Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect...

38
Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem Current theories make a distinction between two types of case, STRUCTURAL case and INHERENT (or LEXICAL) case (Chomsky 1981), similar to the older distinction between GRAMMATICAL and SEMANTIC case (Kurylowicz 1964). 1 Structural case is assumed to be assigned at S-structure in a purely configurational way , whereas inherent case is assigned at D-structure in possible dependence on the governing predicates’ s lexical properties. It is well known that not all cases fall cleanly into this typology . In particular, there is a class of cases that pattern syntactically with the structural cases, but are semantically conditioned. These cases however depend on different semantic conditions than inherent cases do: instead of being sensitive to the thematic relation that the NP bears to the verbal predicate, they are sensitive to the NP’ s definiteness, animacy , or quantificational properties, or to the aspectual character of the VP , or to some combination of these factors. The Finnish partitive is a particularly clear instance of this apparently hybrid category of semantically conditioned structural case. 2 The interest of partitive case goes beyond the fact that it poses an apparent puz- zle for case theory . The combination of conditioning factors governing the partitive raises semantic questions as well. In its aspectual function, partitive case is assigned to the objects of verbs which denote an unbounded event, in a sense to be made clear below . In its NP-related function, partitive case is assigned to quantitatively indetermi- nate NPs (including indefinite bare plurals and mass nouns), even if the verb denotes a bounded event. Moreover, in Slavic, the distinction between perfective and imperfec- tive aspect has the very same two functions (among others). How can these functions 1 This paper was inspired by C. Pi ˜ non’s dissertation. I am deeply grateful to him and to Cleo Condoravdi and Henriette de Swart for their searching comments on earlier versions, as well as to Mary Laughren and David Nash for generously answering my questions about W arlpiri. In addition, the paper has benefited from the scrutiny of two reviewers. 2 For evidence that partitive case is a structural case, see section 3, and V ainikka 1993, who argues that the partitive is the default case assigned to obligatory complements of verbs, prepositions, comparative ad- jectives, caseless numerals, and certain quantifiers. See also Nikanne 1990 and Maling 1993. The present paper is concerned only with the partitive as the case of the object of verbs, the only function in which it alternates with the accusative according to the semantic conditions investigated here. 1

Transcript of Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect...

Page 1: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

PartitiveCaseandAspect

PaulKiparskyStanfordUniversity

1 Partitive caseasa syntacticand semanticproblem

Currenttheoriesmakea distinction betweentwo typesof case,STRUCTURAL caseand INHERENT (or LEXICAL ) case(Chomsky1981),similar to the older distinctionbetweenGRAMMATICAL andSEMANTIC case(Kuryłowicz 1964).1 Structuralcaseisassumedto beassignedatS-structurein apurelyconfigurationalway, whereasinherentcaseis assignedat D-structurein possibledependenceon the governingpredicates’slexical properties.It is well knownthatnot all casesfall cleanlyinto this typology. Inparticular,thereis a classof casesthatpatternsyntacticallywith thestructuralcases,but aresemanticallyconditioned.Thesecaseshoweverdependon differentsemanticconditionsthaninherentcasesdo: insteadof beingsensitiveto the thematicrelationthat the NP bearsto the verbalpredicate,they aresensitiveto the NP’s definiteness,animacy, or quantificationalproperties,or to the aspectualcharacterof the VP, or tosomecombinationof thesefactors.TheFinnishpartitiveis aparticularlyclearinstanceof thisapparentlyhybridcategoryof semanticallyconditionedstructuralcase.2

The interestof partitive casegoesbeyondthe fact that it posesan apparentpuz-zle for casetheory. The combinationof conditioningfactorsgoverningthe partitiveraisessemanticquestionsaswell. In its aspectualfunction,partitivecaseis assignedto theobjectsof verbswhich denoteanunboundedevent,in a senseto bemadeclearbelow. In its NP-relatedfunction,partitivecaseis assignedto quantitativelyindetermi-nateNPs(includingindefinitebarepluralsandmassnouns),evenif theverbdenotesaboundedevent.Moreover,in Slavic, thedistinctionbetweenperfectiveandimperfec-tive aspecthasthevery sametwo functions(amongothers).How canthesefunctions

1This paperwasinspiredby C. Pinon’sdissertation.I amdeeplygratefulto him andto CleoCondoravdiandHenriettedeSwartfor their searchingcommentson earlierversions,aswell asto Mary LaughrenandDavidNashfor generouslyansweringmy questionsaboutWarlpiri. In addition,thepaperhasbenefitedfromthescrutinyof two reviewers.

2For evidencethat partitive caseis a structuralcase,seesection3, andVainikka 1993,who arguesthatthepartitive is thedefaultcaseassignedto obligatorycomplementsof verbs,prepositions,comparativead-jectives,caselessnumerals,andcertainquantifiers.SeealsoNikanne1990andMaling 1993. Thepresentpaperis concernedonly with the partitive asthe caseof the objectof verbs,the only function in which italternateswith theaccusativeaccordingto thesemanticconditionsinvestigatedhere.

1

Page 2: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

beunified?And how cancase,a nominalcategory, expressthesamemeaningsastheverbalcategoryof aspect?

Froma typologicalperspective,theaccusative/partitivecasealternationin Finnishis intriguingbecauseits aspectualsideresemblestheso-calledconativecasealternationbetweenaccusativeanddativeobjectsfoundin AustralianandPolynesianlanguages,amongothers(Hale1982,Laughren1988,Simpson1991).Thesemanticeffectof thetwo casealternations,andtheclassof verbsthatparticipatein them,arealsosimilar.And the conativedativealsoseemsto straddlethedistinctionbetweenstructuralandinherentcase. The dativeobject is syntacticallytransitivein manyrespects,yet theconativehasbeenarguedto bea kind of antipassiveconstruction,attributedby somelinguiststo NP-movementin thesyntax,by othersto theoperationof a lexical rule atthelevelof argumentstructure.

Finally, thereis a historicalaspectto the problem,which hasbeenthe subjectofmuchdebateamongFinno-Ugrists.Partitivecaseoriginatedasapurelyadverbiallocalcasewith the meaning“from”. It developedfirst its NP-relatedfunctions,in severalstages.Theaspectualfunctionwasthelast to emerge.How is this stepwiseextensionof thepartitive’susesrelatedto its shift from asemanticcaseto a structuralcase?

In this paperI put forwardananalysisof theFinnishpartitive which shedssomelight oneachof theseissues.Thefunctionof partitivecaseis to licenseunboundednessat the VP level. This unifies the aspectualandNP-relatedfunctionsof the partitiveat the level of theVP, andappropriatelygeneralizesto theconativeconstructions.Byseparatingtheconfigurationalassignmentof structuralcaseat S-structurefrom its se-manticconditioning,we preservethe spirit of the distinctionbetweenstructuralandsemanticcase.Theorigin of thestructuralpartitivecanthenbeseenasagrammatical-izationprocessof theclassictype.

2 The semanticsof partitive case

The Finnishpartitive hastwo functions,which canbe termedASPECTUAL andNP-RELATED. Theaspectualfunction,whichFinnishlinguistshavecharacterizedin termsof resultativity(Itkonen1976,HakulinenandKarlsson1979:183,Larjavaara1991)orboundedness(Ikola 1961,Heinamaki 1984,Leino1991),is illustratedin thesentencesof (1) with the verb meaning“to shoot”. It belongsto a classof verbswhich assigncaseto theirobjectsin two differentways,with adifferentaspectualinterpretation.3

(1) a. Ammu-i-nshoot-Pst-1Sg

karhu-abear-Part

//kah-tatwo-Part

karhu-abear-Part

//karhu-j-abear-Pl-Part

‘I shotat the(a)bear/ at (the)two bears/ at (the)bears’

3The relevantobjectcasemarkingsareglossedin boldface. Thus,in (1a) andin (4b), in kaksikarhua‘two bears’,thecaseof theobjectis accusative,markedon theheadkaksi, which in turn assignspartitive tokarhuainternally to theobject.

