its ontological foundation.

The faithful Muslim has little concern for this last question, since he is persuaded, in his faith, that the existence of Islam is the norm, is self-evident, is inscribed in the nature of things willed by God. But the philosopher's mission is to interrogate this ontology of Islam, less to "deconstruct" it than to understand it. This means understanding the ontology of Islam in the thought of the authors of Islam, in their texts, somewhat in the sense in which Michel Foucault considered the work of genealogy or archaeology and in which he spoke of an "ontology of the self."

If we admit this much, then the "political" argument loses its force — and with it the epistemological argument. Studies in political science are too often susceptible to the illusion that it is possible to sever political discourses from the classical metaphysical ones, and then to study them separately, connecting them only to the modern political or religious practices that correspond to them. But this view of things, insufficient in the study of the concepts of Western knowledge, becomes downright absurd when it comes to Islam. In Islam, as in ancient Greece, politics is the discourse on legitimate authority. What kind of authority deserves to be respected? What kind of authority deserves to be the foundation of power? In Islam, the only legitimate authority is that of God, as he is revealed in his books (announced by the prophets), in his "messengers," and in the acknowledged successors of these "messengers" (for example, in Shi'ite Islam, the imams). How could one understand political practices, however shocking or contestable in our eyes, without illuminating them through the exegesis practiced by Muslim authors on the religious revelation of these practices and, consequently, without paying precise attention to the ontology of Islam that is unveiled by the philosophers and theologians, or even by the mystics? It is not in the surface discourse perpetually rehashed by the Muslim jurists that the truth of the political order is best revealed in Islam, but in the works of the philosophers, whether they turn away from politics or attempt to found it. Most often, philosophical and theological syntheses are conscious testimonies to the profound tension that animates Islam, a tension between a temporal vocation and a spiritual vocation that are simultaneously united and opposed.

The choice of an author like Mulla Sadra thus becomes very clear. In order

4

Page 5: The Act of Being - Christian Jambet - Preface to the English Edition

to understand this choice, we must not forget the importance of messianism for the ontology of Islam. Related to the "Servant" whose coming was announced by the prophets of Israel, to the "Suffering Servant" in the Old Testament, and to Jesus, and not without influence from the figure of Mani, who invented the notion of the "seal of prophecy," Muslim spirituality is an intense meditation on the essence, the prerogatives, and the demands of the complete Servant in proximity to his Lord. He is the Perfect Man, and the thinkers of Islam, inspired by the work of Ibn al-'Arabl, focused their thought on the definition of this Perfect Man, on his future coming, and on his silent and active presence in this world and in the other metaphysical worlds. Already, Shfite thought, particularly Isma'llism, had thus proposed a scheme of sacred history, unfolding from its origin in the creation of Adam until the coming of the awaited Resurrector.

The study of such an ontology of history, one of the richest versions of which we are presenting here, is extremely important if we want to move forward in the comparative study of the three messianisms — Jewish, Christian, and Muslim. Such a study reveals a conception of human becoming that includes the exigency of man's divinization, or rather of his fulfilled resemblance to God, who made man in his own image and established him as "caliph of God on earth." The concept of the essential motion of all existents toward that point where the Perfect Man becomes the mirror of the divine names, a concept that we find in Mulla Sadra, remarkably illuminates the dynamic orientation of Islam. Part of what is at stake in such a study is a philosophy of history that renounces the assertion of a supposed "disenchantment of the world," and that renounces any abdication before a supposed "secularization" of historical time, seeing the every day as only a surface phenomenon, beneath which the conflict internal to biblical and Qur'anic messianism carries on its work. Toward what end? Toward what reconciliation? Toward what irreducible alterity? These are the very questions we face today.

The epistemological argument that maintains that these systems of thought are rendered obsolete by modern science or by the ascendancy of modern political thought disregards something that is nonetheless glaringly obvious. It is pointless to say to an entire culture that it is "behind," or that it has not completed the necessary journey to the age of scientific truth. It would be more useful to ask: Why, today, has such a culture, combined in a very complex way with multiple contributions from the West — in technology, economy, and ideology — begun to move, on the historical stage, so decidedly against the grain, and in such a flagrant way? Why is the present historical moment characterized by such a historical initiative?

