Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton...

24
THE WEAK CASE FOR GLOBAL ECONOMIC GOVERNANCE Dani Rodrik 1 Institute for Advanced Study September 2014 The argument for global economic governance is weaker than is usually thought, for two sets of reasons. First, most of the failures global rules aim to fix are domestic in nature and cannot be properly addressed internationally. Second, the autonomy of nation states retains significant normative value. These notes elaborate on these counterarguments. Thinking about global governance: first principles Global problems, it is said, require global solutions. So the search is on for global governance, with policy makers as well as academics proffering visions of new forms of governance that leave the nation state behind. Few of these advocates envisage a truly global version of the nation state; a global legislature or council of ministers is too much of a fantasy. The solutions on offer rely instead on new conceptions of political community, representation, and accountability. The hope is that these innovations can replicate many of constitutional democracy’s essential functions at the global level. The crudest forms of such global governance envisage straightforward delegation of national powers to international technocrats. Perhaps for obvious reasons, economists are particularly enamored of such arrangements. For example, when the European economics 1 This text is prepared as background reading for a presentation at the Princeton International Relations Colloquium, and draws heavily from several of my recent writing: The Globalization Paradox, Norton, 2011, chap. 10; After the Fall: The Future of Global Cooperation (written jointly with Jeff Frieden, Michael Pettis, and Ernesto Zedillo), July 2012; and Who Needs the Nation State? (Roepke Lecture), Economic Geography, 89(1), January 2013.

Transcript of Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton...

Page 1: Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton Universitysee$how$the$principle$of$subsidiarity$applies,$Iwill$make$adistinction$between ... narrow$interests,$the$world$economy$would$slide$into$rampantprotectionism$and

THE  WEAK  CASE  FOR  GLOBAL  ECONOMIC  GOVERNANCE  

Dani  Rodrik1  Institute  for  Advanced  Study  

September  2014    

The  argument  for  global  economic  governance  is  weaker  than  is  usually  thought,  for  two  

sets  of  reasons.  First,  most  of  the  failures  global  rules  aim  to  fix  are  domestic  in  nature  and  

cannot  be  properly  addressed  internationally.  Second,  the  autonomy  of  nation  states  retains  

significant  normative  value.  These  notes  elaborate  on  these  counter-­‐arguments.    

 

Thinking  about  global  governance:  first  principles  

Global  problems,  it  is  said,  require  global  solutions.    So  the  search  is  on  for  global  

governance,  with  policy  makers  as  well  as  academics  proffering  visions  of  new  forms  of  

governance  that  leave  the  nation  state  behind.    Few  of  these  advocates  envisage  a  truly  global  

version  of  the  nation  state;  a  global  legislature  or  council  of  ministers  is  too  much  of  a  fantasy.    

The  solutions  on  offer  rely  instead  on  new  conceptions  of  political  community,  representation,  

and  accountability.    The  hope  is  that  these  innovations  can  replicate  many  of  constitutional  

democracy’s  essential  functions  at  the  global  level.  

The  crudest  forms  of  such  global  governance  envisage  straightforward  delegation  of  

national  powers  to  international  technocrats.    Perhaps  for  obvious  reasons,  economists  are  

particularly  enamored  of  such  arrangements.    For  example,  when  the  European  economics  

                                                                                                                         1  This  text  is  prepared  as  background  reading  for  a  presentation  at  the  Princeton  International  Relations  Colloquium,  and  draws  heavily  from  several  of  my  recent  writing:  The  Globalization  Paradox,  Norton,  2011,  chap.  10;  After  the  Fall:  The  Future  of  Global  Cooperation  (written  jointly  with  Jeff  Frieden,  Michael  Pettis,  and  Ernesto  Zedillo),  July  2012;  and  Who  Needs  the  Nation  State?  (Roepke  Lecture),  Economic  Geography,  89(1),  January  2013.        

Page 2: Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton Universitysee$how$the$principle$of$subsidiarity$applies,$Iwill$make$adistinction$between ... narrow$interests,$the$world$economy$would$slide$into$rampantprotectionism$and

-­‐2-­‐    

network  VoxEU.org  solicited  advice  from  leading  economists  on  how  address  the  frailties  of  the  

global  financial  system  in  the  wake  of  the  2008  crisis,  the  proposed  solutions  often  took  the  

form  of  tighter  international  rules  administered  by  some  kind  of  technocracy:  an  international  

bankruptcy  court,  a  world  financial  organization,  an  international  bank  charter,  or  an  

international  lender  of  last  resort,  and  so  on.2      

Others,  such  as  Anne-­‐Marie  Slaughter,  have  focused  on  transnational  networks  created  

by  regulators,  judges,  and  even  legislators.    These  networks  can  perform  governance  functions  

even  when  they  are  not  constituted  as  inter-­‐governmental  organizations  or  formally  

institutionalized.    Such  networks,  Slaughter  argues,  extend  the  reach  of  formal  governance  

mechanisms,  allow  persuasion  and  information  sharing  across  national  borders,  contribute  to  

the  formation  of  global  norms,  and  can  generate  the  capacity  to  implement  international  norms  

and  agreements  in  nations  where  the  domestic  capacity  to  do  so  is  weak.3      

John  Ruggie  has  emphasized  the  parallel  role  that  global  civil  society  can  play,  by  

enunciating  global  norms  of  corporate  social  responsibility  in  human  rights,  labor  practices,  

health,  anti-­‐corruption,  and  environmental  stewardship.    The  United  Nation’s  Global  Compact,  

which  Ruggie  had  a  big  hand  in  shaping,  embodies  this  agenda.    The  Compact  aims  to  transform  

international  corporations  into  vehicles  for  the  advancement  of  social  and  economic  goals.    The  

goal  is  to  allow  the  private  sector  to  shoulder  some  of  the  functions  that  states  are  finding  

                                                                                                                         2    See  http://voxeu.org/index.php?q=node/2544.    3  Anne-­‐Marie  Slaughter,  A  New  World  Order,  Princeton  University  Press,  Princeton  and  Oxford,  2004.    

Page 3: Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton Universitysee$how$the$principle$of$subsidiarity$applies,$Iwill$make$adistinction$between ... narrow$interests,$the$world$economy$would$slide$into$rampantprotectionism$and

-­‐3-­‐    

increasingly  difficult  to  finance  and  carry  out,  as  in  public  health  and  environmental  protection,  

narrowing  the  governance  gap  between  international  markets  and  national  governments.4          

Joshua  Cohen  and  Charles  Sabel  have  gone  even  further  in  outlining  a  future  in  which  

accountability  takes  a  truly  global  form.    They  envisage  global  deliberative  processes  among  

regulators  which  feed  into  the  development  of  a  global  political  community,  with  people  

coming  to  share  a  common  identity  as  members  of  an  “organized  global  populace.”5    At  the  end  

of  the  day,  true  global  governance  requires  individuals  who  feel  that  they  are  global  citizens.    

