Philosophy of John Macmurray

download Philosophy of John Macmurray

of 511

Transcript of Philosophy of John Macmurray

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    1/510

    THE POLITICAL, SOCIAL, AND

    ECONOMIC IDEAS OF

    JOHN MACMURRAY

    VICTOR DOUGLAS EDNEY

    THESIS PCJR Ph.D.

    as EXTERNAL STUDENT

    by PRIVATE STUDY

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    2/510

    UMI Number: U616007

    All rights reserved

    INFORMATION TO ALL USERS

    The quality of this reproduction is dependent upon the quality of the copy submitted.

    In the unlikely event that the author did not send a complete manuscript

    and there are missing pages, these will be noted. Also, if material had to be removed,a note will indicate the deletion.

    Dissertation Publishing

    UMI U616007

    Published by ProQuest LLC 2014. Copyright in the Dissertation held by the Author.

    Microform Edition ProQuest LLC.

    All rights reserved. This work is protected against

    unauthorized copying under Title 17, United States Code.

    ProQuest LLC

    789 East Eisenhower Parkway

    P.O. Box 1346

    Ann Arbor, Ml 48106-1346

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    3/510

    BSS

    r

    b(o\0

    < 2> \ \ O S I & 2 2

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    4/510

    - 2 -

    ABSTRACT OF THESIS

    The title and the table of contents of this thesis, in one respect,

    fully convey its contents, substance, and plan. Here is expounded,

    surveyed, and critically appraised certain branches of Macmurray' s

    thought.

    Very little, if any, of either Macmurray or his work has been

    written about in this way, if at all. So this thesis is, as it

    should be, a unique and original contribution to knowledge and

    scholarship.

    The prograirme and procedure has been to expound his ideas under

    suitable headings according to subject matter, and to follow this -

    from time to time - with a relevant appraisement, rather than

    intersperse criticism with exposition.

    But Macmurray1 s thought is so broad, so encompassing, so diverse

    and intricate that it must never be imagined that adequate justice

    has been, or could be, done to the subjects contained in the title in

    such a short compass. Thus whilst not exhaustively covering the

    subject in exposition, which would require at least ten thesis of

    this length, it has also not been possible to raise, discuss, and

    positively answer numerous questions which frequently come to mind as

    we read both the original texts and this exposition of them.

    Many, of course, have been raised, researched, met, and

    answered. But many more must wait for further researches, and for

    more space to consider and probe them.

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    5/510

    - 3 -

    The above has had to be made clear for I would not want it to be

    thought that this is, and was meant to be, a definitive work in the

    selected field of Macmurray1 s ideas.

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    6/510

    _ 4 -

    TABLE OF CONTENTS

    Page

    Introduction and Biographical Note.......................... 5

    Freedom...................................................29

    Religion.................... 68

    Science................................................149

    A r t ................................................... 199

    Marxism..................................................251

    Philosophy...............................................310

    Psychology...............................................395

    History..................................................453

    A Short Evaluation....................................... 496

    Bibliography and Sources.............................. 505

    Macmurray's Sources andPossible Sources................... 507

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    7/510

    - 5 -

    A NECESSARY INTEOXKTION

    For years John Macmurray has been overlooked or almost

    deliberately ignored. Yet about 1930 he enjoyed widespread public

    and popular allegiance and acclaim for his broadcast talks on

    realistic, practical, down-to-earth, philosophy in relation to

    contemporary and fundamental problems; problems of such an

    intransigent and intractable nature that they are still essentially

    the same, still with us, today; and still unsolved. In the early

    1940s he was still around and known, especially in association with a

    new political party, Commonwealth, which had proclivities towards

    moral and social regeneration, and had quite a following. Since that

    time, apart from some modest and minority academic attention,

    Macmurray has sunk into obscurity and oblivion.

    Yet he gave so .much, and has so much to give. This thesis is

    written in the belief that much of what he had to say, made explicit,

    and taught, is as relevant, meaningful, and indeed downright

    essential today as it was when first enunciated. And if originally

    enthusiastically heard but coolly unimplemented then, Is nevertheless

    worth bringing to the fore to be given a second chance of

    consideration and, it is hoped, put into practice.

    For although a man of thought, Macmurray' s whole emphasis was on

    action and practice. No ivory tower of pure thinking for him. No

    withdrawing from the world. Thought is for living, or it is not

    worth bothering about.

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    8/510

    - 6 -

    What then are some of the ideas Macmurray introduced and

    propounded? As with the ideas of every thinker not all are of such

    originality and profundity that they need special attention and

    consideration. But those of vital and essential interest are the

    following. However, first a word of warning. In the readability,

    fluency and ease of writing; in the core of the idea; and in the

    telling, Macmurray can be, or may seem to be, simple and even

    commonplace. You read him, or hear of one of his ideas, and think -

    What's all the fuss about; we know of, or are doing, this already.

    But this is not so. If you pause, reflect, and look deeply enough,

    you will realize that none of his ideas, as given in the following

    summary, are yet, nor within an age of becoming, a part of our

    general, social, psychological, moral, cr educational ethos. None

    have been incorporated into our thought, behaviour, or actions -

    public cr personal. In ourselves, and in our society, we are still

    thinking, feeling, believing, and doing all the things Macmurray

    would wish us not tp think and do. So; be cautious of Macmurray's

    easy style and presentation - especially in his popular and best-

    known books. Their seeming simplicity belies their originality,

    depth, and profundity.

    So what are some of the things which, so original yet so out of

    step with the general feeling and ideas of those times and these,

    Macmurray told, or still has to tell us?

    But first -

    A Biographical Note.

    John Macmurray was b om at Maxwell ton, Kirkcudbrightshire, on

    the 16th February 1891. His father, James, was a civil servant; and

    the family were deeply religious, a fact for which he says, "he was

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    9/510

    - 7 -

    fortunate". (SKR 5). The home was one of Christian piety in the

    traditional Calvanism of the Scottish Church. This had a strong

    intellectual strain. The Bible was the book both of inspiration and

    of reference in case of dispute. There was a distrust and

    suppression of emotion, and doctrine was paramount. Macmurray speaks

    of the shock he received when he first heard by chance that, in

    contrast to science, religion expressed the emotional aspects of

    human consciousness. (SRR 5). Hitherto for him religion had been

    purely intellectual and the fount of control and discipline.

    Macmurray was educated at a local grammar school, but later his

    father asked to be transferred to Aberdeen solely for the sake of the

    children's education. (SRR 7). At Aberdeen Macmurray went to Robert

    Gordon's College.

    In the 1890s there was a tremendous upsurge of evangelistic

    fervour, much of it springing fran America, and Macmurray's parents

    were not unaffected by it. They experimented with several Baptist

    sects, eventually becoming Plymouth Bretheren, but still retaining

    their Calvanist rigidity (SRR 6). When young, Macmurray's father had

    wanted to be a missionary, but the Boxer Movement and parental

    commitments had prevented this. Perhaps influenced by this knowledge

    Macmurray went, eventually, to Glasgow University specifically to

    become a missionary in China. But his enthusiasm for this soon

    waned.

    But from an early time Macmurray had been a Bible-class teacher,

    and continued as an open-air and tent evangelist whilst still at

    Glasgow studying. Gradually however, about this time of his life,

    although not once in all his years was he ever not totally committed

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    10/510

    - 8 -

    to religion, Macmurray began to doubt his own religious sincerity,

    and the sincerity of all formal religion. He says (SRR 9), "It is

    possible to have a real religious experience coupled with religious

    beliefs and practices which are fallacious and undesirable; or to

    hold sincerely and convincedly to religious beliefs and practices

    with no reality to sustain them". Here we have the beginning,

    although as he says he did not fannulate it till much later, of the

    whole import and essence of Macmurray' s religious teaching and

    outlook. This insight is the root of all that Macmurray has to say

    about religion.

    But parallel with his long-experienced and deep religious

    knowledge and way of life is another interest - science (SRR 10).

    This interest began before he had reached his teens. Science came to

    him, he says, like a revelation (SRR 10). He wanted to become a

    scientist, and although fighting strongly against his schoolmasters

    who had insisted on him pursuing the classics, he was eventually

    forced to compromise, but became the only student at school, and

    later at university, permitted to study science as an extra subject.

    Biology, chemistry, and geology were his main science subjects. And

    science, either predictably or perversely, was the only university

    subject in which he gained a medal 1

    At university he was very much taken up with the then widespread

    and influential Student Christian Movement. Apart from anything else

    "It taught him that religious fellowship could be fun". (SRR 13). In

    other words, his religious severity and strictness began to melt and

    warm up under the influence of more liberal Christians around him.