To answer this by attempting to justify the "modernity" of Islamic science is pointless. To answer by deploring the "perverse" effects of a dead thought or a culture blocked in its development is to proffer a contradiction in

5

Page 6: The Act of Being - Christian Jambet - Preface to the English Edition

terms. How, indeed, could a dead thought have any living effect (contestable or not, that is not the question here) if it is truly dead? What it would be necessary to understand, rather, is the following.

On the one hand, we would need to understand how the philosophy of Islam has a certain living power, from the very fact that it is not foreign to world history, because it is connected to and even interlinked with our own metaphysical destiny, both Greek and biblical. In the past, it already gave life to some of the most enduring categories of our vision of the world. A central example is provided here, when I examine the question of the existence of essence, in an attempt to give what I call the Avicennian moment its full importance.

On the other hand, we would have to ask how, against the background of a common metaphysics, Islam has maintained convictions foreign to those that made possible the development of modern philosophy in the West, as well as the worldviews that derive from these convictions. That is, we would have to ask how it is not a thing of the past but rather lives according to its own rhythm, in a mode of historical life with its own logic, its own time, and its own autonomous finalities.

Such work goes far beyond the ambition of the present study. But it is at least within this perspective that I have written it. I would like to specify my method. My goal here was not primarily that of a historian of Islamic philosophy, although I do believe that I have been faithful to history and its demands. It is as a philosopher that I have attempted to read the philosophers, whether Western or Eastern, who are interrogated here. My only ambition has been to receive as faithfully as possible what Sadra and those associated with him were trying to say, and to render manifest, in the language of a Western philosopher living today, the mode of appearance of being evident for these spirits in their immediate and direct vision. My method strives to be the phenomenology of a becoming, of a metamorphosis of thought, from its Hellenic bases to the Islamic figure of an absolute that is different from the absolute unveiled in Western Christian thought. That is my obvious debt to Hegel, whose teaching still seems indispensable to me, whatever the contestations with which practically all contemporary discourses have assailed it.

Finally, I would like to express my gratitude and admiration for the scrupulous and rigorous work done by Jeff Fort in translating this work into English — for he has done more than translate it; he has given it another life in a fitting and adequate philosophical language (and that is his specific contribution to this text), in all faithfulness to the original French. His work provided the occasion for a number of corrections and specifications, and in that sense, too, it cannot be seen as the passive reconstruction of a book in another language. Any errors or omissions in this book fall to me; the

6

Page 7: The Act of Being - Christian Jambet - Preface to the English Edition

improvements and elucidations, however, owe a great deal to him. And for this I offer him my warmest thanks.

Christian JambetParis, August 2004

Notes

1. Christian Jambet, La logique des Orientaux: Henry Corbin et la science des formes (Paris: Seuil, 1983), published in the series L'Ordre Philosophique, edited by Francois Wahl.2. Raymond Schwab, The Oriental Renaissance: Europe's Rediscovery of India and the East, 1680-1880, trans. Gene Patterson-Black and Victor Reinking (New York: Columbia University Press, 1984). First published in French in 1950, this book deals primarily with the discovery of India, but it also illuminates the appropriation of Persian culture by the philosophers of German Idealism and, more generally, the intellectual opening of Europe to "Oriental" systems of thought.3. On contemporary Shi’ite Islam as the result of a long history in which an essentially mystical religion succumbed to a political interpretation of the question of authority, allow me to refer to a work I recently co-authored: Moham-mad-Ali Amir-Moezzi and Christian Jambet, Qu'est-ce que le shi'isme? (Paris: Fayard, 2004).4. Ernest Renan, Averroes et L'averroisme, 3rd rev. ed. (Paris: Michel Levy Freres, 1866).

7