2

Page 3: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

b. Ammu-i-nshoot–Pst-1Sg

karhu-nbear-Acc

//kaksitwo-Acc

karhu-abear-Part

//karhu-tbear-PlAcc

‘I shotthe(a)bear/ two bears/ thebears’

In theaspectuallyirresultative,unboundedversion(1a),theverbhasapartitiveobject,anddenotesanactivity (in Vendler’ssense),“to shootat”. In theaspectuallyresultative,boundedversion(1b), it hasanaccusativeobject,anddenotesanaccomplishment,“toshootdead”.4 In contrast,the unboundedversion(1a) is non-committalas to whathappenedto thebear,andits useconversationallyimplicatesthattheshot(s)missed.

In addition to verbslike “shoot”, Finnish hasverbswhich are intrinsically un-bounded,suchas“love”, “seek”,and“touch”, andverbswhichareintrinsicallybounded,suchas“kill”, “get”, “find”. Themajority of Finnishverbs,in fact, belongto oneofthesetwo classes.

To illustrate the NP-relatedfunction of partitive case,consideran intrinsicallyboundedverbsuchassaada“get”. Theobjectsof suchverbsarepartitivewhentheyarequantitativelyindeterminate(in particular,whentheyareindefinitebarepluralsormassnouns),otherwiseaccusative:

(2) a. saa-nget-1Sg

#karhu-abear-Part

//#kah-tatwo-Part

karhu-abear-Part

//karhu-j-abear-Pl-Part

‘I’ll getthe(a)bear/ (the)two bears/ bears’

b. saa-nget-1Sg

karhu-nbear-Acc

//kaksitwo-Acc

karhu-abear-Part

//karhu-tbear-PlAcc

‘I’ll getthe(a)bear/ two bears/ thebears’

Herethepartitivein effectmarkstheindefinitenessof barepluralor massnounobjects(amorepreciseformulationwill begivenlater).

Aspectuallyunboundedverbs,on theotherhand,assignpartitivecaseto ALL theirobjects.With suchaverb,apartitivebarepluralobjectis ambiguousbetweenadefinitereadingandanindefinitereading:

(3) a. etsi-nseek-1Sg

karhu-abear-Part

//kah-tatwo-Part

karhu-abear-Part

//karhu-j-abear-Pl-Part

‘I’m looking for the(a)bear/ (the)two bears/ (the)bears’

b. etsi-nseek-1Sg

#karhu-nbear-Acc

//#kaksitwo-Acc

karhu-abear-Part

//#karhu-tbear-PlAcc

‘I’m looking for the(a)bear/ two bears/ thebears’

Forexample,etsinkarhujacanmean“I lookedfor thebears”(aspectualpartitivity), or“I lookedfor bears”(bothaspectualpartitivity andNP-relatedpartitivity).5

4Barring specialcontextualinformation, (1b) is understoodto meanthat I killed the bear, its Englishcounterpartsimply that my bullet hit the mark, with possiblybut not necessarilyfatal results. Contextualinformationcanyield theEnglish-typeinterpretationin Finnish(Heinamaki 1984),andit seemsthat it canalsoyield theFinnish-typeinterpretationin English.

5But in theresultativemeaning,etsia cantakeaccusativeobjects;thedictionaryNykysuomenSanakirjacitestheexample(presumablyfrom a mathproblem)Etsi luvunalkutekijat (Acc.pl.) “Determinetheprimefactorsof thenumber”.

3

Page 4: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

The propertyof verbssuchasampua“shoot, shootat” is that they shareboth ofthesepatterns.With sucha verb,a partitivebarepluralobjectthereforeyieldsa three-way ambiguity: ammuinkarhuja (see(1b)) canmean“I shotat thebears”(aspectualpartitivity), “I shotbears”(NP-relatedpartitivity), or “I shotatbears”(both).

In theexamplescitedso far, boundednesscoincideswith resultativity. Onemightbe led to the conclusionthat boundedpredicatesaresimply thosethat denotean ac-complishmentor achievement,andunboundedpredicatesarethosethatdenotestatesandactivities(processes).A closerlook showsthatresultativityis not thedecisivecri-terion. A classof boundedirresultativeverbs,suchasomistaa“own”, nahda “see”,assigncaselike resultativeverbs:6

(4) a. omista-nown-1Sg

#karhu-abear-Part

//#kah-tatwo-Part

karhu-abear-Part

//karhu-j-abear-Pl-Part

‘I own the(a)bear/ (the)two bears/ bears’

b. omista-nown-1Sg

karhu-nbear-Acc

//kaksitwo-Acc

karhu-abear-Part

//karhu-tbear-PlAcc

‘I own the(a)bear/ two bears/ thebears’

Eventhough“own” isnon-resultativelike “seek”,it assignscaselike achievement/accomplishmentpredicatessuchas“get”.

Thefollowing diagnosticis helpful for building anintuition aboutthecategoryofboundednesswhich determinesthecasemarkingof theobjectin Finnish.A predicateis intrinsically unboundedif it canbemodifiedby degreeadverbssuchas(some)more,a lot, verymuch,a bit, somewhatless,considerably, slightly, referringto theextentof asingleeventuality. Whatis relevantis thegradabilityof theevent:boundedpredicates,whethertelic or atelic, admit of no degree. However,boundedpredicatescan stillreceiveanunboundedinterpretationasa resultof a durative/iterativereadinginducedby adverbsor othermeans.Suchreadingscanalsoinducepartitivecase(e.g.reading(3) of (11b)below, andsection6).

(5) Unboundedverbalpredicates:

a. Thesportsmanshotat abearsomemore.

b. I lookedfor thekeya lot.

c. Mary wantedthebookverymuch.

d. Thecustomertouchedthevasea bit.

e. Johnmodifiedthepasswordradically.

f. How muchdid youstudythetheorem?

g. Mary lovedBill up to apoint.

h. Fredusedthebooksomewhat.6Thefisrt versionin (4a)(like (2a)saankarhua) is OK with ‘bear’ understoodasa massnoun,referring

perhapsto a quantity of bearmeat, viz. ‘I own bear’. Seesection6 on the circumstancesunderwhichboundednesscanbecoerced.

4

Page 5: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

i. I expectedthispresentlessthanAlice did.

j. Theboxprotectsthenecklaceconsiderably.

Contrasttheverbalpredicatesin (6), which arebounded(abstractingawayfrom tem-poralunboundedness).7

(6) Boundedverbalpredicates:

a. #Thesportsmankilled a bearsomemore.

b. #I foundthekeya lot.

c. #Maryownedthebookverymuch.

d. #Thecustomerboughtthevasea bit.

e. #Johnrecalledthepasswordradically.

f. #Howmuchdid youprovethetheorem?

g. #MarymarriedBill up to a point.

h. #Fredfinishedthebooksomewhat.

i. #I got thispresentlessthanthanAlice did.

j. #Theboxcontainsthenecklaceconsiderably.