    He also perceived at this time that "there was no branch of creative

    human effort which could not be integrated with Christianity". (SRR

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    11/510

    - 9 -

    13).

    Further religious and scientific studies taught him four more

    things. 1) Firstly; that the theology and scriptual texts, on which

    he had been brought up, would not stand up to serious scrutiny or

    criticism. Their dogmatism was becoming repugnant to him. 2)

    Secondly; religion is not to be identified with theology, nor with

    any system of belief or beliefs. (SRR 15. SRR 16/7). 3) Thirdly;

    that religion ought to be non-sectarian and interdenominational in

    character, and be also missionary and ecumenical in essence, outlook,

    and practice. 4) Fourthly; Macmurray reasoned that when a

    scientific theory has been proved to be invalid or outmoded you do

    not overthrew and renounce science. On the contrary; you pursue it

    more avidly. Why then, when a particular religious conception is

    shown to be puerile or untenable, renounce religion, as countless

    people were doing and are still doing when certain religious beliefs

    and dogmas no longer stand-up? "Could we not hope that through

    testing and modification we should arrive at a religion which science

    need not be ashamed to serve?". This last insight of Macmurray1 s had

    an important and profound effect upon the development of his

    religious ideas and outlook. It explains how, and why, he is able to

    cling fast to his religion despite all his scientific interests, a

    position which was very unusual at that time, the first decade of

    this century. It reveals, too, why Macmurray insists, against all

    the conventional conceptions of it, that religion - to retain its

    credibility - must become, and be, empirical.

    In 1913 John Macmurray took his first degree, at Glasgow

    University, and in the same year won a Snell Exhibition to Oxford,

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    12/510

    - 10 -

    and entered Balliol College in October 1913. But his course was far

    from finished when, with the coming of the First World War, he joined

    the R.A.M.C. in October 1914. He chose this branch of the Services

    because, although not a full pacifist,he had qualmsand reservations

    about war and killing not yet fullyworked out. But by 1916 he had

    realized, so he says, (SRR 16) that hewas as much a part of the

    fighting organisation as if he were inthe front line; so he took a

    commission as lieutenant in the 40th. Cameron Highlanders. On leave

    in that same year, 1916, he married Elizabeth Hyde. They had no

    children. Also in 1916 he was awarded the M.C. Wounded near Arras

    early in 1918, he was invalided home, but not discharged for a

    considerable time. Indeed, he was allowed to return to Oxford and

    took his degree in the simmer of 1919, before he was finally and

    officially allcwed to leave the Army. (SRR 16).

    Out of his experience in the War Macmurray learned, inter alia,

    two things very important to his subsequent thinking. Firstly, the

    removal far ever of .the fear of death. This was, and is, "a

    tremendous gain in reality; for until we reach it - however we do

    reach it - we cannot see our life as it really is, and so we cannot

    live it as we should.11 (SRR 18). Secondly, Macmurray learned or

    decided to remove himself, and never join again, any Christian Church

    or denomination; yet, of course, remaining a full and committed

    Christian. It is interesting how this second determination came

    about. On leave from France he preached in a North London church

    about being on guard against the "war mentality", and of the need for

    reconciliation. (SRR 21). On saying this he met with cold hostility

    and was shunned by the congregation as he left the church. This left

    an indelible impression upon him of the mistakenly, to him,

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    13/510

    - 11 -

    nationalistic and limited character of the conventional and orthodox

    churches. This vow of non-attachment he broke only in the early

    1960s, when he joined fully, after years of admiration going back at

    least to the First World War, the Society of Friends.

    On the whole Macmurray was, as were so many of his

    contemporaries, disillusioned by the War. According to him the only

    major result of it, and this was wholly unintended, was the setting

    up of communism in Russia. (SRR 19). But not until later did

    Macmurray concern himself with Marxism; and this occurred by chance.

    He attended a religious conference on "What Is Christianity?" at

    which one of the study groups were asked to prepare a contributory

    paper on the then rather novel and topical subject of communism (SRR

    25). Macmurray, not at that time knowing very much about it,

    actually wrote the paper. Instantly, he, in various ways unique to

    him, discovered certain unusual - not the commonplace ones -

    associations between Christianity and communism. From then on

    communism played a big part in his thinking. However, whether he is

    to be regarded, or regarded himself, as a communist, is an open

    question and is discussed in the relevant chapter later.

    No known thinker has especially influenced Macmurray, nor does

    he acknowledge any or speak of any indebtedness. He does say (SRR

    24) that, like Kierkegaard, he was aroused and stimulated by the

    problem of "What is Christianity?" or "Hew to become a Christian".

    And he speaks of Martin Buber as one of the "very greatest of modem

    thinkers". (SRR 24). If not an existentialist Macmurray is often on

    the fringes of it. In "Ten Modem Prophets," (Frederick Muller

    1944). J.B. Coates says that "Intellectually, Macmurray has been

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    14/510

    - 12 -

    greatly influenced by Bergson", but in all Macmurray's works Bergson

    is mentioned only once, and then rather casually.

    Discharged frcm the Army, Macmurray resolved to join with

    anybody or any organisation to prevent war occurring again. He hoped

    to become a member of staff of the newly formed League of Nations

    (SRR 22) but this was not to be. Instead, philosophy became his task

    and profession for life.

    After taking his degree at Oxford he was, in 1919, appointed

    John Locke Scholar, and in the same year became a lecturer at

    Manchester University. From 1921/2 he was Professor of Philosophy at

    the University of Witwatersrand, South Africa. Returning from there

    he was made a fellcw and tutor of Balliol College, 1922-1928. During

    the early 1930s he gave his very popular B.B.C. talks cn philosophy

    and the contemporary world; and this whilst at the University of

    London as Grote Professor, 1928-1944. To finish his academic career

    he then moved to Edinburgh University as Professor of Moral

    Philosophy, 1944-58..

    During the years 1953/4 he gave the renowned Gifford Lectures at

    Glasgow University. These were published as "The Form of the

    Personal" (2 volumes), and refer to one of Macmurray1 s foremost,

    exploratory, and pioneering themes, the fruits and development of

    which have hardly begun. They foreshadow an area to be defined and

    formulated, yet too far ahead for contemporary man, with his

    principal interest and obsession in knowing, manipulating, and

    exploiting the exterior world, to the neglect of emotional

    development and the promotion of true human relationships,

    understanding, and mutuality.

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    15/510

    - 13 -

    Altogether Macmurray wrote 24 books. Stemming from his

    scientific interests his main recreation was gardening. He died on

    21st June 1976.

    There ends a brief biographical note.

    What then were -

    Macmurray1s Major Contributions

    1) Emotional Reason

    Everybody in our society, and indeed throughout Western

    civilisation, is conditioned to the idea that thinking can be, or

    should be at its best, imbued with reason. Not all thinking is; far

    from it. Some of the biggest efforts, and hours of valuable time,

    both in private and public life, are taken up with pointing out the

    flaws and lack of reasonableness in others, rarely if ever in one's

    cwn, thinking and arguments.

    Embedded in this idea of satisfactory thinking are the notions

    of logic and rationality. They are not the same. But here is not

    the place to discuss them. Sufficient if we knew and agree that

    thinking includes some reason, or ought to, and the more of it the

    better. Most, too, would agree that although rational thinking can

    be found in nearly all branches of human knowledge, its most advanced

    exemplification, so far, is in the scientific area of enquiry.

    Along with this idea it is universally accepted that the enemy

    of good and reasoned thinking, the enemy within which prevents it

    fran ever becoming good thinking, is emotion; this apart, of course,

    from mere structural failings. It is our emotions, we believe, which

    keep us fran thinking satisfactorily. Just as we are on the verge of

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    16/510

    - 14 -

    thinking successfully feeling intervenes and ruffles reason. We

    suspect, too, that feeling interferes with thinking even if we are

    unaware of it. It certainly does in other people, when we are only

    too pleased to tell them that they are "rationalizing", which despite

    the name, means just the opposite of what it might be thought to

    mean.

    Emotion, according to this widespread view of it, at the best

    interpretation we can put upcn it, a-raticnal or a-reasonable. But

    beyond this, most would say that our emotions are the seat and fount

    of unreason and of irrationality; and that they are incurably so.

    The very nature of emoticn is to be thus. This is how it is.

    Thought alone has the monopoly, or the possible monopoly, of the

    highly commendable and laudable characteristic of reason and

    rationality. So says the conventional wisdom.

    This is not so, says Macmurray. Nothing is farther from the

    truth. Feeling can be as rational, and imbued with reason, as

    thought. Like thought it often isnt. But it can and should be.

