Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

56
8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1 http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 1/56 1 What Knowledge Management Has Managed to Do to Knowledge 1. Much Ado about Knowledge: Why Now? 2 1.1. Historical Myopia as a Precondition for Knowledge Management 5 1.2. What’s in a Name?: “Knowledge Management” 12 2. Knowledge and Information: The Great Bait and Switch 16 3. The Scientist: KM’s Enemy Number One? 20 1

Transcript of Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

Page 1: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 1/56

1

What

KnowledgeManagement

Has Managedto Do toKnowledge

1. Much Ado about Knowledge: Why Now? 21.1. Historical Myopia as a Precondition for Knowledge

Management 51.2. What’s in a Name?: “Knowledge Management” 12

2. Knowledge and Information: The Great Bait and Switch 163. The Scientist: KM’s Enemy Number One? 20

1

Page 2: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 2/56

4. The KM Challenge to Knowledge in Theory and Practice 234.1. KM and the End of Knowledge in Theory: The

Deconstruction of Public Goods 23

4.2. KM and the End of Knowledge in Practice: TheDisintegration of the University 30

5. Back to Basics: Rediscovering the Value of Knowledge inRent, Wage, Profit 36

6. The Epistemic Empire Strikes Back: Metapublic Goods andthe Injection of Academic Values into Corporate Enterprise 44

7. Squaring the KM Circle: Who’s Afraid of Accelerating theProduction of New Knowledge? 49

1. Much Ado about Knowledge: Why Now?

“Knowledge management,” “knowledge society,” and not least theburgeoning employment prospects of “chief knowledge officers”(“CKOs”) are signs of our times. To the naïve observer, it is perfectlyobvious that knowledge has always played an important role in theorganization and advancement of society. In that sense, saying thatwe live in a “knowledge society” would seem to be no more infor-mative than saying that we live in a “power society” or a “moneysociety” or a “culture society.” But perhaps “knowledge” here isreally an instance of what rhetoricians call catachresis, i.e., the strate-gic misuse of words, a euphemism for something a bit unsavory. Afterall, that knowledge would need to be literally “managed” suggeststhat its growth should not be left in a wild state: at best it remainsunused and at worst it is wasted. Yet, this managerial mindset goesagainst the grain of the last 2500 years of Western thought, which

has valued the pursuit of knowledge “for its own sake,” regardlessof its costs and benefits.

People who claim to know something about KM must decidewhether the field is more about knowledge or management . The darksecret of this field is that its name is an oxymoron, for as soon asbusiness enters the picture, the interests of knowledge and manage-ment trade off against each other. After all, why spend valuableresources generating new knowledge, if one can simply try to do what

one has always done, only more efficiently? To be sure, rising to thelevel of efficiency demanded of the market can take different forms.It may take the Taylorist route of increasing the level of surveillanceon one’s own workers, so that more of the fruits of their labors are

2 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 3: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 3/56

reaped by their corporate employers. Alternatively, it may involveacquiring a better understanding of the market itself. In short: Whatdo consumers want? Who, if anyone, is currently providing it? Or,

more ambitiously: What can consumers be made to want?It is only in response to these questions that knowledge is of inter-

est to management. In that respect, “knowledge management” is littlemore than talk about ordinary management in a world that hasbecome a little too complex for traditional managers to handle.However, complexity is primarily a mathematical feature of reality,referring to an increase in the number of dimensions that need to betaken into account. We can acknowledge that our world has become

more complex without necessarily concluding that it demands a qual-itatively different mode of analysis. Managers who remain skepticalof the value of investing in people and machines designed to providesomething called “knowledge management” figured this out a longtime ago.

We are used to thinking that knowledge is produced by hard workthat is never fully rewarded, the fruits of which are neverthelessdistributed as widely as possible. For economists, this is what dis-tinguishes knowledge as a public good . However, from a KM stand-point, it is not a very economic scenario. It would be better for thereverse to occur. Effort toward innovation would then be discour-aged except where profits are likely to follow. This would license, onthe one hand, the redundancy of research staff and, on the other, theacquisition of intellectual property rights. In both cases, capturingknowledge takes precedence over cultivating it.

Generally speaking, the competitive advantage likely to be gainedfrom the introduction of a new product largely depends on one’s

ability to create a demand for it, which usually has more to do withan ability to second-guess consumers than anything truly revolu-tionary in the product itself. Thus, relatively small innovations canend up making major profits for big companies, while truly radicalinnovations can be easily captured or ignored. And if the fate of non-petroleum-fueled cars is any indication, some innovations may evenbe captured in order to be ignored.

These features of the Realpolitik of KM acquire a special poi-

gnancy in the country from which I write, the United Kingdom. Itbegins to explain why the recent surge in the number of British sci-entific publications and patents has failed to enhance our nationalcompetitiveness in global markets. Even if there is some truth to the

What Knowledge Management Has Managed to Do to Knowledge 3

Page 4: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 4/56

widespread view that scientists and businesspeople do not commu-nicate with each other very well, a deeper problem is that business-people regard the need for new knowledge as the moral equivalent

of a necessary evil: the more necessary, the more evil. Economistsoften fail to recognize this point because of the rather patronizingattitude towards business that is enshrined in their “constrained opti-mization” model of rational action. In this model, the average cor-porate executive appears as a harried and impatient person—a“bounded rational” agent, in Herbert Simon’s terms—who muststrike a balance between doing what is best in the short and longterms (Fuller 1985). This may involve curtailing the work of the

Research and Development (“R&D”) division. However, had thecorporation a limitless supply of time and resources, it would(allegedly) increase its R&D investments and eventually reap the cor-responding benefits, since new knowledge is presumed to be the royalroad to an increased market share.

The rise of knowledge management reveals that “the average cor-porate executive” does not think like this at all. Indicative is thedifference in the biological imagery to which the economist and theKM specialist typically appeal. Economists regard new knowledgeas spontaneously generated, much like a mutation that eventuallybecomes the basis for a new species. Despite their pessimism aboutthe prospects for controlling the growth of knowledge, economistsare generally optimistic that such uncontrolled growth will ultimatelyresult in overall good. In contrast, knowledge managers regard theuncontrollable character of knowledge growth as itself a problem.Where economists imagine a proliferation of new variations andspecies, knowledge managers see only potential weeds that crowd out

the effort needed to maximize profitability. Where economists see“factors of production” in the staff and equipment of the averageknowledge-intensive firm, knowledge managers see “conspicuousconsumption,” the cost-effectiveness of which is presumed dubious,unless proven otherwise.

Difference in historical perspective plays an important role here.Economists’ views of knowledge remain anchored in the IndustrialRevolution of the late 18th and early 19th century, when capitalized

innovation did indeed result in a general expansion of markets andincrease in wealth—at least in the Europeanized world. However,KM is anchored in the “information explosion” of the late 20th andearly 21st century, in which corporations are struggling to cope with

4 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 5: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 5/56

overflowing databases, the care of which has been left to a highlyskilled but mobile labor force.

But knowledge management is equally about academics whose

employment prospects have been improved since the 1980s bymoving from the arts and sciences faculties to the business schools.This move reflected the global success of capitalism (a.k.a. USA) oversocialism (a.k.a. USSR) that marked the end of the Cold War. Hereit is worth recalling that, generally speaking, the expansion of thearts and sciences faculties in universities in the 19th and 20th cen-turies had been nation-building exercises motivated by the prospectof citizen mobilization in time of war. The humanities provided

instruction in the values that needed to be upheld; the social sciencestaught the relevant mechanisms of social control; and the natural sci-ences contributed to the consolidation and upgrading of the nation’sinfrastructure and defense system. However, in times of peace, thesedisciplines potentially created obstacles to commerce by reifying dif-ferences that could be otherwise negotiated away in the free exchangeof goods and services. Thus, from a strictly capitalistic standpoint,language differences between trading partners are not indicative of vast cultural chasms that require many years of experience—oradvanced academic degrees—to fathom. Rather, they provide oppor-tunities to construct more efficient forms of communication, whatlinguists call “pidgins,” that circumvent the need for all this learn-ing. KM continues this “if it’s good for academia, it’s bad for busi-ness” mentality—only now within academia itself.

These observations about the origins of knowledge managementare complicated by a couple of factors. The first pertains to the field’shistorical myopia, the second to the arbitrariness of the field’s name.

1.1. Historical Myopia as a Precondition forKnowledge Management

Even those academics who in the 1980s were driven by “marketconditions” into business schools were taken by surprise by the incur-sion of capitalist values into their own workplaces. I refer here notonly to the increased need for “external” (i.e., non-university) sources

of income to validate a “demand” for one’s research, but also the useof production and consumption metrics to judge research quality—that is, the number of papers and/or patents produced and the fre-quency with which they are cited. However, academics have tended

What Knowledge Management Has Managed to Do to Knowledge 5

Page 6: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 6/56

to interpret this situation as heralding the emergence of a newpost-industrial order, the knowledge society (Stehr 1994), in which“knowledge” is the new “capital” and “knowledge management” the

science of this revolutionary order. Seen through these rose-tintedspectacles, knowledge now matters to business in ways it never hasbefore.

Unfortunately, this vision is persuasive only to those with a shorthistorical memory. Ever since Joseph Schumpeter (1961) introducedthe “entrepreneur” as the lifeblood of capitalism in 1912, there hasbeen a general appreciation of the centrality of new knowledge—a.k.a. “innovation”—to capital accumulation. However, the

legendary entrepreneur championed by Schumpeter was not anacademic specialist but a “self-made man” whose confidence wasmatched only by his determination. The entrepreneur was moreEdison than Einstein: a master of induction, not deduction. (In fact,Schumpeter’s favorite example was Henry Ford, who, unlike Edison,managed to incorporate his innovations into a sustained profit-making institution.) But nowadays everyone is more educated. Thegreat entrepreneur of our times, Bill Gates, was a Harvard dropout,not a semiliterate journeyman. And, of course, the people who workfor Bill Gates have at least a bachelor’s degree. Given this shrinkagein social distance between academia and industry, it is easy for aca-demics to imagine that business has (finally!) come to realize the valueof knowledge to enterprise. This explains the rather sanguine outlookof most of the popular and academic KM literature.

As the reader will have already gathered, my attitude is more skep-tical. A concept that informs my skepticism and plays an importantexplanatory role in the pages that follow is the  positional good 

(Hirsch 1977). KM’s most lasting contribution to our understandingof the nature of knowledge may be its practical demonstration that,other things being equal (i.e., no special effort to institutionalizeknowledge as a public good), knowledge is naturally a positionalgood: Its value is directly tied to its scarcity, such that the more peoplewho possess it, the less valuable it is. This begins to explain the easewith which management gurus have established themselves as theo-rists and vendors of “intellectual capital” (Stewart 1997). Indeed, the

so-called KM revolution is best understood as the extension of fairlyconventional management principles to a more demanding class of producers and consumers. What makes them so demanding? I shallfocus mainly on how knowledge workers differ from manual labor-

6 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 7: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 7/56

Page 8: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 8/56

sense of having little control over how their products are used. Butthis is a price knowledge workers are often quite happy to pay forretaining control over the actual conduct of their work. Here man-

agement has learned a valuable lesson from the U.S. atomic bombproject, which combined exceptionally high funding for very talentedpeople with low day-to-day accountability of their activities. In theend, the goods were delivered. The lesson runs deeper. When man-agers interfere with the conduct of knowledge work, knowledgeworkers have the ability to bite back and interfere with managerialwork. Indeed, most scientist-led calls for greater public accountabil-ity have been motivated by the perception of state interference with

the conduct of their own work (e.g., surveillance, coercion), whichthen spills over into more inclusive concerns about the infringementof civil rights. The managerial solution to this problem is capturedin the U.S. poet Robert Frost’s memorable line: “Good fences makegood neighbors.” In KM lore, Frost’s principle surfaces in the needfor management to provide a friendly “self-organizing” environmentthat enables knowledge workers to report when they feel ready. (Cor-respondingly, managers should prepare to cut their losses if the reportis not satisfactory.) Knowledge workers are themselves portrayedas psychologically more complex than manual laborers, sportingpowers of “reflexivity” lacking in more primitive employees. This iscode for the fact that knowledge workers are relatively detached fromcorporate goals, yet capable of preventing those goals from beingrealized.

