Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s...

32
Sender’s Payoff Proof Sender’s Behaviour Ethical-Type Sender Conclusion Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost HARRY PEI Department of Economics, Northwestern University Canadian Economic Theory Conference May 8th, 2020

Transcript of Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s...

Page 1: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Sender’s Payoff Proof Sender’s Behaviour Ethical-Type Sender Conclusion

Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost

HARRY PEIDepartment of Economics, Northwestern University

Canadian Economic Theory ConferenceMay 8th, 2020

Page 2: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Sender’s Payoff Proof Sender’s Behaviour Ethical-Type Sender Conclusion

Motivation: Sender’s Commitment to Disclosure Policies

Bayesian persuasion game (Kamenica and Gentzkow 2011):

• Payoff-relevant state ω ∈Ω, with Ω finite.

• Sender commits to a disclosure policy σ(·|ω)ω∈Ω,with σ(·|ω) ∈ ∆(M).

• Sender honours her commitment after observing ω , and sends m ∈M.

• Receiver observes message m, and chooses action a ∈ A.

Controversial: Can the sender commit to disclosure policies?

• Sender’s optimal disclosure policy requires nontrivial mixing

& some messages lead to strictly higher payoffs compared to others.

• Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest.

Page 3: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Sender’s Payoff Proof Sender’s Behaviour Ethical-Type Sender Conclusion

Microfoundation: Repeated Communication Games

A patient sender communicates with a sequence of receivers.

• State of the world ωt ∈Ω, with ωtt∈N i.i.d.

• Sender privately observes ωt and sends a message mt ∈M.

• Receiver observes ωs,ms,ast−1s=0 and mt, and then chooses at ∈ A.

Folk theorem result of Fudenberg, Kreps and Maskin (1990):

• In many games of interest, patient sender’s equilibrium payoff isstrictly bounded away from her optimal commitment payoff.

Future receivers cannot perfectly monitor sender’s mixed actions.

Existing solutions: Allow sender-commitment to kick in, e.g.,

• sender can commit to truthfully disclose private randomisations;

• with positive prob, sender is a commitment type that mechanicallycommunicates according to her optimal disclosure policy.

Page 4: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Sender’s Payoff Proof Sender’s Behaviour Ethical-Type Sender Conclusion

My Model: Repeated Communication w/o Commitment

Time: t = 0,1,2, ...

• Long-lived sender (discount δ ) vs sequence of short-lived receivers.

In period t,

• State ωt ∈ ωh,ω l, i.i.d. over time, with Pr(ωt = ωh) = p ∈ (0,1/2).

• Sender observes ωt and sends mt ∈ mh,ml.

• Receiver chooses at ∈ ah,al after observing ωs,ms,ast−1s=0 and mt.

Receiver’s payoff: 1at = ωt.

Sender’s stage-game payoff: 1at = ah−C ·1mt 6= ωt. Alternative View

• C ∈ C1, ...,Cm, perfectly persistent, sender’s private info (or type).

• Baseline model: 0≤ Cm < Cm−1 < ... < C1 < 1.

Every type of sender has a strict incentive to mislead receivers.

• Receivers’ full support prior belief π ∈ ∆C1, ...,Cm.

Page 5: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Sender’s Payoff Proof Sender’s Behaviour Ethical-Type Sender Conclusion

Overview of Three Theorems

1. Characterise every type of patient sender’s highest equilibrium payoff.• conditions s.t. all types’ highest equilibrium payoffs converge to

their respective optimal commitment payoffs.

2. Distinctions between strategic-type sender and commitment-type.• No type of strategic sender uses his optimal disclosure policy at

every on-path history.

3. Allowing for ethical type senders (i.e., lying cost ≥ 1).• Characterise when can all non-ethical types can attain their

optimal commitment payoffs.

• The possibility of being ethical and having a high lying cost canhurt non-ethical type senders

Page 6: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Sender’s Payoff Proof Sender’s Behaviour Ethical-Type Sender Conclusion

Related Literature

Repeated communication: Best and Quigley (17), Mathevet et al. (19).

• No type of sender can commit to disclosure policies. Sender cannotcommit to truthfully disclose private randomisations.

Static communication with lying cost: Kartik et al. (07), Kartik (09), Guoand Shmaya (19), Nguyen and Tan (19)

• Sender observes the state, cannot perform info control.

• Non-ethical sender can be hurt by ethical types.

Repeated games with persistent private information: Aumann andMaschler (65), Hart (85), Shalev (94), Cripps and Thomas (03), Peski (14).