    Reason, as we so mistakenly believe, is not the prerogative of

    thinking. Our emotions must be seen to be as equally subject to, and

    as much in need of reason, as our thought.

    Moreover, Macmurray goes further. "Reason," he says (RE 26) is

    primarily an affair of the emotions whilst the rationality of

    thought is the derivative and secondary one". He could not make his

    point clearer. Emotion is the essence of our being. Thought is

    secondary. We are essentially "feelers" not thinkers. Therefore

    until we make our feelings as rational as our thought can, at its

    best, sometimes be, we can never live satisfactorily. Macmurray

    suggests, even if he does not state it outright, that all our

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    17/510

    - 15 -

    problems, personal and public, private and social, psychological and

    relational, are due to our almost total obliviousness to this fact of

    human existence. Western man has got into the cul-de-sac of

    obsession with thinking which blinkers him to the need for emotional

    growth and emotional objectivity; to the need for emotional reason.

    At first hearing, this notion may not sound radical and

    revolutionary. Modem psychology, you may say, has been around for

    some time and this has said quite a lot about the emotions. But

    reflect upon Macmurray's contention; allow it to penetrate and

    permeate your awareness, and you will soon come to realize its

    startling originality and perceptiveness. It calls far nothing short

    of a complete shift of emphasis, and a redirecting of our way of

    life, of our values, and of our way of seeing things. Only thus will

    we find the path that may lead us out of the immense difficulties and

    problems of this present age of man.

    As with all these introductory sections, only the barest minimum

    has been given concerning Macmurray's thought. A much fuller

    exposition and justification, in this case, is given in the chapter

    on Macmurray's psychological thought. But there can be no doubt that

    the concept of Emotional Reasons has been Macmurray' s greatest,

    penetrating, and most profound contribution and insight into this

    fundamental and important aspect of our living. Some may have hinted

    at the notion; others intuitively or vaguely discerned it. But only

    Macmurray has made it explicit.

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    18/510

    - 16 -

    2) The Personal

    This is Macmurray's most major contribution after Bnotional

    Reason. In fact, emotional reason, although important in its own

    right can be seen, when both are known and fully comprehended, as a

    vital element of the Personal. Here again, when you first come to

    understand what the personal is, nothing is more tempting than to say

    - "Bosh! We've known that all our lives. What is it but another

    name for the spiritual. We certainly don't need to be told about it

    as if it were some important discovery like Copemicumism or

    electricity".

    But look around you. Hew many people do you know who are living

    Personally? Are you living thus, except far very brief, unintended,

    and discontinuous periods each day?

    What is the Personal? The Personal is the third order. We are

    all familiar with orders. The basic, because most ubiquitous and

    extensive, is the material order. This includes all the physical

    aspects of existence - the Earth, atoms, things, the basic substances

    of our bodies, to name but some. The essence of this order is

    fixity, rigidity, regularity, uniformity, usually a certain

    persistency and permanency, behaving always according to fixed laws;

    passivity, unfreedom, non-self-directing or self-reproducing,

    egoless; all the qualities we associate with thingdem.

    The second order is the organic. Here are included all plants,

    trees, fish, bacteria, insects, animals, and certain aspects of man.

    The essence of this order is sentience, drives, desires, will to

    survive, adaptability, procreation, conditioned response, life cycle,

    and inevitable individual extinction.

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    19/510

    - 17 -

    And then coming through, existing upon and as it were,

    creatively emerging from the first two is the third carder, the

    Personal. I say "emerging from" as this is the best way to depict it

    at this stage of our exposition and understanding. But Macmurray

    believes the Personal to be the most basic and fundamental of the

    three. But more elaboration and discussion of this in the text later

    on.

    What is the essence of the Personal? Freedom, openness,

    creativity, intention, self-consciousness, objectivity, rationality,

    reason; and just as important - as we are all, car can be, or should

    be, all Personal together - interdependence, mutuality, relatingness,

    and the most advanced and satisfactory of these and of the Personal,

    fellowship, friendship, and love. The Personal can never be imposed.

    It cannot be implemented by law, social order, politics, force, cr

    administration. The attainment of it, of its very nature, must be

    from choice, and of self-volition.

    As you will ncw> recognise, the Personal has been around a long

    time. Macmurray argues with considerable justification, that Jesus

    discovered the Personal. If nothing else it has been Implicit in

    religious teaching - especially those of Christianity - for

    centuries. But. as with Qnotional Reason, what Macmurray has done is

    to give it a form and definition, a sort of philosophical and logical

    acceptability; he has brought it down to earth. We were conscious of

    it before; he has made us self-conscious of it. And by doing this

    never again can it be something vague, something you by accident,

    choice, education, or cultural environment heed and attend to or not.

    He has identified it, articulated it, and named it. From now on

    nobody who understands what Macmurray has made explicit about the

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    20/510

    - 18 -

    Personal, however sceptical of regarding man as anything but a highly

    complex, involved, and computerised animal, can not intend to live in

    the Personal. If you do not you are, as it were, degrading your own

    existence.

    Before you came to the last paragraph, and the reference there

    made to it, it is highly inprobable that you could have read these

    introductory remarks on the Personal without the word and concept of

    religion arising in your mind. Far the Personal, as so empirically

    defined by Macmurray, for the first time in the history of human

    thought and awareness is, for him and I believe for us all from now

    on, because of Macmurray' s insights and articulations, is to be

    associated, if not absolutely coincidentally and oo-existently, with

    religion.

    So, to Macmurray we owe the explication of the Personal.

    3) Religion

    Without being "religious", at least not in any visible,

    conventional, or recognizable sense, religion is the all-important,

    all-including, thing for Macmurray. There are few branches of human

    learning and culture about which Macmurray does not have plenty to

    say and threw enlightenment upon. Science, art, psychology, thought,

    economics, politics, communism, philosophy, ethics, and society all

    receive considerable attention, some even commanding whole books of

    exposition and discussion. But mingling and intermingling through

    all is Macmurray's penchant, his thing, that which he perceives as

    the essential factor of humanness, the ground of all living -

    religion. With such permeation and penetration we cannot help but

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    21/510

    - 19 -

    get the feeling that religion is natural, not that Macmurray ever

    mentions the word in this context. But that is what he consciously

    or unconsciously, intentionally or unintentionally, is conveying.

    And whether this is his open intention or not, from this perception

    of naturalness and religious normality, an extremely important and

    far-reaching effect occurs; at least for those who are prepared to

    understand and heed what Macmurray is saying.

    One problem troubles countless people today, try as they may to

    brush it aside. It is - Hew to be religious. Millions of sceptics,

    agnostics, atheists, secularists, and humanists are, at heart even if

    not overtly, yearning to be religious. And countless people who are

    ostensibly religious, believing, and orthodox, and within the fold

    are, whether openly seen to be or not, confronted by the same

    problem. Either they have their doubts, witness the mental and

    intellectual struggles of so many bishops; or they are vaguely aware

    of shortcomings in their behaviour, practices, relationships,

    approaches, and attitudes. And yet another group, and a very large

    one indeed, especially amongst the young, are those trying every

    cult, from fringe religious organisations, the occult, astrology,

    spiritualism, evangelism, the maharishi, and Scientology to drugs,

    addictions, pot, and pops - to name but a fewl Everywhere, people

    knowingly and unknowingly are trying desperately, almost frantically,

    and in however a substitute fashion, to be religious, yet to no

    satisfactory, real, and happy effect. All is phoney, false,

    ephemeral, and unsatisfying in the long run, if not in the short.

    Why is there this intense seeking? There are three reasons.

    Firstly; the important, even if not the sole, roots of our Western

    society are in Christianity. Therefore if for any cause, perhaps for

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    22/510

    - 20 -

    example because of the effects of science and technology, the link

    with our roots is broken or partially severed, there must inevitably

    be a widespread feeling of voidness and loss; not so much a feeling

    of longing for what was as a disorientation, especially as those

    things which are most intrinsic, vital, and sustaining in our lives,

    namely values, become unstable as a result.

    Secondly; the same applies to individual lives, not merely to

    society in general. Countless numbers of people alive today were

    reared directly, or in the lengthening shadow of Christianity, even

    if it was only a conventionalised Christianity exemplified by church-

    going or by school assembly. To many it was more, of course. The

    loss of this, shrugged-off with indifference by many, cannot but be

    felt, even if unadmitted. Something, however vague and

    unidentifiable, has gone from their lives.

    Thirdly; and here we come to what no doubt Macmurray would call

    the essential reason; the reason which exists apart from both general

    history and individual experience. And to understand this fully we

    must recall the last section of this introduction; the Personal. We

    are, you remember, made to be Personal. To be Personal is what we

    are, or what we must become. Only thus can we be ourselves. We are

    things, and often have to exist as such; we are creatures and must

    act organically. But superimposed on all this, and indeed making it

    very difficult far us, is the Personal. And it is in this order that

    we must intend to live and be.