The  nation  state  does  not  have  many  defenders.    As  Sen  puts  it,  “there  is  something  of  a  

tyranny  of  ideas  in  seeing  the  political  divisions  of  states  (primarily,  national  states)  as  being,  in  

some  way,  fundamental,  and  in  seeing  them  not  only  as  practical  constraints  to  be  addressed,  

but  as  divisions  of  basic  significance  in  ethics  and  political  philosophy.”6  At  the  same  time  few  

would  deny  that  political  authority  still  remains  vested  for  the  most  part  in  national  

governments.    The  global  government  arrangements  described  above  require  the  transfer  of  

substantial  authority,  and  indeed  sovereignty,  from  national  institutions  to  transnational,  multi-­‐

national,  or  multilateral  entities.    This  is  difficult  because  national  sovereignty  is  zealously  

guarded,  not  least  by  domestic  politicians  who  do  not  want  to  see  their  prerogatives  eroded.    

The  challenge  is  not  going  to  get  easier  in  the  years  ahead.    The  rising  powers  of  the  world  

economy  -­‐-­‐  China,  India,  Brazil  and  other  emerging  market  economies  -­‐-­‐place  if  anything  

greater  importance  on  national  sovereignty  than  the  traditional  great  powers.          

                                                                                                                         4  John  G.  Ruggie,  Reconstituting  the  Global  Public  Domain  -­‐-­‐  Issues,  Actors,  and  Practices,”  European  Journal  of  International  Relations,  vol.  10,  2004,  pp.  499-­‐531.    5  Cohen  and  Sabel,  2005,  p.  796.    6  Amartya  Sen,  The  Idea  of  Justice,  Harvard  University  Press,  Cambridge,  MA,  2009,  p.  143.    

Page 4: Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton Universitysee$how$the$principle$of$subsidiarity$applies,$Iwill$make$adistinction$between ... narrow$interests,$the$world$economy$would$slide$into$rampantprotectionism$and

-­‐4-­‐    

But  there  is  more  to  it  than  the  self-­‐interest  of  national  politicians.  Arguments  on  behalf  

of  new  forms  of  global  governance—whether  of  the  delegation,  network,  or  corporate  social  

responsibility  type—raise  troubling  questions.    To  whom  are  these  mechanisms  supposed  to  be  

accountable?    From  where  do  these  global  clubs  of  regulators,  international  non-­‐governmental  

organizations,  or  large  firms  get  their  mandates?    Who  empowers  and  polices  them?    What  

ensures  that  the  voice  and  interests  of  those  who  are  less  globally  networked  are  also  heard?    

In  a  nation  state,  the  electorate  is  the  ultimate  source  of  political  mandates  and  elections  the  

ultimate  vehicle  for  accountability.    If  you  do  not  respond  to  your  constituencies’  expectations  

and  aspirations,  you  are  voted  out.    The  democratic  state  is  tried  and  tested.    Its  global  

counterpart  sounds  too  experimental  and  utopian.7  

Discussions  in  the  G20,  World  Trade  Organization,  and  other  multilateral  fora  often  

proceed  as  if  the  correct  remedy  for  our  economic  problems  is  always  more  global  cooperation  

–  more  rules,  more  harmonization,  more  discipline  on  national  policies.  In  view  of  the  practical  

and  substantive  challenges  that  global  governance  faces,  we  need  a  more  calibrated  approach  

that  focuses  on  areas  where  the  need  for  building  global  institutions  is  greatest,  while  not  

wasting  political  or  organizational  capital  in  areas  where  the  returns  are  small.        

Going  back  to  basics,  the  principle  of  “subsidiarity”  provides  the  right  way  of  thinking  

about  issues  of  global  governance.    It  tells  us  which  kinds  of  policies  should  be  coordinated  or  

                                                                                                                         7  For  example,  it  is  interesting  that  Slaughter’s  most  telling  illustrations  of  networked  global  governance  come  from  the  area  of  financial  markets.    She  points  to  the  International  Organization  of  Securities  Commissions  (IOSCO)  and  the  Basel  Committee  on  Banking  Supervision  as  networks  of  regulators  that  set  global  rules  for  financial  markets.    Most  economists  would  say,  however,  that  these  institutions  have  failed  to  deliver  an  adequate  set  of  rules.  Many  would  also  argue  that  they  have  been  too  dominated  by  financial  industry  interests  and  that  the  Basle  Committee’s  capital  adequacy  rules  have  in  fact  played  a  contributing  role  in  both  the  Asian  financial  crisis  of  1997-­‐98  and  the  global  financial  crisis  of  2008-­‐2009.  

 

Page 5: Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton Universitysee$how$the$principle$of$subsidiarity$applies,$Iwill$make$adistinction$between ... narrow$interests,$the$world$economy$would$slide$into$rampantprotectionism$and

-­‐5-­‐    

harmonized  globally  and  which  should  be  left  largely  to  domestic  decision-­‐making.    The  

principle  demarcates  areas  where  we  need  extensive  global  governance  and  areas  where  only  a  

thin  layer  of  global  rules  is  adequate.    To  use  a  concrete  illustration,  we  can  think  of  this  as  a  

choice  between  a  WTO-­‐type  (thick)  global  regime  versus  GATT-­‐type  (thin)  regime.  

The  premise  in  what  follows  is  that  any  practical  mechanism  of  global  governance  must  

rely  on  the  willingness  of  national  governments  to  submit  to  international  discipline.    Nation  

states,  the  primary  decision-­‐making  units  in  the  world  economy,  must  be  provided  with  a  

reason  as  to  why  it  is  in  their  interest  to  cooperate  and  coordinate,  rather  than  go  at  it  alone.    

Transnational  altruism  is  not  a  reliable  pillar  on  which  to  construct  global  governance.          

To  see  how  the  principle  of  subsidiarity  applies,  I  will  make  a  distinction  between  four  

different  variants  in  which  economic  policies  come.    I  start  from  the  two  extremes,  “purely  

domestic  policies”  and  “global  commons  policies,”  which  are  the  easiest  to  describe  and  have  

the  most  direct  implications  for  global  governance.  Then  I  turn  to  the  trickier  intermediate  

cases,  which  I  call  “beggar-­‐thy-­‐neighbor”  and  “beggar-­‐thyself”  policies.    

 

(a) Purely  domestic  policies  

At  one  extreme  are  domestic  policies  that  create  no  (or  very  few)  direct  spillovers  across  

national  borders.    Examples  are  educational  policies,  highway  safety  standards,  and  urban  

zoning.    Since  the  object  of  regulation  in  both  instances  is  a  non-­‐traded  service  (human  capital,  

local  transportation,  and  real  estate,  respectively),  such  policies  do  not  affect  economic  

interests  of  other  countries,  at  least  directly.    They  therefore  require  no  international  

Page 6: Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton Universitysee$how$the$principle$of$subsidiarity$applies,$Iwill$make$adistinction$between ... narrow$interests,$the$world$economy$would$slide$into$rampantprotectionism$and

-­‐6-­‐    

agreement  and  can  be  safely  left  to  domestic  policymakers.  This  seems  to  be  widely  accepted,  

as  there  is  little  clamor  for  internationalization  of  regulation  in  such  areas.          

