Pavlo Prokopovych Presentation SAED 2011

download Pavlo Prokopovych Presentation SAED 2011

of 20

Transcript of Pavlo Prokopovych Presentation SAED 2011

  • 8/6/2019 Pavlo Prokopovych Presentation SAED 2011

    1/20

    Domain L-Majorization and Equilibrium Existence in Discontinuous Games

    by Pavlo Prokopovych (KEI and KSE)

    July 1, 2011

  • 8/6/2019 Pavlo Prokopovych Presentation SAED 2011

    2/20

    The Single Deviation Property

    Consider a compact game G = (Xi; ui)ni=1: Denote X = X1X2: : :Xn

    and by EG X the set of pure strategy Nash equilibria of G

    Barelli and Soza (2009), Nessah and Tian (2009), Reny (2009):

    A game G = (Xi; ui)ni=1 has the single deviation (SD) property if when-

    ever x 2 XnEG, there exist a prole of deviation strategies d 2 X anda neighborhood UX(x) ofx such that for all x

    0 2 UX(x), there is a playeri for whom ui(di; x

    0

    i

    ) > ui(x0)

    Both better-reply secure games and diagonal transfer continuous games pos-sess this property

  • 8/6/2019 Pavlo Prokopovych Presentation SAED 2011

    3/20

    SDP 1

    1:pdf

  • 8/6/2019 Pavlo Prokopovych Presentation SAED 2011

    4/20

  • 8/6/2019 Pavlo Prokopovych Presentation SAED 2011

    5/20

    Two Remarks about the Single Deviation Property

    (1) The assumption that for all x0 2 UX(x), there is a player i for whom

    ui(di(x); x0i) > ui(x

    0) implies that the set of nonequilibrium points is

    open in X

    (2) The assumption that a deviation strategy is dened for each player sim-

    plies the proof:

    Every nonequilibrium point x has an open neighborhood U(x) on whicha well-behaved correspondence Fx = (F1; : : : ; F n) is dened (Fi(z) =di(x) for z 2 UX(x))

    On the other hand, having to dene a deviation strategy for each player

    makes assumption (ii) less tractable. It is not always necessary

  • 8/6/2019 Pavlo Prokopovych Presentation SAED 2011

    6/20

    The Single Deviation Property: Equilibrium Existence

    Reny (2009): a three-person quasiconcave game with the SD property having

    no Nash equilibrium in pure strategiesIn that example, it is impossible to construct a cover of X for whichassumption (ii) of Corollary 1 (on the convex hulls of deviation strategiesis satised)

    Consider a two-player game (X = X1 X2 = [0; 1] [0; 1])

    It has the single deviation property, however not every open cover ofX satisesthe assumption on the the convex hulls of deviation strategies

  • 8/6/2019 Pavlo Prokopovych Presentation SAED 2011

    7/20

    SDP 3

    2:pdf

  • 8/6/2019 Pavlo Prokopovych Presentation SAED 2011

    8/20

    The Weak Single Deviation Property

    A game G = (Xi; u

    i)n

    i=1has the weak single deviation (WSD) property if

    whenever x 2 XnEG, there exist an open neighborhood UX(x) of x, a

    set of players I(x) N = f1; : : : ng, a collection of deviation strategies

    fdi 2 Xi : i 2 I(x)g such that, for every x0 2 UX(x)nEG, there exists

    i 2 I(x) with ui(di; x0i) > ui(x

    0).

    The WSD property covers games with a non-closed set of Nash equilibria

    (such as second-price sealed-bid auctions)

  • 8/6/2019 Pavlo Prokopovych Presentation SAED 2011

    9/20

    The Weak Single Deviation Property: Equilibrium Existence

    Theorem 1 Let G = (Xi; ui)i2N be a compact game. Suppose that

    (i) G has the weak single deviation property, i.e. for each x 2 XnEG, thereexist an open neighborhoodUX(x) ofx, a set of playersI(x) N, a collection

    of pointsfdi(x) 2 Xi : i 2 I(x)g such that, for everyx0 2 UX(x)nEG, there

    exists i 2 I(x) with ui(di(x); x0i) > ui(x

    0);

    (ii) for each A 2 hXnEGi and every z 2 \x2AUX(x), there exists i 2

    [x2AI(x) such that zi =2 cof[x2Adi(x)g.Then G has a pure strategy Nash equilibrium.

    Theorem 1 follows from a more general result, Theorem 3

  • 8/6/2019 Pavlo Prokopovych Presentation SAED 2011

    10/20

    Equilibrium Existence in Two-Player Games

    Theorem 2 If a two-player, compact, quasiconcave gameG = (Xi; ui)2i=1

    has the weak single deviation property and each Xi is a subset of the realline, then G has a Nash equilibrium.