In this context, the Taylorist “scientific manager” brandishingstopwatch and clipboard does not produce the best results. Instead,management must resort to less obtrusive means, especially the em-

ployment of ethnographers whose status is not higher but equalto or, better still, lower than that of the knowledge workers theyobserve and report back on. The presumption here is that knowledgeworkers—and, to a certain extent, consumers—operate in ways thatare mysteriously superior to those of management. Fathoming theseways would (presumably) lead to increased profit margins. At thevery least, the resort to subtle means shows that managers are justas alienated from their workers as vice versa. Such double alienation

is necessary for KM to acquire its luminous status. Of course, thisstate of affairs may simply reflect that managers now employ workersand serve customers more sophisticated than they are. It wouldnot be the first time in the history of capitalism that a “knowledge

8 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 9: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 9/56

gap” has emerged. The very fact that businesspeople, traditionallynot known for their literary interests, have turned many self-helpmanagement books into bestsellers suggests that they do not quite

believe that native wit and practical experience are sufficient to seethem through the next shareholders’ meeting. Indeed, the mass-mar-keted self-help management book was born of the 1929 New Yorkstock market crash, when it became blatantly obvious that “produc-ers” were a class divided against itself. In Marxist terms, the ownersof the means of production—the shareholders—suddenly realizedthat they did not know how their agents—the managers—were han-dling their investments.

The first modern management guru, Peter Drucker, emerged fromthis traumatic episode and has successfully exploited its potentialrecurrence for the better part of a century. Drucker’s own innovationwas to anticipate that the gap between knowledge workers and theirmanagers would come to resemble the original one between man-agers and owners that led to the 1929 crash: a case of the same shoenow being on the other foot. However, Drucker never lost sight of the fact that knowledge workers are still workers. Thus, his long-standing dislike of both academia and middle management can beeasily understood as part of a strategy to ensure that knowledgeworkers remain relatively atomized and hence more easily shaped tothe will of corporate policymakers. On the one hand, universitiestend to undermine the loyalty of knowledge workers, much likeguilds and unions, by promoting performance standards (a.k.a.“validity” and “reliability”) that increase the costs of knowledgework in ways that their corporate employers would prefer to avoid(e.g., the purchase of state-of-the-art equipment, longer and more

elaborate experimental trials). On the other, the presence of inter-mediate corporate levels tends to hybridize the role of manager andknowledge worker, which in turn threatens to take corporate policy“off message,” as managers come to think more like knowledgeworkers. Better, then, to leave knowledge workers formally detachedfrom the management structure, while encouraged to communicatetheir findings and concerns to managers in a relatively unmediatedfashion. In that case, managers can be assured of having a clear view

of corporate interests when dealing with these communications(Drucker 1988).

This “management at a distance” approach is often portrayedas indicative of the respect that management accords knowledge

What Knowledge Management Has Managed to Do to Knowledge 9

Page 10: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 10/56

workers, as opposed to the more “hands-on” approach applied toeven skilled manual laborers. However, this impression needs to betempered by another implication of the distancing move, namely, that

the KM literature tends to treat knowledge workers as if they wereconveyors of precious metals that management then needs to extractfrom their less than precious bodies, especially through the arts of knowledge engineering  and the design of customized computersknown as expert systems. In terms of the factors of production,knowledge workers appear more as raw materials than labor.

Arguably this move is a step in the direction of dehumanization,but interestingly it tends not to be perceived this way—perhaps

because knowledge workers identify more with the specific (cerebral)character of their work than with the very fact that it is work. In anycase, KM is peppered with metaphors from chemistry that regard thefact that knowledge workers “know more than they say” as “ore”that comes to be “purified” once knowledge engineers articulate andextend it (Nonaka 1991). The ethnographers involved in knowledgeengineering tend to be enthusiastic about this cycle of cognitiveextraction, purification, and synthesis for reasons unrelated to theoverall corporate strategy in which their work fits. Ethnographers areusually hired to help render knowledge workers more accountable oreven redundant, but they themselves are fascinated by the opportu-nity to fathom knowledge workers as a subculture whose practiceselude the larger corporate culture. This curious symbiosis betweenethnographers and managers is central to the trumpeted success of Xerox PARC as a long-term exercise in knowledge management(Brown 1991).

The alchemy of knowledge management, then, lies in the ability

to combine people of rather complex and often opposing motives todeliver the traditional goods of management, namely, higher profitmargins. As I have been suggesting, the overall thrust of empiricalKM research is toward increasing the manipulability and disposabil-ity of knowledge workers. We shall return to this theme in moredetail in Chapter 3, as we examine information technology as KM’srevolutionary principle. However, some influential KM research cutsagainst this general tendency. I refer here to a body of work ema-

nating from the Harvard–MIT axis in Cambridge, Massachusetts,spearheaded by Chris Argyris and Donald Schon, and updated andpopularized by Peter Senge (Argyris 1957, Argyris and Schon 1978,Senge 1990). This work, associated with the concept of “organiza-

10 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 11: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 11/56

tional learning,” stresses the need for melding managerial and workerperspectives into a common mindset. Here knowledge workers ap-pear intellectually open (and hence accountable) only to each other

but not to managers or clients. In this context, KM becomes an exer-cise in encouraging these captive elites to extend their ethic of open-ness to the larger business community, during which the knowledgeworker’s perspective would (one hopes) come into alignment withmanagement’s (Argyris 1991). I shall not formally address this strandof the KM literature because Drucker, in his Machiavellian way, maybe right that the long-term interests of business are not really servedby having knowledge workers think more like managers. Neverthe-

less, I strongly endorse the general point that the ethic of opennessneeds to be distributed more widely. I shall develop this point inChapter 4 under the rubric of a civic republican approach to knowl-edge management.

Finally, knowledge workers are not the only complicated beings inthe KM universe. So, too, are knowledge consumers. Nevertheless,knowledge managers have tried to stick close to Drucker’s (1954)maxim: “There is only one valid definition of business purpose: tocreate a customer.” Admittedly, the “hidden persuaders” of the largeadvertising agencies can no longer so easily induce consumer demandfrom their skyscraper offices on Madison Avenue (cf. Galbraith 1967).But this fact is far from mysterious. If it is possible to deconstructmagic after repeated exposure to a trick, why should not a similar cog-nitive awareness emerge in the case of commercial advertising? Thus,in our “post-Fordist” world of “flexible capitalism,” mass marketinghas yielded to more customized forms of hidden persuasion andsubliminal seduction that address various levels of consumer sophis-

tication. Alongside the usual bombardment of mass media are invita-tions to more “participatory” and “user-centered” forms of productdesign—usually in relation to new information technology—thatappeal precisely to those consumers who regard themselves as sophis-ticated (cf. Greenbaum and Kyng 1991). Once again, ethnographersturn out to function well as facilitators, since by fixating on the localvictories that discerning users score over arrogant software designers,they ignore the more systemic power relations between producers and

consumers that remain largely untouched. The thin line dividing par-ticipation from cooptation is thus missed.

A reality check here is Karl Polanyi’s (1944) version of marketsocialism, which called for “consumer collectives” to tie market

What Knowledge Management Has Managed to Do to Knowledge 11

Page 12: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 12/56

prices to values that can be realized only by virtue of being partof a community (e.g., a religion or social movement). In that case,consumers do not face producers as atomized individuals but as

members of an organized group with sufficient market leverage tonegotiate the terms on which new products are introduced. Anyonewho has witnessed the ventriloquism that passes for market re-search in focus groups will realize how far we currently are fromPolanyi’s ideal.

1.2. What’s in a Name?: “Knowledge Management”

Strictly speaking, the mass academic exodus to the businessschools occurred in anticipation that capitalism would triumph oversocialism. The turn to KM began in the early 1980s, just as RonaldReagan and Margaret Thatcher adopted the final hard-line Westernstance that coincided with the internal collapse of the Soviet regime.I say “coincidence” deliberately, since it is superstitious to think thatthe politically conservative and economically liberal ideology associ-ated with Reagan and Thatcher had much to do with—or, moreimportantly, is vindicated by—the fall of the Soviet Union. Had theDemocrats prevailed in Washington and Labour in London duringthis period, Moscow would have probably suffered the same fate.But then we would have traced the Soviet demise to its failure toprovide adequate welfare for its population, not its repression of thefree exchange of information. In that case, we would have called thefield under investigation in this book “welfare management” ratherthan “knowledge management.”

Indeed, the welfare and knowledge management perspectives were

born joined at the hip in the 18th century European Enlightenment.During this period, political theorists began to argue that there wasa more integral connection between a state and its inhabitants thanprevious theorists had thought: A ruler should not simply keep thepeace; s/he also had to provide for their welfare (Manicas 1986, 26ff).Statecraft thus had to go beyond the usual threats and deceptions,since rulers were now expected, as Adam Smith would say, to increasethe wealth of their nations. This historic change of attitude had three

important consequences. First, it led to a managerial conception of the state, in which economic matters acquired a public significancethat had been previously left in the hands of private households and

12 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 13: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 13/56

corporations. Second, it fostered a more discriminating sense ofcitizenship as “contribution to society,” especially for purposes of raising and distributing revenue. Finally, it led to the systematic col-

lection of data about people’s lives, culminating in a hardening of social categories (into classes and even races), which were then pro-jected backward as having been implicit throughout history.

The defining moments in the state’s reconstitution as welfaremanager were the American and French Revolutions in the finalquarter of the 18th century. Both were instigated by middle-class tax-payers incensed by the state’s fiscal mismanagement. The generationfollowing these revolutions witnessed the emergence of the original

knowledge management gurus, Henri de Saint Simon and AugusteComte, who designed schemes to harness innovations in science andtechnology to the state’s newly acquired welfare functions. To besure, these functions were seen as directly benefiting the middle classand only indirectly those below them. Nevertheless, the legacy of these gurus remains in the continuing ideological resonance of theircoinages, “socialism” and “positivism.” Perhaps of even deeper sig-nificance has been that representation of data known as “statistics,”a slightly shortened version of “state-istics.” Not surprisingly, amongsocial scientists, there has been a strong positive correlation betweenfaith in the state’s powers and reliance on statistical data as “indica-tors” of larger socioeconomic tendencies. Thus, those skeptical of theauthority of statistics, such as followers of the liberal political econ-omist Friedrich von Hayek (1952), have wanted to draw a sharp dis-tinction between “knowledge” and “information.” Knowledge is aproperty of individual minds that largely reflects their unique cir-cumstances, whereas the information provided by statistics is at best

a crude summary of the subjective states of knowers that cannot bereliably used to base large-scale social policy. (We shall see in the nextsection that KM has tended to undo this distinction.)

As it happens, the expression “knowledge society” also has a dualorigin in welfare and knowledge management, but this time in thesecond half of the 20th century. It is normally traced to two ratherdifferent social thinkers who nevertheless are also credited withhaving first identified the “postmodern” condition: Daniel Bell

(1973) and Jean-Francois Lyotard (1983). Bell’s image of “intellec-tual technologies” enabling an increasingly observant administrativestate to curb the excesses of advanced capitalism was clearly

What Knowledge Management Has Managed to Do to Knowledge 13

Page 14: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 14/56

grounded in Keynesian economics and the subsequent growth of what the sociologist Alvin Gouldner (1970) memorably called the“welfare–warfare state” of the Cold War era. Bell’s “intelligent

system” was a top-down processor, be it the central government ora computational model of the mind. Whatever else one might sayabout Bell’s vision of “post-industrial society,” it was designed inlarge part to “rationalize” or “contain” the effects of capitalism, sothat it produced a sufficient level of prosperity without destabilizingthe balance of power between and within nations.

However, the end of the Cold War has yielded a new vision of theknowledge society. From this more Lyotardian standpoint, Bell is a

bit of an embarrassment. What he regarded as signs of intelligent lifein the social system are now seen as misguided acts of will to disruptknowledge’s naturally fragmented and fluctuating state. Indeed, thedominant image of this revised knowledge society is that of themarket, a parallel distributing processing unit, to quote the corre-sponding model of brain. Computers are themselves envisioned asmany personal terminals connected together in a network rather thanall to one mainframe generator. Even computer languages are nowvalued less for their algorithmic powers than for the conceptualspaces left open by their “incompleteness” and “undecidability,”which, in turn, demand the “interactivity” of the user. Not surpris-ingly, then, Hayek (1948), as Keynes’s main opponent, was amongthe very first to have interrelated the political, economic, and psy-chological aspects of this new “self-organizing” image of the knowl-edge society.

The historical trajectory of the knowledge society is not quiteso simple as a reversion from central planning to devolved control.

Otherwise, something called “knowledge management” would neverhave come to be all the rage. Here we do well to distinguish threeways of characterizing social knowledge (or labor, for that matter),which together are indebted to Hayek (1948, 83–6), that earlydevotee of Hayek, the phenomenologist Alfred Schutz (1964, Pren-dergast 1986), and Hayek’s colleague Fritz Machlup (1984, 186–9):(i) dispersed ; (ii) distributed ; (iii) divided . The list proceeds in orderof knowledge’s increasing role in stabilizing society.