Thesamediagnosticalsopicksout theclassof unboundedquantitativeindetermi-nateNPsthatgetNP-relatedpartitivecasein Finnish:

(7) a. UnboundedNP predicates:A lot of bears,a lot of coffee.

b. BoundedNP predicates:#A lot of bear,#alot of thebear,#alot of a bear,#alot of two bears,#alot of manybears.

TheNPcontrastatstakedoesnotcorrespondexactlyto definitenessor to anyotherfamiliar determinerfeature.Formally indefinitebareplural or massnounsdo not al-waysget assignedpartitive casewith verbslike “get” or “seek”. Theydo so only ifthey havea quantitativelyindeterminatedenotation. The examplesin (8) illustratehow evenindefinitebarepluralsandmassnounsgetaccusativecaseif theydenoteaconventionallydelimitedset(of knownor unknowncardinality).

(8) a. Anu-llaAnu-Adess

onbe-3Sg

loistava-tbrilliant-PlAcc

oppilaa-tstudent-PlAcc

‘Anu hasbrilliant students’

b. Anu-llaAnu-Adess

onbe-3Sg

loistav-i-abrilliant-PlPart

oppila-i-tastudent-PlPart

‘Anu has(some)brilliant students’

c. Aki-llaAki-Adess

onhave-3Sg

iso-tbig-PlAcc

silma-teyes-PlAcc

//viikse-tmustache-PlAcc

‘Aki hasbig eyes/ a mustache’

7Theimaginativereaderwill find unboundedconstrualsof someof theseverbalpredicates.To just thatextent,theyshouldalsoallow degreeadverbsin English,andpartitiveobjectsin Finnish.

5

Page 6: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

d. Aki-llaAki-Adess

onhave-3Sg

iso-j-abig-PlPart

silm-i-aeyes-PlPart

//viiksi-amustache-PlPart

‘Aki hasbig eyes/ mustachesin hispossession’

e. Vauva-llaBaby-Adess

onhave-3Sg

pitka-tlong-PlAcc

hiukse-thair-PlAcc

‘The/ababy’shair is long’

f. Vauva-llaBaby-Adess

onhave-3Sg

pitk-i-along-PlPart

hiuks-i-ahair-PlPart

‘The/ababyhas(some)longstrandsof hair’ (on its head,in its hand,etc.)

(8a)meansthatall of Anu’sstudentsarebrilliant, andimplicatesthateveryonein somerelevantcomparisonsethasstudents.(8b) is indeterminatein boththeserespects.8 In[8c], theuseof accusativecasein effectimpliesinalienablepossession:theeyesmustbeAki’ sown two eyesandthemustachehisownmustache(thelattera pluraletantumin Finnish).9 In contrast,[8d] suggestsanindeterminatenumberof alienablypossessedobjects,suchasglasseyesor anatomicalsamplesin a vat, falsemustaches(of whichtheremustnow beseveral),etc. (8e)refersonly to thetotality of thebaby’s own hair,(8f) couldbeaboutpartof thebaby’s own hair, or aboutan indeterminatenumberofloosestrandsit hasin its possession.

Conversely, a singularor definiteNP getsthe NP-relatedpartitive if it is generic.In (9), ‘this rose’is partitivebecauseit means“rosesof thisparticularkind”:

(9) Puutarhurigardener

istutt-iplant-Past3Sg

kaikkialleeverywhere

tatathis-Part

ruusu-a.rose-Part

‘The gardenerplantedthis roseeverywhere.’

Summarizing,we cansaythatanobjectis partitiveeitherif it governedby oneofa classof unboundedverbalpredicates(the aspectualcondition),or if it is quantita-tively indeterminate(theNP-relatedcondition). TherehasbeenmuchdisputeamongFinnish linguistsaboutthe questionwhetherit is possibleto unify theseconditions.Someclaim thattheaspectualandNP-relatedfunctionsof thepartitivearefundamen-tally distinct(Itkonen1976,Larjavaara1991).Othersarguethatunboundednessis thecommondenominatorof both(Heinamaki 1984,Leino1991).Thereareprobablytworeasonswhy thelatter,unifiedanalysishasnotbeenmoregenerallyaccepted:thelackof aprecisedefinitionof thecentralconceptof (un)boundedness,andthefact thatthereare languagesin which the partitive (or anotherobliquecase)haseither just the as-pectualfunctionor just the NP-relatedfunction. In this paperI attemptto overcomeboththeseobstacles,by providinga definitionof (un)boundednessthatcoversthefullrangeof accusative/partitivecontrastsin Finnish,andby showinghowthedifferenceintherole this featureplaysin Finnishandin theotherlanguagescanbesystematicallycharacterized.

8Thecontrastis approximatelythatof “Her studentsarebrilliant” vs. “Shehassomebrilliant students”.AnotherpossibleEnglishrenderingwould be“Shehasabrilliant groupof students”vs. “Shehasagroupofbrilliant students.”

9If we imaginethatAki hasmorethanonehead,then[8c] canof courserefercollectively to all thepairsof eyesandto all themustacheswhich hemayhaveon thoseheads.

6

Page 7: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

It hasbeenknownfor a long time that thepartitivevs. accusativecasecontrastinFinnishsharessomeof its functionswith the aspectcontrastin RussianandsomeoftheotherSlaviclanguages.In fact, theconceptof boundedness(Russianpredel’nost’)is standardin Slavic aspectology. This parallelismhasbeenemphasizednotablybyDahl andKarlsson(1976)andby Dahl (1985). Theypoint out that if eitherthe verbis atelic (doesnot denotea completedevent),or theobjectis anindefinitebareplural,then Russianin generalrequiresimperfectiveaspect,and Finnish requirespartitivecase(see(10a)).Thus,in (10a)perfectiveaspect(in Russian)andaccusativecase(inFinnish)requireboth that the verb is telic, andthat the object is plural anddefinite.The samesentenceswith imperfectiveaspectand partitive case,respectively, are 3waysambiguous(see(10b)):

(10) a. OnHe

napisa-l(Perf.)write-PstM3Sg

pis’m-aletter-PlAcc

(Russian)

HanHe/she

kirjoitt-iwrite-PstM3Sg

kirjee-tletter-PlAcc

(Finnish)

‘He wrotetheletters’(. . .andleft) (telic V, def.NP)

b. OnHe

pisa-l(Imperf.)write-PstM3Sg

pis’m-aletter-PlAcc

(Russian)

HanHe/she

kirjoitt-iwrite-PstM3Sg

kirje-i-taletter-Pl-Part

(Finnish)

(1) ‘He wrote(some)letters’(. . .andleft) (telic V, indef.NP)(2) ‘He waswriting letters(. . .whenI came) (atelicV, indef.NP)(3) ‘He waswriting theletters(. . .whenI came) (atelicV, def.NP)

The contextsappendedin parenthesesto the translationsshowonecharacteristicuseof theaspectualopposition,thatof markingprogressiveversuscompletedevents.However,the oppositionmarkedby objectcasein Finnishandby aspectin Russianhasa muchwider rangeof interpretations,which againareoften parallel in the twolanguages.Considertheexample“He openedthewindow” in (11). Theatelic imper-fective/partitiveversionin (11b)canhave,in additionto its progressive-typemeaning“He wasopeningthewindow(. . .asJohnwalkedin)”, severalothersensesof temporaldelimitationor incompleteness:“He openedthewindowfor awhile” (it remainedopenfor a limited time only), or “He openedthewindowa bit” (it wasnot fully opened),or“He keptopeningthewindow” (iterative).10

(11) a. Russian:OnHe

otkry-l (Perf.)open-PstM3Sg

oknowindow-Acc

Finnish:HanHe

avas-iopen-Past3Sg

ikkuna-nwindow-Acc

10Not all thesesecondaryusesof the imperfectivein Russianhavecounterpartsin the Finnishpartitive,andvice versa;in section6 below I arguethat the verbalor nominalstatusof the categorylargely predictswhich onesoccur.