    The proof of Theorem 2 is lengthy since in it a cover satisfying the conditions

    of Theorem 1 is constructed

    The fact that I(x) may be a proper subset of N plays an important role inthe proof

    To check whether assumption (ii) holds, it is enough to check it for every pairof elements of the cover

  • 8/6/2019 Pavlo Prokopovych Presentation SAED 2011

    11/20

    SDP 5

    3:pdf

  • 8/6/2019 Pavlo Prokopovych Presentation SAED 2011

    12/20

    Qualitative Games: Some Denitions

    In the description of a game, each payo function can be replaced witha preference correspondence:

    Pi : X Xi; Pi(x) = fzi 2 Xi : ui(zi; xi) > ui(x)g:

    The corresponding qualitative game is denoted by = (Xi; Pi)i2N

    A strategy prole x 2 X is an equilibrium of if Pi(x) = ? for all i

    For = (Xi; Pi)i2N; we call the set Dom = [i2NDomPi the domain of (all points that are not equilibria)

  • 8/6/2019 Pavlo Prokopovych Presentation SAED 2011

    13/20

    Qualitative Games: Equilibrium Existence

    Theorem 3 Let Xi be a nonempty, compact, convex subset of a Hausdor

    topological vector space and = (Xi; Pi)i2N be a qualitative game. Sup-

    pose, for each x 2 Dom, there exist I(x) N, and an (n + 1)-tuple

    (D1x; : : : ; D

    nx ; Ux), where D

    ix : X

    Xi and Ux is an open neighborhood ofx in X, such that

    (i) DomDix = Ux and Dix has open lower sections in X for all i 2 I(x), and

    DomDix = ? for all i 2 NnfI(x)g;

    (ii) for each A 2 hDomi and every z 2 \x2AUx, there exists i 2 [x2AI(x)

    such that zi =2 cof[x2ADix(z)g.

    Then has an equilibrium.

  • 8/6/2019 Pavlo Prokopovych Presentation SAED 2011

    14/20

    Domain L-Majorized Games

    If = (Xi; Pi)i2N has no equilibrium and Assumptions (i) and (ii) of

    Theorem 3 hold, then it is possible to construct a strict correspondenceF : X X with open lower sections and such that x =2 coF(x) for all

    x 2 X (dubbed "of class L" by Yannelis and Prabhakar 1983)

    In our terminology, the game with Dom = X is domain L-majorized

    It follows from the maximal element existence theorem for correspondences of

    class L (Yannelis and Prabhakar 1983, Theorem 5.1) that DomF 6= X,

    a contradiction

  • 8/6/2019 Pavlo Prokopovych Presentation SAED 2011

    15/20

    Domain L-Majorized Correspondences

    There are a number of generalizations of the notion of an L-majorized corre-

    pondence (Yannelis and Prabhakar 1983).

    A correspondence F : X Y is domain L-majorized if there exists a corre-

    spondence F : X Y of class L such that DomF DomF

    For = (Xi; Pi)i2N, it is important not to impose the assumption that each

    Pi is domain L-majorized (a too strong assumption)

    A number of properties of domain L-majorized correspondences are studied

  • 8/6/2019 Pavlo Prokopovych Presentation SAED 2011

    16/20

    Two Corollaries of Theorem 3

    A generalized version of the Fan-Browder collective xed-point theorem:

    Corollary 2 Let X1; : : : ; X n be nonempty, compact, convex subsets of Haus-

    dor topological vector spaces, and X = i2NXi. For each i 2 N, letDi : X Xi have open lower sections. If for each x 2 X, there exists

    i 2 N such that Di(x) 6= ?, then there exists x 2 X and i 2 N such that

    x 2 coDi(x).

    Corollary 3 Let each Xi be a nonempty, compact, convex subset of a Haus-dor topological vector space and let = (Xi; Pi)i2N be a qualitative game.

    Assume that, for each i 2 N the correspondence Pi : X Xi is domain

    L-majorized. Then has an equilibrium in X.

  • 8/6/2019 Pavlo Prokopovych Presentation SAED 2011

    17/20

    The Strong Single Deviation Property

    A game G = (Xi; ui)i2N has the strong single deviation property if whenever

    x 2 XnEG, there exist an open neighborhood UX(x) ofx; a set of indexes

    I(x) N; a family of open neighborhoods fUXi(xi) : i 2 I(x)g, a

    collection of deviation strategies fdi 2 Xi : i 2 I(x)g; and a number"(x) > 0 such that, for every x0 2 UX(x)nEG, there exists i 2 I(x)

    with ui(di; zi) "(x) > ui(x0) for all zi 2 UXi(xi)

    Neighborhoods UXi

    (xi

    ), i 2 I(x), and a positive constant "(x) are added

    to the denition of the weak SD property

  • 8/6/2019 Pavlo Prokopovych Presentation SAED 2011

    18/20

    Better-Reply Security Amended

    Lemma 1 A compact gameG = (Xi; ui)ni=1 with no pure strategy Nash

    equilibrium has the strong single deviation property if and only if it is

    better-reply secure.

    Corollary 4 If G = (Xi; ui)ni=1 is compact, quasiconcave, and has the

    strong single deviation property, then it possesses a pure strategy Nash

    equilibrium.

    The better-reply security condition can be amended by considering, insteadof GrG, the nonequilibrium graph of G; GrnG = f(x; u) 2 X Rn j

    ui(x) = ui for all i 2 N and x 2 XnEGg

  • 8/6/2019 Pavlo Prokopovych Presentation SAED 2011

    19/20

    An Example

    Consider the following simultaneous-move timing game between two players

    with X1 = X2 = [0; 1] (Reny 1999). The payo to player i is given by

    ui(xi; xi) =8>:

    1; if xi < xi;

    'i(xi); if xi = xi;1; if xi > xi;

    where 'i(xi) = 1 if xi = xi and xi < 0:5; and 'i(xi) = 0 if xi = xiand xi 0:5.

    The set of Nash equilibria of the game is not compact, therefore, Renys

    theorem can not be applied. However the game has the strong single

    deviation property

  • 8/6/2019 Pavlo Prokopovych Presentation SAED 2011

    20/20

    TG

    4:pdf