POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

download POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

of 47

Transcript of POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    1/47

    1

    Classical and Civil History

    the Transformation of

    Humanism

    John G. A. Pocock

    1. Gibbon in the Memoirsinsisted that from childhood he could never have

    been other than a historian [1] , and little evidence has appeared to makeus think otherwise. Yet it is a riddle for his biographers to explain whatwent on in his mind between 1764, when he paid his visit to Rome, and

    1774 when he was immersed in writing the Decline and Fall[2 ] ; thisthough there is copious evidence in the form of letters and journals,

    records of and commentaries on his reading, critical essays and sketches

    of historical projects. It is possible for scholars to disagree, with a vigour

    approaching acrimony [3] , on how he shaped his intentions towards hisone major work. The present study is not a biography, and will not commit

    itself to the pursuit of these problems. Its intention rather is to establishsome major contexts in which Gibbon lived and wrote, and to employ

    these in exploring the significance of what he was and did [4] . The nextgroup of chapters, therefore, will take au pied de la lettrehis assertion

    that he was born to be a 'historian', and will enquire what it meant to

    practice the activity we term 'historiography' in the culture Gibbon

    inhabited.

    2. Biographical threads of course run through these enquiries, and a

    crucial moment has to be that of the visit to Rome in October 1764. There

    is contemporary evidence that this visit was an important experience; he

    wrote to his father to say that there had never been such another people

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    2/47

    2

    as the Romans in the history of the world, and that for the sake of

    mankind he hoped there would never be again [5 ]. The collision it is nota balance between admiration and condemnation articulates the

    essence of the eighteenth century's view of antiquity, and what it meanswill have to be explored again. Alongside this statement in a letter written

    from Rome when Gibbon was there, we must place the immortal

    Capitoline vision mentioned at the end of the Decline and Falland

    asserted again in the Memoirs, where he says he sat musing among the

    ruins of the Capitol while the barefooted friars were singing Vespers in the

    temple of Jupiter, and the idea of writing the decline and fall of the City

    first started to my mind [6 ]. The Memoirsassert that his journal recordsthis incident on the evening of October 15, but in fact it does not, and the

    experience may be a creation of memory or a literary invention [7]. Ineither and in any case, it associates Gibbon with a complex of topics

    central to the literate mind of his age; it links the theme of Roman

    republican and imperial greatness and decay with that of the Catholic

    Church's substitution of itself for the empire. Gibbon possessed (we do

    not know when he bought) the works of Thomas Hobbes, and may by

    1764 have been familiar with that philosopher's characterisation of the

    Church as the ghost of the deceased Roman empire, sitting crowned

    upon the grave thereof [8] . The second theme led away from the first,towards the late antique, medieval and oriental history which Gibbon tells

    us had been among the discoveries of his childhood [9 ], and reminds usthat from the first he had been something more than a classicist. His

    letter to his father, and much in the Memoirsbesides, revolve around

    Roman greatness and its fall; but the barefooted friars lead inexorably

    into ecclesiastical and medieval history the history of barbarism and

    religion which classically- trained humanists, especially when their

    culture was Protestant, had to study precisely because they disdained itso much. Philosophesmight propose to ignore all Christian history as

    unworthy of attention; historians in the eighteenth century, no less than

    at other times, knew that they must study it in order to understand how it

    had happened. And the history of the city, said to have started to

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    3/47

    3

    Gibbon's mind as he viewed the ruins of the Forum, could not be

    separated from the history of both empire and church. This too was a real

    tension; in the conclusion of the Decline and Fall, a history of empire as

    well as of barbarism and religion which had carried him to the ends of theearth, Gibbon was to write three chapters on the history of the medieval

    city as a political, ecclesiastical and architectural structure.

    3. The Capitoline vision may be used to explore another twofold theme:

    that of the presence of the classical paradigm in early-modern neo-Latin

    historiography, coupled with that of its incessant modification [10].Though the Enlightened historians modified and obeyed it in their own

    way, the tension within historiography was very much older and can be

    traced back to Roman culture itself. To state the paradigm first, in a form

    which Gibbon knew and recognised in his writings, 'history' was by a

    powerful convention [11] supposed to be a record of the deeds of greatmen, or of great peoples in the persons of their kings, captains and

    magistrates, written by the protagonists themselves, or by participants in

    or witnesses of their actions, and preserved in writing and in memory. The

    writing of history might be an official activity, the work of a priest, scribe

    or poet charged with it as his function, or in the polisor republic the

    activity of a citizen, who as a protagonist or participant alternatedbetween action and leisure, action and contemplation, action and

    recollection. A citizen might choose to write the history of his times,

    perceiving like Thucydides that they would be the scene of extraordinary

    and exemplary actions; but if he thought them extraordinary, he might be

    obliged to explain wherein they differed from times and actions preceding

    them, and the concepts of a past and its unlikeness to the present might

    begin to appear in historiography. Narrative historians thus composed

    might be preserved, and read as records of deeds done of old; and thusthere might appear 'historians' in a new sense of the term, who like Livy

    set out to narrate, meaning to re-narrate, the res gestaeor things done

    in the city ab urbe conditaor since its foundation, including the especially

    significant action of the foundation itself. But only if such a history

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    4/47

    4

    obtained eminent authority would its author come to be recognised as a

    historian himself; otherwise he would be not only a narrator of other

    men's deeds but a compiler of other men's narratives, and they would be

    the 'historians', a title to which he could not aspire. The compilers of theearly 'general histories of England' conflated the works of Sir Thomas

    More for the reign of Richard III, Sir Francis Bacon for that of Henry VII,

    Lord Herbert of Cherbury for that of Henry VIII, William Camden for that

    of Elizabeth I and Lord Clarendon for the Great Rebellion; only in

    epitomising and continuing the last did Bishop Kennett take on himself,

    with justifiable misgivings, the role and the style of 'historian' [12]. It wasunclear whether 'historiography' was an action fit only for the actor,

    soldier or statesman, or for the cleric or scholar whose function was to

    record only and not to act; the increasing activity of clerics in medieval or

    humanists in Renaissance culture was one cause of the slow

    transformation in the nature of 'history'.

    4. History thus defined was an antique and classical activity; it recorded

    the actions of men in ancient and typically Greek and Roman times and

    was written in Greco-Roman style by authors trying to be as like as they

    could to ancient authors and ancient actors. One source of 'modern'

    historical sensibility was the question of how far a 'modern' could identifyhimself as an 'ancient' simply by imitating the latter's deeds or his words.

    It was a military, political and masculine activity; to find a woman writing

    it was as rare as Anna Comnena or Christine de Pisan, while to find a

    woman's deeds as its subject was rarer still there were few heroines in

    war or statecraft between Semiramis of Babylon and Elizabeth of

    England. The issue of gender was less crucial in shaping it than the issue

    of literacy, or rather of clerisy; were the historians of antiquity men of

    action who had turned to writing in their retirement, or were they sophistsand rhetors whose business was words, not deeds, who recorded,

    narrated, evaluated and above all verbalised the actions performed by

    others? The history of historical writing is in fact a history of

    clericalisation, of the steady annexation of action by interpretation until

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    5/47

    5

    the point is reached where interpreters can deny both actors and authors

    any existence beyond that which the written and increasingly self-

    interpretative word chooses to invent them in; but in the still neo-

    classical culture of Enlightenment the heroic model remainedparadigmatic. The historian should be man of action as well as

    interpretation, of the sword as well as the pen; the captain of militia had

    not been useless (though the reader might smile) to the historian of

    empire.

    5. Applied in its pure form, the classical paradigm was not more than a

    mirror, the miroir des princesin which the deeds of the exemplary

    individual were exhibited as they had been in life, to be admired,

    condemned, pitied and judged in the memory of posterity; and memory

    was not more than the storehouse or theatrumin which the images were

    exhibited and the judgments reiterated. These need not be positive; while

    glorification was a prime aim of historiography, condemnation was

    always an alternative, and in the culture of late-medieval and Tudor

    England there were mirrors for magistrates which exhibited repeated

    instances of the fall of princes[13]. Edifying as these might be, it waspossible for the Christian imagination which preserved the Greco-Roman

    model to question its values. Samuel Johnson, one of the more Christianminds of the eighteenth century, did so in his epitaph for Charles XII of

    Sweden.

