Philosophy in the Carolingian Empire

download Philosophy in the Carolingian Empire

of 5

Transcript of Philosophy in the Carolingian Empire

  • 8/9/2019 Philosophy in the Carolingian Empire

    1/5

    Philosophy in the Carolingian Empire

    Outside the Roman Empire the world was transformed beyond recogni-tion. The life of the prophet Muhammad came to an end in 633, and within

    ten years of his death the religion of Islam had spread by conquest from its

    native Arabia throughout the neighbouring Persian Empire and the

    Roman provinces of Syria, Palestine, and Egypt. In 698 the Muslims

    captured Carthage, and ten years later they were masters of all North

    Africa. In 711 they crossed the Straits of Gibraltar, easily defeated the Gothic

    Christians, and Xooded through Spain. Their advance into northern

    Europe was halted only in 732, when they were defeated at Poitiers by

    the Frankish leader Charles Martel.

    Charles Martels grandson Charlemagne, who became king of the

    Franks in 768, drove the Muslims back to the Pyrenees, but did no more

    than nibble at their Spanish dominions. To the east, however, he con-

    quered Lombardy, Bavaria, and Saxony, and had his son proclaimed king of

    Italy. When Pope Leo III was driven out of Rome by a revolution, Charle-

    magne restored him to his see. In gratitude the Pope crowned him as

    Roman emperor in St Peters on Christmas Day 800a date which, if not

    the most memorable in history, is at least the easiest to remember. Thus

    began the Holy Roman Empire, which at Charlemagnes death in 814

    included almost all the Christian inhabitants of continental western

    Europe.

    Charlemagne was anxious to improve standards of education and cul-

    ture in his dominions, and he collected scholars from various parts of

    Europe to form a Palatine School at his capital, Aachen. One of the most

    distinguished of these was Alcuin of York, who took a keen interest in

    AristotlesCategories. The logic textbook which he wrote, Dialectica, takes the

    form of a dialogue in which the pupil Charlemagne asks questions and the

    teacher Alcuin gives answers. Alcuin retired in the last years of his life to

    run a small school in the abbey of St Martin of Tours, of which he later

    became abbot. He spent his time, he told the emperor, dispensing to thispupils the honey of Scripture, the wine of classical literature, and the

    apples of grammar. To a privileged few he displayed the treasures of

    astronomyCharlemagnes favourite hobby.

    When philosophy revived between the ninth and eleventh centuries, it

    did so not within the old Roman Empire of Byzantium, but in the Frankish

    P H I L O S O P H Y A N D F A I T H

    29

  • 8/9/2019 Philosophy in the Carolingian Empire

    2/5

    Empire of Charlemagnes successors and in the Abbasid court of Muslim

    Baghdad. The leading philosophers of the revival were, in the West, John

    the Scot, and in the East, Ibn Sina (Avicenna).

    John was born in Ireland in the Wrst decades of the ninth century. He is not

    to be mistaken for the more famous John Duns Scotus, who Xourished in the

    fourteenth century. It is undoubtedly confusing that there are two medieval

    philosophers with the name John the Scot. What makes it doubly confusing

    is that one of them was an Irishman, and the other was for all practical

    purposes an Englishman. The ninth-century philosopher, for the avoidance

    of doubt, gave himself the surname Eriugena, which means Son of Erin.

    By 851 Eriugena had migrated from Ireland to the court of Charles the

    Bald, the grandson of Charlemagne. This was probably at Compiegne,

    which Charles thought of renaming Carlopolis, on the model of Constan-

    tinople. Charles was a lover of things Greek, and the astonishingly learned

    Eriugena, who had mastered Greek (no one knows where), won his favour

    and wrote him Xattering poems in that language. He taught liberal arts at

    the court for a while, but his interests began to turn towards philosophy.