(i) Lyotard’s image of the knowledge society comes closest to aknowledge dispersion, in which a competitive labor marketreduces “skill” to scarce locally relevant knowledge, the value

14 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 15: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 15/56

of which may be expected to change (and may even be con-verted to non-human capital) according to market conditions.Thus, your knowledge is most valuable if it complements that

of others in your immediate situation, thereby enabling all of you to collaborate in activities that will benefit each of youdifferently. This is what Castells (1996) has dubbed our“network society.”

(ii) Socially distributed knowledge implies somewhat less flexi-bility, as the spatio-temporally situated character of knowl-edge reinforces a common cultural identity among peoplelocated together that resists attempts at standardization,

homogenization, and globalization.(iii) In this scheme, the division of labor appears, contrary to itsclassical sociological image as the vanguard of modernization,as a strategy designed to arrest the natural flow of knowledgeby locking people into fixed status positions (a.k.a. “classes”).Only now the capitalist factory replaces the feudal estateas the model of the well-ordered society. “Disciplines” and“professions” have traditionally enforced a division of laboramong knowledge workers. The recent extension of intellec-tual property legislation may represent an ironic step “backto the future,” whereby many of the feudal elements of socialdivisionism receive a new lease on life.

In this context, it is significant that the first modern managementguru, Peter Drucker, was a younger contemporary of Hayek, Schutz,and Machlup. Like them he studied political economy with Ludwigvon Mises at the University of Vienna in the interwar years. Mises

was the center of one of the two main “Vienna Circles” that flour-ished in the 1920s. Like the more famous circle that included LudwigWittgenstein, this one was also concerned with laying micro-foundations for science. But their focus was the social, as opposedto the natural, sciences. Where Wittgenstein’s group looked to sym-bolic logic, Mises’ looked to situated experience. Moreover, whereasWittgenstein’s group was locally known as the “Red Vienna Circle”because of the known socialist commitments of its leading members,

Rudolf Carnap and Otto Neurath (though not Wittgenstein himself),Mises’ group had a decidedly bluer complexion, broadly committedto the liberalism of classical political economy. In particular, theywere highly critical of Weimar Germany’s tendency to reduce democ-

What Knowledge Management Has Managed to Do to Knowledge 15

Page 16: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 16/56

ratization to mass mobilization, which in turn imputed a spuriouscognitive superiority to organized groups over situated individuals(cf. Cartwright et al. 1996; Peukert 1993, Chapter 8).

2. Knowledge and Information:The Great Bait and Switch

“Knowledge” and “information” have virtually had to reversemeanings to arrive at knowledge management’s baseline assump-tions. This transformation has removed much of the contemplativeand even ethereal quality of classical philosophical conceptions of 

knowledge, thereby contributing to the incisive and critical spiritof knowledge managers. But at the same time, it has introduced acoarseness into the handling of its putative object, knowledge, oftenby reducing it to information. This should raise the alarm for thoseinterested in the future of organized inquiry.

In the Middle Ages, “information” was, as the original Latin sug-gests, the process by which forms were transferred (or “communi-cated”) from one material thing to another. Things were thus“informed” in the course of acquiring distinct identities. The imagegoes back to Plato’s creative deity who functioned as the “UltimateInformant.” A secular version of this vision survives in the idea that“genetic information” is copied in the course of reproducing thespecies. As for “knowledge,” it was the mind’s representation of thisprocess, which was usually understood in relatively passive terms.Knowledge was the result of the mind’s receptiveness to what liesoutside it. The type of discipline needed to acquire knowledge wasthe removal of obstacles to reception, including false ideas and prej-

udices. It is a discipline most familiar today from the contemplativephilosophies of the Orient (which is now thought to have been asource of Plato’s own thought). Yet, it continued to capture theWestern imagination well into the modern period. The founder of modern rationalism, Rene Descartes, underwent this discipline toarrive at what he took to be the foundations of knowledge, “Cogitoergo sum” (“I think, therefore I am”). Even modern empiricism—which is normally seen as counterposing experience and contempla-

tion—has treated valid ideas as the product of robust impressions lefton the mind, which again implies that knowers are glorified recep-tacles, or mere “buckets,” as Karl Popper (1972) said in disdain.

16 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 17: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 17/56

Page 18: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 18/56

enemy aircraft on a radar screen. “Knowledge” is defined comple-mentarily as the background mentality that enables the strategist toact decisively upon this information.

Economists are familiar with the stripped-down definition of infor-mation as whatever an agent needs to determine her market strategy(cf. Schiller 1988). It can be understood in terms of what an agentneeds either (i) to consume or (ii) to  produce before deciding on acourse of action.

(i) As an act of consumption, the search for information takesresources that are then no longer available for pursuing the

chosen course of action. This is Herbert Simon’s (1981)problem of bounded rationality, and it is perhaps here that thedifference between the epistemologist and the economist ismost apparent. The main reason that the epistemologiststresses quality control in the search process is that she pre-sumes that a more methodical search will lead to knowledgethat will enable the agent to perform better. In contrast, theeconomist presumes no such neat link between the quality of information and the quality of action—and hence she does notmake the quality of the agent’s search her overriding concern(Fuller 1993a, 198ff).

(ii) As an act of  production, the search for information involvesthe construction of mediating instruments—so-called infor-mation and communication technologies—that enable notonly the current agent to achieve the current goal, but alsoother agents to achieve related goals. The idea here is that,short of perfect information about each other’s moves, if 

agents try to pursue their goals directly, they will probablyinterfere with each other’s efforts, which render them less effi-cient than had they first pursued a common goal—a reliablemedium for the exchange of information—and then pursuetheir own respective personal goals. On this view, the searchfor knowledge emerges in much the same way as the institu-tion of money, a point first explored in detail by the Germansociologist Georg Simmel (1978, Chapter 6), a point to which

I shall return in Chapter 2.

From a philosophical standpoint, this conflation of knowledge andinformation is unabashedly “relativist,” in the sense that there is no

18 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 19: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 19/56

standard of validity beyond the context that calls for knowledge.Thus, knowledge is whatever enables an agent to choose betweenvarious ways of investing her efforts, assuming the optimal use of 

resources. The thoroughness of the agent’s search and the reliabilityof her findings are not questioned. Whereas an epistemologist wouldadvise the agent to hold off from any decision until “all the evidenceis in,” the knowledge manager would steer the agent away fromregarding the search process as an end in itself, recalling that theagent is motivated to acquire knowledge only in order to eliminateundesirable courses of action. After all, the search itself involves con-suming the same resources—time, money, effort—that the agent will

subsequently need for other purposes. Once the agent learns enoughto eliminate all but one option, the search is complete (cf. Stigler1961). Still harboring philosophical scruples, economists prefer tocall this “difference that makes the difference” for action “informa-tion” rather than “knowledge.” But from a KM standpoint, name-calling is less important than figuring out how to lower the cost of future searches.

This equation of knowledge and information brushes aside severalquestions: Must the agent be able to expressly recognize the infor-mation as a piece of knowledge, say, by articulating it as part of atheory? Is it even necessary that the agent embody the informationin her proper person, as opposed to, say, in some other agent ormachine at the agent’s disposal? These questions define a sphere of inquiry that cuts across economics, political science, and psychology.It is bounded by, on the one hand, the “principal-agent theory”(Guston 2000, Chapter1) and, on the other, the creation of “smartenvironments” from “offloaded” intelligence (Norman 1993). In

short, whenever expedient, the efficient agent lets someone or some-thing else do one’s own thinking. That “something else” may eventurn out to be the law.

Generally speaking, the very buying and selling of goods imposeadditional costs that are normally transferred to the price the goodscan fetch at market. These are transaction costs (Lepage 1987, apopular extension of the pioneering work of Ronald Coase in thisarea). Thus, an elaborate legal system develops to regularly redis-

tribute the costs and benefits of the market’s activities. It covers,among other things, maintenance of the trading site, advertisementof the market’s existence and contents, and even quality assurance of the goods traded. The point is to render the market predictable, so

What Knowledge Management Has Managed to Do to Knowledge 19

Page 20: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 20/56

that agents are encouraged to return and expand their trading inter-ests. For example, modest payment for a trading permit may relievethe trader of the burden of having to check the quality of the goods

for himself. Economists often refer to this as the “internalization of externalities,” a process which, according to Douglass North, wasmore important for the rise of capitalism in the West than the mereincrease in productive capacities (North and Thomas 1973, De Soto2000). As we shall see in Chapter 2, perhaps the most important partof this elaborated legal system is intellectual property law, whichimposes, in the name of an inventor or author, a regulated fee onthose interested in building on her innovation for purposes of devel-

oping their own products. The stability and growth characteristicof modern capitalist economies arguably stem from the delicatebalance of incentive and reward fostered by intellectual property law.

3. The Scientist: KM’s Enemy Number One?

The contrast in the action orientation of experimental scientistsand knowledge managers should alert us to the unholy alliancelurking behind any corporation’s R&D division, regardless of theresources and freedom lavished upon its employees. Scientists regardknowledge as an end in itself, whereas managers regard it as a meanstoward market-driven ends. Thus, absent some striking discovery orinvention that quickly enables a corporation to improve its marketshare, scientists and managers often find themselves at loggerheads.Indeed, a minor scandal of knowledge management is that corpora-tions routinely flourish—even today—without spending much onR&D. From a managerial standpoint, scientists want to waste endless

time and space searching for the ultimate truth, whereas from a sci-entific standpoint, managers want something that will work just longenough to make a killing in the market. Of course, each side hasdemonized the other’s utopia perfectly, but luckily ours is a world of negotiated settlements. Scientists have been known to persuade man-agers (who have not been already persuaded by the KM literature!)that robust investment in research is an insurance policy against theeffects of long-term market competition.

To appreciate the awkward status of scientists in the KM univ-erse, it is worth recalling how “scientist” came to denote someoneprofessionally engaged in the systematic pursuit of knowledge,a.k.a. “science.” When William Whewell introduced “scientist” into

20 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 21: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 21/56

English in the 1830s, he had to overcome the time-honored objec-tion enshrined in the first line of Aristotle’s Metaphysics that knowl-edge is something anyone with sufficient leisure at his or her disposal

can—indeed, should—pursue. The suggestion that salaried special-ists are uniquely entitled to the mantle of science was initially receivedwith as much skepticism as the idea that only professional athleteshave a serious interest in physical fitness. As it happens, Whewell,Master of Trinity College Cambridge, was partly reacting to therecent coinage of “artist” to capture those trained in “mechanics col-leges” (precursors of the British polytechnics), who were contribut-ing more palpably to the ongoing Industrial Revolution than

university graduates. If it now seems odd that people called “scien-tists” and “artists” originally competed for the same social and eco-nomic space, simply consider that until the end of World War II(when a period specifically called the “Scientific Revolution” wascoined), the Italian Renaissance was normally portrayed as the pin-nacle of both science and art, as exemplified by that fading culturalicon, Leonardo da Vinci.

The origin of the word “scientist” raises some very large questionsabout the political economy of knowledge production. BeforeWhewell, knowledge was not something systematically acquired inorder to save time or make money. On the contrary, it took up time(that was otherwise not productively employed) and spent money(i.e., wealth that was above what was needed for maintainingone’s household); hence, it was the quintessentially leisured pursuit.Indeed, it would not be far-fetched to envisage such pursuits as ahigh-grade form of gambling : Sometimes the hours conducting exper-iments and observing nature turned up something genuinely useful,

but for the most part it was a hit-or-miss affair that attracted onlythe most “speculative” of human capital investors. Typical was earlyRoyal Society member Robert Boyle, a gentleman–farmer who livedoff his inheritance while engaged in scientific pursuits that would laythe foundations of modern chemistry. In Whewell’s own time, thislifestyle was pursued by Charles Darwin, whose failure as a medicalstudent was more significant as a loss of face than of income.

To be sure, the life of inquiry was pursued by more than curious

men of leisure. Those who suffered a decline in family and personalfortunes have also been prime candidates for assuming the risks thathave occasionally been issued in scientific innovations. For example,Galileo’s career approximated that of the entrepreneur who, in

What Knowledge Management Has Managed to Do to Knowledge 21

Page 22: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 22/56

 Joseph Schumpeter’s classic phrase, “creatively destroys” markets(Brenner 1987). As for that greatest of scientists, Isaac Newton, hewas the model for Whewell’s professional scientist. Newton, of

relatively humble origins, was one of the few early Royal Societymembers who had to draw a regular salary from a university in orderto survive. Yet, even he wrote Principia Mathematica in his sparetime. He needed external funding only to publish his arcane and heftytomes, not to conduct the research reported in them. A measure of the long-term significance of Whewell’s semantic innovation is thatmost professional scientists today find themselves in a situation thatis the exact opposite of Newton’s: If one can find the money to do

research in the first place, the publishers are more than happy tooblige in communicating its results.At the popular level, KM’s rise can be seen as a backlash against

professionalism in the pursuit of knowledge—but without the inter-est in reviving the original amateur ethic. At a popular level, the KMmentality resonates with the perceived lack of scientific genius in ourtime. We are more impressed with such early 20th century physicistsas Einstein, Bohr, and Heisenberg, for whom the chalkboard wasthe laboratory, than with the battery of physicists continuing theirwork on multibillion-dollar particle accelerators today. We even rankthose seat-of-the-pants discoverers of DNA’s structure, Watson andCrick, over that well-financed and methodical mapper of the humangenome, Craig Venter, even though the latter has enabled the promiseof biotechnology to become a reality. Perhaps genius will not beascribed to people who require enormous resources prior to the pro-duction of new knowledge. To be sure, considerable resources—botheconomic and cultural—may be needed after a putative breakthrough

to enable it literally to “break through” existing scientific and socialpractices. Indeed, there may be a trade-off here. After all, once thehuman genome was mapped, relatively little had to be spent to pub-licize its boon to medicine.