    His fall was destined to a barren strand,

    A petty fortress and a dubious hand.

    He left the name, at which the world grew pale,

    To point a moral or adorn a tale[14]

    6. The last line accurately states the objectives of classical

    historiography, yet intimates that there is something barren about them.

    Charles appears in the mirror as an image of ultimate lack of meaning,

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    6/47

    6

    but this extends to the mirror itself. Because he was nothing but a warrior,

    a conqueror for whom conquest had no objective beyond itself, his death

    was pure accident, a stroke of fortunamore absurd than tragic; there is

    no magnificent meaning jumping out of that, and no point in preservingthe image other than to say so. The futility of his death is its own warning

    against itself, and the point Johnson finds in this history is contained in

    the title of his poem, The Vanity of Human Wishes. This is a Christian

    concept; for classical antiquity the pursuit of glory was magnificent in

    itself, and its defeat was tragic. Johnson's insistence on anti-tragedy was

    an implied criticism of classical historiography, contained within a

    Christian classicism.

    7. Even in Greco-Roman culture, however, the classical paradigm did not

    operate in its pure form. We are looking here at the origins of 'kings and

    battles' historiography to use a phrase favoured by petty-intellectual

    criticism of l'histoire evnementielleand la storia statale but the

    ancient historians were citizens of republics before they were the

    subjects of Hellenistic kings and Roman emperors. They wrote about the

    deeds in battle and the civic oratory of archonsand strategoi, consuls

    and dictatores, and they knew that the citizen, as captain and magistrate,

    lived within a complex structure of laws and values which gave his actionssignificance and which it was his business to maintain. He might, very

    rarely, be the founder of such a system, the legislator or pater patriae

    there had been conquerors who were legislators, as well as those like

    Charles XII who were not he might preserve it against external enemies

    or internal corruption, find it too far gone in corruption to be preserved,

    or figure as an agent of corruption himself. The system of laws and

    values, which was symbolised by the gods of the city and was in a sense

    the city itself, thus became a factor if not an agent in the historyperceived and written, and furnished heroic action with a context. Nor is it

    the case that to quote another phrase favoured by petty-intellectual

    iconoclasm history was invariably written by the victors. Several of the

    classic historians of antiquity Thucydides, Polybius, Tacitus and of

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    7/47

    7

    neo-classical early modernity Guicciardini, Sarpi, Clarendon wrote

    their histories from the standpoint of the defeated; they wrote to find out

    how things had gone wrong, how great leaders had undone themselves,

    how the unworthy had triumphed, how great political systems haddecayed and disintegrated. The institutional thus set itself beside the

    heroic; it was the city, the monarchy, the empire that gave action

    meaning, and the deeds of the individual were judged as the system

    made them possible and as they had contributed to the system's triumph,

    survival or decay. In this way the laws and values constituting an ancient

    political system became factors and agencies in ancient historiography,

    and without ceasing to be a record of exemplary res gestae, the latter

    became a record of how cities and empires had arisen, flourished and

    decayed. It was nothing new for Gibbon to undertake the history of the

    decline and fall of an empire, since that was one aspect of what

    Thucydides had written, or to accomplish a history of barbarism and

    religion, since that phrase would serve to describe what Herodotus had

    written. On the premise that the great deeds of the barbarians as well as

    the Greeks should be preserved and not forgotten [15] , Herodotus hadfound that this could not be done without detailed accounts of the gods,

    kings and customs of the non-Greek peoples of the Persian imperial

    system. The problem of ethnocentricity necessarily arose, but it is ourmisfortune if we operate a double standard which damns Herodotus for

    colonialism if he depicts non-Greeks as if they were Greeks, and damns

    him for colonialism if he represents them as Others. There is something to

    be said for the view that he found them fascinating and partly intelligible,

    and represented them acting like Greeks in order to outline the ways in

    which they acted otherwise. It is the problem of the external perspective;

    Sparta and Athens existed in a context dominated by the non-Greek

    Persianempire, and Herodotus wrote in order to show how they hadturned back its attempt to colonise them. His narrative thus became an

    exploration of the 'culture' (as we should call it) of the Greek cities, and of

    its victory over the 'culture', military and political, of the invading empire.

    Since we do not have a Persian exploratory narrative of the same events,

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    8/47

    8

    we may seek to invent one [16], or we may enquire whether one hasexisted and we have repressed it; alternatively, if one does not exist,

    whether the practice of writing 'histories' in this sense was specifically

    Greek and afterwards Roman. In Thucydides's history, Sparta and Athensconfront each other in a universe predominantly Hellenic; the

    'barbarians' are marginal to the action, and the question is that of the

    survival, victory and defeat of alternative Hellenic systems, which are

    maintained and destroyed by the actions of their citizens; the Athenians

    do more harm to themselves and others than the Spartans do to them.

    An internal perspective predominates; the issue in history is that of the

    city's ability to maintain itself, and the Hellenic or barbarian 'others' are

    contingent. It can of course be added that a system's power to dismiss

    others to contingency is a way of dominating them even when it is not a

    way of governing them.

    8. The classical paradigm thus depicted the exemplary individual as

    acting in a context, and was capable of generating a history of the

    context he and others had acted in; this is especially the case of the

    transformations of Roman historiography. When we turn from the

    'classical' i. e., the pre-Christian central Mediterranean world to the

    'neo-classical' i. e., late Latin and Enlightened western European wemake a double discovery: first, that the classical paradigm was still so

    prominent that it had been a problem to authors in the generation

    preceding Gibbon's that they could not act the role of noble statesmen in

    retirement which was central to the writing of accredited 'histories' [17],and was still an occasional problem to Gibbon himself that he could not

    write history as the record of exemplary actions [18] ; second, that thehistoriography of contexts, legal, philological, cultural and above all

    religious, had developed in a variety of ways to points where it operatedindependently of the classical paradigm, could not be accommodated to

    it, and might have annexed and digested it if the latter had not been so

    powerful. These phenomena belong to the history of the clericalisation of

    classical culture; the rebellion of the 'polite' litesagainst the clerisies is

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    9/47

    9

    part of it, and the debate about the ruditsand the gens de lettresis

    another. Were the latter to overthrow the hegemony of philological

    scholarship established by Renaissance humanism, and could they do so

    without becoming a new ruling clerisy themselves? Gibbon and Humewere among the later though not the last of the gentlemen of letters; in

    the next century historians were to be typically professionals and even

    professors. In Glasgow and Gttingen, however, the last-named sub-

    species was not unknown in Gibbon's time.

    9. Arnaldo Momigliano gave the study of Gibbon's historiography its

    modern form by observing that his achievement was to integrate

    philosophic history with humanist and antiquarian scholarship [19]. Itdoes not lessen Momigliano's point in the least to add that this

    integration of both with classical narrative was the commonly recognised

    problem of historical writing in the late seventeenth and eighteenth

    centuries the debates between ancients and moderns, polite authors

    and antiquarians, gens de lettresand rudits, all in their several ways turn

    upon it or that the discovery and invention of historical contexts

    unknown to classical historians, into which classical histories had

    somehow to be fitted, had been going on since at latest the sixteenth

    century. A diversity of contexts had been built up, giving rise to theperceptions that structures of human life in the past differed from those

    obtaining in the present, that history itself might come to denote the

    archaeology of the past and the narrative of its transformation into

    subsequent pasts and presents, and that the deeds of individuals and

    peoples, Greeks and barbarians, were no longer simply exemplary, but

    had to be interpreted as certainly performed in past contexts and

    possibly but not certainly active in transforming them into those

    which had existed subsequently at present. To confront this set ofperceptions with the classical paradigm is to confront the 'modern' and

    the 'ancient' understandings of the term 'history', and it is correct to add

    that the Decline and Fallappeared at a time when the two were still

    distinct. Gibbon will sometimes write in the classical mode, re-narrating in

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    10/47

    10

    his text what some 'authority' or 'historian' tells him of ancient actions

    and actors, while adding in erudite footnotes a commentary which now

    and then indicates that he has doubts about what his authority obliges

    him to narrate. It is possible to classify his chapter-headings and sub-headings into those which narrate events and those which generalise

    about episodes and patterns in historical change. There are here and

    there passages in which he pauses to take note of the classical paradigm

    and the circumstances in which he regretfully finds it inappropriate.