• Uninformed player is impatient + non-zero sum.

Reputation w/o commitment types: Weinstein and Yildiz (16), Pei (19).

Cost of lying: Gneezy (05), Gneezy et al.(18), Sobel (20).

Page 7: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Sender’s Payoff Proof Sender’s Behaviour Ethical-Type Sender Conclusion

BenchmarksRecall that in the baseline model, 0≤ Cm < Cm−1 < ... < C1 < 1.

1. Type Cj’s optimal commitment payoff: v∗∗j ≡ p+p(1−Cj).

2. Repeated communication game when C is common knowledge.

• Patient sender’s highest equilibrium payoff is p,i.e., her payoff in a 1-shot interaction by fully disclosing ω .

Why?

• At every history s.t. receiver plays ah with positive prob,exists message m′ s.t. receiver plays al for sure,and the sender sends m′ when the state is ω l with positive prob.

• Sending m′ when the state is ω l at every such history is sender’sbest reply, from which her stage-game payoff ≤ p.

Other Benchmarks

Page 8: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Sender’s Payoff Proof Sender’s Behaviour Ethical-Type Sender Conclusion

Patient Sender’s Highest Equilibrium PayoffRecall that in the baseline model, 0≤ Cm < Cm−1 < ... < C1 < 1.

For every j ∈ 1,2, ...,m, let

v∗j ≡ p(

1+C1−Cj

2p+C1(1−2p)

)

Theorem 1

For every ε > 0, there exists δ ∈ (0,1) such that when δ > δ ,

1. @ BNE such that type C1 attains payoff strictly more than v∗1,

@ BNE such that type Cj attains payoff more than v∗j + ε , ∀ j≥ 2.

2. ∃ sequential equilibrium s.t. the sender attains payoff within an ε

neighbourhood of (v∗1, ...,v∗m).

Page 9: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Sender’s Payoff Proof Sender’s Behaviour Ethical-Type Sender Conclusion

Implications of Theorem 1

Formula for type Cj’s highest limiting equilibrium payoff :

v∗j ≡ p(

1+C1−Cj

2p+C1(1−2p)

)

1. Depends only on Cj and C1, not on type distribution and other types.

2. v∗1 = p, and p < v∗j < p+p(1−Cj) for every j ∈ 2, ...,m.

Every type except for C1 can strictly benefit from incomplete info.

Puzzle: Extract info rent in the long run & preserve info advantage.

3. As C1→ 1, v∗j → p+p(1−Cj) for every j ∈ 1,2, ...,m.

Every type can approximately attain her optimal commitment payoff.

Page 10: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Sender’s Payoff Proof Sender’s Behaviour Ethical-Type Sender Conclusion

Proof of Theorem 1: Overview

Sufficiency: Construct equilibria that approximately attain v∗ ≡ (v∗1, ...,v∗m).

• High-cost type mixes to provide cover for low-cost types.

• Low-cost types mix except when the posterior prob of high-cost type issufficiently high, in which they have strict incentive to lie.

• Low-cost types can rebuild their reputations after milking them.

According to every pure best reply of low-cost type, he needs to tell thetruth for a certain number of periods to reach a history in which he hasa strict incentive to lie.

Necessity: Type Cj’s payoff cannot significantly exceed v∗j .

• Relate repeated game outcome to a constrained optimisation problem.

• Value of constrained optimisation problem is v∗j .

• Establish the necessity of the constraints for BNE in the repeated game.

Page 11: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Sender’s Payoff Proof Sender’s Behaviour Ethical-Type Sender Conclusion

Rewrite Players’ Stage-Game in Normal Form

Sender’s stage-game pure action:

• a : Ω→M, with a ∈ A.

Receiver’s stage-game pure action:

• b : M→ A, with b ∈ B.

Rewrite players’ stage-game payoff functions as:

• ur(a,b) and us(C,a,b).

Page 12: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Sender’s Payoff Proof Sender’s Behaviour Ethical-Type Sender Conclusion

Necessity: v∗j as a Constrained Optimisation Problem

Proposition 1

v∗j is the value of the following constrained optimisation problem:

maxγ∈∆(A×B)

∑(a,b)∈A×B

γ(a,b)us(Cj,a,b),

subject to:

1.∑

(a,b)∈A×Bγ(a,b)us(C1,a,b)≤ p,

2. for every b ∈ B that the marginal distribution of γ on B attachespositive prob to,

b ∈ argmaxb′∈B

ur(γ(·|b),b′),

where γ(·|b) is the distribution over sender’s stage-game actionconditional on the receiver’s stage-game action being b.