Of  course,  in  practice  regulations  in  non-­‐traded  markets  influence  the  rest  of  the  

economy  and  therefore  have  implications  for  other  nations  as  well.  Highway  safety  standards  

for  example  can  affect  the  demand  for  oil  and  its  price  on  world  markets.    Nothing  is  purely  

domestic  when  general  equilibrium  implications  are  taken  into  account.    But  it  is  understood  or  

presumed  that  such  effects  are  indirect,  uncertain,  and  that  the  intent  of  policies  is  not  to  

discriminate  against  foreign  economic  interests.    

   

(b) Global  commons  policies  

At  the  other  end  are  policies  that  relate  to  “global  commons,”  such  as  global  climate.  

The  characteristic  of  a  global  commons  is  that  the  outcome  for  each  nation  is  determined  not  

by  domestic  policies  per  se,  but  by  (the  sum  total  of)  all  countries’  policies.    The  classic  case  is  

greenhouse  gas  emissions.    Global  climate  is  a  pure  global  public  good,  in  that  no  country  can  

be  excluded  from  benefiting  from  the  control  of  greenhouse  gases  in  other  countries,  nor  can  a  

country  keep  the  benefits  of  such  policies  to  itself.              

There  is  a  very  strong  case  for  establishing  global  rules  in  these  policy  domains,  since  it  

is  in  the  interest  of  each  country,  left  to  its  own  devices,  to  neglect  its  share  of  the  upkeep  of  

the  global  commons.    Absent  a  binding  agreement,  the  rational  strategy  for  any  small  country  is  

to  free  ride  on  other  countries’  emissions  policies.    Since  each  country  reasons  the  same  way,  

the  decentralized  outcome  is  one  where  no  country  invests  in  costly  climate  control  policies.    

Page 7: Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton Universitysee$how$the$principle$of$subsidiarity$applies,$Iwill$make$adistinction$between ... narrow$interests,$the$world$economy$would$slide$into$rampantprotectionism$and

-­‐7-­‐    

Hence  failure  to  reach  global  agreement  would  condemn  all  to  a  collective  disaster.8    That  is  

why  there  is  no  alternative  to  global  governance  in  the  area  of  climate  change,  as  difficult  as  it  

may  be  to  achieve.        

True  global  public  goods  are  rare.    Even  though  the  global  economy  is  often  portrayed  in  

a  similar  light,  in  fact  few  economic  policies  qualify  as  “global  commons  policies”  in  the  sense  

sketched  out  above.    We  commonly  hear  statements  to  the  effect  that  “a  growing,  open  world  

economy  is  a  global  public  good.”  The  idea  seems  to  be  that  as  each  nation  pursues  its  own  

narrow  interests,  the  world  economy  would  slide  into  rampant  protectionism  and  everyone  

would  lose  as  a  result.                  

But  this  logic  relies  on  a  false  analogy  of  the  global  economy  as  a  global  commons.    

What  makes  global  warming  a  global  rather  than  national  problem,  requiring  global  

cooperation,  is  that  the  globe  has  a  single  climate  system.  It  makes  no  difference  where  the  

carbon  is  emitted.    One  might  say  that  all  our  economies  are  similarly  intertwined,  and  no  

doubt  that  would  be  true  to  an  important  extent.  But  in  the  case  of  global  warming,  domestic  

restrictions  on  carbon  emissions  provide  no  or  little  benefit  at  home.  By  contrast,  good  

economic  policies  –including  openness  -­‐-­‐  benefit  the  home  economy  first  and  foremost.    The  

economic  fortunes  of  individual  nations  are  determined  largely  by  what  happens  at  home  

rather  than  abroad.    If  open  economy  policies  are  desirable  it’s  because  openness  is  in  a  

nation’s  own  self-­‐interest—not  because  it  helps  others.    Openness  and  other  good  policies  that  

contribute  to  global  economic  stability  rely  on  self-­‐interest,  not  on  global  spirit.      

                                                                                                                         8  Large  countries  have  some  incentive  to  control  emissions,  to  the  extent  that  their  contribution  to  the  global  stock  of  greenhouse  is  non-­‐trivial.    

Page 8: Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton Universitysee$how$the$principle$of$subsidiarity$applies,$Iwill$make$adistinction$between ... narrow$interests,$the$world$economy$would$slide$into$rampantprotectionism$and

-­‐8-­‐    

Put  differently,  the  desirability  of  free  trade  and  appropriate  financial  regulations  at  the  

national  level  is  largely  independent  of  policies  in  other  countries.    If  other  countries  also  follow  

“good”  policies,  all  the  better  for  us.    But  differently  from  climate  change,  there  is  no  logic  that  

suggests  countries  will  systematically  follow  policies  that  are  harmful  to  the  world  economy.  In  

fact,  quite  to  the  contrary.      

However,  there  are  two  caveats.    First,  sometimes  domestic  economic  advantage  comes  

at  the  expense  of  other  nations.    Second,  there  is  no  guarantee  that  countries  will  do  what  is  

economically  right  for  themselves,  for  reasons  of  domestic  politics  gone  awry  or  sheer  

ignorance.    These  exceptions  give  us  two  intermediate  cases  between  purely  domestic  policies  

and  global  commons,  which  we  analyze  under  the  headings  of  “beggar-­‐thy-­‐neighbor  policies”  

and  “beggar-­‐thyself  policies.”      

 

(c) Beggar-­‐thy-­‐neighbor  policies  

These  are  policies  whereby  a  nation  derives  an  economic  benefit  at  the  expense  of  

other  nations.  The  purest  illustration  occurs  when  a  dominant  supplier  of  a  natural  resource,  

such  as  oil,  restricts  supply  on  world  markets  so  as  to  drive  up  world  prices.    In  this  instance  the  

exporter’s  gain  is  the  rest  of  the  world’s  loss.    Plus  there  is  an  additional  global  deadweight  loss  

due  to  the  supply  restriction.    A  similar  mechanism  operates  with  the  so-­‐called  “optimum  

tariff,"  whereby  a  large  country  manipulates  its  terms  of  trade  by  placing  tariffs  on  its  imports.  

There  is  a  clear  case  in  these  instances  for  global  coordination  taking  the  form  of  limiting  or  

prohibiting  the  use  of  such  policies.            