    Momigliano was right to note that Gibbon successfully overcame the

    problem of writing both kinds of history together, but did not suggest that

    he dispelled it or that it ceased to exist.

    10. We have to remember that the classical paradigm was not more than

    a paradigm: that is, a model or authoritative programme, which exercised

    great power over reality without necessarily existing in an untrammeled

    form. Among the exemplary individuals whose actions were recounted,

    there had been legislators who founded cities among the barbarians at

    least, there had been prophets who had founded religions and these

    had given human life new laws, new forms, and new structures which had

    made some peoples different from all others. There was a canon of such

    founders: Theseus, Lycurgus, Solon, Romulus, Cyrus and by a dangerouslyimportant elision Moses; and these were remembered not because they

    taught philosophy by their examples, but because they had changed the

    world by instituting new systems of law. There were those remembered

    because they had furthered, or momentarily arrested, or tried and failed

    to prevent, the decay and corruption of the systems the legislators had

    founded Tiberius and Gaius Gracchus, Marius and Sulla, King Josiah and

    Judas Maccabaeus and these could be viewed ironically or tragically, as

    agents whose deeds had had paradoxical results. There were also those Caesar, Augustus, Constantine, Justinian remembered with profound

    ambiguity, because they had transformed the intelligible world under the

    guise of preserving it, in ways which could be evaluated both negatively

    and positively, and in either case divisively. In examining these cases, we

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    11/47

    11

    pass from the antique to the late antique, from the ancient to the

    modern, and from the classical to the neoclassical; but the cases are for

    the most part Roman, and we do not leave behind the historians who

    wrote according to the classical paradigm. From Livy and Tacitusthemselves, Roman historical memory was not simply of triumph and

    domination, but of decline and fall, and the latter if not also the former

    phenomena occurred in a world of structures and contexts, as well as of

    heroes and examples.

    11. Ancient historiography, however, was only in a limited degree

    antiquarian or scholarly, and to understand the genesis of 'history' in its

    modern form we have to examine the growth of clerical elites who

    excelled in the resurrection of past contexts, with which the narratives of

    past deeds came to be surrounded. It is important to bear in mind that

    this was not necessarily what the agents in building these elites saw

    themselves as doing or aimed at doing. We have, in other terms, to

    investigate the growth of contexts, built up by a diversity of actors

    pursuing a diversity of objectives, but ending in each case in the

    construction of a highly textualised tissue of words, perceptions and

    institutions, constituting a past state of affairs in which historical actors

    came to be seen as operating and which came to be seen as having ahistory of its own. Increasingly, each such 'context' came to be

    accompanied by an elite of ruditspossessing the specialised knowledge

    and critical techniques necessary to interpret it; and a point came to be

    reached at which 'history' as we use the term was written by these

    elites, studying the formation and transformation of past contexts, and

    not by 'historians', as the authors of classical narratives, past and

    present, continued to be known.

    12. This is the problem of 'humanism and historiography', examined in a

    recent study of the subject [20] . By 'humanist' a notoriouslycomprehensive term is meant those who published, annotated and

    criticised the texts, first Greco- Roman and classical, later neo-Latin,

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    12/47

    12

    vernacular and medieval, inherited by western European culture from its

    various pasts. They were composed of diverse groups, with diverse skills

    and objectives. If they had anything which was common to all, it was a

    concern with the past states of language, in the first instance Greek andLatin when in the condition of supposed perfection which was

    characterised as 'classical': Greek when it was Attic, Latin when it was

    Augustan, though a valuable study of the 'invention' of the 'classical'

    could be, or very likely has been, written. They often carried their

    insistence on classical canons to the point of fanaticism there were

    those who rejected the whole New Testament on the grounds that the

    Apostles wrote impure Greek [21] but a crucial moment was reachedwhen classicism proved to be self-defeating and it was discovered that

    no 'modern' could write the Greek of Demosthenes or the Latin of Cicero,

    still less make it the living language of his own culture, no matter how

    long and diligently the ancient styles had been studied and practiced

    there. Language thus became the means of reconstituting a past state of

    the culture, and at the same time of distancing the past from those most

    committed to reconstituting it; while the very hopelessness of pursuing

    language to its 'pure' or 'classical' condition led to the discovery that

    language itself had a history and could not be divorced from its contexts

    [22]. By a complex series of reactions and backlashes, the defeat of pureclassicism led scholars to interest themselves in language in its non-

    classical or 'barbarous' conditions: in demotic Greek or late and medieval

    Latin, in the romance vernaculars derived from Latin, or in the altogether

    un-Mediterranean languages in Latin Europe typically Germanic,

    Gothic or Anglo-Saxon which had established themselves as the means

    of certain types of expression. For theological and ecclesiological

    reasons, there were those who studied Hebrew, Aramaic, Syrian and

    Arabic, and sought to decipher Egyptian inscriptions, though a complexof attitudes, Christian, anti-clerical and what we now call 'orientalist',

    kept these studies apart from the 'humanist' mainstream. By a further

    series of responses, certain modern languages Italian in its Tuscan

    form, French in its Parisian, English in its Georgian or Augustan aimed

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    13/47

    13

    at 'classicisms' of their own, imitating or emulating the Greek and Roman

    models, and consequently making discoveries about their own 'Gothic' or

    'polite' history, and comparing the present state of their culture with the

    'barbaric' or 'classical' past.

    13. 'Philology' like 'grammar', usable as a collective term for the whole

    corpus of textual studies thus became capable of providing a world of

    contexts within which the classical paradigm must operate and by which

    it came to be modified. By the mid-eighteenth century, however, it had

    not replaced the continuingly powerful classical paradigm and was not

    necessarily seen as competing with it; historians moved back and forth

    between the two styles, alternating between narratives of action and

    studies of personality on the one hand, examinations of structures and

    their change religion, law, literature, manners on the other, and

    allowing the two to interact as their pens led them. We shall find that

    Gibbon continued in this dual mode to the end of the Decline and Fall, and

    that his doing so had something to do with the maintenance of a still

    partly aristocratic lifestyle and its ideology. Nor would it be sufficient to

    confront the 'old' or classical historiography with a 'new', based on the

    humanist recovery of texts and contexts. There was a third presence, and

    therefore a third contestant, in the relationship. The Neapolitan visionaryGiambattista Vico as is usual with Vico, we have to add that his writings

    could have been known to Gibbon but to all appearance were not

    declared that philology, rather than philosophy, furnished the keys to

    truth, and that history was a series of poems in which the human species

    had inscribed and enacted itself. To understand Vico's claim, we should

    have to address the standing and meaning of the term 'philosophy', and it

    is no less important to do so if we confine ourselves to the less daunting

    task of understanding other historians of the age.

    14. 'Philosophy', as a generic term, denoted the whole field of the human

    mind's knowledge of reality, up to and sometimes beyond the point at

    which reality became the knowledge of God. It included and in principle

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    14/47

    14

    subsumed the study of the processes of knowledge themselves, and a

    central component of Enlightenment was the apparently, and sometimes

    really, humble claim that the human mind should confine itself to the

    study of its own workings and the limited range of knowledge open to it;the philosophical and historical problem of Enlightenment is the extent to

    which this claim to set limits to the mind's powers in fact expanded them.

    'Philosophy' rendered the study of the human and the moral sciences the

    study of 'nature' and increasingly of 'human nature', and the problem in

    understanding the character of 'historical' thought in the eighteenth

    century is to determine the extent to which the study of the increasingly

    rich context of changing conditions of human life, which 'humanism' and

    'philology' had been bringing to light for two or three centuries, was still

    contained within the study of 'nature' or was escaping from it to the point

    where 'history' became an autonomous mode of knowledge. Gibbon, like

    Hume, continued to maintain the unchanging character of 'human nature'

    and 'the human mind', but this was rather a key to understanding the

    infinite diversity of its products and the forms it had assumed in the

    course of history than a means of reducing them to the operations of

    invariable laws. The word 'laws', however, is crucial because of the

    plurality of its meanings. No branch of 'humanism' or of 'philology' had

    been more fecund in the revelation of past contexts than the study ofsystems of law, whether Roman, barbaric or exotic; and just when

    humanist philology was making the discovery that Latin could be spoken

    with purity only in a purely Roman world, humanist jurisprudence had

    been making the same discovery with regard to the practice of Roman

    law [23] . The study of the 'laws and customs' of diverse societies was thestudy of as many societies each in its historical uniqueness, for the

    reason that law organised the fabric of social living in its entirety to the

    point where each law could be practiced only under the conditions whichit had itself organised, and it could be said that human beings without

    losing their common underlying 'human nature', nevertheless became

    distinct cultural, psychological and even moral beings as a result of living

    in societies distinctively organised by their 'laws'. This perception, while

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    15/47

    15

    vital to the humanist and philosopheinvention of 'history' in the modern

    sense of the term, was in itself ancient, resting on the Greek and Roman

    principle that the user was transformed by the usages and acquired a

    'second nature' which was the product of the usages, customs andmanners of a particular social formation. It was of great importance that

    ancient, as well as modern and exotic, systems of law were perceived as

    being partially or wholly based in custom, mos or consuetudo: it could

    thus be said that a people or nation was what it was by virtue of having,

    or having had, its own customs, which were not those of its neighbours,

    and could not be governed, other than despotically, unless governed by

    these customs operating freely [24].