In other words, a “most bang for the buck” principle seems to ruleour intuitive judgements of genius. Television producers know thisall too well. It explains why viewers are more impressed by a JohnDoe who invents something that stumps the experts than by a bat-

talion of well-financed lab scientists who arrive at some equallycounterintuitive and probably better grounded discovery. But theconsequences of requiring payment for research run deeper than thetopic of the next science documentary. If the people who are regu-

22 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 23: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 23/56

larly paid to produce knowledge find publication relatively easy, thenit should come as no surprise that the ratio of useful to uselessresearch turns out to be unacceptably low, at least to the untrained

eye. The knowledge manager promises to sort out this situation.

4. The KM Challenge to Knowledge inTheory and Practice

As a way into the radical shift that KM has introduced into aca-demic conceptions of knowledge, consider the original statement of social epistemology, a research program I designed to answer the

question: How should knowledge production be governed, once weadmit that it has many of the same characteristics of other organizedsocial activities, specifically that knowledge is produced by fallibleand biased agents who pursue conflicting goals against the back-ground of various resource constraints (Fuller 1988, 3)? My formu-lation presumed that the most knowledge should be produced at thelowest cost, a principle that conformed to the so-called constrainedoptimization model of rational action found in neoclassical econom-

ics. Like most other philosophers and economists attracted to thisprinciple, I interpreted it as providing guidelines for an absoluteincrease in society’s knowledge stock. Yet, the principle can be readas more concerned with the  productivity than the sheer productionof knowledge. Thus, if you want “more bang for the buck”—and notsimply more bangs or more bucks—then you may wish to terminatefurther research investments, once the rate of return starts to be toolow. This alternative interpretation of the constrained optimization

model turns out to be KM’s own. Its radical implications for the intel-lectual and institutional dimensions of knowledge production will beexplored below.

4.1. KM and the End of Knowledge in Theory:The Deconstruction of Public Goods

Economists, all too much like philosophers, easily assume that

what is best for knowledge is best for business. Unfortunately, thisacademic conceit carries little weight with professional knowledgemanagers. Indeed, the seemingly liberating quality of knowledgemanagement thinking largely rests on an image of knowledge as dan-

What Knowledge Management Has Managed to Do to Knowledge 23

Page 24: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 24/56

gerous if allowed to grow wild. At a hands-on level, this reflects the“search and retrieval” problems that corporations face when hugeinvestments in computers fail to improve their ability to access salient

information in a timely manner (Scarbrough and Swan 1999). At amore abstract level, it helps explain the unflattering reduction of knowledge to “information” often found in the literature. Interms of the Australian economist Colin Clark’s (1957) influentialtrichotomy, knowledge managers invoke metaphors drawn fromthe primary sector of the economy—knowledge is thus “captured,”“mined,” and “cultivated.” It is most decidedly not “manufactured”(a secondary sector metaphor familiar to Marxist and social con-

structivist accounts of science) and, only when necessary, “delivered”as a service (a tertiary sector metaphor that had been popular withDaniel Bell and many of the original knowledge society theorists).

Knowledge managers are mainly interested in exploiting existingknowledge more efficiently so as to capture a larger share of themarkets in which they compete. A concern for producing moreknowledge and distributing it more widely merely subserves thatgoal. Indeed, knowledge management may be seen as being mainlyin the business of manipulating scarcity, at either the supply or thedemand side of the exchange equation. Knowledge managementstrategies tend either to restrict the production of knowledge andopen up its distribution, or vice versa. Thus, knowledge managersare urged to adopt a strategy of “outsource or specialize” for theirfirms: that is, either rent forms of knowledge that others can producemore cheaply or own forms of knowledge that others cannot (andsubsequently will not) produce more cheaply (Stewart 1997, 90–1).

As a global knowledge strategy, an example of the former route is

requiring credentials for employment, while extending access to thosecredentials to anyone able and willing to go through the trouble of acquiring them (e.g., a university education). Since the number of positions remains scarce relative to those eligible to fill them, theglobal result is a more focused and competitive labor market. For aninstance of the general strategy of opening up knowledge production,while restricting its distribution, consider the rent-seeking incentivesbehind the pursuit of intellectual property (Machlup 1984, 163ff).

As we shall see in the next chapter, with the liberalization of patentlaw, the easiest way down this route is to privatize something thatwas previously treated in the public domain and thereby avoid theuncertainties of invention altogether.

24 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 25: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 25/56

To appreciate the Realpolitik attitudes of knowledge managers, weneed look no further than the difference between their and most econ-omists’ view of scientific innovation in wealth production. Econo-

mists tend to treat innovation as an unalloyed and often unanalyzedgood, whereas businesspeople regard it as good only insofar as ithelps their firm maintain or increase its competitive advantage inthe market. Generally speaking, the competitive advantage likelyto be gained from the introduction of a new product—including aknowledge-based product—largely depends on one’s ability to createa demand for it, which usually has more to do with an ability tosecond-guess consumers than anything truly revolutionary in the

product itself. The idea of social capital captures this magical abilityto get “the most bang for the buck” because of one’s position in themarket (Coleman 1990, Chapter 12). Thus, relatively small innova-tions can end up making major profits for big companies, while trulyrevolutionary innovations can end up being ignored or “captured”by more market-savvy competitors because of the innovators’ mar-ginal status.

Because innovation turns out to be such a risky means of securinglarger profits, companies have been traditionally reluctant to devotetoo much of their operating budgets to R&D. The most cost-efficientoperation gets the biggest bang from the smallest buck, whichmeans—in knowledge terms—that one exploits what one knowsbetter than one’s competitors and blocks all attempts to supersedethat knowledge. This point is typified by the business strategy thatwould have a company devote considerable attention to acquiringintellectual property rights for existing innovations, regardless of whether the company in question actually originated the innovations

(Stewart 1997, Chapter 4). In this respect, any technique specificallydesigned to accelerate the growth of knowledge potentially poses achallenge to the business community as fundamental as that to thescientific community. For if philosophers (and most economists)of science believe that the intrinsic unpredictability of new knowl-edge renders a planned increase in innovation close to a logical im-possibility, the average corporate executive is willing to grant thepossibility of such planning but then go on to question its cost-

effectiveness as a business strategy.To be sure, economists often do not seem to believe they have a

quarrel with the business approach to innovation policy. However,this may be wishful thinking born of the idealization methods of eco-

What Knowledge Management Has Managed to Do to Knowledge 25

Page 26: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 26/56

nomics. Economists tend to take the relationship between innovationand market advantage as given, the only remaining question beinghow much time will pass before the innovation provides adequate

returns on an initial investment of resources. Thus, to the economist,businesspeople often appear impatient, albeit perhaps justifiably so,since the average corporate executive must manage other short-termissues alongside the long-term concerns represented by the company’sR&D division. But were the company equipped with an indefinitetimeframe and corresponding resources, it would eventually reap thebenefits of its original R&D investments: so say the economists.

Unfortunately, this patronizing appeal to the constrained opti-

mization model does not capture how the business world seesmatters. For them there is nothing especially sacrosanct about knowl-edge that makes it worthy of indefinite promotion. If anything, inlines of what I shall later call the “profit-oriented” model, the needfor knowledge in business is always the moral equivalent of a neces-sary evil. In striking contrast, economists generally locate the valueof new knowledge in some conception of “natural” scarcity associ-ated with its origins, typically in self-selected communities or theminds of exceptional individuals, neither of which are transparent topublicly accessible forums. Consequently, tacit knowledge is valuedmore highly than explicit knowledge—the “something extra” thatexplains the difference between innovative and routinized economicsystems once the usual factors of production have been taken intoaccount. But once tacit knowledge is codified, according to this view,it no longer offers a competitive advantage. In that sense, it becomesa  public good  (Dasgupta and David 1994). This has made econo-mists generally skeptical about the possibilities for managing, culti-

vating, or expediting the growth of knowledge. Indeed, they tend totreat new knowledge as occurring just as “naturally” or “sponta-neously” as climatological changes, which also affect a society’s pro-ductive capacity in significant yet largely unforeseeable ways.

However, knowledge managers are unimpressed by the brutenessof this conception of nature, be it human or physical. Regardingknowledge as part of the primary sector of the economy, they see itas a natural resource worthy of cultivation. Of course, like natural

resources, the exploitability of a piece of knowledge is never knownin advance. But by the same token, effort may be focused on devel-oping replacements for resources that could run out in the longterm—hence the emergence of computerized expert systems and bio-

26 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 27: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 27/56

medical syntheses of genetic materials as growth areas in knowledge-based industries.

In this respect, the KM movement can be seen as the final stage in

the retreat of knowledge’s status in the economy from a public goodin the tertiary sector to a natural resource in the primary sector. Thisdevolution is captured by the following narrative. In the beginning,when economists first started to think about knowledge in economicterms, knowledge was regarded as a “public good,” which meantthat once knowledge is produced, more than one person can consumeit at the same time (Samuelson 1969). There are two importantversions of this idea. The first is the ethereal good , in which once

it is produced, consumers of the good incur no additional costs(Thompson 1982, Bates 1988). The second is the collective good ,according to which it would cost more to restrict consumption of thegood than to allow its free use; moreover, any cost imposed on con-sumers would not result in a palpable gain for producers (Olson1965). On either reading, one is invited to imagine that, once dis-covered, knowledge spreads naturally, only to be arrested by artifi-cial means. Clearly, the public good conception has aimed toapproximate the classical philosophical ideal of knowledge as uni-versal not only in applicability but also accessibility.

Unfortunately, the appeal to a distinct category of “public goods”rests on a semantic trick, since even though producers of these goodscannot reap all the benefits of their products, additional effort is stillneeded to enable that knowledge to benefit everyone ( cf. Machlup1984, 121–159). (A free rider should never be confused with a uni-versal subject.) The collective goods version already draws attentionto the problem, since according to Mancur Olson, they are main-

tained by keeping the access costs low for collective members andhigh for non-members: i.e., tax breaks for the natives and high tariffsfor foreigners. In other words, the “universe” covered by the knowl-edge good is relative to a particular community, whose collectiveidentity is reinforced by the presence of the good. Thus, an insightthat originally took a genius, such as Einstein’s theory of relativity,is supposedly now accessible to anyone who can read a physics text-book. The highlighted phrase reveals the hidden access costs of public

goods (cf. Callon 1994). Einstein’s efforts to arrive at relativity theoryappear significantly greater than a student’s efforts to understand it,only if it is presumed that the student already brings to the physicstext the relevant background knowledge. But as a matter of fact, this

What Knowledge Management Has Managed to Do to Knowledge 27

Page 28: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 28/56

background knowledge often does not come cheap (e.g., a universityphysics degree) or even well-marked in the text (e.g., obscure allu-sions and jargon). A text in relativity theory may thus be likened to

a mass-produced toy, which costs little to purchase but then requiresadditional costs to be assembled.

The economic mystique of knowledge largely rests on keepingthese access costs hidden. It is underwritten by the commonsenseintuition that the “hard work” of invention or discovery comes withthe original development of an idea, and that the subsequent workof transmitting, or “distributing,” the idea to others is negligible bycomparison. Economists tend to neglect the costs of distribution in

these contexts because they talk about knowledge  production interms of the material good embodying the knowledge (e.g., Einstein’soriginal articles), whereas they talk about knowledge consumptionin terms of the knowledge “contained” in the material good (e.g.,Einstein’s ideas). Given this asymmetrical treatment, it is not sur-prising that knowledge has often struck economists as an enigma.But the puzzle is dissolved, and knowledge starts to look more likeother goods, once the distribution of a knowledge good is includedas part of the good’s overall production costs. In that case, knowl-edge is necessarily knowledge for someone. As we shall see in Chapter3, the advent of customized expert systems takes that additional step.