Page 9: Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton Universitysee$how$the$principle$of$subsidiarity$applies,$Iwill$make$adistinction$between ... narrow$interests,$the$world$economy$would$slide$into$rampantprotectionism$and

-­‐9-­‐    

In  some  instances,  beggar-­‐thy-­‐neighbor  effects  may  be  intermingled  with  other,  

domestic  motives.    Consider  for  example  currency  undervaluation,  which  is  often  treated  as  a  

mercantilist  policy  aimed  at  extracting  economic  advantage  from  other  countries.    China’s  

motive  in  pursuing  such  a  policy  seems  to  have  been  primarily  to  accelerate  its  economic  

growth  by  promoting  structural  change  from  low-­‐  to  high-­‐productivity  areas.    To  the  extent  that  

this  policy  generates  an  external  surplus,  it  requires  that  other  nations  be  willing  to  bear  the  

counterpart  deficits.    But  in  what  sense  does  this  impart  a  harm  on  other  countries?    In  the  case  

of  China’s  currency  policies,  for  example,  it  was  often  asserted  prior  to  the  global  financial  crisis  

that  there  was  a  willing  partner  in  the  United  States.    America’s  trade  deficit  allowed  it  to  

borrow  and  finance  its  consumption  and  credit  boom  on  the  cheap,  while  China  subsidized  its  

exports  through  a  cheap  renminbi.    There  were  some  complaints  in  the  U.S.  from  those  

adversely  affected  by  China’s  exports.    But  these  complaints  were  drowned  by  those  who  

argued  the  relationship  was  mutually  beneficial,  even  if  of  doubtful  sustainability.  

Global  imbalances  have  become  a  much  more  serious  issue  in  the  aftermath  of  the  

financial  crisis.  This  is  partly  because  there  is  a  sense  that  large  current  account  surpluses  such  

as  those  of  China  have  contributed  to  financial  fragility  in  the  past.    It  is  also  due  to  the  spike  in  

unemployment  in  the  U.S.  and  the  adjustment  difficulties  in  the  Euro  zone.  When  the  economy  

looks  like  it  is  caught  in  a  situation  of  inadequate  aggregate  demand,  external  deficits  

contribute  to  the  problem  and  aggravate  unemployment.    Paul  Krugman  famously  wrote  in  

2009  that  “we’re  looking  at  1.4  million  U.S.  jobs  lost  due  to  Chinese  mercantilism.”9  Whether  

there  is  such  a  direct  link  or  not,  currency  policies  that  export  unemployment  and  financial  

                                                                                                                         9  Krugman  2009,  http://krugman.blogs.nytimes.com/2009/12/31/macroeconomic-­‐effects-­‐of-­‐chinese-­‐mercantilism/.  

Page 10: Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton Universitysee$how$the$principle$of$subsidiarity$applies,$Iwill$make$adistinction$between ... narrow$interests,$the$world$economy$would$slide$into$rampantprotectionism$and

-­‐10-­‐    

instability  increasingly  look  like  beggar-­‐thy-­‐neighbor  policies.  They  are  an  area  where  global  

cooperation  and  coordination  becomes  necessary,  at  least  among  systemically  large  countries.      

Rules  with  regard  to  bank  secrecy  or  the  taxation  of  capital  present  other  instances  

where  there  is  a  mix  of  considerations.    A  jurisdiction  that  is  set  up  as  a  pure  tax  haven,  with  the  

sole  objective  of  attracting  deposits  and  capital  from  abroad  can  be  said  to  gain  economic  

advantage  at  the  expense  of  other  nations  and  to  follow  beggar-­‐thy-­‐neighbor  policies.    But  

what  if  a  nation  views  low  taxes  or  strict  secrecy  as  “correct”  policies  to  follow  for  domestic  

reasons,  regardless  of  consequences  for  cross-­‐border  flows  of  money?  Then,  even  if  such  

policies  have  adverse  effects  on  others,  the  case  for  global  coordination  is  significantly  

weakened.    Disciplining  low-­‐tax  jurisdictions  under  such  considerations  would  require  an  

account  how  a  global  economic  loss  is  created  in  the  absence  of  coordination.  

Analytically,  it  helps  to  distinguish  between  the  level  of  a  policy  that  is  domestically  

optimal  absent  cross-­‐border  interactions  and  the  increment  in  that  policy  that  becomes  

desirable  once  those  interactions  are  taken  into  account.    There  should  be  a  much  higher  

threshold  for  disciplining  the  first  component.  Take  tariffs  for  example.    Suppose  t  is  the  

domestically  second-­‐best  level  of  taxation  in  an  economy  (due  to,  say,  revenue  reasons),  

holding  the  external  terms  of  trade  constant.    Assume  that  the  optimal  level  of  the  tariff  

becomes  t’  =  t  +  dt  once  external  terms-­‐of-­‐trade  effects  are  taken  into  account.    The  dt  

component  of  the  tariff  is  the  pure  beggar-­‐thy-­‐neighbor  component,  which  ought  to  be  

regulated  internationally.    There  is  much  less  ground  for  international  discipline  on  t,  unless  

other  countries  can  demonstrate  significant  negative  spillovers  which  more  than  offset  the  

benefits  to  the  home  country.    

Page 11: Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton Universitysee$how$the$principle$of$subsidiarity$applies,$Iwill$make$adistinction$between ... narrow$interests,$the$world$economy$would$slide$into$rampantprotectionism$and

-­‐11-­‐    

           

(d) Beggar-­‐thyself  policies  

Beggar-­‐thy-­‐neighbor  policies  have  to  be  distinguished  from  what  we  may  call  “beggar  

thyself”  policies.    The  latter  are  policies  whose  economic  costs  are  borne  primarily  at  home,  

even  though  they  may  produce  effects  on  others.    Examples  are  agricultural  subsidies,  bans  on  

genetically  modified  organisms,  or  lax  financial  regulation.    In  each  instance,  there  may  be  costs  

to  other  countries.    But  these  policies  are  deployed  not  to  extract  advantages  from  other  

nations,  but  because  other  competing  policy  objectives  at  home  –  such  as  distributional,  

administrative,  or  public-­‐health  concerns  -­‐-­‐  dominate  the  economic  motives.    

Consider  for  example  agricultural  subsidies  in  Europe.    Economists  generally  agree  that  

these  are  inefficient  and  that  the  benefits  to  European  farmers  come  at  large  costs  to  everyone  

else.    Economists  also  agree  that  the  bulk  of  those  costs  are  paid  by  European  residents,  in  the  

form  of  high  prices,  high  taxes,  or  both.    The  subsidies  do  produce  spillovers  to  other  nations.    

Agricultural  producers  around  the  world  get  hurt,  while  consumers  of  agriculture  benefit.      

Even  though  the  presence  of  such  spillovers  is  often  taken  to  establish  a  case  for  global  

governance  over  these  policies  –  as  in  the  Doha  Round  of  trade  negotiations  –  it  is  not  clear  

why  that  should  be  so.    There  can  be  two  reasons  for  the  pursuit  of  beggar-­‐thyself  policies:  

there  can  be  compensating  non-­‐economic  benefits,  or  the  government  in  question  can  be  

simply  making  a  mistake.    Consider  each  of  these  two  possibilities  in  turn.  

Say  that  European  governments  have  decided  the  economic  costs  of  agricultural  

subsidies  are  worth  paying  for  as  the  price  for  sustaining  healthy  rural  farming  communities.    