    15. These perceptions entailed both material and moral reality. In

    societies primarily agrarian and secondarily commercial or governed in

    such a way as to entail the ideological assertion of these priorities one

    of law's principal functions was to regulate, describe and inscribe the

    occupancy of land, and the notion of 'property' originally denoted the ties

    which 'law' declared to link the individual to the land and define his being

    as that of an individual so linked. Some individuals were so far bound to it

    as to become objects in which other individuals had 'property'; others

    became 'proprietors', meaning individuals whose 'rights in', 'to', or 'over'land, beasts, goods and other individuals made them 'free' in the sense of

    having access to the law and a capacity to claim, assert, vocalise and

    inscribe a place in its processes which defined their autonomy. This

    capacity was generalised and philosophised until it became a moral

    claim, an assertion of capacity for both autonomy and sociability; and

    one of the central assertions of Eurocentricity, as far back at least as the

    sixteenth century, was the assertion that only in Europe had the

    interaction of barbaric freedom with Roman jurisprudence[25]

    producedthe free tenures protected by law which had made the European free,

    sociable, dynamic, expansive, and capable of assuming moral

    responsibility for his own actions capable, in short, of libertas et

    imperium. A great deal of what we call 'materialist' social thinking

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    16/47

    16

    originates in the exploration of the propositions that personality is rooted

    in property, society in the earth and its products, spirit in matter, the

    Logos in the Flesh.

    16. Jurisprudence became the main source of scientia civilis[26] in thematerial, institutional, moral and therefore philosophical senses of the

    term, because it furnished the richest and most comprehensive set of

    vocabularies for describing and regulating the full range of man's life in

    civil society. (The term 'man' is used deliberately, because the

    jurisprudence of gender, in so far as such a thing could be said to exist,

    operated to exclude women, not from society, but from property,

    citizenship, visibility and history.) During the seventeenth century, and

    running on into the eighteenth, occurred the revival of natural

    jurisprudence often under Remonstrant and Arminian auspices which

    tended to supply a morality of social living, in the place of a theology of

    grace, as the chief instrument of human happiness here and hereafter;

    we have seen how this was the instrument by which enlightenment

    replaced wars of religion, especially in Protestant cultures. The scientia

    civilis, based on philology and enlarging its scope as it supplied an

    increasing wealth of contexts in which life was conducted and actions

    recorded and evaluated, became at the same time the dominantvocabulary of both morality and soteriology, approaching the point at

    which the incarnate God himself must be understood as a social and

    historical being. The science of man became a science of nature and

    society, and there arose schemes which depicted the generation of

    society itself in the course of nature. If there had been a time in nature

    when men existed but society did not it was easier to depict this in

    terms of pre-Christian philosophy and jurisprudence than in those of the

    Hebrew and Christian scriptures such schemes were in a sensehistorical; but they tended to employ concepts of nature universal and

    abstract enough to be incompatible with that reconstitution of specific

    contexts in the past which is of the essence of post-classical history. This

    is why it was supposed, for so long that the assumption is not yet

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    17/47

    17

    eliminated from our minds, that schemes of natural jurisprudence were

    by their nature unhistorical, and that a mental revolution against their

    paradigmatic domination was necessary before the human being could

    discover his being in history.

    17. As against this, however, we have been increasingly aware of

    processes in early modern European thought through which the genesis

    of society became historically specific and both incorporated and

    generated those contexts of past culture on which historical thinking is

    founded. Jurists supposed a 'state of nature' in which property and law

    did not yet exist, and went on to hypothecate processes rooted in human

    nature in the raw, by which appropriation could be said to have occurred

    [27]. In an important conceptual move, however, widely distributed andperhaps unthinkingly performed, they connected these processes with a

    scheme first found in Greek and Latin poetry and cosmogony, which

    depicted primeval humans first as gathering the fruits of the earth and

    hunting its animal inhabitants, then as learning to domesticate its beasts,

    next to cultivate its soil for vegetable products, and finally to exchange

    these products through invented metallic media 'money the medium of

    exchange'. In this marriage of the poetic imagination with natural

    jurisprudence the process could be accommodated to the Book ofGenesis only by supposing post-diluvial man to have regressed to a 'state

    of nature' are to be found the origins of those 'stages of history', two or

    four in number, which dominate so much in the increasingly historical

    jurisprudence and scientia civilisof the eighteenth century [28]. Changesin the philosophy of law and the theological and epistemological

    perceptions of human nature did so much to facilitate their growth that it

    can be studied as part of the history of philosophy, but this is not quite

    the same as the history of that contextualisation of the past which is hereconsidered as central to the history of historiography. Here processes

    must be discovered which led to the identification of these abstractly

    conceived and universal stages with specific societies or conceptualised

    past stages of societies actually existing. A crucial role must be assigned

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    18/47

    18

    to the identification developing slowly after the Spanish encounter with

    some but not other Mesoamerican peoples of the solitary and feral

    existence of wandering individuals or male-headed patriarchal groups,

    imagined by Greek poets and philosophers as the condition of theCyclopes, first with the human condition in the 'state of nature', next with

    the small kinship-based societies, sometimes in or near to a hunter-

    gatherer economy, encountered or invented by European voyagers and

    settlers in various parts of the globe. In this way occurred the momentous

    and destructive invention of the 'savage' and the identification of the

    'state of nature' with the 'savage condition' imposed upon specific

    peoples in lands, outside Europe, and now and then within it [29]. Theancient literary invention of the 'wild man', 'man of the forests', selvaggio,

    sauvageor orang-utan[30] was conflated with the jurists' conception ofthe 'natural man' or man in the 'state of nature', not yet humanised by

    appropriation or the invention of law or extended social relations; and the

    resultant construction was imposed upon a great many human societies,

    supposed to be mere hunter-gatherers because they did not practice

    agriculture by the individualising instrument of the plough. Such societies

    were supposed to be living in the 'state of nature', not yet fully humanised

    as individuals; and the effects of this supposition, very often devastating

    for them, greatly enhanced European societies' consciousness of theirown historicity. Navigation, colonisation and commerce organised large

    sections of global humanity into the increasingly if misleading concrete

    stages invented by the scientia civilis.

    18. Concurrently with this development, but in ways that situate it more

    intimately interior to a European consciousness of history, occurred the

    growth at the end of the seventeenth century of a sense of almost

    revolutionary modernity in the public and theoretical languages ofseveral societies of Europe's northern Atlantic seacoasts, as they

    succeeded in putting behind them an era of religious wars. They saw

    themselves as distinguished by the growth of credit structures which

    facilitated the state's control of armed force [31] , and by a post-fanatical

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    19/47

    19

    form of religion which put an end to unreal perceptions of God as

    immediately present and made virtue and even salvation an affair of

    practising the usages and values of civilised society. They grouped these

    changes together under the paradigm of 'commerce', and expressed anacute awareness of the distance which 'commerce' established between

    'modern' society and its Christian, feudal, barbaric and even classical

    predecessors. The relations they were able to affirm between themselves

    and the first and last of these four were especially crucial to their self-

    understanding and self-evaluation, and it has been suggested that this

    was the point at which Western man for the first time saw his history as

    paradoxical, entailing both secular gain and cultural loss [32] . Neo-classical in their continuing admiration for Greek and Roman values, they

    perceived not only as had their Renaissance predecessors that they

    could not re-create the life of ancient society, but that their neoclassical

    values themselves commanded that they should not attempt to do so.