In short, the maintenance of public goods requires considerablework to ensure that everyone potentially has access to the goods.Provision for education and dissemination—normally tasks under-taken by the state bureaucracy—is the source of these hidden costs.They remain hidden because economists tend to conceptualize publicgoods in an equivocal fashion. Prima facie, the nature of the good

itself is specified “objectively,” while the value derived from the goodis specified “subjectively” (Bartley 1990, 47–50). However, a clue tothe problem with this interpretation is that the only aspect of sub-jectivity that interests public goods theorists is that one’s possessionof them can be described without reference to anyone else’s posses-sion, in which case such goods would appear to be divisible and hencequintessentially private.

Consider this point in light of a paradigm case of a public good.

Although a town commons is supposed to be a public good, for allof the town’s residents to benefit from the commons, they must interalia occupy different plots at the same time or the same plot at dif-ferent times. The semantic trick here involves conflating a distinction

28 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 29: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 29/56

originally drawn by the Polish logician Stanislaw Leszniewski as partof a solution to Russell’s paradox (Smith 1994, 213–225). The dis-tinction contrasts the distributive and the collective interpretation of 

class terms. The key term in the logic of classes is “membership,”which may be interpreted in two ways. “John Doe is a member of the public” may mean either that John is one instance of what “thepublic” signifies (distributive) or that he is a proper part of the thingcalled “the public” (collective). In that case, a public good can beunderstood as a collectively defined product whose use is defineddistributively. Logicians nowadays would put the matter moreharshly: the concept of public good results from equivocating

between the “intensional” and “extensional” definitions of “good.”Armed with such equivocation, one can reclassify virtually anythingas a public good. That there happen to be relatively few public goods(at least of interest to economists) thus reflects some deeply held prej-udices—masquerading as ontology—about the sorts of things thateveryone should be compelled to maintain so that anyone can haveaccess to them.

The equivocation between the distributive and collective interpre-tations of class terms obscures two sorts of devaluation that maybefall public goods, each attributable to a kind of “overuse.” Forsimplicity’s sake, let us return to the town commons. On the onehand, overuse may imply that the plots are becoming dirtier andhence returning smaller benefits to users; on the other, overuse mayresult in each plot becoming smaller through an increase in thenumber of users sharing the commons simultaneously. In the onecase, repeated usage degrades the good; in the other, increased divi-sion does so. These overuses become evident once public goods are

also seen as positional goods, since their value can be ascertainedonly once one knows how many others possess the good. The barefact that many benefit from a public good may lower its value for apotential consumer of that good. Thus, there are two ways by whichthe democratic extension of higher education may erode higher edu-cation’s value as a public good: either as larger course enrollmentslower the quality of instruction or as a larger number of academicdegree-holders lowers the competitive advantage one receives from

the degree.Why has the equivocal character of public goods gone relatively

unnoticed up to now? One reason may be that economists take forgranted the background welfare-state conditions that have enabled

What Knowledge Management Has Managed to Do to Knowledge 29

Page 30: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 30/56

such goods to appear “public.” If public goods are akin to the prover-bial frictionless medium of intellectual exchange, then the welfarestate contributes the relevant ceteris paribus clause. After all, absent

regular government provision for activities such as park maintenanceand educational quality assurance, the value afforded by the towncommons and the university system would quickly devolve accord-ing to market-driven norms: those who can pay could gain access toan excellent private good; those who cannot would have to settle foran inferior product. Following Schumpeter (1950), it has becomeincreasingly clear that what pass for “public goods” are part of thestate’s strategy for facilitating the circulation and accumulation of 

capital, at the same time buffering the citizenry from its worst effects.Little surprise, perhaps, that the knowledge manager’s demystifica-tion of public goods occurs at a time when many national govern-ments are failing to serve both capital and citizens within tighterbudgetary regimes and an ideological climate that precludes the mostobvious solution, namely, higher taxes on the private enterprises thatmost directly benefit from a healthy supply of public goods, espe-cially education (cf. O’Connor 1973).

4.2. KM and the End of Knowledge in Practice:The Disintegration of the University

 Joseph Schumpeter (1954, 536) usefully highlighted two alterna-tive goals for political economy that were hotly debated in the late18th and early 19th centuries. They are captured by two Greekcoinages of the period: chrematistics and catallactics. The former

concerned the sheer accumulation of wealth, and the latter the ratio-nal organization of exchange relations. In this context, Adam Smithcan be understood as having argued the delicate thesis that the“wealth of nations” is best pursued as a long-term strategy, the short-term focus of which is state provision of a free labor market thatenables people to discover how they are most productively employed.In short, a catallactic orientation is a better means to chrematisticends than the direct pursuit of chrematistics. Thus, Smith was unim-

pressed by the displays of wealth that characterized the great Easternempires and had been mimicked by Spain and France in their nation-building efforts from 1500 to 1750. In these cases, too much signifi-cance was attached to either the sheer quantity of bullion in the

30 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 31: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 31/56

Page 32: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 32/56

or consumption depends on the perceived returns. An antipathy touniversities is one of the few sentiments common to the revolution-ary European philosophers, scientists, and inventors who lived in the

200 years prior to Humboldt’s institutional renovation. Virtually all,at some point, expressed a desire to see all the scholastic tomes eatenby worms, engulfed in flames, or otherwise erased from historicalmemory. For them, universities represented a waste of talent andeffort that was an affront to humanity. Interestingly, a very similarattitude to one readily found in Galileo, Bacon, Descartes, and Humewas also found among the Muslims who legendarily torched theLibrary of Alexandria in 641 a.d. (Fuller and Gorman 1987). Before

Edward Gibbon’s revisionist account in The Decline and Fall of theRoman Empire (1788), this episode had been emblazoned in theWestern psyche as the paradigm case of religious fanaticism tri-umphing over enlightened learning. As it happens, the celebratedLibrary was little more than an unorganized warehouse of stockpiledbooks. It did not so much advance human knowledge as demonstratethe wealth of the Pharaohs who could afford to acquire these books.Egypt’s Muslim conquerors regarded this gesture as a blasphemoususe of our God-given powers. Islam’s own seminal contributionto KM was the deployment of its trading language, Arabic, toconsolidate the Greco-Roman intellectual heritage for purposes of elaboration and evaluation. This was its ultimate legacy to theoriginal European universities, whose charters enabled the autono-mous pursuit of knowledge in a way that had been prohibited underIslamic law.

Knowledge management updates the spirit that led to the burningof the Library of Alexandria and the stigmatizing of universities

during the Scientific and Industrial Revolutions. An ironic conse-quence of the traditional belief that knowledge is produced andconsumed rather differently from other material goods is that itsindefinite pursuit has been presumed to be an unmitigated good. Thishas led to a set of knowledge policies that, from a KM standpoint,look nothing short of superstitious (Fuller 1997, Chapter 4). Thedogma of “trickle-down effects” (from knowledge production to eco-nomic well-being) codifies this superstition. Even the founder of “sci-

entometrics,” Derek de Solla Price (1978), had already seen that thebest predictor of a research-intensive society is electricity consump-tion per capita—not, say, income per capita. (Think about the costsof maintaining research facilities, especially after the computer revo-

32 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 33: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 33/56

lution.) In other words, a Martian scanning Earth’s economic indi-cators would naturally conclude that so-called knowledge produc-tion is designed to show off how much wealth nations can afford to

waste. (“Knowledge accumulation” would be a better phrase.) To besure, this was Aristotle’s original point about leisure as a prere-quisite for pure inquiry, which Michael Polanyi (1957, 1962) pro-moted to a moral imperative, given the temptations to harnessknowledge production to military–industrial concerns. Yet, knowl-edge managers fail to be impressed, and universities as the principalknowledge-producing institutions in modern society have respondedunimpressively.

In the words of former Fortune editor Thomas Stewart (1997, 76),universities are “dumb organizations” that are “high on humancapital” but “low on structural capital”: A fast food chain such asMcDonalds is a “smart organization” because it makes the most of its relatively ill-trained staff by maximizing the interconnectivity of the staff’s activities. Business as usual in academia proceeds almostexactly in reverse, which is why its well-educated staff must be specif-ically required, if not begged, to attend department meetings anddeclare office hours. Thus, from a KM standpoint, the traditionaluniversity is a whole that is much less than the sum of its parts, andacademic administrators are little more than high-paid custodians of car parks, classrooms, and other campus facilities. Imagine a firmwhose goals are dictated almost entirely by the various trade unionsfrom which its labor force is drawn. Each union has the final say onthe performance standards to which its members are held. Manage-ment ensures that the firm’s employees do not interfere with eachother’s work, without aspiring to any greater level of cooperation and

coordination of effort. If we replace “trade union” with “academicdiscipline” or “professional association,” the firm starts to look likea university.

However, universities have begun to take the “dumb organization”label to heart by modeling themselves on McDonalds’ performancemeasures and the conclusions drawn from them. McDonaldsfamously records its success on its “golden arches” signs, not in suchconventionally economic terms as profits, but the number of prod-

ucts sold—or rather, “served,” which evokes (without demonstrat-ing) the idea of “satisfied customers.” This practice, limited to U.S.outlets, is a brilliant stroke of public relations in a country thatfancies itself full of “informed” consumers. The genius of this move

What Knowledge Management Has Managed to Do to Knowledge 33

Page 34: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 34/56

is to appeal to a quantitative indicator that can never decrease, yetat the same time it can suggest room for improvement. The down-side of such an open-ended metric is that it can easily become an end

in itself, which is precisely the situation in which British academiafinds itself today. Unlike the United States, whose educational sectoris constitutionally devolved to a mix of public and private institu-tions, the United Kingdom largely follows the European pattern of state centralization. Whereas the McDonalds mentality has typicallyentered U.S. education through the hiring of professional managersat particular institutions, in 1988 it became the official U.K. policyfor higher education’s accountability to the taxpayers. Thus, every

4–5 years, the United Kingdom is subjected to the Research Assess-ment Exercise (RAE), which ranks every discipline in every univer-sity. The result is a set of academic “league tables”—the impliedmetaphor is from football—that ranks every department at all of theU.K.’s 100-odd universities. These are then published in the leadingbroadsheet newspapers and become the basis for student choice, cor-porate sponsorship, and most of all, state funding.

In some respects, the RAE has been a clear success. Few academicshave complained about it, which may be explained by the U.K.’sseemingly limitless sense of gamesmanship. (In the U.S., someonewould have by now found something sufficiently unjust about theRAE’s implementation to bring a lawsuit that would have halted theexercise.) Moreover, the U.K.’s research productivity has increasedand become more prominent internationally. Indeed, the exercise isnow emulated by other countries in need of an academic audit. Ithas even spawned, within the U.K., a periodic exercise in “teachingquality assessment” (TQA). Yet, whatever their respective merits, the

RAE and TQA have little, if anything, to do with each other. TheTQA is driven by a desire to maximize the number of highly skilledworkers. And if well-trained workers continue to be paid less in theU.K. than in other parts of the world, TQA should contribute to aneffective global market strategy. The motives behind RAE are moreelusive, since a high rate of scientific publications and patents is morea striking indicator than an underlying cause of a nation’s wealth.In the symbolic world of politics and public policy, this is not a

trivial point but one worth keeping in perspective. In effect, theRAE is about the cultivation and identification of knowledge prod-ucts that are “high quality” in a sense not unlike that of an unal-loyed precious metal.

34 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 35: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 35/56

In short, because of some lingering superstitions about the instan-taneous impact of new knowledge on social and economic well-being,an academic bullionist model of universities coexists with some KM-

style knowledge policies. Thus, in his 1999 keynote address to theannual meeting of the Higher Education Funding Council of England,the United Kingdom’s minister for science and technology (and heirto a major supermarket chain) Lord David Sainsbury praised aca-demics on the following grounds: The United Kingdom has 1% of the world’s population, does 6% of the world’s science, produces 8%of the world’s scientific publications, and gets 9% of the world’s sci-entific journal citations—this despite a 20% reduction in government

spending on scientific research over the last 10 years (i.e., since theend of the Cold War). Instead of querying the logic that links thesestatistics (e.g., is the accumulation of publications and citations any-thing more than bullionism?) or perhaps recommending that U.K.academics could make good use of more research funding, Sainsburyconcluded that the results justified the continued use of RAE-ledcompetitive rationing as a national funding policy, without necessar-ily increasing the overall pot of funds.

The problems with Sainsbury’s assessment are manifold but notuncharacteristic of contemporary confusions over how exactly oneassesses the state of knowledge production. I can only list the prob-lems here, but together they provide a strong argument for knowl-edge management returning to basics:

1. Even academics working in public institutions are increasinglyreliant on private funding for their research. Indeed, many arenow virtually self-funding, often obtaining more than they

would from public sector agencies. Yet, however helpful thisdevelopment is to balancing state budgets, it does not consti-tute increased “productivity” as measured by “the most bangfor the buck” principle.