    New the area especially relevant to the Personal is that of

    religion. Religion exists, hcwever inadequately, gropingly, or

    unconsciously, to promote the Personal. Because, therefore, however

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    23/510

    - 21 -

    seriously or however reluctantly and superficially we are and must

    pursue the Personal, we are self-evidently, all and every one of us,

    religious and involved with religion. It is of our very essence.

    The immature expressions of religion manifested so far have, quite

    naturally, "turned off" millions of people in today's world. But

    this does not in any way detract from our need for religion.

    We can see now why countless are wondering how to be religious.

    And why the important contribution Macmurray has made to religion is

    that, whether totally acceptable or not, he has given us the clue as

    to hew we can recognize that, despite all our own ideas, and the

    ideas of the contemporary world, we are and must live in a religious

    context. We are religious whether we recognize it or not, for it is

    the most natural and normal thing for all men to be. We are

    Personal, and religion is the area, the ambience, of the Personal.

    Macmurray makes it possible for us to be religious again, and

    possibly at a more advanced, maturer, stage than before. Macmurray

    has metamorphosed religion. By discovering this, by showing religion

    to be as normal and as natural a part of human existence as thinking,

    breathing, and relating, he has gone a long way to making unbelievers

    religious again; and believers less eager to portray religion as

    something special, spiritual, sacred, and supernatural; something

    only for the "elect" and chosen and thus putting everybody else off.

    Religion for Macmurray is simply living Personally.

    4) Freedom

    Apart from religion Macmurray, throughout his works, has more to

    say about freedom than anything else. It is a major and important

    conception of his, and he brings much original thought to it. And

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    24/510

    - 22 -

    where he is not original he, as perhaps we have come to expect by now

    of him, puts an emphasis on some aspect almost ignored in

    contemporary thought and action.

    The important contribution Macmurray makes regarding freedom is

    that he deepens and broadens our awareness and apprehension of it.

    Ask most people, not merely the man in the street but those in the

    more educated and higher controlling and influencing strata of

    society, what they understand by freedom, and they will give some

    sort of political answer possibly extended to include rather vague

    references to such social matters as freedom of the press and freedom

    of assembly. One thing is certain. You can be sure nothing will be

    said about psychological freedom, that is freedom of the emotions and

    of the self.

    Yet this is Macmurray's greatest concern when the question of

    freedom arises. Moreover, he links the two. Structural and

    institutional freedom, that is political and social freedom, may be

    there for all to benefit from, but none can satisfactorily benefit

    unless they are personally free; that is, free in themselves and in

    their emotions. In a sense, political freedom, except formally and

    without any real meaning and substance, cannot exist without personal

    freedom. This is because the most unfree, yet energetic and vigorous

    members of society - the pcwer lovers - will take over, and do take

    over, even in a democracy. They then subtly and insidiously

    manipulate the feeling of the numerous and the majority but less

    power-driven of the people. Thus in a "free" society most people are

    unfree.

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    25/510

    - 23 -

    Hew has this situation arisen? Because, says Macmurray, we have

    freed thought but not emotion. Freedom of thought started about five

    hundred years ago, and from tentative and opposed beginnings

    progressed to its greatest expression in science. The essence of

    scientific thought is freedom and reality. Without preconceptions or

    dogmatism and authority, it operates in freedom, seeking solely for

    what is, not for what it would wish to be. Science is the prime

    example of what all freedom, contrary to popular conceptions of it,

    must contain; and that is discipline. The discipline of relating

    itself, whatever the cost - in human pride, vanity, or dignity - to

    reality.

    But although we have freed thought, and thus related it to

    reality and shifted its centre of balance from "in here" to "out

    there", from subjectivity to objectivity, to our immense advantage

    thought-wise, we have not freed our emotions. And remember, as

    Macmurray so pertinently reminds us - indeed, he might be said to

    instruct us, so oblivious is contemporary society to the fact - that

    the essence of our living is our emotional life. Our emotions are

    the vital, essential, part of ourselves. Not only does all

    experience come by and through our emotions, feelings, and senses,

    but all our evaluations, and hence our choices are determined by our

    emotions and not by our thinking.

    Earlier we considered the importance of emotional reason and

    growth. No less an aspect of this, for Macmurray, is the freeing of

    emotion. Yet in this area we are enchained, biased, and as unfree

    and unreal as thought was in its pre-scientific era. Only as we

    bring the same freedom to our emotional life can we grow and develop

    into satisfactory, personal, human beings. The irony is that the

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    26/510

    - 24 -

    cannon ethos tells us that we are free, mainly because we enjoy

    constitutional freedoms. Moreover, many people, probably the

    majority, think that more money and more material possessions would

    make them more free. Considering Macmurray's ideas on personal,

    emotional, and psychological development and freedom, additional

    possessions have very little to do with freedom essentially.

    Macmurray gives interesting and cogent reasons and historical

    analysis as to why we are in this state of emotional unfreedom.

    This introductory section can only hint at Macmurray's

    penetrating and valuable contribution to our understanding of

    freedom. Much more will be elaborated upon in the relevant chapter.

    But enough has been given to indicate the insight Macmurray has

    brought to this vital topic, and of the importance of what he has to

    say about it.

    5) Monism

    Of all the five major tendencies or advocacies considered in

    this introduction, Macmurray's monisn is the least heightened,

    focused, reinforced, and re-expounded by him. The other ideas have

    each been encapsulated in one or more books, devoted more or less

    exclusively to their subject matter. Not so his monism. Yet it

    pervades all his writings and thought. If one thing is the essence,

    if not the substance, of Macmurray, it is this.

    Macmurray is the foremost monist of our time. He may not be the

    foremost in advocacy and intention, arguing, expounding, and

    defending his case in the most detailed, logically reasoned, and

    extended way. That, as we have come to knew, is not Macmurray's

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    27/510

    - 25 -

    method. For him the proof of the pudding is in the eating (or should

    we say, in the experiencing) not in an inspection, analysis, and

    admiration of the list of ingredients, however brilliant and

    convincing these may be.

    Nevertheless, there can be no doubt that Macmurray

    unquestionably considers the world as one, and merely by reading him

    we totally and automatically feel this to be so. Very subtly, or

    though not consciously or deliberately, and certainly with no

    ulterior motive, Macmurray through his writing and the consequent

    shifting and redirecting of feeling which we experience, is able to

    bring about a change in us imperceptibly; and without the doubtful

    necessity of logical argument we become monists. Through him, and

    the way he writes, we see and experience the point, and the need of

    so being.

    Why is monism, and to be monist, so important? Because, both in

    ourselves and throughout Western civilisation, if not in all extant

    civilisations and cultures, we are divided. Now sometimes, and at

    different times in history, division or centrifuged interests and

    farces are necessary for growth, or at legist as an essential catalyst

    and precursor to growth. At other times unifying, centripetal,

    monistic, interests and directions are essential to promote and

    create cohesion, both within ourselves and in society at large.

    Indeed, such monism may be essential to survival. Of such an era is

    the one in which we are now living.

    It was Plato who first divided our consciousness, reinforced by

    Descartes the father of the modem world, philosophy-wise. Since

    then we have been bedevilled by dualism, and even by pluralism.

    Existence, the world, man, thought, politics, and religion must have

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    28/510

    - 26 -

    or perhaps in the light of Macmurray we ought to say, "are seen by us

    to have" - two or more sides or aspects. Obvious examples of dualism

    are inexhaustible, but here are some to remind us; mind and matter,

    body and soul, left and right, heaven and hell, science and religion,

    will and passion, reason and emotion, spiritual and temperal, either

    or. And examples of pluralism are; mind, body, and spirit; the

    trinity; and social classes - upper, middle, and lower. Nobody can

    say that dualism is not an inbuilt feature of our way of perceiving

    the world, life and ourselves.

    But, inconceivable as it may seem to us, conditioned as we are

    by the structure of Western thinking and perceiving process, we do

    not have to see things in this way. They are merely categories we

    have created in the human mind, mainly for our seeming convenience.

    And its effects have reached a dangerous stage as we well knew.

    According to Macmurray, since primitive times, only one people have

    been totally and naturally monist; the Jews of the Old Testament.

    His admiration for them, in this respect, is immense. This example

    of monism forms for Macmurray one very important aspect (about half,

    if one can roughly apportion it) of his "clue" to history. For

    monism to appear so important speaks far itself in Macmurray's

    thought.