    There thus arose 'quarrels of the ancients and moderns', in which some

    claimed a modern capacity to achieve ancient values more fully than had

    the ancients themselves, and others laid claim to values which surpassed

    and negated those at which the ancients had aimed; while the capacity to

    criticise modern society in the name of ancient values was by no means

    extinguished [33]. The succession of past contexts to one another,around which the concept of a civil history was taking shape, became

    increasingly exposed to conflicting evaluations, and the process of

    historical change was perceived in correspondingly sophisticated terms.

    19. We are outlining some of the processes by which there took shape in

    the late seventeenth and eighteenth centuries a 'civil' and even a

    'philosophical history', with which 'history' written according to the

    classical paradigm, persisting in a deeply neoclassical culture, had to co-exist and continued to contend. A crucial late step in its development was

    the advent of ethical and aesthetic schemes of 'manners' and

    'politeness', denoting codes of human interaction, partly courtly and

    partly civic in origin, which linked the Ciceronian and Senecan codes of

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    20/47

    20

    beneficial exchange in ancient society with those of modern 'commerce'

    a term which denoted exchange of services, manners, ideas and values,

    as well as of material goods. These codes were neither heroic nor

    transcendent, but were consciously limited to the conduct of the existingsociety and its culture. It came to be affirmed, however, that in an epoch

    when 'commerce' here very much in the sense of 'trade' had been

    more highly developed than in any which had preceded it, a 'politeness'

    often identified with 'taste', 'science', and the epistemologies of Locke

    and the third earl of Shaftesbury, could flourish in ways to which all

    previous history, organised into 'stages' of the growth of 'commerce',

    served as the introduction. It became possible for Voltaire to propose

    rewriting history, not as the Esprit des Loisbut in the form of an Essai sur

    les Moeurs: for Burke to declare that manners were more important than

    laws; for Burke and Ferguson to affirm that a universal commerce of

    manners distinguished modern Europe both from Asian civilisation and

    from that of ancient Greece and Rome [34] .

    20. We cannot understand the philosophy of manners without

    comprehending the extent to which they were designed to replace the

    attempt of a Christian civilisation to live directly by spiritual values; and in

    the setting of the present chapter, this means that we must retrace oursteps and examine the Christian impact upon history written according to

    the classical paradigm, as well as the relation between Christian history

    and the modern historiography which was designed to replace classical

    and Christian alike. The classical paradigm defined 'history' in terms of

    exemplary deeds in war and statecraft; it had an extensive moral

    dimension and could narrate and evaluate the protagonist's deeds in

    terms of justice and legislation as well as exemplary prowess; we have

    seen that within its structure, 'history' could become the birth, growthand decline of a society or a system of laws. Yet its morality was secular

    and this-worldly; glory was one of its ultimate concepts; its vision of the

    world was political, and its vision of politics heroic. The classical age in

    which it was written had not contained the vision of a church, a human

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    21/47

    21

    association formed to live in this world while pursuing values to be

    realised only beyond it, an association which extended beyond the living

    and even the dead, considered as members of society, to become a

    fellowship and communion with God himself, said to have lived on earth ina human body and on his departure to have left his disciples members of

    his spiritual substance. It was far from clear how the history of such a

    church could be written, and writing history might be a means of

    diminishing or replacing the belief in and practice of its existence. The

    advent of Christian history was thus a challenge to the classical paradigm

    [35] .

    21. It was a further problem to comprehend how a churchman,

    consecrated as a priest to pursue Christian fellowship and communion

    with God, could figure as a historian given the sense in which the

    classical paradigm defined that term. He was not primarily a citizen; the

    alternation between civic action and leisurely retirement, in which history

    was written and which was central to the understanding of what history

    was, meant nothing to him. He might be a celibate, even a monk,

    separated by vows from the physical and political being of society; even

    as one of the 'secular' clergy, living by definition 'in the world', he lived

    there in pursuit of values which were not those of the city or the empire,and church and city might unite in asking him, from polar opposite

    positions, why he was writing history at all. It is not easy to call to mind a

    case in which she was a nun, one of a community of women pledged to

    live out of this world; though given the spread of scholarship among such

    communities, even this most scandalous challenge to the classical

    paradigm is not unthinkable. Male or female, the ecclesiastical or

    sacerdotal historian was mistrusted, as living by values other than those

    which commended and legitimated the writing of history; Gibbon oncewrote of a monk, who in the profound ignorance of human life had

    presumed to exercise the office of historian [36] . Nevertheless, theexistence and even the legitimacy of ecclesiastical history could not be

    denied, given the premise that the church was an association of human

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    22/47

    22

    beings living in the world and its time, as well as a communion of saints or

    fellowship of spiritual beings living beyond both. There was, in

    Augustinian parlance, a church militant as well as a church triumphant.

    The former was in history, and made history as well as suffering itself tobe made by it; if as the orthodox affirmed the former was of one

    substance with the latter, history was even shaped by the church

    triumphant acting from beyond it. There were those as diverse as

    Marsilius of Padua, Thomas Hobbes of Malmesbury, and Benjamin Hoadly

    bishop of Bangor who laboured to deny the essential unity of church

    militant and church triumphant, and presented the former as part of

    secular history in no way differing from it; but when these appeared, they

    found themselves confronted by a formidable apparatus of sacred and

    ecclesiastical history which they must go about unmaking. Hobbes did

    this by representing the church as the ghost of the deceased Roman

    empire, and by implication little more. We need to understand, however,

    what more it claimed to be.

    22. God in all three persons existed beyond time and history, but had

    acted in time and the history of mankind by a series of acts, distributed

    among revelation, covenant, prophecy and incarnation, of which the two

    most crucial were the 'old dispensation' given at Sinai which hadconstituted Israel as a people peculiarly God's and the 'new

    dispensation' consisting in Christ's incarnation, death and redemption

    and concluding in the descent of the Spirit at Pentecost; this had brought

    the old Israel to the end of its mission and substituted a new, the church

    which was at once a communion of humans in fellowship with God and

    one another, and the continued presence of Christ in his mystical though

    no longer his natural body. This series of acts, not yet concluded since

    more were to come, constituted 'sacred history', the record of God'saction in and upon time, and of time as transformed by that action.

    Sacred history could be written and had left its own scriptures to record

    it; it was possible for a human author to paraphrase and enlarge it by

    means of commentary. Sacred history in the first place consisted of the

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    23/47

    23

    record of action with regard to specific societies: initially the people of

    Israel, a community existing among the great empires of Egypt and

    Babylon, Assyria and Media, Macedon and Rome; subsequently the

    church, a communion local in its origins but held capable of including thewhole of humanity. There were also those to whom God had not

    communicated himself directly, but whose history could nevertheless be

    traced, ever since the dispersion of the houses of Ham, Shem and Japhet

    after the Confusion of Tongues had distinguished them into many

    lineages, or gentes, of whom God had chosen to act only through that of

    Abraham, Isaac and Jacob. Sacred history had as its paired opposite that

    which was known as 'gentile history', and the question was whether the

    history of peoples not defined by covenant and revelation formed part of

    God's action in the world or was consigned to some outer darkness of

    merely 'secular' history meaning by that term the 'history' of time

    unredeemed by divine action. If so excluded, did the uncovenanted

    peoples generate a history significant in their own terms, or was their

    existence devoid of ultimate meaning? The easy solution was to bring

    them into the story in so far as their actions had affected the history of

    God's purposes through, or for, his own people. The prophets of the Exile

    had presented the kings of Egypt, Babylon and Assyria as God's

    instruments in the punishment of Israel grown false to its covenant withhim, and a history of the ancient Near or Middle East could therefore be

    constructed around that of Israel as paradoxically its center a small

    and disregarded nation possessing a significance exceeding that of its

    enormous neighbours. But the problem grew far more complex when the

    history of the first Israel, and then that of the second, encountered that

    of Troy, Athens, Sparta and Rome: a history neither barbarous, idolatrous

    nor oriental, but documented in incomparable richness by a literature

    and sculpture, including a historiography, altogether its own a literaturewhich furnished Christian and Enlightened civilisation with almost all its

    cultural models, and appropriated the names of 'humane letters',

    'humanity' in the sense of humanitasand 'humane' or 'human' as opposed

    to sacred history. The Greek and Roman gentestransformed the question

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    24/47

    24

    of gentile history by rendering the history of unredeemed man the history

    of Athens and Rome as opposed to Jerusalem, and enlarging 'classical'

    and 'humane' history to a point where it threatened to engulf sacred

    history itself. The neoclassical historian could choose to be a neo-pagan,finding the meaning of existence in classical values rather than in

    Christian; and whatever his choices, his hand was strengthened by the

    circumstance that his history contained that of the Hellenic 'philosophy',

    Platonist and Aristotelian, on which a great part of the edifice of Christian

    belief and doctrine had come to be founded.