2. But even if we accept that British research activity has becomemore productive, that may be an artifact of researchers beingpaid wages that are low relative to the quality of the work theydo. After all, even in our high-tech world, most research expen-

diture is still for labor. A revisit to Marx’s theory of surplusvalue may not be amiss here.

3. To what extent does funded research contribute to “humancapital development,” i.e., seeding the next generation of 

What Knowledge Management Has Managed to Do to Knowledge 35

Page 36: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 36/56

researchers—say, through quality undergraduate education andgraduate training—or, for that matter, the next generation of informed non-specialist consumers of new research?

4. Lacking a clear productive relationship between academic pub-lications and economic well-being, perhaps the major long-termbenefit of an increasingly competitive system is the unintendedone of people exiting the mainstream knowledge productionmarkets (i.e., academic appointments) in order to establish theirown niches which, as with the Scientific and Industrial Revo-lutions, eventually “creatively destroy” those markets: Is thenext Cervantes to be found among science-fiction writers and

cyberwarriors?

5. Back to Basics: Rediscovering the Valueof Knowledge in Rent, Wage, Profit

Clearly we need to take a step back—indeed, to the beginning.Consider knowledge production from the three sources of incomeoriginally stipulated by Adam Smith: rent , wage, and  profit. Thereare a couple of ways of motivating the relationship between thesethree entities, which are compared systematically in Figure 1.1. Thefirst is to envisage them as forming an idealized historical sequencefrom pre-capitalist to capitalist modes of value assignment. Thesecond involves focusing on their respective attitudes toward time asa measure of value. In the jargon of welfare economics, rent-seeking“discounts” the future in favor of the past, in that payment is madefor things already done, even if that deters the ability to do some-thing else later. In contrast, profit-seeking discounts in reverse, as it

favors ongoing and likely future returns at the expense of past invest-ments. Finally, wage-seeking sticks to the classical ideal of the labortheory of value, whereby one is simply paid for what one actuallydoes, without reference to what has been or is likely to be done.

Rent is traditionally associated with income from land, but itcarries some additional connotations. The payment of rent typicallyimplies the need to remove a barrier in the way of achieving one’sgoals. For example, before setting up a factory, one must first pay

rent on the land where the factory is to be built. Economists havetraditionally disliked rent as a source of income because landownersdo not need to do anything productive in order to exact rents fromtenants: they simply need to own the land and perhaps maintain it

36 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 37: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 37/56

What Knowledge Management Has Managed to Do to Knowledge 37

SOURCE OF RENT WAGE PROFITINCOME

FRAME OF “Science” “Scientist” (the “Scientific” (theREFERENCE (a body of professional) character of knowledge) things)

KNOWLEDGE IS . . . What you build What you do What youon provide

VIRTUE OF Authority Craft EfficiencyKNOWLEDGE

EPISTEMOLOGY Foundational Practical Instrumental

AIM OF Power through Craft at the Power at theKNOWLEDGE craft expense of expense of craft

power

“DIVISION OF Expert Team ComparativeLABOR” MEANS deference cooperation advantage

LABOR MARKET Restrict entry Promote entry Promote exitSTRATEGY and restrict exit

PAYMENT FOR Grant (for past Salary (for Prize (forKNOWLEDGE performance) ongoing work) finished product)

“PROGRESS” Completing a Refining a Diffusing anMEANS world-picture tradition innovation

“NATURE” Property to be Raw material Obstacle to beMEANS staked out to be shaped overcome

THE EFFECT OF Adds value by Orthogonal to Subtracts valueCODIFICATION explaining craft’s tacit by cheaply

ON KNOWLEDGE craft nature replacing craft

ECONOMIC Tribute Labor UtilityABSTRACTION

LIMIT CONCEPT Credentials Artisanship Automation

Figure 1.1.Three potential sources of value in knowledge production

Page 38: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 38/56

at a level that is attractive to potential tenants. As long as producersdo not already own land, and land is scarce, it will be rational forlandowners to charge them rent. Of course, the rentiers may not wish

to lease the land at all. In that case, they refuse to create the condi-tions for economic growth because they are under no pressure to riskpotentially unreliable tenants. Analogously, economically secure aca-demics—say, career civil servants whose livelihood is based on thetraining and examination of the new generation of recruits to theirranks—are not especially motivated to overturn existing knowledgeregimes. This has often been cited as an important factor in explain-ing why the politically and economically more advanced societies of 

China and India did not foster the climate of innovation that eventu-ated in Europe’s “Scientific Revolution” (Collins 1998, Chapter 10).From a KM standpoint, the need to qualify in academic forms of 

knowledge in order to gain professional accreditation—be it busi-ness, engineering, law, or medicine—may be seen as a form of intel-lectual rent that is imposed on the student (cf. Tullock and McKenzie1975). Is knowledge of economics really necessary to succeed in busi-ness? Is physics necessary to succeed in engineering? Is biology nec-essary to succeed in medicine? Until the early 20th century, theanswer to all these questions was no. But now the answer is yes,because one is not “licensed” to practice these professions, unless onefirst has acquired the relevant university training. In the past, pro-fessionals were known for their track record; now increasingly it isfor their credentials (Collins 1979). In a sense, one could tell the storyof the rise of academic power in the 20th century as a matter of turning ever larger portions of everyday life into intellectual realestate to which academic disciplines hold the deeds. The map of this

real estate is often called a “world-picture” that allows access to a“domain of reality.” (Note the spatial metaphors associated with thisconception of knowledge.)

But it would be a mistake to regard epistemic rent-seeking asentirely a matter of academics restricting the entry of non-academicsto their ranks. A version of the same practice transpires inside acad-emia, albeit more subtly, since academics are trained, in effect, to payrents before they are formally demanded. I refer here to that abstract

act of tribute involved in crediting another academic with part of one’s own work in the form of a citation (Fuller 1997, Chapter 4;Fuller 2000a, Chapter 5). As in Mafia-style relations, preemptivepayment is often intended less as ancestor worship than as insurance

38 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 39: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 39/56

against future harm in the peer review process, a point to which Ishall return in the next chapter.

Notwithstanding the apparent cynicism of my remarks, the pursuit

of academic knowledge is not entirely reducible to rent-seeking, sinceit is not clear who would take a personal interest in upholding stan-dards in the knowledge that is allowed to circulate around society,were it not for academics. Left to their devices, businesspeople andother professionals may prefer a free market environment, whereknowledge claims are made willy-nilly and the consumer is simplytold “Let the buyer beware!” This function of academic knowledgecorresponds to the historic role that aristocratic landowners have

played in conserving the land from corner-cutting factory-buildersand housing developers. One can think of the important roles playedby state-commissioned academic laboratories in testing productsbefore they are marketed and informing the patent office on how (if!)an invention can be understood as the application of known scien-tific principles (Fuller 2000a, Chapter 6). Some of this perspectivesurvives in the cultivation of “metapublic goods,” which are dis-cussed in the next section.

Wage is income paid according to the amount of labor performed.Although presumably this labor is performed in aid of making goodsthat can then be sold at market, the crucial feature of wages is thatthey are paid simply for doing the work, regardless of the price atwhich the goods are sold. When people talk about the pursuit of knowledge as “an end in itself,” the wage conception is normallyimplied. In contrast with the rent-seeking landowner image, the wageconception is associated more with farmers who enjoy getting theirhands dirty in the art of raising crops, regardless of how much land

they own or how much their crops fetch at market. Scientific workis often discussed in these terms, especially given the unpredictablerelation between the effort expended in the laboratory and the ulti-mate impact of the knowledge produced in that setting. In thisrespect, Max Weber’s (1958) exhortation to new recruits to the aca-demic ranks, “Science as a Vocation,” is a classic expression of whatI am calling the wage orientation.

Economists have observed that the differences in salary among

academics is not as wide as the differences in their research produc-tivity would predict: strong producers do not usually earn that muchmore than weak producers (Frank 1984). Indeed, an awareness of this fact helps explain the attraction that the world of science parks,

What Knowledge Management Has Managed to Do to Knowledge 39

Page 40: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 40/56

intellectual property, and related business ventures has held for moreentrepreneurial scientists. The usual justification for salary compres-sion is that academics primarily pursue knowledge because that is

what they want to do, not because they intend to come up with lucra-tive findings, etc. In addition, since academic markets are definedmore vaguely than commercial markets, there is no clear measureof value, or “bottom line,” that determines the worth of a particu-lar piece of academic knowledge. Finally, there is a long tradition—perhaps superstitious—that claims that some of the most importantfindings are made as a by-product of inquirers just following theircuriosity without any preconceived goals. All of this points to the

wage conception.It is important to appreciate the difference between the wage andrent conceptions of knowledge because academics like to see them-selves in terms of the former, not the latter. Consequently, modes of payment that formally acknowledge social capital, and hence rewardcredentials or past achievements, are often subject to controversywithin the academic community. For example, grants for research aretypically made on the basis of one’s reputation in the field, whichtends to reinforce the distinction between the “haves” and “havenots” in academia: if you have not already done something signifi-cant, you are unlikely to get a grant to do something significant.Rarely are grants given simply for the quality of the proposal alone.The grant system thus operates—often quite explicitly—to promoteand inhibit certain lines of inquiry, depending on their relationshipto what has already been done. For that reason, less orthodox aca-demics often forgo the usual grant agencies and seek private funding,which tends to be awarded in a more overtly speculative fashion, in

the spirit of a venture capitalist or prospector.This brings us to the third form of income,  profit, which is tradi-

tionally the return on the investment of land and labor, as determinedby the price that goods fetch at market. The basic idea is that youmanage to get back something more than you originally put in. The“scientific” way to pursue profit is to defer any discounting of thefuture, by spending the time now to understand something deeply, sothat you can act more efficiently in the future. Of course, trial-and-

error can often produce the same results as scientifically informedinquiries, but usually it takes longer, since the innovator cannot takeadvantage of the organized memory of academic knowledge—andoften this extra time is not available. From a business standpoint, the

40 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 41: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 41/56

problem may boil down to knowing enough of the language that aca-demics use to be able to access what one needs to know. In that case,great value should be placed on people who can “decode,” “trans-

late,” and otherwise remove the linguistic barriers to accessing aca-demic knowledge. With this aim in view, Executive Ph.D. programs,co-sponsored by academia and business, have emerged that aredesigned to equip middle managers with the research skills needed toexploit the commercial potential of the knowledge base contained inthe scientific literature. (I shall raise countervailing dimensions of these programs in the next section.)

Clearly, the value that the profit-seeker places on knowledge is

the most removed from the academic ethos. To see just how non-academic it is, consider the various ways in which one might place avalue on knowledge of arithmetic. For the profit-seeker, the value of arithmetic is as a systematic form of calculation that provides signi-ficant shortcuts to counting. The next logical step for the profit-seekeris to figure out how to mechanize this knowledge, so that people donot have to do the arithmetic themselves, but can delegate it to apiece of technology. Although it might initially take a while todevelop such a technology, the effort would be endlessly repaid interms of the amount of time and energy saved whenever a calcula-tion needs to be made. For the profit-seeker, then, knowledge is quiteliterally a necessary evil: the more necessary, the more evil—hence,the impulse to move it out of the mind and into the environment.Perhaps the purest case of the profit-seeker’s approach to knowledgeis Donald Norman (1993), the cognitive scientist who popularizedthe design of “smart environments” that enable people to “offload”routine knowledge from their brains to their surroundings so they

can think about emergent issues.Rent- and wage-seeking knowledge producers see the matter much

differently. For the rent-seeker, the codification of arithmetic meansthat one does not fully understand how to calculate if he or she doesnot know the fundamental principles that render the calculationsvalid. Acquiring this knowledge entails taking courses and passingexaminations in arithmetic. The wage-seeker is interested in arith-metic as an inherently valuable mental skill, regardless of the uses

to which it can be put. Indeed, the wage-seeker is likely to discoverparadoxes and puzzles by pursuing the logic of arithmetic thoughtwherever it may lead. Nevertheless, both the rent- and the wage-seeker want to ensure that those interested in arithmetic undergo

What Knowledge Management Has Managed to Do to Knowledge 41

Page 42: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 42/56

formal training. Consequently, both would regard the profit-seeker’sinterest in mechanizing arithmetic as potentially depriving them of their livelihood, much as automation has historically made redun-

dant much of the industrial labor force. In other words, the profit-seeker is rewarded solely for actual results, not for sheer effort orpast track record. However, she may benefit from rent- and wage-seeking knowledge producers—the former providing quality con-trol checks and the latter a sense of exploratory openness—thatmay otherwise be crowded out by the competitive environment ofthe marketplace.