Page 13: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Sender’s Payoff Proof Sender’s Behaviour Ethical-Type Sender Conclusion

Relate Maximisation Problem to the Repeated Game

For any strategy profile in the repeated game((σCj)

mj=1,σr

), let

γj(a,b)≡E(σCj ,σr)

[ ∞

∑t=0

(1−δ )δ t1(at,bt)= (a,b)]

for every (a,b)∈A×B.

Type Cj’s discounted average payoff by playing σCj in the repeated game

equals her expected stage-game payoff under γ j ∈ ∆(A×B).

Objective function in the maximisation problem:

∑(a,b)∈A×B

γj(a,b)us(Cj,a,b).

Page 14: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Sender’s Payoff Proof Sender’s Behaviour Ethical-Type Sender Conclusion

Relate Maximisation Problem to the Repeated Game

For any strategy profile in the repeated game((σCj)

mj=1,σr

), let

γj(a,b)≡E(σCj ,σr)

[ ∞

∑t=0

(1−δ )δ t1(at,bt)= (a,b)]

for every (a,b)∈A×B.

Type C1’s discounted average payoff by playing σCj in the repeated game

equals her expected stage-game payoff under γ j ∈ ∆(A×B).

First constraint in the maximisation problem:

∑(a,b)∈A×B

γj(a,b)us(C1,a,b)≤ p.

This constraint is necessary in equilibrium if:

• type C1’s equilibrium payoff ≤ p. Proposition 2

Page 15: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Sender’s Payoff Proof Sender’s Behaviour Ethical-Type Sender Conclusion

Relate Maximisation Problem to the Repeated Game

For any strategy profile in the repeated game((σCj)

mj=1,σr

), let

γj(a,b)≡E(σCj ,σr)

[ ∞

∑t=0

(1−δ )δ t1(at,bt)= (a,b)]

for every (a,b)∈A×B.

Second constraint in the optimisation problem:

• for every b ∈ B that the marginal distribution of γ on B attachespositive prob to,

b ∈ argmaxb′∈B

ur(γj(·|b),b′).

This follows from the learning argument in Gossner (2011):

• Since public signals statistically identify sender’s stage-game action.

• Receiver’s prediction about sender’s action is correct in all except for abounded number of periods.

Propositions 3 and 4

Page 16: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Sender’s Payoff Proof Sender’s Behaviour Ethical-Type Sender Conclusion

Distinction between Rational Type and Commitment Type

How will patient sender behave in equilibria in which his payoff ≈ v∗?

• Will he use his optimal disclosure policy in every period?

Sender’s stage-game pure action:

• a : Ω→M, with a ∈ A.

Let aH be the honest strategy and aL be the lying strategy:

aH(ω) =

mh if ω = ωh

ml if ω = ω l,aL(ω) =

mh if ω = ωh

mh if ω = ω l,

Sender’s optimal disclosure policy: Mixing between aH and aL.

Page 17: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Sender’s Payoff Proof Sender’s Behaviour Ethical-Type Sender Conclusion

Patient Sender’s Behaviour in High-Payoff Equilibria

Theorem 2

Suppose m≥ 2. For every small ε > 0, there exists δ ∈ (0,1) such that

when δ > δ , for every BNE that attains payoff within ε of (v∗1, ...,v∗m),

no type plays aH and aL both with positive prob at every on-path history.

Remarks:

1. Also applies to a type whose cost of lying is 1,

i.e., indifferent between lying and not when the state is ω l.

2. Contrasts to the commitment type in Mathevet et al. (2019).

Page 18: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Sender’s Payoff Proof Sender’s Behaviour Ethical-Type Sender Conclusion

Proof of Theorem 2

Suppose type Cj plays aH and aL with positive prob at every on-path history.

• Playing aH in every period is her best reply against σr.

• Playing aL in every period is her best reply against σr.

For every type Ci that has higher lying cost (i.e., lower index)

• Type Ci plays aH with prob 1 at every on-path history.

Consider two cases:

Case 1: This type Cj is not type C1.

• Type C1 plays aH with prob 1 at every on-path history.

• Type C2 separates from type C1

after the first time she sends mh when the state is ω l.

• Type C2’s payoff is at most (1−δ )+δp,

which is strictly smaller than v∗2. This leads to a contradiction.

Page 19: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Sender’s Payoff Proof Sender’s Behaviour Ethical-Type Sender Conclusion

Proof of Theorem 2

Case 2: This type Cj is type C1.