    23. The genealogy of the sons of Noah could be employed in tracing the

    origins of all the peoples, though it did not replace the creation and

    ancestor myths recorded of other gentes, including especially those of

    the Greeks and Romans. There arose and was intensified by humanist

    scholarship in the fifteenth through seventeenth centuries a

    complicated science known as chronology, aimed at reconciling the

    gentile accounts of primeval time and the actors in it with those given in

    the Old Testament and legitimised by the followers of the New [37] . Of allbranches of premodern Christian learning this is perhaps the most alien

    to the post-Enlightened mind; it is full of such propositions as James

    Ussher's undeservedly notorious dating of the Creation to 4004 B. C., andidentifications of biblical with non-biblical figures that read more

    strangely still; but it was the discovery of geological time in the

    nineteenth century which put an end to it, rather than the denunciations

    of Jewish chronology by philosopheswho could only substitute some

    other or no other, and we shall find that its abandonment produced

    immediate effects less startling than might be supposed. However, the

    science of sacred and universal history was greatly complicated by the

    increasing knowledge, thrust upon Europeans in the age of globalexpansion, of civilisations Indian, Chinese and Meso-American [38] , notto be found in biblical or Greco-Roman literature and possessing

    chronologies of their own even harder to reconcile with the Judeo-

    Christian than were those of Mesopotamia or still-undeciphered Egypt.

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    25/47

    25

    Some of these chronologies, like the Maya, Europeans did their best to

    destroy; others, above all the Chinese, survived, were reported and

    presented Christian thought with new problems. It was not merely that

    Chinese and Hindu chronologies were excessively hard to reconcile withthose worked out in the Christian-Hellenic-Mesopotamian encounter, or

    that China, vaguely known to the ancients, and America, utterly unknown

    to them, presented difficulties to the Noachic genealogies. The latter

    problem was in fact solved by supposing to our minds not objectionably

    that America had been peopled by humans from northern Asia, thus

    making both Chinese and pre-Columbian Americans descendants of

    either Ham or Japhet. The crux was rather that the newly-discovered

    civilisations enlarged and complicated the problem of gentile history, and

    so of the identity between sacred history and universal.

    24. Gentile history might be excluded from sacred history, on the grounds

    that the Lord had not made himself known to the gentiles through

    revelation and covenant, and so had not employed or commissioned

    them in the fulfillment of his purposes. In that case their history might

    have gone on at a distance, in darkness and without meaning; at most

    exemplifying the condition of fallen man when grace was not extended to

    it. But it came to be held that there was a natural as well as a revealedlaw, and a harmony of some kind between the two; so that the ancient as

    well as the newly-discovered gentiles (or heathen) had lived in nature

    and according to it, and might be the subjects at least of natural history

    meaning investigations of nature not necessarily entailing the written

    records of human actions. History was only one of the sciences of man,

    and natural jurisprudence in the role of scientia civiliswas increasing the

    number of the latter. The gentiles, furthermore, were not excluded from

    the providence of a God who was lord of all the earth and must employ allmankind in the fulfillment of his purposes. There was a sense, however, in

    which no history of providence could be written; its ways were inscrutable

    and past finding out, and became visible, even as mysteries, only at those

    points at which they intersected with the record of revealed 'sacred

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    26/47

    26

    history' in the proper sense of the term. Christian chronology, which

    flourished in renaissance and baroque forms, was in fact the science of

    these intersections; and 'universal history', as laid out by such a master

    as Bossuet [39] , was the history of God's actions in the old and newdispensations, written so as to include the history of those gentile nations

    who had impinged upon it and acquired significance from their part in it.

    Egypt, Babylon, Assyria, Macedon, Persia and Rome had played vital if

    hostile roles in the history of the two dispensations, from the Pharaoh of

    Exodusthrough Pilate in the Gospels to the Caesars of the persecutions;

    and we might think of Bossuet as a Christian Herodotus, aware that the

    great actions of the heathens as well as the Jews and Christians must not

    be forgotten, and that the history of the former must be written, but more

    insistent than Herodotus that it was significant, and therefore intelligible,

    only as contributory (through the mysterious wisdom of providence) to

    the latter. The history of Islam, however inimically viewed, was visible

    from the standpoint of sacred history, though it arose too late to play a

    part in the making of the dispensations, and therefore need not be

    studied in much detail. But problems of quite another sort arose from the

    discovery of civilisations and histories in further Asia and Mesoamerica,

    which were not mentioned in either sacred or classical history, could only

    be remotely connected with Judeo- Christian chronology, and had playedno part whatever, not even a hostile one, in sacred history as the record

    of the dispensations. There were now known to be recorded 'gentile'

    histories altogether indifferent to the history of God's actions in the world

    unless the latter could be rewritten so as to include them and

    'universal history' could henceforth be understood either as what it

    meant to such as the compilers of the English Universal Historystudied

    by Gibbon, namely an attempted encyclopedia of all the histories of all

    the nations so far as they were known, whether they interacted withsacred history or not [40] . There could in principle be a natural, even acivil, history of man, or of human society, written independently of the

    Judeo-Christian dispensations; we shall have occasion to note the

    savagery with which Voltaire employed Chinese history to displace

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    27/47

    27

    Jewish, and by implication Christian history from any central place. This

    did not mean that he wanted to study Chinese history for its own sake,

    though there were both Jesuits and philosopheswho did; once he had

    achieved his destructive purpose he dropped it, and the Essai sur lesMoeurs, in name an histoire universelle, is in fact a history of Europe.

    Modern historiography has been so much a product of Europe's quarrel

    with its various pasts that the histories of India, China, Japan and the

    peoples without history [41] have yet to be normally included in it, andit is easier to contest the notion of history itself than to write it on a

    global scale. Comprehensive histories of the human race for the most

    part resemble the original Universal Historyin being libraries rather than

    unitary volumes.

    25. Sacred history merged into 'ecclesiastical history' at the point where

    the church became the vehicle of Christ's presence among his

    worshippers, and the several events of divine action in the world became,

    as it were, institutionalised in the church's continuing existence, to

    endure until the climactic events of the eschataor last days. As time

    lengthened in the expectation of these events, it became possible and

    necessary to envisage the church's continuity as history, and extend that

    vision to include either sacred or gentile history previous to the events Incarnation, Resurrection, Ascension, Pentecost which had established

    the church after Christ's physical departure. Ecclesiastical historians were

    thus both sacred historians and historians of the church considered as a

    human community; the first of them, after the evangelists themselves,

    was Eusebius of Caesarea, a contemporary of the emperor Constantine,

    considered the founder of ecclesiastical history as a literary genre [42].From him the genre was held to have derived a dual character. In the first

    place it was designed drawing on the events of sacred history in thebroader sense to validate the church's continuously acting as the

    vehicle, primarily of Christ's presence in the sacraments, secondly of

    orthodox truth concerning his teachings and his nature, thirdly of the

    authority to administer the sacraments and the word in which he was

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    28/47

    28

    present, and therefore to speak in his name. As the history of the church

    became increasingly a history of debate and contestation concerning

    Christ's nature, and concerning the distribution of authority among the

    officers and ministers of the church in which he was present, the historyof these debates required to be written; but it was written with the aim of

    upholding orthodoxy and authority and became in its way a vehicle and

    not the only one of tradition. It was still being written in this way by

    Bossuet, Tillemont, Fleury and other Catholic ecclesiastical historians in

    the generations immediately preceding Gibbon's.