The unique contribution of Western science to knowledge pro-

duction has been to enable the scientist’s craft to maintain its auton-omy against tendencies toward devolution to either a priesthood (i.e.,rent-driven) or a technology (i.e., profit-driven). The university is theinstitution most responsible for enabling scientists to stay the course,but its restraining power has been considerably eroded in recent yearsthrough the introduction of market forces. On the one hand, educa-tion is devolving into a credentials mill; on the other, research isdevolving into intellectual property. As a result, that archetypalknowledge producer, the academic scientist, is becoming a roledivided against itself.

Of course, science may internally manifest profit-seeking or wage-seeking tendencies but appear to be primarily rent-seeking withrespect to the larger society. In other words, whatever competitive-ness exists within science may be offset by the barriers that preventpeople from entering the competitive field. The cost of acquiring theright credentials most immediately comes to mind. At the beginningof the 20th century, it was still common for amateurs to contribute

to scientific journals—much less so today.However, in some important respects, the rent-seeking tendencies

of science have yielded to the profit paradigm, as universities increasetheir dependency on researchers and teachers on fixed-term con-tracts. The “harder” sciences tend to bear the brunt of the contractresearchers, whereas the “softer” sciences absorb more of the con-tract teachers. The difference reflects the source of income: lucrativegrants versus student enrollments. Both types of knowledge workers

are oriented more toward delivering their goods and services just-in-time than developing long-term skills likely to result in an improve-ment of the academic base, something knowledge managers derideas just-in-case knowledge (Stewart 1997, 131). The latter is meant to

42 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 43: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 43/56

Page 44: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 44/56

Page 45: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 45/56

of universities. They are virtues that even business has begun toappreciate, as firms suffer from corporate amnesia (Kransdorff 1998), the negative by-product of quickly formed, flexibly organized

associations of providers and clients. Although the existence of thesenimble networks has enabled the business community to adapt to achanging competitive environment, the only knowledge traces theyleave are those embodied in their constitutive nodes and joint prod-ucts. But once a network’s mission is accomplished, its human nodessimply disperse and connect with other nodes to form new networksin pursuit of new projects. The precedent for this diabolical situationis captured by the phrase “market failure,” which is the economist’s

way of talking about goods that markets fail to generate because noone finds it in their interest to produce them. This is because the costof producing the goods can never be completely recovered in profits.In welfare economics, market failure defines the frontier that justifiesstate provision of public goods. Similarly, we may speak of the roleof universities in redressing network failure by reproducing andextending knowledge that might otherwise be lost through networkdispersion.

Knowledge managers have yet to realize the full significance of uni-versities in this capacity because they tend to diagnose networkfailure much too locally, as mere instances of “knowledge hoarding.”The idea here is that companies become dependent on the servicesof certain employees—often IT personnel—who do not make theirknowledge directly available. We are asked to envisage these humannodes as blocking the flow of information in the network by refus-ing to share what they know with the other nodes. Thus, the knowl-edge hoarder appears as a moral failure who needs to be taught

greater concern for her colleagues. Little is said about the emerg-ence of knowledge hoarding as a defensive strategy for remainingemployed or even employable in the knowledge economy’s volatilelabor market. The KM targeting of the individual knowledge hoarderaims to ensure that firms receive an adequate return on their “knowl-edge investments,” as measured by the clients, contacts, or Web linksthat employees accumulate. It is very much the point of view of man-agers trying to keep their firms afloat. However, from a more global

perspective the tendency of knowledge to escape from its formativenetworks may be seen as a positive market mechanism for counter-acting the corporate hoarding of knowledge, which could result inthat ultimate blockage of free exchange, a monopoly.

What Knowledge Management Has Managed to Do to Knowledge 45

Page 46: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 46/56

In a related context, Michael Perelman (1991) has introduced theconcept of metapublic goods, which attempts to resurrect some keyfeatures of public goods in a market where the leading producers

exert imperfect control over the flow of their goods, so that free ridersand pirates flourish in a parallel “black market.” The most realisticsetting for “creative destruction” of an existing market—and hencethe production of new knowledge—is where a barrier is placed toachieving ends by the usual means, which then demands that onecome up with legal or illegal alternative means. The most obviousbarrier is the temporary monopoly afforded to a patent holder, butit may be simply the fact that knowledge is transmitted neither instan-

taneously nor intact; rather, its transmission requires effort on thepart of both sender and receiver, which is not always completely suc-cessful. Of special relevance here are two groups: (a) those who failto receive the message intended for them and (b) those who receivethe message despite its not being intended for them.

The trial-and-error character of these efforts indirectly generatesits own knowledge base, a metapublic good. The more peopleinvolved in this process, the smarter the collective. This process isepitomized by the activities surrounding software piracy. These goodsmay be generated in two complementary ways: on the one hand, themanufacturer (say, Microsoft) does not catch the bugs in its latestsoftware, but a self-organized user group does and then takes the ini-tiative to remove them; on the other, instead of dispersing or evenregulating the user group, the manufacturer exploits the group’s find-ings in designing new software. In short, metapublic goods flourishbecause it is more cost-effective for corporations to learn from piratesthan to prosecute them for piracy.

As my last comment suggests, metapublic goods differ signifi-cantly from public goods in that their provision is not maintained bythe state. Rather, metapublic goods are unintended consequences of market activity that market leaders can then strategically convert tothe usual divisible goods. Universities may be able to counteract thistendency and thereby perform a crucial role in the maintenance of metapublic goods. In other words, universities institutionalize knowl-edge escape so as to redistribute the corporate advantage accumu-

lated in a firm’s staff, databases, and intellectual property. Classicallythis task has involved synthesizing disparate cases from their origi-nal contexts of discovery and inferring larger explanatory principles,which are then subject to further study and ultimately dissemination

46 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 47: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 47/56

through teaching and publication. This was certainly WilliamWhewell’s original vision of the “scientist’s” profession. Nowadaysthese activities extend beyond contemplating the design of nature to

“troubleshooting” and “reverse engineering” products to enable theirimprovement and even replacement (Fuller 2000a, Chapters 6, 7). Inshort, universities function as knowledge trust-busters whose owncorporate capacities of “creative destruction” prevent new knowl-edge from turning into intellectual property.

But academia can penetrate corporate knowledge practices beyondbeing an institutionalized “loyal opposition” to the marketplace.Perhaps the most hopeful sign is the establishment of the Executive

Ph.D. as a degree program in business schools. The pilot for thisprogram, appropriately called “Fenix” (“phoenix”), began as ajoint venture between the highest levels of academia and busi-ness in Sweden. (The Web site is http://www.fenix.chalmers.se.)Academia is represented by the Chalmers University of Technology(Sweden’s answer to MIT or Imperial College) and the StockholmSchool of Economics. Business is represented by most of the majorSwedish multinational corporations, including Volvo, Ericsson, andAstraZeneca. The premise behind this program is that the businessworld is much too dynamic today and hence needs to recover thequalities of mind that have enabled academics to sustain collectivebodies of knowledge that not only survive changes in fashion, butalso provide standards for evaluating new forms of knowledge. Beingon top of the latest trend makes good business sense only if the trendis likely to leave a lasting trace. Otherwise, one risks wasting effortnow and suffering obsolescence later—“overadaptation” in thejargon of evolutionary biology. Moreover, as corporations come to

regard themselves as potential victims of a mobile labor force, theyhave begun to appreciate the standpoint of the “knowledge disad-vantaged,” which in turn renders the public-good conception of knowledge more attractive than perhaps it previously seemed.

Business initially wanted to tap into what was imagined to bean unfathomed wealth of knowledge lodged in esoteric texts andinscrutable databases. Thus, “advanced research skills” were seen asenabling middle managers to subject the scientific literature to such

favored KM activities as “mining” and “prospecting.” However, asthe Executive Ph.D. program has evolved, the sense of what countsas “metal” and “ore” has shifted from a hardcore KM orientationto one more attuned with academic values. Indeed, some have

What Knowledge Management Has Managed to Do to Knowledge 47

Page 48: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 48/56

claimed that the Executive Ph.D. might create a “virtual academiccommons” (Hellstrom 2002) in the business world. The clearestexample of the relevant gestalt switch is the move away from think-

ing that some brute sense of “information” is the metal that needsto be extracted from its orelike theoretical and methodologicalencasement. Instead, these budding “doctors of business” come toregard this encasement not so differently from how stock market ana-lysts think of “fundamental” indicators. One learns not to be tooimpressed by a striking research result, unless one is in a position tojudge the robustness of the theory and method that inform it. Judg-ments of this sort usually involve some knowledge of the history of 

the research field in question.An easily overlooked feature of the Executive Ph.D. program isthat its academic staff consists mainly of contract researchers whowere drawn into paid collaboration with business because of thepaucity of regular academic posts. Often the collaboration results inthe contract researcher adopting habits associated with the businessworld, notably a penchant for problem-oriented thinking aimed atpractical short-term solutions. This can then make it difficult for thecontract researcher to become reintegrated into academic culture,once a regular post opens up, and at a deeper level can engenderhostility to the distinctive institutions of that culture, such as peerreview, tenure, and the value of basic research. However, the exactopposite occurs as well, whereby the staff of the Executive Ph.D.program serve as de facto academic ambassadors and perhapseven colonizers (Jacob and Hellstrom 2000). Thus, business doctoralstudents acquire habits of mind that were not part of their under-graduate degree training (usually in narrow technical subjects) and

that have not been especially fostered in the business environmentswhere they have been working. These include a tolerance, respect,and capacity for sustained reading, rigor, abstraction, synthesis, andcriticism.

Indeed, the Executive Ph.D. program addresses the problem of cor-porate amnesia quite literally by teaching students how to institu-tionalize a corporate conversation that continually rehearses thehistory and re-plots the aims of the organization in light of current

practice. At a metaphysical level, this conversation constructs whatmight be called the “subjectivity” or “conscience” of the firm. Inpractice, it amounts to keeping written records of corporate goalsthat can be used to evaluate subsequent performance and changes of 

48 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 49: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 49/56

the collective mind. Regardless of the firm’s actual market perfor-mance, an academically informed corporate subjectivity would adoptthe standpoint of a player who has yet to win. Thus, one would aim,

not for conservative adjustments to the current market paradigm, butto “creatively destroy” the paradigm by introducing new productsthat force competitors to rethink their market strategy.

The spread of Executive Ph.D. programs will not necessarily rescueacademia from KM’s tendency toward bottom-line thinking. Afterall, the contemporary university does suffer from a fundamentalstructural weakness. The teaching function, which is organized interms of rigidly defined departments, works at cross purposes with

the research function, which favors largely self-organizing interdisci-plinary teams. There is no doubt that this tension has only worsenedin recent years. Research activities—be they in the lab or in the field—have required more time and space away from the preparationand delivery of courses. It may well be, then, that knowledge man-agers will persuade universities of the cost-effectiveness of allowingresearch to migrate off their grounds. In time research would becomecompletely outsourced to facilities specially tailored to the needs of major clients. Academic employees would be then left with the peren-nial job of filling classrooms. But by the time this scenario comes topass, one may hope that there will be enough holders of ExecutivePh.D. degrees in public and private sector administration to undo thedamage that will have been done.

7. Squaring the KM Circle:Who’s Afraid of Accelerating the

Production of New Knowledge?

That innovation can reconfigure markets for purposes of unleash-ing new sources of wealth is as old as capitalism itself. What is rel-atively new—and still controversial—is the idea that the productionof new knowledge should be promoted explicitly and always. Forexample, two economists who have been among the most astute the-orists of innovation, Thorstein Veblen and Joseph Schumpeter, were

suspicious of both the motives and consequences of the promiscuouspursuit of new knowledge. Veblen (1904) saw endless innovation asmotivated by “businessmen” (i.e., the corporate marketing division)who persuade investors to prefer the future over the present, thereby

What Knowledge Management Has Managed to Do to Knowledge 49

Page 50: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 50/56

undermining the value of what workers currently do. For his part,Schumpeter (1950) saw the relationship between innovation and cor-porate survival as akin to that of charisma and routinization, accord-

ing to Max Weber. In other words, persistent market instability willeventually lead the state and industry to agree to discourage specu-lative investments in new knowledge. In Veblen’s telling, endlessinnovation is unfair to the ordinary worker; in Schumpeter’s, it issystemically unsustainable. Nevertheless, the Holy Grail of contem-porary knowledge management is that knowledge growth can bedeliberately accelerated.

To be sure, this goal also flies in the face of philosophical wisdom,

which claims that, as a matter of principle, scientific progress cannotbe predicted or planned. This “principle” is typically presented as amatter of logic, but it is better seen as a matter of ethics. The mainissues concern whether (or under what conditions) one ought toaccelerate knowledge growth—not whether it can be done at all,since the answer to that question is clearly yes.