    Once, commenting on a text on the borderline between grammar and

    logic, he wrote no one enters heaven except through philosophy.9

    Eriugena Wrst engaged in philosophy in 851 when invited by Hincmar,

    the archbishop of Reims, to write a refutation of the ideas of a learned and

    pessimistic monk, Gottschalk. Gottschalk had taken up the problem of

    predestination where Augustine had left oV. He was reported to have

    deduced from the texts of Augustine something that was generally there

    left implicit, namely that predestination aVected sinners as well as saints. It

    was, he taught, not only the blessed in heaven whose ultimate fate had

    been predestined, the damned also had been predestined to hell before they

    were ever conceived. This doctrine of double predestination seemed to

    Archbishop Hincmar to be heretical. At the very least, like the monks of

    Augustines time, he regarded it as a doctrine inimical to good monastic

    discipline: sinners might conclude that, since their fate had been sealed

    long ago, there was no point in giving up sinning. Hence his invitation toEriugena to put Gottschalk down (PL 125. 845).

    Whether or not Gottschalk had been accurately reported, Eriugenas

    refutation of his alleged heresy was, from Hincmars point of view, worse

    9 See J. J. OMeara, Eriugena(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988), chs. 1 and 2.

    P H I L O S O P H Y A N D F A I T H

    30

  • 8/9/2019 Philosophy in the Carolingian Empire

    3/5

    than the disease. Eriugenas arguments were weak, and in attacking the

    predestination of the damned, he emasculated the predestination of the

    blessed. There could not be a double predestination, he said, because God

    was simple and undivided; and there was no such thing as predestination

    because God was eternal. The Wrst argument is unconvincing because if a

    double predestination threatens Gods simplicity, so too does the distinc-

    tion between predestination and foreknowledge, which was the favoured

    solution of Gottschalks opponents. The second argument does not pro-

    vide the desired incentive to the sinner to repent, because whatever

    temporal qualiWcation we give to the divine determining of our fate, it is

    certainly, on the Augustinian view, independent of any choice of ours

    (CCCM 50. 12).

    The Frankish kingdom was torn by doctrinal strife, and both Gottschalk

    and Eriugena found themselves condemned by Church councils. The

    Council of Quierzy in 853the third of a seriesdeWned, against

    Gottschalk, that while God predestined the blessed to heaven, he did

    not predestine others to sin: he merely left them in the human mass of

    perdition and predestined only their punishment, not their guilt. The

    condemnation of Eriugena, at Valence in 855, aYrmed that there was

    indeed a predestination of the impious to death no less than a predestin-

    ation of the elect to life. The diVerence was this: that in the election

    of those to be saved the mercy of God preceded all merit, whereas in

    the damnation of those who were to perish evil desert preceded just

    judgement. The Council fathers were not above vulgar abuse, saying

    that Eriugena had deWled the purity of the faith with nauseating Irish

    porridge.

    Despite his condemnation, Eriugena remained in favour with Charles

    the Bald and was commissioned by him in 858 to translate into Latin three

    treatises of Dionysius the Areopagite: theDivine Names, theCelestial Hierarchy,

    and theEcclesiastical Hierarchy. He found the Neoplatonic ideas of Dionysius

    congenial and went on to construct his own system on somewhat similar

    lines, in a work of Wve volumes called On Natureor, to give it its Greektitle,Periphyseon.

    There are, according to Eriugena, four great divisions of nature: nature

    creating and uncreated, nature created and creating, nature created and

    uncreating, and nature uncreating and uncreated (1. 1). The Wrst such

    nature is God. The second is the intellectual world of Platonic ideas, which

    P H I L O S O P H Y A N D F A I T H

    31

  • 8/9/2019 Philosophy in the Carolingian Empire

    4/5

    creates the third nature, the world of material objects. The fourth is God

    again, conceived not as creator but as the end to which things return.