Even  though  the  policy  is  economically  inefficient,  in  this  case  it  serves  a  broader  social  purpose  

Page 12: Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton Universitysee$how$the$principle$of$subsidiarity$applies,$Iwill$make$adistinction$between ... narrow$interests,$the$world$economy$would$slide$into$rampantprotectionism$and

-­‐12-­‐    

and  therefore  is  optimal,  from  Europe’s  own  perspective.    A  direct  implication  is  that  any  global  

effort  to  reduce  or  eliminate  these  subsidies  would  leave  Europe  worse  off.    Even  if  such  an  

attempt  were  to  produce  net  economic  benefits  to  the  rest  of  the  world,  it  would  come  at  the  

expense  of  socio-­‐economic  losses  for  Europe.  Thus  there  would  seem  to  be  a  very  weak  case  

for  global  discipline.    After  all,  it  should  not  be  up  to  the  “global  community”  to  tell  individual  

nations  how  they  ought  to  weight  competing  goals.      

This  doesn’t  preclude  a  global  conversation  over  the  nature  of  diverse  benefits  and  

harms  to  the  parties.  Such  conversations  can  be  helpful  in  reducing  international  

misunderstanding  about  the  objective  of  policies,  and  sometime  in  establishing  new  behavioral  

norms.  They  can  also  enable  some  Coasian  bargains  to  be  struck  if  the  losses  incurred  by  other  

nations  do  exceed  domestic  benefits.  But  global  restrains  on  domestic  policy  space  on  account  

of  the  spillovers  per  se  would  seem  inappropriate  since  there  is  no  prima  facie  reason  why  the  

economic  interests  of  other  nations  ought  to  take  precedence  over  the  social-­‐economic  

benefits  to  the  home  nation.  Once  again,  it  is  unclear  whether  the  net  benefit  to  the  world  from  

global  discipline  is  positive.                      

The  case  against  global  regulation  becomes  even  stronger  when  the  spillovers  to  the  

rest  of  the  world  from  the  economically  “harmful”  policy  are,  on  balance,  positive.    This  may  

seem  unlikely,  but  note  that  it  is  indeed  the  case  with  export  subsidies  in  agriculture.    Economic  

analysis  suggests  that  such  subsidies  improve  the  terms  of  trade  of  the  rest  of  the  world  and  is  

therefore  a  “gift”  from  a  country  to  its  trade  partners.    Some  countries  or  groups  are  harmed,  

of  course.  But  it  is  difficult  to  see  why  this  should  be  a  reason  for  restraining  home  country  

policies.    Consider  an  analogous  situation  where  a  country  decides,  unilaterally,  to  reduce  its  

Page 13: Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton Universitysee$how$the$principle$of$subsidiarity$applies,$Iwill$make$adistinction$between ... narrow$interests,$the$world$economy$would$slide$into$rampantprotectionism$and

-­‐13-­‐    

import  tariffs.    Similar  to  the  export  subsidy  case,  some  other  nations  –  those  who  import  

similar  things  -­‐-­‐  may  well  get  hurt.  Yet  economists,  reasonably,  would  never  contemplate  

enacting  global  rules  that  restrict  a  country’s  ability  to  liberalize  its  trade!              

Let’s  now  go  to  the  second  case  where  the  country  in  question  has  actually  made  a  

“mistake.”    So  presume  that  agricultural  subsidies  are  an  unambiguously  bad  idea,  even  when  

all  other  potential  non-­‐economic  benefits  are  taken  into  account.    Yet  somehow  the  country’s  

political  system  has  failed,  and  delivers  a  bad  policy.    Indeed,  there  is  no  guarantee  that  

domestic  policies  accurately  reflect  societal  demands.  Policy  makers  may  be  ignorant  or  

captured.    Even  democracies  are  frequently  taken  hostage  by  special  interests.    

In  principle,  both  domestic  and  foreign  welfare  would  be  enhanced  if  one  could  design  

global  rules  that  prevent  such  mistaken  policies  from  being  adopted.    The  trouble  is  that  similar  

policy  failures  can  take  place  at  the  international  level  as  well.    Most  economists  would  agree  

that  banking  interests  and  pharmaceutical  companies  have  exerted  too  much  influence  in  

setting  Basle  capital  adequacy  rules  and  WTO  intellectual  property  rules,  respectively.    

Moreover,  it  is  not  easy  to  distinguish  in  practice  domestic  policy  failures  from  non-­‐economic  

considerations.    Technocratic  governance  at  the  global  level  may  fail  to  reflect  adequately  the  

kind  of  non-­‐efficiency  objectives  that  play  a  role  in  democracies,  as  in  the  agricultural  subsidy  

context  for  example.  In  other  words,  technocrats  (trade  lawyers,  economists,  financial  

specialists)  may  substitute  their  own  normative  judgments  for  those  of  democratic  polities.    

As  Keohane,  Macedo  and  Moravcsik  point  out,  there  are  various  ways  in  which  global  

rules  can  enhance  democracy  -­‐-­‐    a  process  that  they  call  “democracy  enhancing  

multilateralism.”  Democracies  have  various  mechanisms  for  restricting  the  autonomy  or  the  

Page 14: Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton Universitysee$how$the$principle$of$subsidiarity$applies,$Iwill$make$adistinction$between ... narrow$interests,$the$world$economy$would$slide$into$rampantprotectionism$and

-­‐14-­‐    

policy  space  of  decision  makers.  For  example,  democratically  elected  parliaments  often  

delegate  power  to  independent  or  quasi-­‐independent  autonomous  bodies.  Central  banks  are  

often  independent  and  there  are  various  other  kinds  of  checks  and  balances  in  constitutional  

democracies.  Similarly,  global  rules  can  make  it  easier  for  national  democracies  to  attain  the  

goals  that  they  pursue  even  if  they  entail  some  restrictions  in  terms  of  autonomy.  Keohane  at  

al.  discuss  three  specific  mechanisms:  global  rules  can  enhance  democracy  by  offsetting  

factions,  protecting  minority  rights,  or  by  enhancing  the  quality  of  democratic  deliberation.  

However,  just  because  globalization  can  enhance  democracy  does  not  mean  that  it  

always  does  so.  In  fact  there  are  many  ways  in  which  global  governance  works  in  quite  the  

opposite  way  from  that  described  by  Keohane  et  al.  Anti-­‐dumping  rules,  for  example,  augment  

protectionist  interests.  Rules  on  intellectual  property  rights  and  copyrights  have  privileged  

pharmaceuticals  companies  and  Disney  Company  against  the  general  interest.  Similarly,  there  

are  many  ways  in  which  globalization  actually  harms  rather  than  enhances  the  quality  of  

democratic  deliberation.  For  example,  preferential  or  multilateral  trade  agreements  are  often  

simply  voted  up  or  down  in  national  parliaments  with  little  discussion,  simply  because  they  are  

international  agreements.  Globalization-­‐enhancing  global  rules  and  democracy-­‐enhancing  

global  rules  may  have  some  overlap;  but  they  are  not  one  and  the  same  thing.  