• aL in every period is type C1’s best reply against σr,

from which she attains payoff at least p− ε .

• Type C1’s stage-game payoff from playing aL:

* 1− (1−p)C1 if receiver plays ah following mh.* −(1−p)C1 otherwise.

This implies a lower bound on the prob that sender gets 1− (1−p)C1:

Q(

1−(1−p)C1

)−(1−Q)(1−p)C1≥ p−ε⇔Q≥ p+(1−p)C1− ε.

• Type C2’s payoff by playing aL in every period is at least:

Q(

1− (1−p)C2

)− (1−Q)(1−p)C2,

which is strictly greater than v∗2 + ε when ε is small.

Page 20: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Sender’s Payoff Proof Sender’s Behaviour Ethical-Type Sender Conclusion

Incorporate Ethical Type Senders

Relax the assumption that C1 < 1. Instead, assume that:

• C1 ≥ 1, i.e., exists ethical type

• Cm < 1, i.e., exists non-ethical type

Let C∗ be the lowest lying cost among the ethical types.

Theorem 3There exist equilibria s.t. all non-ethical types attain their optimalcommitment payoffs iff

C1(C∗−1)< 2. Full Statement

Non-ethical sender can attain commitment payoff:

• iff C1 and C∗ are low enough.

i.e., increasing C1 or C∗ hurts non-ethical type sender,

& introducing additional types can hurt non-ethical types.

Page 21: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Sender’s Payoff Proof Sender’s Behaviour Ethical-Type Sender Conclusion

More Ethical Types Hurt: Outside Option Effect

Illustrative example:

• Two types: C2,C3, with C3 ∈ (0,1) and C2 = 1+ ε .

Type C3 can attain his Bayesian persuasion payoff.

• Introduce another type C1 that is large enough such that:

C1(C2−1)> 2.

Type C3 cannot attain his Bayesian persuasion payoff.

Page 22: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Sender’s Payoff Proof Sender’s Behaviour Ethical-Type Sender Conclusion

Outside Option Effect

If type C3 attains commitment payoff in equilibrium, then

• Type C3 lies while does not separate from type C2.

Type C2 needs to lie with some frequency despite his lying cost > 1:

• An upper bound on type C2’s payoff.

Question: How much is type C2 willing to lie?

Presence of type C1 decreases type C2’s willingness to lie.

• Type C1 can secure payoff 0 by always telling the truth.

• Type C2’s minimal payoff by imitating type C1’s equilibrium strategy.

This yields a lower bound on type C2’s equilibrium payoff.

Page 23: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Sender’s Payoff Proof Sender’s Behaviour Ethical-Type Sender Conclusion

Concluding Remarks

Repeated communication game without any commitment.

• Sender has persistent private info about her psychological cost of lying.

Different from commitment-type approach:

• Strategic-type sender’s incentive constraints lead to novel predictionson equilibrium payoffs and behaviours.

Takeaways:

1. Persistent private info (partially) restores sender’s commitment.

• Microfoundation for sender’s commitment to disclosure policies.

2. High-cost type’s behaviour 6= Stationary commitment behaviour.

3. Possibility of being ethical may hurt non-ethical sender.

Page 24: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Alternative Benchmarks

Sender commits to disclosure policy after observing C before observing ω .

• Every type’s equilibrium payoff is p+(1−p)C.

One-shot communication w/o commitment:

• Let k be the smallest integer s.t. π(C1)+ ...+π(Ck)≥ 1−2p1−p .

• For every i≤ k, type Ci’s payoff is pCk.

• For every j > k, type Cj’s payoff is Ck− (1−p)Cj.

Not a good benchmark since:

• Short-term info rent does not survive in the long-run.

• Some types of sender receive strictly higher payoff compared tooptimal commitment payoff

⇒ Not a satisfactory microfoundation for sender-commitment. Back

Page 25: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Comment: Two Views on Lying Costs

Sender’s stage-game payoff: 1at = ah−C1mt 6= ωt

• Non-consequentialism view (Immanuel Kant 1797).

• Sender incurs a psychological cost whenever the face value of hermessage 6= her knowledge about state.

• Used in economic models of Kartik et al. (07), Kartik (09).

Alternatively, consequentialism view of Martin Luther.

• Sender incurs lying cost only when her lie has caused damages.

• Main takeaway messages apply under both views.

Back

Page 26: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

1st Constraint: Type C1’s Highest Equilibrium Payoff

Proposition 2

For every BNE and for every on-path public history ht,

if Ci is the highest-cost type in the support of receiver’s belief at ht,

then type Ci’s continuation payoff at ht is at most p.