7

Page 8: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

‘He openedthewindow’ (in two seconds)

b. Russian:OnHe

otkry-va-l (Imperf. )open-Imperf-M3Sg

oknowindow-Acc

Finnish:HanHe

avas-iopen-Past3Sg

ikkuna-awindow-Part

(1) ‘He wasopeningthewindow’ (asJohnentered)(2) ‘He openedthewindow’ (for a while)(3) ‘He openedthewindow’ (partly)(4) ‘He openedthewindow’ (againandagain)

Notethat in English“He openedthewindow somemore” allowseachof thereadingscorrespondingto (2), (3), and(4).

What ties theseaspectualfunctionsof partitive caseand imperfectiveaspectto-gether?And how do theyjointly relateto theNP-relatedfunction?Beforeattemptingto answerthesequestionslet us take a look at two recenttheoriesof partitive casemarking.

3 DeHoop: partitive asweak structural case

In an influential thesis,de Hoop (1992)proposedto resolvethe puzzleof the statusof the partitive by enrichingthe typologyof structuralcase.In additionto structuralcaseof the traditionally recognizedtype, suchasaccusativecase,which shedubbedSTRONG structuralcase,de Hoop proposeda categoryof WEAK structuralcase,ofwhich theFinnishpartitiveis aninstantiation.Weakstructuralcasesaredefaultcases,configurationallylicensedat D-structure.But (unlikestrongstructuralcases),theyarenotconfigurationallylicensedby all transitiveverbsbutonly by asubclassof them.

Syntactically, weakstructuralcasein deHoop’stheoryis configurationallylicensedatD-structure.Its specialsyntacticpropertyis thatit canonly belicensedin theirbasicD-structureposition.In consequence,NPsbearingweakstructuralcasedonotundergoscrambling(which de Hoopassumesto be A-movement).Semantically, weakstruc-tural casehasthe propertythat it inducesanexistentialreadingon the NP that bearsit. Accordingto deHoop,NPsthatbearweakstructuralcasearepredicatemodifiers,which areassumedto combinesemanticallywith the verbalpredicate,restrictingitsdenotationin the mannerof adverbialmodifiers. NPs that bearstrongcase,on theotherhand,arearguments,interpretedasgeneralizedquantifiers.

De Hoop’s accountconstitutesa pioneeringattemptto connectthe syntacticandsemanticpropertiesof partitivecasein a principledway. However,it doesnot go farenough.On the semanticside,it positsno intrinsic connectionbetweenverbclassesandNP properties,therebyleavingtherelationbetweencaseandaspectunexplained.And on the syntacticside, it glossesover the fundamentaldifferencesbetweenthe

8

Page 9: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

Finnish partitive caseand the other putativeinstancesof “weak” case,suchas theTurkish bareaccusative,or the Inuit absolutive. Thesehaveto do with specificity— not quantitativeindeterminacy— andunlike the Finnishpartitive havethe samedistributionin singularandpluralNPs.Also, while (accordingto deHoop)weakcasein thoselanguagesblocksscrambling,in Finnishpartitiveobjectscanscrambleexactlylike accusativeobjects.For example,in (12) theobjectkarhuja “(the) bears”andtheadverbialsusein“often”, Lapissa“in Lapland”, andhaulikolla “with the/ashotgun”canbein anyof the24possiblemutualorders,regardlessof definitenessandtelicity:

(12) MattiMatti

ampu-ushoot-3Sg

useinoften

Lapi-ssaLapland-Iness

hauliko-llashotgun-Adess

karhu-j-abear-Pl-Part

‘Matti oftenshoots(at) (the)bearswith ashotgunin Lapland.’

Thus,althoughthe Finnishpartitive is supposedto be the prototypicalweakcase,itactuallydoesnot conformto theallegedsyndromeof weakcasepropertiesidentifiedby deHoop.

Otherthanthefalsepredictionaboutscrambling,it is notclearwhatconsequencesdeHoop’stheoryhasfor thesyntaxof partitivecasein Finnish.Eventhebasicdistribu-tion of thepartitiveseemsto bea problemfor it. As explainedin section1, partitiveisassignedby anytransitiveverbto quantitativelyindeterminateobjects(theNP-relatedpartitive),andby a propersubclassof transitiveverbsto anyobject(theaspectualpar-titive). De Hoop proposesto accountfor the formerby her principle (p. 90 ff.) thatobjectsbearingstrongandweakcasehavestrongandweakreadings,respectively(i.e.referentialvs. existentialreadings).But evenindefiniteNPswith accusativecasecanhaveexistentialreadings,so this cannotbe the relevantconditionfor NP-relatedpar-titive case. To accountfor the aspectualfunctionof the partitive,de Hoop proposesthat “a partitiveobjectcanbe regardedprimarily aspartof a predicateratherthanasanindependentargument”(p. 98), andthatobjectsof atelicverbsarereally predicatemodifiers,licensedby weakcaseat D-structure(p. 111). Shortof anaccountof howpredicatemodifiers,or NPswith weakcase,comeby their two interpretations(NP-relatedandaspectual),this is hardlymorethana restatementof thegeneralizationtobeexplained.

In anycase,theideathatpartitiveobjectsarepredicatemodifiersfalls afoulof thefact that theycanbe conjoinedwith accusativeobjects. In suchstructuresas(13), itis hardto seehow the object in the secondconjunct,the partitive ‘books’, could beanalyzedasa predicatemodifierwhich restrictsthedenotationof theverbalpredicate‘buy’, ratherthan as an argumentof it, parallel to the accusativeobjectof the firstconjunct,theaccusative‘newspaper’.

(13) Ost-i-nbuy-Pst-1Sg

lehde-nnewspaper-SgAcc

jaand

kirjo-j-a.book-Pl-Part

‘I boughtthe/anewspaperandbooks’

Thestatusof partitiveobjectsasargumentsis confirmedby animportantgeneral-izationof FinnishsyntaxknownasSiro’s Law, which statesthat a simpleclausecan

9

Page 10: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

haveat mostoneobject.11 This generalizationholdsregardlessof whatthecaseof theobjectis. However,a clausecanhavean object(whetheraccusativeor partitive) to-getherwith apredicatemodifier,in factwith anynumberof predicatemodifiers.Thus,a partitive object is structurallyparallel to an accusativeobjectand not structurallyparallelto apredicatemodifier.

Moreover,partitiveobjects,like accusativeobjects,cannotbefreelyomitted,whereaspredicatemodifierscan.

(14) a. MattiMatti

koskett-itouch-Pst3Sg

kirja-abook-Part

‘Matti touchedthe/abook.’

b. *MattiMatti

koskett-i.touch-Pst3Sg

‘Matti touched.’

Partitiveobjects(like accusativeobjects)canbesubjectsof predication,predicatemodifierscan’t.

(15) a. Kayta-nuse-1Sg

sohva-asofa-SgPart

sanky-na.bed-Ess

‘I usethesofaasabed.’

b. *Nuku-nsleep-1Sg

sohva-llasofa-Adess

sanky-na.bed-Ess

‘I sleepon thesofaasa bed’.