So  it  is  problematic  as  a  general  rule  to  try  to  fix  domestic  policy  failures  by  setting  

global  rules  that  define  what  acceptable  policies  are.    But  we  can  envisage  another  type  of  

global  discipline  which  acts  directly  on  the  relevant  margin.    I  have  in  mind  procedural  

requirements  designed  to  enhance  the  quality  of  domestic  policy  making.    Global  disciplines  

pertaining  to  transparency,  broad  representation,  accountability,  and  use  of  

Page 15: Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton Universitysee$how$the$principle$of$subsidiarity$applies,$Iwill$make$adistinction$between ... narrow$interests,$the$world$economy$would$slide$into$rampantprotectionism$and

-­‐15-­‐    

scientific/economic  evidence  in  domestic  proceedings  –  without  constraining  the  end  result  –  

are  examples  of  such  requirements.  

Disciplines  of  this  type  are  already  in  use  in  the  WTO  to  some  extent.    The  Agreements  

on  Safeguards  and  Anti-­‐Dumping  specify  domestic  procedures  that  need  to  be  followed  when  a  

government  contemplates  restricting  imports  from  trade  partners.    Similarly  the  SPS  Agreement  

explicitly  requires  the  use  of  scientific  evidence  when  health  concerns  are  at  issue.    Procedural  

rules  of  this  kind  can  be  used  much  more  extensively  and  to  greater  effect  to  enhance  the  

quality  of  domestic  decision-­‐making.    For  example,  anti-­‐dumping  rules  can  be  improved  by  

requiring  that  consumer  and  producer  interests  that  would  be  adversely  affected  by  the  

imposition  of  import  duties  take  part  in  domestic  proceedings.    Subsidy  rules  can  be  improved  

by  requiring  economic  cost-­‐benefit  analyses.  

 

Summing  up  on  global  governance    

To  summarize,  different  types  of  policies  call  for  different  responses  at  the  global  level.    

The  conceptual  framework  laid  out  here  suggests  the  following  typology  of  optimal  global  

regimes:  

A.   Purely  domestic  policies  require  no  global  action.  

B.     Global  commons  require  globally  harmonized  policy  regimes.    (Example:  a  global  

set  of  rules  that  allocate  emission  permits.)      

C.   Beggar-­‐thy-­‐neighbor  policies  require  the  regulation  of  cross-­‐border  spillovers.    

(Examples:  tariff  bindings  and  restrictions  on  maximum  size  of  current  account  

deficits/surpluses.)  

Page 16: Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton Universitysee$how$the$principle$of$subsidiarity$applies,$Iwill$make$adistinction$between ... narrow$interests,$the$world$economy$would$slide$into$rampantprotectionism$and

-­‐16-­‐    

D.   Beggar-­‐thyself  policies  require  global  regimes  aimed  at  enhancing  quality  of  

domestic  decision-­‐making.    (Examples:  rules  pertaining  to  transparency,  

representativeness,  accountability,  and  use  of  scientific/economic  evidence  in  domestic  

proceedings.)  

Different  types  of  policies  call  for  different  responses  at  the  global  level.    At  present,  too  

much  global  political  capital  is  wasted  on  harmonizing  beggar-­‐thyself  policies  (particularly  in  the  

areas  of  trade  and  financial  regulation),  and  not  enough  on  beggar-­‐thy-­‐neighbor  policies  (such  

as  macroeconomic  imbalances).    Over-­‐ambitious  and  misdirected  efforts  at  global  governance  

will  not  serve  us  well  at  a  time  when  global  cooperation  is  bound  to  remain  in  limited  supply.    

The  principles  above  leave  plenty  of  room  for  international  cooperation  over  economic  

matters.    But  they  do  presume  a  major  difference,  when  compared  to  other  areas  like  climate  

change,  in  the  degree  of  international  cooperation  and  coordination  needed  to  make  the  global  

system  work.    In  the  case  of  global  warming  self-­‐interest  pushes  nations  to  ignore  the  risks  of  

climate  change,  with  an  occasional  spur  towards  environmentally  responsible  policies  when  a  

country  is  too  large  to  overlook  its  own  impact  on  the  accumulation  of  greenhouse  gases.    In  

the  global  economy  self-­‐interest  pushes  nations  towards  openness,  with  an  occasional  

temptation  towards  beggar-­‐thy-­‐neighbor  policies  when  a  large  country  possesses  market  

power.10    A  healthy  global  regime  has  to  rely  on  international  cooperation  in  the  former  case;  it  

has  to  rely  on  good  policies  geared  towards  the  domestic  economy  in  the  latter.  

                                                                                                                         10 In  the  language  of  economics,  the  global  climate  is  a  “pure”  public  good  whereas  an  open  economy  is  a  private  good,  from  the  standpoint  of  individual  nations,  with  some  external  effects  on  others.    

Page 17: Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton Universitysee$how$the$principle$of$subsidiarity$applies,$Iwill$make$adistinction$between ... narrow$interests,$the$world$economy$would$slide$into$rampantprotectionism$and

-­‐17-­‐    

Let  me  go  one  step  further.  I  would  claim  that  virtually  none  of  our  global  economic  

problems  today  arise  from  the  absence  of  international  discipline  per  se.  Global  poverty  and  

low  growth,  financial  instability  and  crises,  trade  protectionism  –  these  are  all  failures  that  

derive  from  the  pursuit  of  policies  that  harm  the  home  economy  first  and  foremost.  Global  

rules  that  are  meant  to  prevent  doing  damage  to  others’  economies  can  make  at  best  little  

contribution  to  fixing  these  failures.  And  they  can  do  real  harm  when  they  preclude  the  

achievement  of  legitimate  domestic  goals.            

 

A  normative  case  for  the  nation  state  

Historically,  the  nation  state  has  been  closely  associated  with  economic,  social,  and  

political  progress.    It  curbed  internecine  violence,  expanded  networks  of  solidarity  beyond  local  

communities,  spurred  mass  markets  and  industrialization,  enabled  the  mobilization  of  human  

and  financial  resources,  and  fostered  the  spread  of  representative  political  institutions  (Tilly  

1992,  Gellner  1983,  Pinker  2011,  Kedourie  1993  [1960],  Anderson  2006).    Civil  wars  and  

economic  decline  are  the  usual  fate  of  today’s  “failed  states.”  For  residents  of  stable  and  

prosperous  countries,  it  is  easy  to  overlook  the  role  that  the  construction  of  the  nation  state  

played  in  overcoming  such  challenges.    The  nation  state’s  fall  from  intellectual  grace  is  in  part  a  

consequence  of  its  achievements.  