    26. In the second place, Eusebius had been the historian of Constantine,

    and therefore of the establishment of Christianity as the recognised

    religion of the empire: a momentous if not climactic event in both

    ecclesiastical and civil history. From this time history became tam

    ecclesiastica quam civilis, a narrative of sacred co-existing with secular

    history the word 'secular' denoted both time and the organisation of

    human life as it was lived in time and the history of the church as we

    have seen it emerging became intertwined with that of civil authority and

    civil action; a history conceived not merely in gentile but in specifically

    Roman and classical terms. The ecclesiastical historian became one of

    those who wrote to the requirements of the classical paradigm, but sincehe was a citizen of the civitas Deirather than of the civitas terrenahe had

    his own ends in writing and developed his own idiom [43] , and there wasalways something anomalous about his presence in the company of

    classical historians. As a minister of the Spirit, what business had he

    recounting the deeds of emperors? How did those deeds appear when

    performed in the context set by sacred history? As a member of the

    vehicle of grace which was above nature and transformed it, was it his

    function to hold the mirror of history in which human nature wasreflected? The views one held of the nature of Christ might affect one's

    understanding of both ecclesiastical and civil authority, and the process

    might be repeated in reverse; neither the emperor Constantine nor his

    historian Eusebius had always been orthodox in the debate between Arius

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    29/47

    29

    and Athanasius, and later historians of the church were obliged to record

    the partial heresy of the church's first historian [44] . The intensity oftheological debate, and the civil authority's involvement in it, in the age

    of the Fathers and the Councils, gave the ecclesiastical historian much torecord that was unedifying and even scandalous, and sacred history

    which narrated the actions of the Spirit had at the same time to narrate

    the actions of men, even of saints and confessors, in whom human nature

    appeared in its least redeemed form. This was inherent in the concept of

    the church militant in a still fallen world, and did not in itself challenge

    orthodoxy; but it offered a series of tempting opportunities and telling

    arguments to those who would recount the church's human and civil

    history in ways that challenged its sacredness.

    27. During the two centuries preceding that in which Gibbon wrote the

    Decline and Fallthe structure of ecclesiastical history as perceived in

    Latin Christianity was deeply changed as a consequence of the

    Protestant Reformation [45] . For Catholics it remained, with greatlyincreased urgency, a means of displaying the uninterrupted continuity of

    orthodoxy and authority in the church that was its continuing presence.

    This enterprise heightened rather than retarded the growth of techniques

    of textual and other criticism within Catholic scholarship, but these werealways at the service of authority. A crisis had occurred in the late

    seventeenth century, when Richard Simon's histoires critiquesof the Old

    and New Testaments had aimed to show that the scriptures were less

    reliable than the tradition of the church that interpreted them, but had

    horrified Bossuet and others who saw Simon as separating authority from

    its foundations [46]; to sceptical (but not necessarily unbelieving)onlookers it seemed that Bossuet was determined to have his cake and

    eat it. This, however, was primarily a crisis within the discourse of Catholicauthority. Since Luther's own time there had been a Protestant discourse

    as it came to be termed [47] which challenged orthodoxecclesiastical history at its roots. A great part of the history of the church

    must now be a narrative and explanation of papal usurpation of the

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    30/47

    30

    acquisition by the successors of St. Peter (if that was what they were) of

    powers that did not rightfully belong to them; and the problem of the

    terms in which this history of false authority was to be written merged

    with that of establishing the structure in which Christ's true presence hadbeen maintained during the centuries there were enough of them to

    constitute a millennium of the papal usurpation. The simplest rhetorical

    device available to Protestant ecclesiastical historians was that of

    supposing that since the true church was by definition the presence of

    Christ, a structure claiming falsely to act in his name must be the work,

    and thereby the presence, of Antichrist a being mentioned in the

    Christian apocalyptic writings and now promoted to an incessantly

    important role in Protestant historiography. To identify the papacy with

    Antichrist was to institutionalise the latter, and furthermore to identify

    the greater part of the church's institutional history as his work and his

    presence. The visible church was condemned, and the history of the true

    church, Christ's true presence, identified with that of the invisible. Christ

    had been present in his Word, acting in the hearts of his true followers

    oppressed by the powers of this world, including that of the papal

    Antichrist. But if the church's institutional structure, including its

    distribution of constituted authority, was held to provide the mystical

    body in which Christ's incarnation was continued, a strictly invisiblechurch did not furnish him with such a body and might be held to

    compromise the doctrine of his incarnation. The history of the church

    might come to be a history of recurrent pentecosts, of actions by the

    Third rather than the Second Person of the Trinity; a history of the active

    Spirit rather than the communicated Son; an antinomian history in which

    the institutions of the visible church were always corruptible and normally

    corrupt, and the Spirit acted occasionally to maintain the invisible church

    whidh resisted corruption. There were many sectarian histories of thiskind, one of them Gottfried Arnold's Kirchen- und Ketzerhistoriewhich

    Gibbon did not read at Lausanne [48] .

    28. In these extreme forms, Protestant historiography became in the

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    31/47

    31

    eyes of many including many Protestants a history of enthusiasm

    and not an ecclesiastical history at all. That is, there were many

    Protestants who most strongly desired to remain part of the history of

    the visible church and of the continuous structure of its authority sincethe Apostles, the Fathers and the Councils; they desired to remain within

    Christ's body, the action in this world of the undivided Trinity, and of the

    history of the Logos Incarnate. For such Protestants, the history of the

    papal usurpation must be written differently. There were those who

    horrified their fellows by denying that the Pope was Antichrist, and of

    these some wrote the history of papal authority as an accident of civil

    history, an effect of the disruption of the Roman empire and the advent

    of the Gothic and Frankish kingdoms [49]. Gallican Catholics, who did notaffirm the papal power a usurpation, but maintained the independence of

    the monarchie franaisefrom its jurisdiction, did not write history very

    differently; and this was to remove the papal usurpation from the field of

    sacred history where it figured as an Antichristian or a diabolic event

    into that of ecclesiastical and at the same time that of civil history. By

    this route, as by many others, we reach the point at which civil and

    ecclesiastical history were seen to interact. The initiator of such a history

    was of course Constantine, who like his historian Eusebius was displayed

    in a momentously ambiguous role. On the one hand he was an actor insacred history, the imperial prophet who had seen the cross in the sky

    and acted by victory in battle to unite Christ's body, the church, with the

    structure of empire. On the other hand he was God's flawed instrument,

    rather Saul than David; a deeply imperfect being as, to do him justice,

    he did not deny who had brought the church into conjunction with the

    necessary imperfections of the earthly city, with consequences of which

    the almost immediate outbreak of heresy and his own involvement in it

    were emblematically the first. Constantine was a contested figurethroughout the medieval debates between church and empire, and the

    early-modern debates between the church catholic and the church

    reformed; whenever, in short, the conjunction between spiritual and

    secular authority seemed imperfect or contestable. To some he had won

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    32/47

    32

    eternal glory by setting up the church in the empire; to others he had

    erred by subjecting the church to the empire and enabling emperors to

    make unjustified claims on popes and bishops; to others again, he had

    erred not merely by enabling popes to make claims on emperors, but farmore deeply by involving the church in the sin of attempting the exercise

    of civil government. To many this was the origin of the papal usurpation,

    to some the beginning of Antichrist's reign in the church, which had

    commenced its thousand-year rule from one or other of Constantine's

    donations to the clergy [50] . In the Scots version of a widespreadanecdote:

    When Constantine set up Sylvester hie,

    On civill seat in his empire of Rome,

    This voyce from heaven then sounded michtilly:

    Now poyson is pourit out on Christendome. [51]

    But if the civil power was among the victims of Antichrist's usurpation, it

    might be thought of as maintaining even as acting as the vehicle of

    the continued presence of Christ among men. The Christian emperor

    might be Christ's captain against his false representative even though,

    perhaps even because, Christ had warned Peter to put up his sword; hemight even be Christ's representative, entitled to act in his person, and

    the empire rather than the church the vehicle of Christ's reign among

    men. When the thousand-year reign of Antichrist was ended, the

    thousand-year reign of the saints might begin, with the emperor at its

    head until Christ should return in his risen person. Such visions were

    articulated when medieval emperors came to Rome intending a reform of

    the papacy; they were entertained again when the English king, imperato

    in suo regno, took up the cause of the invisible church and a new andpurer Constantine rendered it visible by embodying it in his kingdom.

    Such a Protestant emperor might come closer being a 'type of Christ', a

    figure of incarnation, than the unbaptised Constantine himself had ever

    come.