Partitiveobjectsantecedeboundanaphorsunderthesameconditionsasaccusativeobjects.Predicatemodifiersneverdo.

(16) a. Ve-i-nbring-Pst-1Sg

vieraa-nguest-SgAcci

huonee-see-nsa.room-Illat-3Sgi

‘I broughttheguestinto his/herroom.’

b. Ve-i-nbring-Pst-1Sg

viera-i-taguest-Pl-Parti

huone-i-sii-nsa.room-Pl-Illat-3Pli

‘I broughtguestsinto their rooms.’

c. *Roiskut-i-nsplash-Pst-1Sg

kylpyhuonee-ssabathroom-Inessi

seina-lle-enwall-SgAll-3Sgi

‘I splashedin thebathroomontoits walls.’

The last two grammaticalfactsconstituteevidencethat the Finnishpartitive is astructuralcase. de Hoop indeedrecognizesthe structuralstatusof the partitive onthebasisof theevidenceadducedby Vainikka1993.But thefact thatthepartitiveis astructuralcasewouldseemto undermineherclaimthatthepartitiveis apredicatemod-ifier. Structurally, partitiveobjectsarecompletelyanalogousto accusativeobjects,anddifferentfrom adverbialmodifiersor obliqueobjects.Thedistinctionbetween“weak”

11More generally,aVP canhaveonly onedirectargument(seesection7).

10

Page 11: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

and“strong” structuralcase,andtheassignmentof NPsbearing“weak” structuralcaseto thecategoryof predicatemodifiers,might beexpectedto havesomesyntacticcon-sequences.But asfar asI cantell, it hasnone.

I concludethatdeHoop’stheoryof casedoesnotaccountfor thedistributionor in-terpretationof partitivecasein Finnish.Theideathatthepartitiveis a“weak” structuralcasedoesnot shedanylight on its grammar. It hasneitherthesemanticpropertiesex-pectedonthatanalysis,noranysyntacticpropertiesthatwouldshowthatit is anythingmoreor lessthana directobject.

4 Krifka: a unified semanticsfor partitive case

A differentperspectiveon the Finnishpartitive is openedup by Krifka 1992. Whilehe doesnot addressthe syntacticaspectsof the problem,he formulates,for the firsttime, an explicit semanticanalysiswhich unifies the meaningsof partitive caseandimperfectiveaspect(his “progressive”),or at leastthe meaningsof someimportantusesof them.

Theessenceof Krifka’s proposalis thatpartitivecaseandimperfectiveaspectarepredicatemodifiersthatmean“part of”:

(17) 1. PART = λPλx′∃x[P (x) ∧ x′ v x]2. PROG= λPλe′∃e[P (e) ∧ e′ v e]

Thus,Part(Pred)andProg(Pred)denotethesetof entitiesthatarepartsof entitiesthathavethepropertyPred.

Krifka showsthat, at the VP level, partitive objectmarking is equivalentto im-perfectiveV markingprovidedthat certainadditionalconditionshold. First, V mustdenoteapredicatewith DIVISIVE REFERENCE:12

(18) P hasDIVISIVE REFERENCEiff ∀x∀y[P (x) ∧ y v x→ P (y)]

Thatis,Pis closedunderthesubpartrelation.Forexample,write hasdivisivereferencebecauseanypartof aneventof writing is alsoaneventof writing.13

Secondly, thethematicrelationR betweenanobjectin thedenotationof thenomi-nalpredicateandaneventin thedenotationof V musthavethepropertiesin (19). Thisconjunctionof propertiescharacterizesverbsof creation(suchaswrite) andverbsofconsumptionanddestruction(suchaseat).

(19) a. UNIQUENESSOF OBJECTS: ∀e, x, x′[R(e, x) ∧R(e, x′)→ x = x′](therecanbeno two distinctobjectswhichbearR to thesameevent)

12Nominal predicatesaswell asverbscanhavedivisive referenceor not: for example,gold hasdivisivereference(for anypartof gold is alsogold), but thegold or a bookdoesnot havedivisive reference(for partof thegold is not thegold, andpartof abookis not abook).

13We setasideherethe so-calledminimal partsproblem,that an eventcannotin fact be subdividedadinfinitum.

11

Page 12: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

b. UNIQUENESSOF EVENTS: ∀e, e′, x[R(e, x) ∧R(e′, x)→ e = e′](therecanbeno two distincteventswhichbearR to thesameobject)

c. MAPPING TO OBJECTS: ∀e, e′, x[R(e, x) ∧ e′ v e → ∃x′[x′ v x ∧R(e′, x′)]](if aneventbearsR to anobject,anysubpartof theeventbearsR to somesubpartof theobject)

d. MAPPING TO EVENTS: ∀e, x, x′[R(e, x) ∧ x′ v x → ∃e′[e′ v e ∧R(e′, x′)]](if aneventbearsR to anobject,anysubpartof theobjectbearsR to somesubpartof theevent)

In orderto get the partitive to yield the progressivereading,Krifka 1992:48sup-plementsthe two mappingproperties[19c,d]with anadditionalassumptionwhich hestatesasfollows:

(20) If aneventbearsR to anobject,thenthewholeobjectis eventuallysubjectedtotheevent.

This is in factaproblematicassumption,asKrifka himselfpointsout,since“Johnwaswriting a letter” (or its counterpartin Finnish) in no way implies that Johnactuallyfinishedwriting thewholeletter.

An exampleof a verb that hasthe propertiesin (19) is write, in the “authorial”sense.It satisfiestheuniquenessof objectsproperty[19a]: writing a letterandwritingthefirst line of theletteraredifferentevents.It satisfiestheuniquenessof eventsprop-erty [19b], providedwe assumethat you can’t authorthe sameletter twice (whereasyou canclearly “write” thesameletter twice in othersenses,for example,if you aresendingthe identicalmessageto two people,or if you area professionalcopyist).14

And it clearlysatisfiesthetwo mappingproperties[19c,d].Let usfurthermoreassumethatit alsosatisfiestheproperty[20] (settingasidetheabovementionedobjection).ByKrifka’s theoremit thenfollows thataneventof writing partof anobjectis partof aneventof writing the object,andconversely. Theequivalencein (10) is thusa conse-quenceof Krifka’s theory, at leastfor theverbwrite.

But asKrifka pointsout, his accountdoesnot generalizeto otherclassesof verbs(suchas(1), (4), (21)), which lack oneor moreof thepropertiesin (19). Thus,verbslike proveandbuy do not havedivisive reference:part of a provingor buyingeventis not necessarilyitself a provingor buyingevent. Kiss, touch,andshootat lack theuniquenessof objectsproperty:kissingMary andkissingMary’s lips canbethesameevent. And all theseverbs(aswell as suchverbsas want, love, read, andwrite inmanyof its senses)do not havethe uniquenessof eventsproperty:you cando these

14In truth, it is evenpossibleto author thesameletter twice, at leastbecausetwo textsthatyou composecouldaccidentallyturn out identical.Thustheuniquenesspropertiesareproblematic.However,this maybeunimportantbecausetheonly role theyplay in Krifka’s proof (1992:48)is to insurethat thesubpartrelationin (19c) is not trivially satisfiedby thecasex′ = x. But presumablytherequiredproperpart relationcouldbeobtainedby weakermeans.