But  has  the  nation  state,  as  a  territorially  confined  political  entity,  truly  become  a  

hindrance  to  the  achievement  of  desirable  economic  and  social  outcomes  in  view  of  the  

globalization  revolution?    Or  does  the  nation  state  remain  indispensable  to  the  achievement  of  

Page 18: Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton Universitysee$how$the$principle$of$subsidiarity$applies,$Iwill$make$adistinction$between ... narrow$interests,$the$world$economy$would$slide$into$rampantprotectionism$and

-­‐18-­‐    

those  goals?  In  other  words,  is  it  possible  to  construct  a  more  principled  defense  of  the  nation-­‐

state,  one  that  goes  beyond  stating  that  it  exists  and  that  it  hasn’t  withered  away?    

Let  me  clarify  my  terminology.    The  nation  state  evokes  connotations  of  nationalism.    

The  emphasis  in  my  discussion  is  not  on  the  “nation”  or  “nationalism”  part  but  on  the  “state”  

part.    In  particular,  I  am  interested  in  the  state  as  a  spatially  demarcated  jurisdictional  entity.    

From  this  perspective,  I  view  the  nation  as  a  consequence  of  a  state,  rather  than  the  other  way  

around.  As  Abbé  Sieyès,  one  of  the  theorists  of  the  French  revolution,  put  it:  “What  is  a  nation?  

A  body  of  associates  living  under  one  common  law  and  represented  by  the  same  legislature”  

(quoted  in  Kedourie  1993,  7).    I  am  not  concerned  with  debates  over  what  a  nation  is,  whether  

each  nation  should  have  its  own  state,  or  how  many  states  there  ought  to  be.  

Instead,  I  wish  to  develop  a  substantive  argument  for  why  robust  nation  states  are  

actually  beneficial,  especially  to  the  world  economy.    I  want  to  show  that  the  multiplicity  of  

nation  states  adds  rather  than  subtracts  value.      

My  starting  point  is  that  markets  require  rules,  and  that  global  markets  would  require  

global  rules.    A  truly  borderless  global  economy,  one  in  which  economic  activity  is  fully  

unmoored  from  its  national  base,  would  necessitate  transnational  rule-­‐making  institutions  that  

match  the  global  scale  and  scope  of  markets.  But  this  would  not  be  desirable,  even  if  it  were  

feasible.    Market-­‐supporting  rules  are  non-­‐unique.  Experimentation  and  competition  among  

diverse  institutional  arrangements  therefore  remain  desirable.  Moreover,  communities  differ  in  

their  needs  and  preferences  with  regard  to  institutional  forms.  And  geography  continues  to  

limit  the  convergence  in  these  needs  and  preferences.  

Page 19: Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton Universitysee$how$the$principle$of$subsidiarity$applies,$Iwill$make$adistinction$between ... narrow$interests,$the$world$economy$would$slide$into$rampantprotectionism$and

-­‐19-­‐    

Consider  how  financial  markets  should  be  regulated.    There  are  many  choices  to  be  

made.    Should  commercial  banking  be  separated  from  investment  banking?  Should  there  be  a  

limit  on  size  of  banks?  Should  there  be  deposit  insurance,  and  if  so,  what  should  it  cover?  

Should  banks  be  allowed  to  trade  on  their  own  account?  How  much  information  should  they  

reveal  about  their  trades?  Should  executives’  compensation  be  set  by  directors,  with  no  

regulatory  controls?  What  should  the  capital  and  liquidity  requirements  be?    Should  all  

derivative  contracts  be  traded  on  exchanges?  What  should  be  the  role  of  credit-­‐rating  

agencies?  And  so  on.        

  A  central  trade-­‐off  here  is  between  financial  innovation  and  financial  stability.    A  light  

approach  to  regulation  will  maximize  the  scope  for  financial  innovation  (the  development  of  

new  financial  products),  but  at  the  cost  of  increasing  the  likelihood  of  financial  crises  and  

crashes.  Strong  regulation  will  reduce  the  incidence  and  costs  of  crises,  but  potentially  at  the  

cost  of  raising  the  cost  of  finance  and  excluding  many  from  its  benefits.  There  is  no  single  

optimal  point  along  this  trade-­‐off.  Requiring  that  communities  whose  preferences  over  the  

innovation-­‐stability  continuum  vary  all  settle  on  the  same  solution  might  have  the  virtue  that  it  

reduces  transaction  costs  in  finance.  But  it  would  come  at  the  cost  of  imposing  arrangements  

that  are  out  of  sync  with  local  preferences.  That  is  in  fact  the  conundrum  that  financial  

regulation  faces  at  the  moment,  with  banks  pushing  for  common  global  rules  and  domestic  

legislatures  and  policy  makers  resisting.        

  Here  is  another  example  from  food  regulation.    In  a  controversial  1998  case,  the  World  

Trade  Organization  sided  with  the  United  States  in  ruling  that  the  European  Union  ban  on  beef  

reared  on  certain  growth  hormones  violated  the  Agreement  on  Sanitary  and  Phytosanitary  

Page 20: Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton Universitysee$how$the$principle$of$subsidiarity$applies,$Iwill$make$adistinction$between ... narrow$interests,$the$world$economy$would$slide$into$rampantprotectionism$and

-­‐20-­‐    

Standards.  It  is  interesting  that  the  ban  did  not  discriminate  against  imports  and  applied  to  

imported  and  domestic  beef  alike.    There  did  not  seem  to  be  a  protectionist  motive  behind  the  

ban,  which  had  been  pushed  by  consumer  lobbies  in  Europe  alarmed  by  the  potential  health  

threats.    Nonetheless  the  WTO  judged  that  the  ban  violated  the  requirement  in  the  SPS  

Agreement  that  policies  be  based  on  “scientific  evidence.”  (In  a  similar  case  in  2006,  the  WTO  

also  ruled  against  EU  restrictions  on  genetically  modified  food  and  seeds  (GMOs),  finding  fault  

once  again  with  the  adequacy  of  EU  scientific  risk  assessment.)  

There  is  indeed  scant  evidence  to  date  that  growth  hormones  pose  any  health  threats.    

The  EU  argued  that  it  had  applied  a  broader  principle  not  explicitly  covered  by  the  WTO,  the  

“precautionary  principle,”  which  permits  greater  caution  in  the  presence  of  scientific  

uncertainty.  The  precautionary  principle  reverses  the  burden  of  proof.    Instead  of  asking  “is  

there  reasonable  evidence  that  growth  hormones  or  GMOs  have  adverse  effects?”  it  requires  

policy  makers  to  ask  “are  we  reasonably  sure  that  they  do  not?”    In  many  unsettled  areas  of  

scientific  knowledge,  the  answer  to  both  questions  can  be  “no.”    Whether  the  precautionary  

principle  makes  sense  depends  both  on  the  degree  of  risk  aversion  and  on  the  extent  to  which  

potential  adverse  effects  are  large  and  irreversible.      

As  the  European  Commission  argued  (unsuccessfully),  regulatory  decisions  here  cannot  

be  made  purely  on  the  basis  of  science.    Politics,  which  aggregates  a  society’s  risk  preferences,  

must  play  the  determinative  role.  It  is  not  unreasonable  to  expect  that  the  outcome  will  vary  

across  societies.    Some  (like  the  U.S.)  will  go  for  low  prices,  others  (like  the  EU)  for  greater  

safety.    