    If monism, if to be a monist, is so important for us, how are we

    to achieve it? Descartes said, "I think, therefore I am." Here lies

    the root of all our troubles and divisions. Thought, thinking, is

    not the essence, the core, of our being. Thought is only

    instrumental, a means to an end. It can never be anything of itself.

    It can never be ultimate. It can never cause us to experience

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    29/510

    - 27 -

    reality.

    And this is where Macmurray turns the tables, and consequently

    revolutionizes our way of seeing things. Macmurray instead of

    saying, "I think, therefore I am", would say, "I act, therefore I

    am". But even this is not complete enough for him. Reality is

    Personal - remember? - and the Personal includes us all. Therefore

    the ultimate phrase, the ultimate expression of being for Macmurray

    is, "We act, therefore we are". In this conception of action lies

    the clue to Macmurray's monism. For, although thinking can be

    divided an action, at any one particular moment, can never be

    divided. It can only be one thing. For some reason, to be discussed

    later, Macmurray calls this paramountcy of action "agency"; we are

    "agents". But perhaps this whole aspect of his thinking could best

    be called Actionism. Macmurray's monism exists through and by the

    fact that he is an Actionist. We are here to do, not to dream or

    wish.

    What "to act" means is elaborated upon at length. It includes

    the very important conception of "intention", which plays a very big

    part in Macmurray's psychology and philosophy.

    Enough has been said to illustrate how important monism is for

    Macmurray; and of hew essential it is, both in ourselves and in our

    world, to be undivided and seamless. He has shewn how, by redressing

    the balance between thought and action, we can achieve this.

    Macmurray's monism, and of how to be monistic, is certainly one of

    his foremost conceptions - and a means of saving the world. For,

    although unsaid, this no doubt is one of Macmurray's major objects.

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    30/510

    - 28 -

    A Final Note

    The foregoing brief introductory sections have been written with

    two things in mind.

    Firstly; to introduce, in an easy way, a few of the major ideas

    of John Macmurray.

    Secondly; to awaken, arouse, and stimulate interest in an

    important writer and thinker who has much to say of great relevance

    for us today, yet who has been almost totally neglected.

    No attempt has been made at this stage to appraise or criticise

    the ideas presented. In your mind, as you have read, some doubts,

    questions, and even antipathies, will inevitably have arisen. Each

    chapter following contains several sections of criticisn and

    appraisement; and a final chapter will attempt to summarise and

    evaluate overall Macmurray's place, contribution, relevance,

    influence, and shortcomings.

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    31/510

    - 29 -

    FREEDOM

    Relevant Books

    Freedom in the Modem World. (FMW)

    Conditions of Freedom. (CF)

    Philosophy of Communism. (PC)

    Introduction

    Macmurray has many diverse and varied ideas on freedom. It is

    not easy to bring total coherence to them, or to incorporate them

    exhaustively into one system. Although a man of reason and

    rationality Macmurray was not predominantly a man of logic or proof,

    not a man to totally and exhaustively justify what he was saying.

    Nor was Plato - far from it. Yet he was not criticised on these

    grounds.

    This does not mean that Macmurray's views on freedom - or,

    indeed, on anything else - are inconsistent or incongruent; at least,

    not beyond the inevitable and acceptable limits of any thinker. But

    as in all Macmurray's work and intentions, proof of anything said or

    believed is in the living of it, not in verbal substantiation and

    argument. Truth is to be found in living, not in and through

    thinking. Thinking plays a valid and valuable part to this end, but

    it is feeling which gives us our values and it is values which

    determine our life and living - not intellectual thinking. "Thought

    is only verifiable in action." (PC 26).

    Such an outlook is quite against Western tradition, especially

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    32/510

    - 30 -

    since the end of the Middle Ages and the caning of the Modem era;

    and since Descartes. Of this period, science is its prime, although

    by no means sole, manifestation. In philosophy, probably only

    existentialism challenges this. Even Pragmatism is thought-*

    orientated.

    Thus, what Macmurray is really trying to do is to shift the

    whole emphasis of Western thinking and ideas. This is like trying to

    lift a twenty ton rock with, and on, one human shoulder. And if

    followers or acknowledgers are any indication of one's success and

    influence, Macmurray has - at least to date - failed miserably. At

    best, one can say he has gone unheard. Maybe the coming of the

    Permissive Society in the 1960s was in some way, hcwever indirect,

    the result of Macmurray's work. But a lot of study and research

    would be necessary to trace it to him (even as but one factor in a

    complex situation). And nobody has even attempted or suggested it

    yet.

    But there can be no doubt that this major shift of life-

    emphasis, away from thought to feeling and consequent improved

    action, was a very prominent and important theme and intention of

    Macmurray's. It is perhaps unfortunate that Macmurray's style -

    except in the three more academic books - is so "easy" and fluent, so

    readable, that people understand it, or think they do, as they read

    without bothering to find reflection and questioning as to meaning

    necessary. If he were more obscure, and had to be worked at, he

    would be more revered. I remember a student in one of my classes

    saying of another lecturer (with slight intended amusement, but

    nevertheless meant), "He must be a good lecturer, I don't understand

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    33/510

    - 31 -

    a word he says!"

    If Macmurray had the obscurity of Hegel he might well have

    superseded him by now. For he is certainly attempting as major a

    task as Hegel (or Marx).

    But now for freedom. And first of all - what, according to

    Macmurray, is:-

    The Origin of Freedom

    Why do we seem to want freedom? Why has it been a major theme

    and intention of modem man? From whence does this idea in us come

    from? ....................................................

    It might be noted in passing that although the books listed at

    the head of this chapter are obviously, by their titles, the ones

    most devoted by Macmurray to this subject, freedom is often referred

    to throughout his works. It is a major theme.

    Macmurray attributes freedom to two sources.

    1 ) Firstly; to Christianity. "Christianity implanted in us the

    desire for freedom of life". (FMW 48). And again. "The driving

    force belcw the development of Europe has always been the struggle

    for freedom and the clue to that struggle lies in Christianity."

    (FMW 48). (And more generally Macmurray speaks of this influence in

    CF 35).

    One further special exemplification of this contention is given.

    Science, claims Macmurray, is our most notable area of freedom

    attained so far. It results from freedom of thought. And the

    required underlying freedom necessary far its production came not, as

    is usually contended, from the Greeks, but from Christianity with its

    insistence can truth and light. To illustrate this Macmurray quotes

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    34/510

    - 32 -

    from the New Testament, (FMW 38). "This is the condemnation that

    light is come into the world, and men loved darkness rather than

    light because their deeds were evil". For full discussion of this

    see FMW 37/41.

    So Christianity is a major source of the idea of, and need for,

    freedom.

    2) Secondly: freedom is of man's essence, man would not be

    man had he not this urge and need for freedom. To quote CF 16.

    "There is a sense in which freedom is absolute. It is the sense in

    which freedom is the. defining character of Man;, the property which .

    sets us apart from the rest of creation and fixes a gulf between us

    and the highest of the animals.".

    Macmurray then, in acceptable but nevertheless his own meaning

    and interpretation of words and terms, puts forward - or at least

    implies - three ways of being. These are:-

    To act.

    To behave.1(see CF 16/17).

    To react.

    Material things behave. Living things react. But only man

    acts. (There is much more about this, and of the freedom and types

    of morality these three ways of being respectively evoke, in the

    chapters and pages of FMW 175/210, but I do not think it especially

    relevant to develop them at this point. See later in this chapter.)

    To act means to form an intention and seek to realise it (CF

    16). To act is to be free. As Agents - one of Macmurray's most

    major concepts - we are concerned not with what exists or is, but

    with what will be i.e. with the future and our intentions for it.

    The past is fixed and unalterable. The present is merely the point

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    35/510

    - 33 -

    of action. Only in our intention for what is to be are we free.

    "The future is the field of freedom" (CF 17). The only way to deny

    that freedom is of our essence is to assert that we never, nor can,

    act (but only behave or react).

    Beside acting and agency another unique feature of man, as

    equally important and of the essence of freedom, is the Personal,

    also discussed later at length in this thesis.

    So there are Macmurray's two main ideas - Christianity and

    essence - as to why man has, wants, needs, seems to be involved with,

    freedom.

    (Rather than wait to the end of each chapter, I shall from time

    to time interrupt the exposition to make an appraisement and

    evaluation. The first occasion for this is now).