12

Page 13: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

thingstwice to the sameobject. Nevertheless,the equivalencebetweenpartitive andimperfectiveis valid for suchverbsaswell. We havealreadyseenit for “shoot” in (1).It holdsfor “write”, not just in theauthorialsense,but in all senses,asdocumentedin[10]. In general,partitivecasecanbeusedin Finnishfor objectsof numerousverbs,suchas“buy”, “eat”, “read”, andit mustbeusedfor others,suchas“kiss”, which failto meetoneor moreof the requisiteconditionsin [18]-[19], asthe examplesin (21)attest:

(21) a. MattiMatti-SgNom

ost-ibuy-Pst3Sg

maito-amilk-SgPart

(tunni-n)(hour-Acc)

‘Matti boughtmilk (for anhour)’

b. MattiMatti-SgNom

ost-ibuy-Pst3Sg

maido-nmilk-SgAcc

(tunni-ssa)(hour-Iness)

‘Matti boughtthemilk (in anhour)’

c. MattiMatti-SgNom

luk-iread-Pst3Sg

kirjo-j-abook-Pl-Part

(tunni-n)(hour-Acc)

‘Matti readbooks(for anhour)’

d. MattiMatti-SgNom

luk-iread-Pst3Sg

kirja-tbook-Pl-Part

(tunni-ssa)(hour-Iness)

‘Matti readthebooks(in anhour)’

e. AnuAnu

suutel-ikiss-Pst3Sg

Esa-aEsa-Part

//#Esa-n#Esa-Acc

(tunni-n(hour-Acc

//#tunni-ssa)hour-Iness)

‘Anu kissedEsa(for anhour/ #in anhour)’

Krifka (1992,48) suggeststhat partitiveslike thosein [21] areanalogicalexten-sionsof thecasesin (10). This couldmeanseveraldifferentthings,dependingonhowweunderstandtheambiguousterm“analogy”.WhatKrifka probablymeantis thattheyareidiosyncraticusageswhich havearisenhistoricallyby analogyto thesemanticallymotivatedcorecasesin [10]. Anotherview, moreconsonantwith theideathatanalogyis structuraloptimization,includingin particulartheprojectionof a grammaticalregu-larity to newcases,would bethat the innovationsaresystematicusageswithin a newgrammarof Finnishthathasarisenby ageneralizationin therulesof caseassignment.On this view, thecasesin [21] andthecasesin (10) areequallyregularusages,whichwould meanthatKrifka’s analysisis not correctfor the currentstateof the language(althoughit might havebeenfor an earlierstage).I believethe Finnishsystemis an“analogical” innovationonly in this latter sense,and will presentsomeevidenceinfavorof thatpositionin section8.

Krifka’s analysisrepresentsanidealizationwhich missessomesystematicaspectsof Finnishpartitivecaseassignment.Neverthelessit is quite illuminating,andindeedcomesremarkablycloseto characterizingthe partitive usageof anotherFinno-Ugriclanguage,whichrepresentsanancestralstagein theevolutionof partitivecase.In whatfollows I will first presentanalternativeaccountof Finnish,andthen(section8) sketchout thepathandcausesof its evolutionfrom theoriginalsystem.

13

Page 14: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

5 Boundedness

We canunderstandhow thenominalcategoryof partitive casecanhaveanaspectualfunction,andhowtheverbalcategoryof aspectcanhaveanNP-relatedfunction,if wethink of thembothaslicensedby the unboundednessof the VP predicate.This ideais not new. In theFinnishtradition,Leino 1991hasemphasizedthatboundednessis apropertyof situationsandnot just of individual predicatesin isolation. Verkuyl 1972arguesexplicitly thatpropertiesof thedirectobjectinfluencetheaspectof the predi-cate,andthattheoppositionbetweenimperfectiveandperfectiveaspectis notamatterof the lexical categoryitself. Instead,aspectis constructedby thecombinationof theverb and its object (the VP) andsubsequentlyof the VP and its subject. Verkuyl’s(1989)categories“terminative”and“durative” areverysimilar to “bounded”and“un-bounded”usedhere.

As a first approximation,we can say that if a VP denotesan unboundedevent,then its object is partitive in Finnish,and its verb is imperfectivein Russian,and ifit denotesa boundedevent,they areaccusativeandperfective,respectively. In bothlanguages,theVP canhavethis semanticpropertyeitherin virtue of its headV or invirtueof anominaldependent.But themorphologicalmarkingassociatedwith thisse-manticpropertyis uniformly nominalin Finnish,anduniformly verbalin Russian.Forexample,by thecriterionof boundednessmentionedin thefirst section,thatonly un-boundedpredicatesaremodifiableby adverbsof degreesuchasa lot, theVP predicatesin [22] areunbounded,andthe VP predicatesin [23] arebounded.In (22a),the un-boundednesscomesfrom theverbalpredicatehate(inducingthe“aspectualpartitive”in Finnish),andin (22b),theunboundednesscomesfrom theNPpredicatebombs, withquantitativelyindeterminatereference(inducingthe“NP-related”partitivein Finnish).

(22) a. Theyhatedthebombsa lot.

b. Theydroppedbombsa lot.

In (23),boththeverbalpredicatenor theNP predicatearebounded,andthepartitive

(23) a. #Theydroppedthebombsa lot.15

b. #Theydroppedmanybombsa lot.

The majority of telic verbs,suchas thosein (24), are bounded,and assignac-cusativecaseto their objects(unless,of course,theseobjectsarequantitativelyinde-terminate,in whichcasetheygettheNP-relatedpartitive):

(24) ostaa‘buy’, ottaa‘take’, pudottaa‘drop’, suorittaa‘carryout’, kadottaa,menettaa,hukata‘lose (possession)’,havita ‘lose (game,fight)’, loytaa ‘find’, hyvaksya‘accept’, panna,asettaa‘put’, tappaa ‘kill’, antaa, lahjoittaa ‘give’, kaataa‘fell’, mainita‘mention’,siepata‘catch’,omaksua‘appropriate’,ripustaa‘hang’,istuttaa‘plant’.

15This is fineonaniterativereading,but recall from section2 thatpurelytemporalunboundednessgener-ally doesnot sufficefor thepartitive.

14

Page 15: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

andthemajorityof atelicverbs,suchasthosein (25),areunboundedandassignparti-tive caseto all theirobjectsregardlessof thelatter’s type:

(25) a. Psychologicalstates,attitudes:halveksia‘despise’,ihailla ‘admire’, ikavoida‘yearn for’, harrastaa ‘be interestedin (as a hobby)’, huvittaa ‘amuse’,ikavystyttaa ‘bore’, inhota ‘feel revulsiontowards’,kadehtia‘envy’, kart-taa ‘avoid’, kehua,ylistaa ‘praise’, kiinnostaa‘interest’, kiittaa ‘thank’,kunnioittaa‘honor’, moittia ‘blame, reprimand’,onnitella ‘congratulate’,pelata ‘fear’, rakastaa‘love’, sietaa ‘tolerate’,siunata‘bless’,toivoa‘hopefor’, valittaa ‘complainabout’,vihata ‘hate’, vasyttaa ‘tire’.

b. Variousintensionalverbs:koettaa,yrittaa ‘try’, pyytaa ‘ask for’, merkita,tarkoittaa‘mean’,ajatella,pohtia‘think about’,harkita ‘consider’,matkia‘imitate’, paeta‘flee’, kysya ‘ask for’.

c. Continuousmotionor contact:heiluttaa ‘swing backandforth’, ravistaa‘shake’, keinuttaa‘rock’, nyokyttaa ‘nod’, suudella‘kiss’, hyvaill a ‘ca-ress’,koskettaa‘touch’, nussia‘fuck’, hieroa ‘massage’.