Page 21: Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton Universitysee$how$the$principle$of$subsidiarity$applies,$Iwill$make$adistinction$between ... narrow$interests,$the$world$economy$would$slide$into$rampantprotectionism$and

-­‐21-­‐    

  The  suitability  of  institutional  arrangements  also  depends  on  levels  of  development  and  

historical  trajectory.  Alexander  Gerschenkron  (1962)  famously  argued  that  lagging  countries  

would  need  institutions  –  such  as  large  banks  and  state  directed  investments  –  that  differed  

from  those  present  in  the  original  industrializers.    To  a  large  extent,  his  arguments  have  been  

validated.    But  even  among  rapidly  growing  developing  nations,  there  is  considerable  

institutional  variation.  What  works  in  one  place  rarely  does  in  another.      

  Consider  how  some  of  the  most  successful  developing  nations  joined  the  world  

economy.    South  Korea  and  Taiwan  relied  heavily  on  export  subsidies  to  push  their  firms  

outward  during  the  1960s  and  1970s,  and  liberalized  their  import  regime  only  gradually.    China  

established  special  economic  zones  (SEZs)  in  which  export-­‐oriented  firms  were  allowed  to  

operate  under  different  rules  than  those  applied  to  state  enterprises  and  to  others  focused  on  

the  internal  market.  Chile,  by  contrast,  followed  the  textbook  model  and  sharply  reduced  

import  barriers  in  order  to  force  domestic  firms  to  compete  with  foreign  firms  directly  in  the  

home  market.    The  Chilean  strategy  would  have  been  a  disaster  if  applied  in  China,  as  it  would  

have  led  to  millions  of  job  losses  in  state  enterprises  and  incalculable  social  consequences.  And  

the  Chinese  model  would  not  have  worked  as  well  in  Chile,  a  small  nation  that  is  not  an  obvious  

destination  for  multinational  enterprises.  

  Alberto  Alesina  and  Enrico  Spolaore  (2003)  have  explored  how  heterogeneity  in  

preferences  interacts  with  the  benefits  of  scale  to  determine  endogenously  the  number  and  

size  of  nations.    In  their  basic  model,  individuals  differ  in  their  preferences  over  the  public  

goods  –  which  we  might  also  think  of  specific  institutional  arrangements  –  provided  by  the  

state.    The  larger  the  population  over  which  the  public  good  is  provided,  the  lower  the  unit  cost  

Page 22: Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton Universitysee$how$the$principle$of$subsidiarity$applies,$Iwill$make$adistinction$between ... narrow$interests,$the$world$economy$would$slide$into$rampantprotectionism$and

-­‐22-­‐    

of  provision.    On  the  other  hand,  the  larger  the  population,  the  greater  the  number  of  people  

who  find  their  preferences  ill-­‐served  by  the  specific  public  good  provided.    Smaller  countries  are  

better  able  to  respond  to  their  citizens’  needs.  The  optimum  number  of  jurisdictions,  or  nation  

states,  trades  off  the  scale  benefits  of  size  against  the  heterogeneity  costs  of  public  good  

provision.    

  The  important  analytical  insight  of  the  Alesina-­‐Spolaore  model  is  that  it  makes  little  

sense  to  optimize  along  the  market  size  dimension  (and  eliminate  jurisdictional  discontinuities)  

when  there  exist  heterogeneity  in  preferences  along  the  institutional  dimension.    The  

framework  does  not  tell  us  whether  we  have  too  many  nations  at  present,  or  too  few.    But  it  

does  suggest  that  a  divided  world  polity  is  the  price  we  pay  for  institutional  arrangements  that  

are,  in  principle  at  least,  better  tailored  to  local  preferences  and  needs.    

So  I  accept  that  nation  states  are  a  source  of  disintegration  for  the  global  economy.    My  

claim  is  that  an  attempt  to  transcend  them  would  be  counterproductive.  It  would  get  us  neither  

a  healthier  world  economy,  nor  better  rules.      

My  argument  can  be  presented  as  a  counterpoint  to  the  typical  globalist  narrative,  

depicted  graphically  in  the  top  half  of  Figure  1.  In  this  narrative,  economic  globalization,  

spurred  by  the  revolutions  in  transport  and  communication  technologies,  breaks  down  the  

social  and  cultural  barriers  among  people  in  different  parts  of  the  world,  and  fosters  a  global  

community.    This  in  turn  enables  the  construction  of  a  global  political  community  –  i.e.,  global  

governance  –  which  underpins  and  further  reinforces  economic  integration.      

My  alternative  narrative  (shown  at  the  bottom  of  Figure  1)  emphasizes  a  different  

dynamic,  one  that  sustains  a  world  that  is  politically  divided  and  economically  less  than  fully  

Page 23: Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton Universitysee$how$the$principle$of$subsidiarity$applies,$Iwill$make$adistinction$between ... narrow$interests,$the$world$economy$would$slide$into$rampantprotectionism$and

-­‐23-­‐    

globalized.  In  this  dynamic,  preference  heterogeneity  and  institutional  non-­‐uniqueness,  along  

with  geography,  create  a  need  for  institutional  diversity.  Institutional  diversity  blocks  full  

economic  globalization.  Incomplete  economic  integration  in  turn  reinforces  heterogeneity  and  

the  role  of  distance.  When  the  forces  of  this  second  dynamic  are  sufficiently,  strong,  as  I  will  

argue  they  are,  operating  by  the  rules  of  the  first  can  get  us  only  into  trouble.      

 

Concluding  remarks  

The  design  of  institutions  is  shaped  by  a  fundamental  trade-­‐off.  On  the  one  hand,  

relationships  and  heterogeneity  push  governance  down.  On  the  other,  the  scale  and  scope  

benefits  of  market  integration  push  governance  up.    A  corner  solution  is  rarely  optimal.  An  

intermediate  outcome,  a  world  divided  into  diverse  polities,  is  the  best  that  we  can  do.            

Our  failure  to  internalize  the  lessons  of  this  simple  point  leads  us  to  pursue  dead  ends.  

We  push  markets  beyond  what  their  governance  can  support.    We  set  global  rules  that  defy  the  

underlying  diversity  in  needs  and  preferences.    We  eviscerate  the  nation  state  without  

compensating  improvements  in  governance  elsewhere.  The  failure  lies  at  the  heart  of  

globalization’s  unaddressed  ills  as  well  as  the  decline  in  our  democracies’  health.  

   

Page 24: Rodrik-IR Fac Col Paper - Princeton Universitysee$how$the$principle$of$subsidiarity$applies,$Iwill$make$adistinction$between ... narrow$interests,$the$world$economy$would$slide$into$rampantprotectionism$and

-­‐24-­‐    

Figure 1. The dynamics supporting the globalist and nation-state equilibria.