    Appraisement (1)

    1 ) Without being able to substantiate it in detail, I do myself

    feel that Christianity has been a major source of freedom. But

    surely Macmurray could give a better quote frcm the New Testament

    than the one he has given. Moreover, there must be many quotes he

    could give frcm the same source. To those unfamiliar with

    Macmurray's works one might reasonably say that Christianity, as it

    has come down to us, is a restricting, inhibiting, influence - not

    one of freedom. But Macmurray recognises this, especially in the

    realms of feeling and emotion (but not in the area of thought) and

    has given for this a rather interesting reason. This will have to be

    fully discussed later in an appropriate context. Sufficient to say

    here that Macmurray contends that the Christianity we have and know

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    36/510

    - 34 -

    is not the original and real Christianity introduced by Jesus. It

    has all the hall-marks of the culture and attitudes of Ancient Rome.

    So; to go back to this point in the appraisement. It would have

    been better if Macmurray had substantiated his assertion with more

    and relevant evidence.

    2) Regarding his second reason for man's need for freedom i.e.

    that it is of our essence, the fact that you cannot prove it, or

    bring overwhelming evidence to support it may, of itself, be

    sufficient indication of it probably being true. But we must not

    confuse the "unknown" (which the future is) with the "free"). The

    future is definitely unknown, but is it open and free? Much of it

    e.g. movement of the planets, to give but one obvious example, must

    already be part of a deterministic and unfree chain. Is our own

    individual future any the less determined?

    However, if we take Macmurray's ideas, and incorporate them in

    our cwn lives, thoughts, emotions, actions, and relationships we do

    find ourselves becoming "freer". No doubt other "systems" (of the

    right kind) will produce this effect too. So, in experience and

    practice, it would seem that freedom can be enlarged by each one of

    us; and, as it is enlarged, we feel more adequate, satisfactory, and

    effective persons. Thus, through living, Macmurray's contentions

    that to be free is of our human essence, would seem to be "proved" as

    far as it can be. And proved by the method of proof Macmurray all

    along advocates, namely action and living, not thinking. Speaking of

    the rejection of idealism, and the acceptance of the principle of the

    unity of theory and practice, Macmurray says, "they involve the

    belief that all theory must seek verification in action and adapt

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    37/510

    - 35 -

    itself to the possibility of experintent. They make a clean sweep of

    all speculative thought on the ground that the validity of no belief

    whatever is capable of demonstration by argument. They involve a

    refusal at any point to make knowledge an end in itself, and equally,

    the rejection of the desire for certainty which is the motive

    governing speculative thought. The demand for personal certainty is

    only the ideal reflection of the demand for personal security and

    that demand is the psychological basis of the struggle for power

    between individuals, classes, nations and empires." (PC 63).

    End of Appraisement (1 )

    The Paradoxical Position of Man Concerning Human Freedom

    Freedom may be of man's essence; it may be absolute (as

    Macmurray expresses it CF 16). But equally, Macmurray says, it is

    relative - which means that, although made for freedom, although

    freedom is of our nature, we are not always free, able to be free,

    nor even, in many cases, to want to be free.

    As we would expect Macmurray (CF 17) quoted Rousseau's famous

    dictum "Man is b o m free, yet everywhere he is in chains". But, to

    misquote, what I think Macmurray should have said (to be more in line

    with his thinking) is "Man is b om to be free, but everywhere he is

    still emotionally in chains".

    We experience this relativity of freedom in many ways. When,

    for example, we fall short of what we would be, or know ourselves to

    be capable of. And again; in the conflict of conscience versus

    impulse (see CF 17). All other creatures are always themselves, but

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    38/510

    - 36 -

    man's nature is not fixed and predictable. To illustrate this

    Macmurray quotes St. Paul, " - it doth not yet appear what we shall

    be". We are always becoming. We are ourselves yet always we are

    reaching out to be what is, as yet, not ourselves. So this is the

    paradox of human freedom. Our freedom is at once both absolute and

    relative.

    But then there is a second paradox concerning human freedom. Or

    if not a paradox then at least a very marked proviso concerning the

    first, (see CF 18/20). We profess to desire freedom but fear to be

    free.

    On hearing this phrase one is reminded of a book with the same

    theme written after Macmurray's ideas had been published, namely,

    "The Fear of Freedom" by Erich Fromm. This is very relevant to the

    point. What is this fear of freedom? Perpetually - it is not a

    once-for-all choice and done with it - we are each confronted by a

    choice, freedom or security. And most of the time, "inhumanly" and

    "sub-personally", we choose security. This then is the second

    paradox of freedom. We are bom to be free yet out of fear we shun

    it. Yet, and here is the essence of the paradox, we can only be

    ourselves when going for freedom, therefore only in freedom can we be

    secure.

    Going for security in preference to freedom can lead only to

    frustration, and to the destroying of ourselves. "If we aim at

    security we aim at the impossible, and succeed only in multiplying

    the occasions of fear, and magnifying our need far security. There

    is no security for us except in choosing freedom. For our insecurity

    is our fear, and to choose freedom is to triumph over fear". (CF 20).

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    39/510

    - 37 -

    As we shall come to understand as we go along, fear is another

    important theme throughout Macmurray's writings. The desire for

    security is based on fear. Fear is a negative emotion. It either

    shrivels us up and leads into a withdrawal frcm life and people; or;

    it puts into us a mighty urge to power, to conquer all and sundry, to

    master all imagined enemies and sources of fear.

    But it never succeeds. In jungle and instinctive conditions

    fear is necessary, proper, and propitious. At the human, personal,

    level it is disastrous. Most of all - and very much to the point

    here - it is a major source of our unfreedom.

    It is interesting to ask in passing - why is fear such a big

    "thing" with Macmurray? Is its discernment a rational, objective,

    analysis on his part? Or is he somewhere, somehow, a 'fearful, fear-

    filled' person? We cannot tell. But a slight hint might be gleaned

    frcm the following - perhaps. "The free man is the man who takes

    responsibility for his cwn life before God and his fellows. Is it

    any wonder that when we are faced with the challenge of freedom, our

    fear is usually more than a match for its attractiveness; and that we

    seek, far the most part, to escape the demand that it makes upon us?

    This, at least, is my experience; and that our capacity to deceive

    ourselves in this matter is of extreme subtlety." (CF 19). Does

    this give us a clue or not?

    So this is the paradox, concerning freedom, in us. Freedom is

    of our essence as men, as human beings, as persons. However, we are

    not yet free (or only partially so, and each of us has acquired

    different degrees of freedom, of which we may lose or gain more)

    because 1) of our inbetween and transitory state as man. 2) of

    fear(s) in us, evoked by, probably, this very transitory condition in

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    40/510

    - 38 -

    which we find ourselves, and of our consequent need for security.

    Very awkward isn't it I - but very cleverly analysed by Macmurray.

    What is Freedom?

    As we would expect, all of Macmurray's ideas of freedom are not

    concerned with their ontological, philosophical, or theoretical

    aspects, but with their manifestations in life and action. So; in

    practical, psychological, and dcwn-to-earth terms what, for

    Macmurray, is freedom?

    After years of study I believe I know - and am able to summarise

    - what Macmurray meant by freedom. But a serious first half-a-dozen

    readings of his ideas on the matter (one reading will not bother

    you!) will lead you into a miasma of seeming anomalies, even

    contradictions; one moment he seems to regard freedom as "doing as

    you please" absolutely; the next he says that he does not mean this

    at all - so "don11 misunderstand him"!

    Moreover, when you do understand him (or think you do), one of

    the terms essential to his conception of freedom, namely "reality",

    is extremely difficult to comprehend in this context of freedom.

    However, as I say, I believe I knew what he means; but others

    may have a different interpretation, or at least a different

    emphasis.

    Let us start by quoting some of Macmurray's definitions or

    delineations of freedom:-

    To do as we please without restraint or hindrance. (FMW 172).

    To express one's cwn nature in action. (FMW 170).

    To act freely is to act without restraint. (FMW 167).

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    41/510

    - 39 -

    In the absence of personal reality freedom is just impossible.

    (FMW 168).

    Free action is spontaneous action. (FMW 170).

    Free action flows frcm our own nature. (FMW 170).

    Freedom is spontaneity. (FMW 170).

    Communism is therefore the necessary basis of real freedom. (PC 80).

    The free man is the man who takes responsibility for his own life.

    (CF 19).

    Only a real person can be free. (FMW 171 ).

    To be free means not to be under restraint. (FMW 169).

    Freedom depends upon our inner condition. (FMW 172).

    It is obviously untrue to say that we are free to do as we please, if

    we don't know what we want to do. (FMW 172/3).

    Even a real person cannot be free in the face of unreal persons. (FMW

    173).

    And to paraphrase other relevant quotations

    Unfreedom is to be still in the bondage of tradition and authority.

    (FMW 53).

    Undisciplined thought is never free. (FMW 53).

    It is only in friendship that we ever find ourselves completely, and

    so be completely free. (FMW 174).