Verbs which take both partitive and accusativeobjectsdependingon the VP’sboundednessincludeverbsof creationanddestruction(suchasthosein (26a)),otherverbsdenotingeventswhoseprogressis mappedoutinto thepartsof theobject((26b)),andanumberof verbswith differentlexicalmeaningsdependingonthecaseof theob-ject ((26c)).

(26) a. syoda ‘eat’ (partitive: soi piirakkaa ‘ate pie, someof thepie’, accusative:soi piirakan ‘ate a/thepie’), leikata ‘cut’, kaivaa‘dig’, kirjoittaa ‘write’.

b. lukea ‘read’ (partitive’: ‘read (at leastpart of)’, accusative:‘read up tosomepoint’, usually‘finish reading’),tutkia ‘investigate’,siirtaa ‘move’,sekoittaa‘mix’.

c. lyoda ‘beat’ (partitive: ‘beator hit (at) someone’,accusative:‘beatsome-one at something’),nimittaa ‘name’ (partitive: ‘call (by a name)’, ac-cusative:‘nominate’),muistaa‘remember’(partitive: ‘commemorate’,‘re-membersomeonewith agift or greetingonaspecialoccasion’,accusative:‘recall’).

Thefollowing contrastsaretelling (Itkonen1976:180,Hakulinen& Karlsson1979:225ff. Leino1991,Ch. 8,9,Larjavaara1991):

(27) a. Muotifashion

lyhensishorten-Past3Sg

hameenhelma-ahemline-Part

‘Fashionshortenedthehemline.’ [madeit shorter]

b. MuotiFashion

lyhensishorten-Past3Sg

hameenhelma-nhemline-Acc

[madeit short]

(28) a. Siirsi-nmove-Past1Sg

isoaiti-agrandma-Part

‘I movedgrandma.’ [around,aways]

15

Page 16: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

b. Siirsi-nmove-Past1Sg

isoaidi-ngrandma-Acc

‘I movedgrandma.’ [to anotherplace]

Temporalextent(durationor frequencyof iteration)sufficesto makean intrinsi-cally boundedpredicateunbounded;seereading(4) of example(11),or thefollowingcontrast:

(29) a. MattiMatti

lainas-iborrow-Past3Sg

kello-awatch-Part

‘Matti borroweda watch.’ [temporarily]

b. MattiMatti

lainas-iborrow-Past3Sg

kello-nwatch-Acc

‘Matti borroweda watch.’

To summarize:theverbsin [24] takepartitiveobjectsjustwhentheNPis quantita-tively indeterminate(the‘NP-related’partitive).Theverbsin [25] takepartitiveobjectsregardlessof thenatureof theobject(the‘aspectual’partitive).Theverbsin [26] workin bothwaysdependingonthemeaning,e.g.‘eat (at) thesausage’(partitive),‘eat (up)the sausage’(accusative).Whentelic, the verbsin [26] work like the verbsin [24],suchas ‘kill’ (their object is accusativeunlessit is an indefinitebareplural or massnoun).Whenatelic,theverbsin [26] work like theverbsin [25], suchas‘touch’ (theirobjectis partitiveregardlessof its inherentproperties).

Although telicity (or resultativity)by andlargecorrelateswith boundedness,it isnot exactlythe right semanticcriterion for characterizingtheconditionsunderwhichobjectsareaccusative.Thereis botha classof boundedatelic verbswhoseobjectisaccusative(unlessit is quantitativelyindeterminate),anda classof unboundedtelic(resultative)verbswhoseobjectis partitiveregardlessof theNP’snature.

With verbsof thefirst class,thepartitiveshowsonly its NP-relatedside,in spiteoftheirateliccharacter. Itkonen1976callssuchverbs“quasi-resultative”:

(30) omistaa‘own’, sisaltaa ‘contain’,kasittaa ‘comprise’,muistaa‘remember’,tietaa‘know’ (‘savoir’), tuntea‘know’ (‘connaitre’), ymmartaa ‘understand’(some-thing), myontaa ‘acknowledge”,katsoa ‘regard, consider’,oivaltaa ‘realize’,uskoa‘believe’ (something),andsuchperceptionverbsasnahda ‘see’, kuulla‘hear’, huomata,havaita,keksia ‘notice’.16

(31) a. Omist-i-tOwn-2Sg

namatheseAcc

talo-thouse-PlAcc

vuode-nyear-Acc

(*vuode-ssa).(year-Iness)

‘Youownedthesehousesfor ayear(*in ayear).’

b. Omista-tOwn-2Sg

talo-j-a.house-Pl-Part.

‘Youownhouses.’16Many of theseverbstakepartitive objectsin relateduses,eg.ymmartaa ‘understandsomeone’,uskoa

‘believe someone’katsoa‘look at’, andof courseall of themtakepartitive objectswhenthe object is un-bounded,e.g.laatikkosisaltaa suklaata(Partitive) ‘the box containschocolate’.

16

Page 17: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

c. Nae-nSee-1Sg

hane-t.himAcc

‘I seehim/her.’

d. Nae-nSee-1Sg

han-ta.himPart

‘I’m seeinghim/her,I seeabit of him/her.’

Andconversely, sometelic verbstakepartitiveobjects,irrespectivelyof theobject’sNPlevelproperties.E.g.rangaista”’punish”, denotingwhatwouldappearto beatelicevents17 takepartitiveobjectsjustas“love” and“touch” do,aswouldbeexpectedgiventhattheyoccurfreelywith degreeadverbs:

(32) Rankais-i-tinsult-Past-2Sg

he-i-ta.they-Pl-Part

‘Youpunishedthem.’

Leino 1991:166ff. proposesthegeneralizationthatverbsdenotingstatestakeac-cusativeobjects. This coversthe quasi-resultativesin (30), which includeverbsde-noting relationslike “own”, “contain” andverbsof knowing andperceiving. But itwrongly extendsto verbsof emotion,which takepartitive objects(see(25)). Leinosuggeststhat Finnish treatsemotionsas atelic activities rather than as states. Thiscouldnot bea peculiarityof Finnish,for on thestandardtests(e.g.Dowty 1979,Ch.2) theseverbsbehaveexactlyasdo their Englishcounterparts.18 The distinction ishoweverconsonantwith gradability, in thatonecanhate,admire,andfearsomethingmoreor less,whereasonenormallyeitherowns,contains,knows,or seessomethingornot.19

(33) a. TrumplikesNewYork a lot.

b. FredadmiresMary verymuch.

(34) a. #TrumpownsNew York a lot.

b. #JohnknowsMary verymuch.

To capturethe notion of unboundednessfor verbal and nominal predicates,weusethepropertiesof DIVISIVENESS andCUMULATIVITY , redefinedasin (36a,b),andDIVERSITY:

(35) a. P is DIVISIVE iff ∀x[P (x) ∧ ¬atom(x)→ ∃y[y @ x ∧ P (y)]]

b. P is CUMULATIVE iff ∀x[P (x) ∧ ¬sup(x, P )→ ∃y[x @ y ∧ P (y)]]

c. P is DIVERSE iff ∀x∀y[P (x) ∧ P (y) ∧ x 6= y → ¬x @ y ∧ ¬y @ x]

17It passedthe standardaccomplismentdiagnostics:John punishedthe child in an hour, Johnfinishedpunishingthechild.