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    33/47

    33

    29. In the lifetimes of the two generations preceding Gibbon's the

    period in which his kind of historical consciousness was taking shape

    the rulers of Christian and especially Protestant Europe displayed (as we

    have seen) an earnest desire to free themselves from those typified roles

    in sacred and especially millennial history which had proved above all in

    the British kingdoms so disastrously double-edged a weapon in their

    struggle with the papacy. The Gallican Louis XIV found it easier to play

    the role of an Augustus than that of a Constantine; his adversary William

    III rode a white horse and figured as a liberating and millennial emperor

    only in the imagination of Protestant Ireland, being at pains to downplay

    the role in that of Britain, Holland and the Huguenot exiles. Bayle

    triumphed over Jurieu because it was increasingly an objective amongtheir contemporaries to show that the civil power was obtaining the

    ascendancy over the ecclesiastical and putting an end to religious

    conflict. Sculptors, painters and historians joined to depict the rulers of

    the age in neo- classical garb and baroque settings with the same end in

    view; the image of a pre-Christian past in which there had been no church

    and no theological conflicts was serving the modern purpose of rendering

    civil authority (whether absolutist or constitutionalist) supreme in a

    Christian society. Lay authors joined an apparent majority of clericalspokesmen in insisting that sacred history occurred only in the contexts

    provided by civil society and its history; as the Neapolitan Pietro

    Giannone put it, the church was in the republic and not the other way

    round [52] . Pressed in a certain direction, this perception could as wehave repeatedly seen end by depriving the church, and Christ with it, of

    any claim to a divine nature. There was nothing unorthodox, however, in

    affirming that the church was both a divine and a human society, existing

    in both sacred and civil history; and it was often conservative Gallican,

    Lutheran and Anglican historians who put forward the argument, which

    radical believers and unbelievers could both exploit, that the church as a

    human society had been shaped by civil history and had followed the

    increasingly complex patterns of its development. There were orthodox

    historians who elaborated the history of Christian doctrine itself as

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    34/47

    34

    moving towards just this understanding of its own character, and losing

    none of its orthodoxy in the process. In this way historiography acquired

    a dual structure, at once ecclesiastical and civil, to employ a phrase

    common among English historians between Clarendon and Hume [53];and the two served as contexts to one another. If the history of the

    church must in the last analysis conform to that of civil society, the

    history of the latter must be understood in terms of its interactions with

    the church and its claims to embody the actions of the Spirit in sacred

    history, and no amount of 'secularisation' of history would ever return it

    to what it had been in pre-Christian antiquity. We have reached the last

    and the greatest of the contextualisations and clericalisations which were

    imposed on the classical paradigm and transformed it.

    30. The classical paradigm none the less persisted with extraordinary

    strength. Not only was there a continuous undergrowth of exemplary

    miroirs des princes, but the greatest of Enlightened historians Gibbon

    among them commented on the sustained pressure they were under to

    write classical history and their inability to comply with it or to escape

    from it. This predicament can be traced back to the late Renaissance and

    the beginnings of the Wars of Religion, if not further. The most admired

    'modern' historians those, that is to say, proclaimed to have equalledthe achievements of antiquity were held to have equalled the

    achievements of Tacitus [54] ; and when one looks in the Tacitean mirror,one sees not exemplary actions good and evil, so much as the dark and

    knotty mysteries of ragione di statoin which the springs of human

    conduct are forever obscured and the consequences of human actions

    forever unpredictable. One sees Tiberius rather than Scipio, the palace

    rather than the forum, and it is possible to argue that history has become

    the mirror of ragione di statoand the arcana imperiibecause corruptionand tyranny have prevailed over virtue and liberty; in the history of a true

    republic all would be open and intelligible, and the fall of political man

    would not have occurred. But the great Tacitean historians admired in the

    late Renaissance and the baroque period were concerned with historical

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    35/47

    35

    changes even more complex than the decay of liberty, if like their

    predecessors they were the chroniclers of defeat rather than victory.

    Francesco Guicciardini's Storia d'Italiawas concerned with the conflict

    between Hapsburg and Valois which destroyed the city-state politics ofItaly and was the forerunner of the bipolar politics of the European state

    system, and after him the neo-classical masters were historians of

    reason of state and wars of religion. Jacques-Auguste de Thou's

    Historiarum Sui Temporis libri CXXXVII(1605) was a history of the wars in

    France and the Netherlands [55] ; Paolo Sarpi's Historia del ConcilioTridentino(1619) studied the arcana imperii papalisat the heart of the

    Counter-Reformation, and advanced a Tacitean understanding of

    ecclesiastical politics themselves [56] ; P. C. Hooft's NederlandscheHistoorien(1642) was a history of the Dutch revolt against Spain no less

    Tacitean than exemplary [57] ; Lord Clarendon's History of the Rebellion(1702) narrated the civil wars and wars of religion in the three British

    kingdoms [58] . All of these were neo-classical histories; they excelledaccording to the canons of the classical paradigm, yet they dealt with

    matters above all those of history tam ecclesiastica quam civilis of

    which the ancient historians could have had no knowledge at all. They

    were the heirs of Eusebius as well as of Tacitus, but were moving into

    post- medieval and post-Reformation world whose neo-classicism wasparadoxically the emblem of its modernity. A lesser but unjustly

    neglected figure Thomas May, the parliamentary historian of the First

    Civil War, who had earlier written verse histories of great medieval kings

    [59] explains the difficulty of writing classical history underseventeenth-century conditions. However heroic, actions are not

    exemplary when performed in an 'unnatural' civil war; their motivation is

    more obscure than even Tacitus knew, when shaped by differences of

    religious conviction. Speeches by captains to their soldiers cannot berecorded, even if delivered, in the din of a gunpowder battlefield; and

    their place is taken by an exchange of printed manifestoes, unknown to

    the ancients, which has to be considered as itself contributing to

    constrain actions and shape events [60]. The neo-classical, even the

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    36/47

    36

    Tacitist, historian writes in a world where the classical paradigm is only

    partly applicable.

    31. All these historical changes, or rather all these shapings of historicalcontexts unknown to the classical paradigm, were accompanied by

    recent technological or social innovations, such as gunpowder,

    typography, navigation, commerce, fiscality, the standing army, civil

    religion; medieval innovations, such as feudalism, scholasticism,

    barbarian language and laws; late antique innovations, such as Roman

    law, the theology and the authority structure of the Christian church.

    These, and any other discoveries and inventions which might impose

    themselves on the early modern and early Enlightened mind, could be

    brought together under such general rubrics as 'manners' or 'civil

    society', and employed as contexts within which histories according to

    the classical paradigm continued to be written.

    32. David Hume's History of Englandwas divided into reigns, each

    narrated in language closely following that of the chroniclers of the time;

    yet this language was as far as possible rendered modern and polite, the

    accompanying 'philosophical' commentary at times took over the

    structure of narration, and at the end of each reign a chapter wasinserted reviewing the king's character, the significant legislation enacted

    by or under him, the general state of society and the progress (if any) of

    the liberal and occasionally the useful arts during his reign. The history of

    social and cultural conditions (as we should term it) was still regularly, but

    not always, made to subserve the narrative of res gestaein the role of

    contexts; but there was developing a new kind of sequentially-written

    history, whose function was to narrate the transition from one historical

    context, or one generalised state of society, to another. Hume andGibbon, major historians, continued to write the two kinds of narrative

    concurrently, and faced the problem of linking them more revealingly

    than by such convenient copulaeas About this time [...], or During his

    reign the state of society [...]. There were other major historians who

  • 7/28/2019 POCOCK[1]. the Transformation of Humanism

    37/47

    37

    offered subversively like Voltaire in the Essai sur les Moeur more

    conservatively like Robertson in the View of the Progress of Human

    Society... or Ferguson in the Essay on the History of Civil Society

    writings which were essentially, or exclusively, narratives of the processesof social or contextual change. These authors could be termed

    'historians', yet there was an unextinguished doubt whether their works

    were properly to be termed 'histories'; perhaps they were essays,

    discourses, treatises on 'origins' or 'progress', and the word 'history'

    should be reserved for works in which the narrative of exemplary deeds

    remained autonomous if not preponderant. We may even find cardinal

    and crucial contributions to historical literature in works like

    Montesquieu's De l'Esprit des Loisor Adam Smith's Lectures on

    Jurisprudence