Skepticism about the predictability of knowledge growth was bornof extreme tendencies exhibited by capitalist and socialist regimesthat first became clear in the 1920s. They are associated with so-called self-fulfilling and self-defeating prophecies, which occur when-ever a prediction functions as a communication to those whosebehavior is being predicted, who can then respond by either enablingor disabling the prediction’s realization. In this way, we can explainboth the fluctuation of prices in the open market and the single-mindedness of social policies in an authoritarian regime. Specifically,we can explain, on the one hand, how fortunes were made and lostthrough speculation, culminating in the stock market crash of 1929

that launched the Great Depression, and on the other, Soviet andNazi beliefs in the laws of history that motivated atrocities thatwould have been unthinkable, had their perpetrators not thoughtthey knew which way the future pointed.

The basic argument against the possibility of planned knowledgegrowth is simply that by definition a genuine scientific discoverycannot be predicted or planned. Those who claim otherwise aretherefore dealing in hype. This susceptibility to hype was born of the

1920s, the first great period for stock speculation purportedly basedon scientific innovation (Chancellor 1999, Chapter 7). Yet, often theinnovations were not forthcoming—though they managed to gener-ate major investments in the interim—or their significance was over-

50 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 51: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 51/56

sold by advertising agencies, whose recent emergence presupposedthat products had become too sophisticated to sell themselves. In thelatter case, the “innovation” may have merely added a wrinkle or an

efficiency to an already existing demand for a good or service.In addition, the skeptics usually make certain assumptions about

the nature of reality:

(A1) Our inquiries initially have a low probability of capturingthe aspects of reality that interest us.

(A2) There is a direct correlation between the significance of a sci-entific discovery and the degree of surprise it brings to those

who make it. In other words, a quantum leap in knowledgegrowth should always be counterintuitive to those who havebeen monitoring the course of inquiry.

Nevertheless, even if assumption A1 is true, it does not follow thatassumption A2 is also true. To think that it does is to deny that peoplecollectively learn from particular discoveries so as to improve theirability to make discoveries in the future. Once this point is granted,the main logical objection to accelerating the growth of knowledgeis overcome. Speculative investments on prospective revolutionarybreakthroughs are thus not irrational. Kuhn (1970, Chapter 11) hasobserved that scientific revolutions tend to be “invisible” becausethey are generally recognized as such only after the fact. Of course,it is hard to ignore a controversy while it is happening, but the overalldirection of its resolution is known only in retrospect, once officialhistories of the episode are written which distinguish clear winnersand losers. These verdicts track the students, professorships, and

other academic resources the various sides managed to accumulatein the process. Moreover, there is typically some mystery as to whatthe controversy that resulted in the revolution was really about—beyond simply the distribution of social, political, and economicresources to the next generation of inquirers. Since official historiesare calculated to place the winners in the most favorable light, theyoften ignore the fundamental issues that originally divided thedisputants.

In this context, Fuller’s (1988, Chapter 5) “social epistemology”develops Kuhn’s concept of incommensurability, the non-negotiabledifferences that lead to the winner-take-all outcomes of scientificrevolutions. But unlike Kuhn, I argue that these differences are not

What Knowledge Management Has Managed to Do to Knowledge 51

Page 52: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 52/56

deeply metaphysical but themselves artifacts of an institutionalizedcommunication breakdown between kindred intellectual factions,which in principle can be either maximized or minimized, depending

on what we know and want out of our knowledge claims. (Foran innovative and systematic use of computer simulations to trackthe relationship between communication network formations andknowledge distribution, see Carley and Kaufer 1993.) In other words,the “unpredictability” of radical scientific change may be purely afunction of our ignorance of how our own knowledge processeswork, rather than a sign of some unbridgeable disparity between ourstate of knowledge and the nature of reality. If we knew our own

knowledge processes better, we might not be so surprised by what isand is not possible. In that sense, a high incidence of first-order rev-olutionary breakthroughs could be treated as symptomatic of lowcontrol over second-order knowledge processes.

If scientists were regularly compelled to declare shifts in theirresearch commitments—and not only through a self-selecting, partlydevolved, semi-secret peer review system—then revolutions could bestandardized as periodic election-like events, the outcomes of whichwould provide regular feedback to remove the surprise and disrup-tiveness that characterize revolutions. It would not simply be leftto the vicissitudes of the stock market. Indeed, this sublimation of the revolutionary impulse by the electoral process is one of the greatinnovations of civic republican democracy from which science associally organized inquiry might learn. (I explore this civic republi-can alternative in Chapter 4: cf. Fuller 2000a, Chapter 8.)

However, a potential casualty of this institutional innovation maybe that science itself no longer appears to exhibit striking innovation.

The reason, of course, is that scientists would be regularly invited toconsider altering their inquiries, rather than having to bear theburden of forcing innovation on a system that refuses to changecourse unless its guiding principle has failed on its own terms. Theneed for heroics would be thereby eliminated. Indeed, Kuhn himself distinguished scientific from artistic revolutions precisely on thesegrounds, suggesting that only science—by virtue of its normallymonolithic paradigm structure—had proper revolutions that over-

turned an existing order. In contrast, so-called artistic revolutionshave merely demonstrated the ability of a countercurrent to survivealongside the dominant one (Kuhn 1977, 225–239). Applying this

52 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 53: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 53/56

insight from science, politics, and art to business, the implication isclear: The desire for and recognition of innovation increases asnormal market conditions approach monopoly.

A more sophisticated argument against planned knowledge growthis that even if someone thought he or she could predict or plan sci-entific progress, humans are free to determine whether or not ithappens. This argument also makes some assumptions of its own:

(B1) The people whose behavior is predicted or planned knowthat their behavior has been predicted or planned.

(B2) Those people are in a position to prevent or, in some other

way, divert what others have predicted or planned.

Note that B1 and B2 are independent claims. For example, I mayknow that you have predicted something about me, yet I may be inno position to do anything about it. We see this whenever a phy-sician diagnoses someone with a terminal illness. That possibilitycuts against self-defeating prophecies. Conversely, I may be able toprevent your prediction from coming true without realizing it, per-haps because my behavior may not be as consistent as you (or I)think, for example, because of unforeseen interactions betweengenetic dispositions and behavioral patterns. That cuts against self-fulfilling prophecies.

The advancement of social science research has not tended toincrease the number of self-fulfilling and self-defeating prophecies.This is because people exposed to knowledge claims about themselvestypically cannot relate the concepts used in those claims to anythingthey feel they have power over. Often this is because people do not

know how to reorganize themselves in the relevant ways, either ascollectives (in response to socioeconomic predictions) or as individ-uals (in response to health predictions). But sometimes people simplydo not understand the claims. In that respect, when the knowledgeclaims of social scientists go over the heads of lay people, the latterare behaving rather like the animals and things that are incapable of grasping what natural scientists say about them. Moreover, that isoften a necessary (though not sufficient) condition for those claims

being true—because if people knew what was being asserted abouttheir situations, they might take steps to either enhance or diminishthe truth of those assertions. The classic case of the latter was

What Knowledge Management Has Managed to Do to Knowledge 53

Page 54: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 54/56

Bismarck’s creation of the world’s first social security system forindustrial workers specifically in order to preempt Marx’s predictionthat the proletarian revolution would originate in Germany.

In short, new knowledge can be predicted—but only given a strictboundary (hierarchy?) between the knowledgeable and the ignorant.The difference between socialism and capitalism as policy regimeslies in how the boundary is drawn. If socialism institutionalizes theboundary a priori, capitalism allows it to emerge a posteriori. In thisrespect, the central planner and market speculator are two sides of the same coin. The former knows at the outset that his knowledge issuperior (and has the political might to make it so), whereas the latter

takes risks to discover whether his is. That speculator par excellenceGeorge Soros (1998) has argued that capitalism tolerates a danger-ous level of uncertainty in the name of greed, gamesmanship, and thepursuit of novelty. In contrast, socialism’s strong suit has been itsability to contain this volatile side of humanity, albeit often at thecost of stifling innovation and inhibiting risk-taking altogether(Schumpeter 1950). Knowledge management, then, is about plan-ning for what might be called “tolerable variation” or “sustainablechange” in the firm, state, university, or any other organization.Fuller (2000c) uses the term reversibility, which Karl Popper (1957)originally adapted from thermodynamics. The basic idea is that, asopposed to the popular economic doctrine of the “path dependence”of scientific and technological change, “progress” would be measuredby the increased receptiveness to changing a course of action once itsnegative consequences have outweighed its positive ones for suffi-ciently many over a sufficiently long period.

This principle of knowledge policy reversibility, which Popper

himself dubbed “negative utilitarianism,” brings us to two explicitlyethical objections to deliberate attempts to accelerate the growth of knowledge.

1. The most efficient ways to learn more about reality—especiallysocial reality—always seem to involve violating the integrity of human beings. The horrors of Nazi science come to mind mostreadily. But we could equally include, say, traditional religi-

ous objections to opening corpses for medical and scientificpurposes.

2. Any new discoveries made by a knowledge acceleration schemewould benefit those who made (or funded) the discoveries, at

54 Knowledge Management Foundations

Page 55: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 55/56

the expense of others, which may in turn adversely affect powerrelations in society.

There are substantial historical precedents for both objections, butthey do not imply that the knowledge growth cannot, or even shouldnot, be accelerated. All they imply is that the appropriate backgroundsocial conditions must first be in place, so as to prevent the occur-rence of these adverse ethical consequences. Just as the Great Depres-sion led to the establishment of regulatory bodies (e.g., the U.S.Securities and Exchange Commission) to monitor stock market activ-ities, something similar may be needed once knowledge acceleration

becomes a financially viable practice.So far I have only cleared a space for programs designed to accel-erate the growth of knowledge. I have yet to justify the desirabilityof such programs. In terms of the Realpolitik of capitalism, such aprogram would be no more radical than Frederick Winslow Taylor’soriginal program in “scientific management.” Taylor assumed thatnormal performance is not necessarily the best possible and that thosewho do the work are not necessarily in the best position to judgehow to improve its performance. The point now would be to trans-fer these insights from the industrial to the scientific workplace (cf.Fuller 1993b, 307–311). Research in the sociology and social psy-chology of science generally shows that scientific innovation is mostlydetermined by the organization of the scientific work environment(Shadish and Fuller 1994). This is because even individuals with sci-entific training are subject to the same sorts of biases and incapaci-ties as ordinary reasoners (Faust 1985, Arkes and Hammond 1986).What has been traditionally called “the scientific method” is nothing

more than an abstract characterization of how people and thingsneed to be arranged in order for the whole to be greater than the sumof its parts (Fuller 1993a, Fuller 1994a).

Presumably, then, the rate of scientific knowledge production canbe increased by applying this method to science itself. But in orderto ensure the success of such a knowledge acceleration program,potential managers and investors should bear in mind three things:

1. The confidence and trust of the scientific community need to besecured. Scientists must come to see it as in their own interestto cooperate with knowledge acceleration schemes. This maybe the main negative lesson of Taylorism, which failed because

What Knowledge Management Has Managed to Do to Knowledge 55

Page 56: Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

8/11/2019 Steve Fuller - Knowledge Management Foundations - Chapter 1

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/steve-fuller-knowledge-management-foundations-chapter-1 56/56

it appealed to management by going over the heads of the veryworkers who would be most directly affected by its scientificapproach. A similar skepticism and resistance explains why

scientists have been relatively uncooperative with psychol-ogists and sociologists interested in studying their patterns of work and reasoning. To date, most studies with an explicitinterest in improving scientific performance have been doneon either computer simulations (Fuller 1995) or so-called “ana-logue populations” (e.g., students are given problems thatresemble scientific ones: cf. Tweney et al. 1981). There havealso been many insightful comparative studies of knowledge

production based on ethnographic and historical methods, butthese rarely draw any lessons for how knowledge productionmay be improved (e.g., Pickering 1992). They tend to assumethat what is, is good enough.

2. As the pursuit of scientific knowledge has become more expen-sive and its prospect of improving wealth production moreevident, scientists are being increasingly pressured—by both thepublic and private sectors—to improve their rate of return oninvestment. Thus, it is only a matter of time before the scien-tific community is forced to take seriously the issue of acceler-ating knowledge growth in a way they have not had to in thepast. This undermines the objection raised in point 1.

3. The ultimate significance of a scientific innovation cannot bereduced to the competitive advantage it brings one in themarketplace—at least in the relatively short-term sense in whichone normally speaks of “competitive advantage.” The compet-itive advantage one gains from new knowledge largely depends

on one’s ability to create a demand for it (Drucker 1954). Itprobably has more to do with one’s understanding of themarket than anything truly revolutionary in the innovationitself. In this respect, the possibility of accelerating knowledgegrowth is no less a challenge to the business community thanto the scientific community.

56 Knowledge Management Foundations