    To act freely is to take a decision and accept the consequences.

    (CF 19).

    Let me try to collate the above, and bring some cohesion and

    coherence to what may seem a disparate and sometimes incongruent set

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    42/510

    - 40 -

    of assertions. And others could be added, equally as amorphous I

    From the above quotations it will be seen that the key words,

    apart from freedom itself, are:-

    Spontaneity.

    Reality. Real.

    Personal reality.

    Friendship.

    Own nature.

    Inner condition.

    Discipline.

    Responsibility.

    Using, where necessary, these words and concepts, what might be

    said to be Macmurray's ideas cn freedom - in a summary?

    To be free means to be spontaneous, untrammelled, unrestrained -

    even unreflecting. (In "Persons in Relation" Macmurray strongly

    contrasts these two action and reflection - alternating and

    essential phases of life.) To be free means immediacy and

    instantaneousness. It means living and acting creatively at a point

    of time.

    But whilst spontaneity is essential to freedom, not all

    spontaneous action is free. Far frcm it; indeed very little of it

    is. Externally, and more important internally, we are constrained,

    unfree, and inhibited - and this without necessarily having the

    psycho-analytic connotation.

    What, then, must accompany spontaneity in order for our actions

    and our selves to be free? Four things:-

    Reality.

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    43/510

    - 41 -

    Discipline.

    Intention.

    Friendship.

    As we saw earlier Maanurray says that only real persons can be

    free. And so important is this idea of "real" and "reality" that the

    second part of "Freedom in the Modem World" is called Reality and

    Freedom, and five chapters (pp. 116/166), plus many other references,

    are devoted to it.

    Reality might be said to be anything, and our ideas about it.

    "Anything" can be everything external to ourselves, all other people,

    even our own bodies with both their attributes and efficiencies,

    their defects and deficiencies. Included in the tern "ideas" are

    thought i.e. ideation, and feeling, and evaluation.

    Now we can only live freely, and be free, if our ideas, in

    relation to what is not ourselves, are true i.e. if they coincide.

    If they do not coincide, then we cannot be free. To give an

    outlandish example. If my ideas and feelings are such that I persist

    in the "unreality" of believing that carbon-monoxide will serve just

    the same purpose as oxygen in my breathing I shall not be here long,

    let alone be freeI But extreme and ridiculous as this example may

    seem countless people, and all of us sometime in our lives and

    thinking (however much we may think otherwise) have ideas which do

    not coincide with reality. And to that degree we are unreal and -

    more to the point of our present consideration - unfree. We cannot

    act in terms of what is.

    All this seems to me a secular and rational description of a

    situation which used to be religiously stated as (speaking of God)

    "His service is perfect freedom". In other words; one important

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    44/510

    - 42 -

    aspect of freedom, if not all of it, is to discover what is out

    there, how it works, and then fit yourself in with it. If you don't

    you will always be tangled and twisted-up; in other words, unfree.

    The area in man where this conception of Macmurray's has been

    best illustrated is in scientific thinking. All the time we thought

    we knew about the world; all the time we wove imaginative fantasies

    about it, we really got nowhere. But once, from the 15th. century

    onwards, we worked on our ideas about the external world in terms of

    reality we not only got on much better in finding solutions to

    problems, but to the degree that our knowledge was based on reality,

    so equally did we become free. And regarding thought - not emotion

    and evaluation for the moment - the more we really knew, the freer we

    shall increasingly become.

    It is important to note a very pertinent point made by Macmurray

    (FMW 53) - and, incidentally, to see where another of our "words"

    fits in - concerning the above. Thought was increasingly freed from

    the 15th century onwards, freed frcm the fixed, rigid, traditional

    ideas of the Middle Ages. But although this thought was freed it was

    highly disciplined thought. Freedom, in this context, did not mean

    wild, uncontrolled, bizarre, thinking. On the contrary; only by

    relating it totally, through discipline, to what was, did it become

    successful, and enlarge freedom.

    The need to relate it to reality, imposed a necessary discipline

    of its own. "The free thought that has unravelled the mysteries of

    the natural world is not and cannot be undisciplined thought, which

    is never free." (FMW 53) .." It is disciplined by the world with

    which it deals, by testing its conclusions against fact." (FMW 53).

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    45/510

    - 43 -

    The importance of Macmurray's pressing of this point will appear

    later when we come to consider freedom, not of thought, but of

    feelings, and the discovery of values.

    Earlier I spoke, paraphrasing Macmurray, of the absolute and the

    relative aspects of freedom. Another way in which freedan is

    relative for Macmurray concerns intention and the ability to fulfil

    that intention. (See CF 21). Freedom entails responsibility for

    yourself i.e. knowing what you want to do. If a man's wants are

    negligible he does not need much power to fulfil than; and to that

    degree he is soon free. But if a man has immense desires and

    ambitions he has got tobe very important, and command a great amount

    of power to even begin to fulfil them. "But our freedom also depends

    upon what we want to do. For it is no limitation upon a man's

    freedom that he has not the power to do something thathe has no

    desire to do". (CF 21).

    "We can increase our freedom, therefore, by limiting our

    desires. The free man is the man whose means are adequate to his

    ends." (FMW 21 ). This reminds me of a very pertinent remark of Henry

    James. "I call people rich when they're able to meet the

    requirements of their imagination." (The Portrait of a Lady p. 196).

    Thus we can increase our freedom in two ways: -

    1) By reducing our desires.

    2) By increasing our power to achieve them.

    But our chances at the present time of achieving more freedom

    are remote. Our power over the environment has increased out of all

    proportion and expectation; but as this has happened our perception

    of what we want, or could have, have increased even greater. Thus we

    are less free! On the other hand; to reduce desire (as did the

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    46/510

    - 44 -

    saints) in order to enlarge personal freedan has gone out of fashion.

    But presumably for our own happiness, and personal and emotional

    growth, it might be worth trying again. "The increase of power is an

    increase of freedom only if our demands remain relatively stable.

    But this is what they will never do if left to themselves. Plato saw

    this more than two millenniums ago. In the Republic he pointed to

    the fact that though animal desires can be easily satisfied, desire

    in man is insatiable. For when the natural needs of men are

    supplied, new desires appear for more elegant and more complicated

    satisfactions, until the resources available are too few for the

    demands upon them: and in this he found the origin of war.

    The very spectacle of increased resources breeds a corresponding

    proliferation of desires; and if this process is uncontrolled,

    desires always grow faster than the power to satisfy them; for their

    increase is rooted in the creativeness of the imagination. If, then,

    we double our resources while we treble our demands upon them we do

    not increase our freedan. We diminish it. There is no need for

    astonishment that the vast increase of our resources in the last

    generation has gone hand in hand with a loss of human freedom. The

    two variables - the moral and the technological - must both be

    considered. Self-control is as imperative as the control of nature

    if freedom is to be increased or even maintained." (CF 22/3). (See

    also CF 21/2 for very relevant remarks concerning these points).

    The Three Modes of Freedom

    Even as - we saw this earlier - there are three ways of being,

    so there are three corresponding freedoms. These are:-

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    47/510

    - 45 -

    1 ) The freedan of material things, we recognise this when we say

    that things make a "free" fall to the ground if left to their own

    desires and "volition". (For a full exposition and discussion of the

    points merely stated here see FMW chapters 8 and 9).

    This first type Macmurray calls mechanical freedom.

    2) The freedom of living organisms. The essence of their

    freedom is to grew, respond, and adapt themselves to their

    environment. (FMW chapters 8 and 10).

    3) The freedom of persons. "Personal reality expresses itself

    in spontaneous objectivity. (BMW 182). This means we are free - or

    freest - when we relate to, and live in connunion with, that which is

    not ourselves. (FMW chapters 8 and 11). The most advanced and

    satisfactory state of this condition is in our relationships with

    other human beings. Thus only in friendship can we find true, or

    perhaps we should say real, freedom.

    "To realize ourselves we have to be ourselves to make ourselves

    real. That means thinking and feeling really, for ourselves, and

    expressing our own reality in word and action. And this freedom, and

    the secret of it, lies in our capacity for friendship." (FMW 219).

    Thus, being essentially personal by nature, we achieve the

    maximum freedom we are capable of, and can knew, in friendship - and

    better and wider still, in the extension of this which is community.

    The whole of chapter 3 of "Conditions of Freedom" is taken up with

    the analysis and development of this contention of Macmurray's. "The

    prime condition of freedom lies in the character and quality of human

    relations". (CF 31).

    Whilst not a perfect exposition of Macmurray's ideas on "What is

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    48/510

    - 46 -

    Freedom?", I hope I have given enough, and got it together enough, to

    show that at least I have some understanding of what he is, or at

    least intends to be, saying.