Proof is done by induction on number of types in the support.

1. Only one type in the support, similar to the argument in FKM.

Caution: Not implied by FKM given the solution concept is BNE.

2. If conclusion applies when there are ≤ n types in the support,

then it applies when there are n+1 types in the support.

For simplicity, focus on equilibria s.t. at every on-path history, mh induces ah

with weakly higher probability than message ml.Back

Page 27: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Proof of Proposition 2: Induction Step

Given equilibrium((σCi)

mi=1,σr

). Let Cj be the highest-cost type at ht.

• I construct a new strategy σCj based on σCj .

• For every hs ht,

if σCj sends message ml in state ω l at hs with positive prob,then σCj sends message ml with prob 1 when the state is ω l.

otherwise, σCj sends the same message as σCj .

• By construction, σCj is type Cj’s best reply against σr.

Consider all histories that:

• succeed ht, and occur with positive prob under (σCj ,σr).

Partition all those histories into two subsets:

Subset 1: hs is such that from ht to hs, @ outcome (ω l,ah).

Subset 2: hs is such that from ht to hs, ∃ outcome (ω l,ah).

Back

Page 28: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Proof of Proposition 2: Induction Step

Consider type Cj’s continuation payoff at ht by adopting σCj :

• In subset 1, type Cj has never received positive payoff in state ω l.

If hs belongs to subset 2 but hs−1 belongs to subset 1, then:

• σCj sends message ml at hs−1 with prob 0,

⇒ some type Ck sends ml at hs−1 with positive prob.

• After observing ml at hs−1, number of types in the support of receiver’sposterior belief is reduced by at least one.

• Ck: highest-cost type in the support of receiver’s belief at (hs−1,ml).

By definition, Cj > Ck.

Induction hypothesis: Ck’s continuation payoff in period t is ≤ p.

• After observing ω l at hs−1,

type Ck’s continuation payoff ≤ δp if she sends message mh.

• Type Cj’s continuation payoff is also less than δp.

Back

Page 29: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

2nd Constraint is Approximately Satisfied

Proposition 3

For every ε > 0 and j, there exists δ ∈ (0,1) such that,

for every BNE when δ > δ , if γ j attaches probability more than ε to b,

then b is an ε-best reply against γ j(·|b) ∈ ∆(A).

Intuition: Learning argument in Gossner (11).

• Receiver’s prediction about sender’s action is ε-close to sender’s action(based on her true type) in all except for a bounded number of periods.

• If δ is close to 1, then this bounded number of periods have negligibleimpact on γ j(·|b) if the prob of b is not too small.

• γ j(·|b) is close to the subset of ∆(A) that b best replies against.

Back

Page 30: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Convergence of ε-relaxed problem

Let vεj be the value of the optimisation problem that satisfies:

• the first constraint, i.e., type C1’s payoff ≤ p.

• the ε-relaxed version of second constraint.

Proposition 4

limε↓0 vεj = v∗j for every j ∈ 1,2, ...,m.

Back

Page 31: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Sufficiency Part of Theorem 1

LetvN ≡

(−C1(1−p),−C2(1−p), ...,−Cm(1−p)

),

vL ≡(

p+(1−C1)(1−p),p+(1−C2)(1−p), ...,p+(1−Cm)(1−p)),

and vH ≡ (p,p, ...,p).

For every ρ ∈ [0, p1−p ], let

v(ρ)≡ (1−ρ)C1

ρ(1−C1)+C1vH +

ρC1

ρ(1−C1)+C1vL +

ρ(1−C1)

ρ(1−C1)+C1vN .

Proposition 5

For every π > 0 and ρ ∈ [0,ρ∗), there exists δ ∈ (0,1) such that for every π

with π(C1)≥ π and δ > δ , there exists an equilibrium that attains v(ρ).

Back

Page 32: Repeated Communication with Private Lying Cost · Honouring commitment is against the sender’s own interest. Sender’s PayoffProofSender’s BehaviourEthical-Type SenderConclusion

Characterization Result

Theorem 3

1. IfC1(C∗−1)−2 < 0,

then for every ε > 0, there exists δ ∈ (0,1), such that when δ > δ ,there exists a sequential equilibrium in which every non-ethical type Cjobtains payoff at least v∗∗j − ε .

2. IfC1(C∗−1)−2 > 0,

then there exist η > 0 and δ ∈ (0,1), such that in every Bayes Nashequilibrium when δ > δ , every non-ethical type Cj obtains payoff nomore than v∗∗j −η .

Back