    Eriugena tells us that the most important distinction within nature is

    that between the things that are and the things that are not. It is discon-

    certing to be told that God is among the things that are not; however,

    Eriugena does not mean that there is no God, but rather that God does not

    Wt into any of Aristotles ten categories of being (2. 15). God is above being,

    and what he is doing is something better than existing. One name that we

    can give to the ineVable and incomprehensible brilliance of the divine

    goodness is Nothing.10

    Eriugenas third division, the material world, is the easiest to compre-

    hend (3. 3). Like Philoponus, he believes that heaven and earth are made

    out of the same elements; there is no special quintessence for the heavenly

    bodies. The cosmos, he tells us, consists of three spheres: the earth in the

    centre, next to it the sphere of the sun (which is roughly 45,000 miles

    away), and outermost the sphere of the moon and the stars (roughly 90,000

    miles away). While Eriugena thinks that the sun revolves around the

    world, he takes some steps towards a heliocentric system: Jupiter, Mars,

    Venus, and Mercury, he believed, were planets of the sun, revolving

    around it.

    Where do human beings Wt into Eriugenas fourfold scheme? They seem

    to straddle the second and third division. As animals, we belong in the

    third division, and yet we transcend the other animals. We can say with

    equal propriety that man is an animal and that he is not an animal. He

    shares reason, mind, and interior sense with the celestial essences, but he

    shares his Xesh, his outward self, with other animals. Man was created twice

    over: once from the earth, with the animals, but once with the intellectual

    creatures of the second division of nature. Does this mean that we have two

    souls? No, each of us has a single, undivided, soul: wholly life, wholly mind,

    wholly reason, wholly memory. This soul creates the body, acting as the

    agent of God, who does not himself create anything mortal. Even when

    soul and body are separated at death, the soul continues to govern thebody scattered throughout the elements (4. 8).

    As the creator of the body, the soul belongs to that division of nature

    which is both created and creative. This second division consists of what

    10 Eriugenas theology is discussed at greater length in Ch. 9 below.

    P H I L O S O P H Y A N D F A I T H

    32

  • 8/9/2019 Philosophy in the Carolingian Empire

    5/5

    Eriugena calls the primordial causes of things, which he identiWes with the

    Platonic Ideas (2. 2). These were pre-formed by God the Father in his

    eternal Word. The Idea of Man is that in accordance with which man is

    made in the image of God. But that image is deformed in fallen humans.

    Had God not foreseen that Adam would fall, humans would not have been

    divided into male and female; they would have propagated as angels do.

    Their bodies would have been celestial and would have lacked metabolism.

    After the resurrection, our bodies will resume their sexless and ethereal

    form. When the world Wnally ends, place and time will disappear, and all

    creatures will Wnd salvation in the nature that is uncreated and uncreating.

    Eriugena was one of the most original and imaginative thinkers of the

    Middle Ages and built the ideas of his Greek sources into a system that was

    uniquely his own. Reading him is not easy, but his text can cast a fascinat-

    ing spell on the reader. He has a fanatical love of paradox: whenever he

    writes a sentence he can hardly bear not to follow it with its contradictory.

    He often displays great subtlety and ingenuity in showing that the two

    apparent contradictions can be interpreted in such a way as to reconcile

    them. But sometimes his wayward intellect leads him into sheer nonsense,

    as when he writes In unity itself all numbers are at once together, and no

    number precedes or follows another, since all are one (3. 66).

    Though Eriugena constantly quotes the Bible, his system is closer to

    pagan Neoplatonism than to traditional Christian thought, and it is unsur-

    prising thatOn Naturewas eventually condemned by ecclesiastical authority.

    In 1225 Pope Honorius III ordered all surviving copies of the work to be sent

    to Rome to be burned. But legend was kind to his memory. The story was

    often told of Charles the Bald asking him, over dinner, what separates a Scot

    from a sot, and being given the answer only this table. And at one time the

    University of Oxford implausibly venerated him as its founder.11

    Muslim and Jewish PhilosophersThe Christian Eriugena was a much less important precursor of Western

    medieval philosophy than a series of Muslim thinkers in the countries that

    are now Iraq and Iran. Besides being signiWcant philosophers in their own

    11 See OMeara, Eriugena, 21416.

    P H I L O S O P H Y A N D F A I T H

    33