    Appraisement (2)

    1 ) Regarding the paradox of freedom in which man finds himself,

    probably Macmurray's analysis, in principle, is right. Man's

    position for long, at least in or according to religious circles, has

    been recognised as one of in-betweeness. "We are a little lower than

    the angels." "We are fallen creatures." Philosophy, however, seems

    not to over-favour this view - not at least to my knowledge. All

    arguments in this area seem rather either/or; some philosophers

    contending that we are free; others that we are not. In this matter

    perhaps Macmurray introduces a realistic note into the discussion.

    Even Rousseau's dictum, perhaps for rhetorical effect, seems of the

    black and white, absolute, type.

    2) As regards the fear aspect. I am sure much of this is true.

    But whilst Macmurray seems to suggest that the choice has

    continuously to be made between security and freedan, I am not so

    sure about this. There seems to me to be permanently negative people

    in whose lives fear, in a multiplicity of forms, pervades. Whilst

    others are not fear-enveloped. But, of course, even the most

    positive and free-loving person may sometimes be accosted by doubts

    and fears.

    3) Macmurray (CF 19) makes the interesting point that history

    reveals not a struggle of man for freedom, but a struggle to avoid

    it! This is a clever volte-face; not a usual interpretation of

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    49/510

    - 47 -

    history. But it is not wholly true. We are intending always to be

    free; over the last few hundred years anyway. Whether we are or not

    is another matter.

    On the other hand, it does seem that innumerable people do

    depend upon, or are looking for, some form of external authority,

    leader, oracle, god-figure, saviour, prophet, religion, or ideology;

    and to the degree that they are dependent psychologically upon any of

    these, and other similar preps, they are unfree, and desire

    unfreedom. And must retain so. Perhaps at first there is a struggle

    not to be free - as witnessed in the opposition to the ideas of

    Copernicus, Darwin, and Freud - but freedom eventually seems to

    triumph; at least, so far.

    4) We continue new with an appraisement of Macmurray's ideas of

    what Freedom is, or of how it manifests itself.

    As already hinted, it is a pity Macmurray does not "get it

    together" more. To have to try and understand bits and pieces in a

    piecemeal fashion, and make some total coherence of it is quite a

    task. Be this as it may, I feel that Macmurray is on the right

    track. What other writer or thinker has given such valuable

    attention to freedom in the way Macmurray has? Nobody that I knew

    of. Some religious writers, with an axe to grind, are perhaps saying

    the same sort of thing but Macmurray, religious as he might be

    basically, discusses freedom in contemporary and secular terms. We

    all talk of freedom, from the heads of state to the humblest office-

    boy, but apart from political freedom - which is only a very small

    part of it, important as that may be - nobody discusses freedom,

    tries to understand, nor attempt to enlarge it. On the contrary.

    Everybody thinks, wrongly, that they have got it! All except

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    50/510

    - 48 -

    Macmurray.

    Macmurray's idea of freedom and its relation to reality is

    important. Science, as he suggests, proves it. Only as we rightly

    know what we have to contend with, external to ourselves, can we act

    propitiously, and thus be free. If we do not know reality there must

    be a great deal of hit and miss about our responses and behaviour.

    The external and the internal grew together i.e. at the same

    time and out of the same experiences. As we come to know reality so

    we become more real inside, and thus more free. To this whole set-up

    I have always given the name - although Macmurray never mentions or

    suggests it - maturity. But maturity, as we shall try to understand

    it in this context, has not a great deal to do with maturity, and the

    mature person, as we commonly understand it in our society today.

    Today's mature person is one who has swallowed and embodied all

    of the contemporary main-stream values. He is self-sufficient,

    materialistic, has a family intending to go to university or some

    other prestiged and advantaged training, professes to care far others

    but really doesn't care a darrm, holds responsible positions

    irrespective of any moral considerations these positions ought to

    raise and be concerned with; is an IQist, and actively promotes the

    interests of himself and the various limited groups with which he is

    associated, totally oblivious to the interests of other persons and

    groups, or of the interests of the community as a whole. In other

    words; absolutely different from Macmurray's idea of a real and free

    per sen!

    Maturity, as I would have it understood, means and entails a

    great deal of objectivity in thought and consequent actions; much

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    51/510

    - 49 -

    less subjectivity, whether of self or groups; belief in, and the

    practice of, emotional and relational growth - not the static, self-

    complacent , negative, self-indulgent belief that we are what we are,

    and that we feel what we do, and nothing will or could change it.

    Maturity, too, requires social interest, cne-mandan, caring - a sense

    of - and a strong belief and intention that men, all men are personal

    beings, and that we can live satisfactorily only if we promote this

    end.

    If, as I believe, Maanurray meant all these and other similar

    things by his concept of reality, and its importance for freedom,

    then I think he would be better understood if at least the inner, the

    subjective, the felt, side of reality was called maturity, instead of

    calling it "being real". But then, if he called it maturity it would

    inevitably be misunderstood! Incidentally, after all his writing and

    chapters on reality and being real, his description of a "real"

    person (FMW 256/7, and to some extent subsequently - to page 166)

    seems nothing short of ludicrous! Surely our knowledge of whether a

    person is real or not comes from an acquaintance with his

    personality, mind, attitudes, and values. In other words, we must

    have some knowledge of him from his speech and actions. But

    Macmurray, for some reason I have never been able to fathom, seems to

    think that you can go into a room of people and, by just looking,

    pick out the real ones!

    This is surely nonsense - the nonsense of mysticism and

    intuition, which frcm evidence elsewhere you would have thought

    Macmurray utterly despised and rejected. Even if some people do have

    a noticeable aura of calmness and appeal, which sets them apart in a

    crowd, from experience we knew that usually their minds are trivial,

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    52/510

    - 50 -

    their attitudes trite, their character thoroughly selfish and self-

    promoting, their morals non-existent, and eager only to exploit their

    own attractiveness.

    Perhaps you might assume that Macmurray was unconsciously

    projecting his own type of personality and ability to stand out in a

    crowd by some essence or emanation. Far from it. When I met him in

    1971, I was surprised - after reading his works and the person that

    comes through - to find him relatively insignificant and generally

    lacking in any special attraction or charisma. So perhaps if it was

    not projection which made him have this unreal idea of the perceiving

    of real persons, it was an unconscious wish or compensation factor.

    Whatever it was, it certainly produced a strange, inconsistent, and

    unfortunate anomaly.

    Regarding other points as to what freedom is; there is much

    truth in the idea of freedom depending upon our needs and desires.

    Aldous Huxley's ideal - at least in one period of his life, circa

    1946 - was the "non-attached" man. This followed and exemplified, of

    course, in a modem context the religious ideas of many before him,

    as Huxley himself acknowledged - both in title and content - in his

    work "The Perennial Philosophy". Much of Eastern philosophy

    especially Buddhism, so advocated by Schopenhauer in recent times

    (advocated but not practised!), believes that a satisfactory human

    state can be reached only by a reduction, or even an obliteration, of

    desires and wants.

    Thus we have, presumably, the paradox of a man in prison - with,

    needless to say, the right attitude - being the freest man on earth;

    or as free as a man outside who is enslaved by his desires. But if

  • 7/26/2019 Philosophy of John Macmurray

    53/510

    - 51 -

    carried to extremes this approach to freedom entails a complete

    withdrawal from life. Where then would come the real freedom, as

    advocated by Macmurray, found only in the "personal", and in

    friendship and comnunity? So whilst recognising that we can enlarge

    our freedom by reducing wants, Macmurray - it would seen - cannot

    believe in going the whole way, for this would banish freedom, and

    the possibility of it, altogether; or at least the freedom Macmurray

    so earnestly advocates.

    5) Is friendship, which includes fellowship and is extended to

    community, the area and condition of human life where we do, or can,

    achieve freedom? Freedom, by the way, is far Macmurray more

    important, satisfactory, and worthy of humanity, than happiness. "We

    recognise this when we honour those who have been ready to sacrifice

    happiness, and even life itself, for freedom's sake." (CF 16).

    Being quite gregarious myself - if not fanatical about it - I am

    inclined, from my own life and experience, to regard this as true.

    All permanent, or even tendencies to, withdrawal I regard as rather

    pathological. The saints i.e. those that did, I find strangely odd

    and not to be admired. Melancholics and isolates in mental hospitals

    cannot be regarded as enviable nor the sanest amongst us. People who

    choose to live alone seem to be missing out to me however happy and

    contented they may profess to be. The classical example is George

    Gissing in his semi-autobiographical "The Private Papers of Henry

    Ryecroft". It is not possible for me to believe that his so