18For example,verbslike “hate”, “admire”, “fear” do not felicitously combinewith agentiveadverbialssuchas“carefully”, or embedunderverbslike “force” in Finnishanymorethantheydo in English.

19Of course,onemayown,contain,know,or seelargeror smallerpartsof something,whichsimplymeansthat theseverbscantakeNP-relatedpartitive objects.And in sofar asasthesestatesare matterof degree,theverbsdenotingthemdo allow partitive,cf. (31d).

17

Page 18: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

(36) A predicateP is UNBOUNDED iff it is divisiveandcumulativeandnotdiverse.

In (36a,b)the requirementthat x not be the maximalelement(the supremum)or aminimal (atomic)elementensuresthat,for example,aneventof paintinga housemaybe unbounded(with the objecthousein the partitive) evenif the whole houseor thesmallestpart of it was in fact painted.20 The diversity condition (36c) ensuresthatpredicatesthathaveonlyatomicelements(suchasFred), andpredicatesnoneof whoseelementsarerelatedto eachotherby thesubpartrelationarebounded(eventhoughtheysatisfy(36a,b)).

Thedefinition in (36) characterizesquantitativelyindeterminatepluralsandmassnounsasunbounded.Quantitativelyindeterminatecountnounsandindefinitenounswith a cardinalitypredicatearebounded.Certainmorphologicalelementsaffect theboundednessof verbalpredicatesby changingtheir quantitativedetermination.In En-glish, the particleat makesunboundedpredicates,andFinnishsuffixessuchas -ais-andRussianprefixessuchaspo-makeboundedpredicates.

(37) a. Unboundedpredicates:bombs,food,shootat, look for, touch,love,want,contemplate,doubt,use,expect,protect

b. Boundedpredicates:

a. fewbombs,a little food,Russianpoplacet′ ‘to cry for awhile’, pocitat′

‘to readabit of’, Finnishlukaista‘to read(something)in ashorttime’(condition(36a)is metbutnotcondition(36b))

b. manybombs,a lot of food,Russiannacitat′ ‘to readalot of’ (condition(36b)is metbutnotcondition(36a))

c. a bomb,two bombs,thefood,drop,find,kill, lose,marry, own,break,solve, remember, finish, present,contain, own, finish, get, Russianprobolet′ ‘to beill for a certainamountof time’ (perfective!)(neithercondition(36a)norcondition(36b)is met)

Theunboundednessof a VP predicateis compositionallydeterminedfrom theun-boundednessof its constitutentsasfollows:

(38) A VP predicateis unboundedif it haseitheranunboundedhead,or aunboundedargument.

Presumablythis shouldfollow from a compositionalsystemof interpretation,perhapsalongthelinesof Verkuyl1972,1989.

Herearetheexamplesof (22)and(23)again,with theunboundednessof thelexicalpredicatesshown([–B] = unbounded,[+B] = bounded). UnboundedVP predicateshaveanunboundedheador object:

(39) a. Theyhated(–B) thebombs(+B).

20Becausethe accusativeobjectwould imply that the whole housewaspainted,the useof the partitivecarriesadefeasibleimplicaturethatonly partof thehousewaspainted.

18

Page 19: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

b. Theydropped(+B) bombs(–B).

BoundedVP predicateshaveneither:

(40) a. Theydropped(+B) thebombs(+B).

b. Theydropped(+B) manybombs(+B).

In (39a),theVP predicateis unboundedbecauseits headV hatedis unbounded,andin(39b)theVP predicateis unboundedbecauseits objectNP is unbounded.In (40),ontheotherhand,neithertheheadnor theinternalargumentareunbounded,sotheVP isnotunbounded.

We cannow unify theaspectualandNP-relatedfunctionsof theFinnishpartitiveby thefollowing descriptivegeneralization:

(41) Theobjectof anunboundedVP is obligatorilypartitive.

[38] and[41] togetheraccountfor thetwo mainconditionsfor partitivecasediscussedabove,namelythatanobjectis eitheraquantitativelyindeterminateNP(anunboundednominalpredicate),or governedby anatelicverb(anunboundedverbalpredicate).Ifthe verb is unbounded,its objectmustbe partitive whetherthe object is unboundedor bounded.E.g. touchedthe/aflower (part.sg.),touched(the) flowers(part.pl.). Apartitive object is ungrammaticalif the VP is bounded,and an accusativeobject isungrammaticalif theVP is unbounded.A ruleequivalentto (41)applies(togetherwithothers)to licenseimperfectiveaspectin Russian.

Verbswhich areaspectuallyambiguouscanbe treatedasunspecifiedfor bound-edness;oncetheir boundednessis fixed they are treatedin exactly the sameway asthe aspectuallyunambiguousverbsin (22a)and(22b); see(1) and(10). Table [42]illustratesthis for theFinnishandRussianexamplesin (10),with theprogressiveagainservingasan (inadequate)shorthandglossfor theentirerangeof atelic verbalmean-ings:

(42)[+B] object [–B] object

[+B] verb(telic) napisal(perf.) pis’ma pisal(Impf.) pis’makirjoitti kirjeet (Acc.) kirjoitti kirjeita (Part.)‘wrote theletters’ ‘wrote letters’

[–B] verb(atelic) pisal(Impf.) pis’ma pisal(Impf.) pis’makirjoitti kirjeita (Part.) kirjoitti kirjeita (Part.)‘waswriting theletters’ ‘waswriting letters’

The specialcasesin [8] also follow from the rule statedin (41); the Finnishac-cusative/partitivecontrastherereflectsa semanticdistinction betweenboundedandunboundedreferencewhich in this caseis not overtly expressedin English. Supposethat “eyes” in the inalienablypossessedsense(e.g.the eyesin my face)is implicitlyquantified,perhapsmeaningsomethinglike “pair of eyes”,eventhoughit is formallya bareplural. Thenthe expressionin this senseis bounded,andreceivesaccusativecase.In thealienablesense(anatomicalsamples,glasseyes)theexpressionis anormal

19

Page 20: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

bareplural, andthereforeunbounded.(Notethatonly in the lattersenseis it possibleto sayJohnhassomemoreeyes, cf. (5) ff.) This showshow thedistributionof parti-tive versusaccusativecaseon theobjectdependson boundedness,ratherthanon themorphologicalfeaturesof definitenessandnumber,or onthepresenceor absenceof anovertquantifier.

The samepoint canbe madefor imperfectiveaspect,oneof whosefunctionsisto mark unboundednessat the level of the VP. Considerthe abovementionedverbalpredicatessuchaspoplacet′ ‘to cry for a while’, pocitat′ ‘to reada bit of’, nacitat′ ‘toreada lot of’ probolet′ ‘to beill for a certainamountof time’ (see(37)). Theseverbsare[+B] themselves,andtheyimposeaquantifiedreadingontheircomplement,whichmakesit [+B], evenif it is morphologicallyan indefinitebareplural. The resultingVP is therefore[+B] andrequiresperfectivemorphology. For example,in theRussiansentence

(43) nabrali(+B)Pref-gather-PAST-3Pl (Perf)

grybov(+B)mushrooms-GenPl

‘they pickeda lot of mushrooms’(Forsyth1970:22)

theverbalprefixna-combinessemanticallywith thebarepluralobjectgrybov“mush-rooms”([–B] by itself) to makea quantified(andtherefore[+B]) expression“a lot ofmushrooms”.

Theobjectof aVP complementgovernedby anunboundedverbis optionallyparti-tive. Forexample,when“try” and“begin” takeaVPcomplementcontainingaboundedverb,theobjectof thatverbis optionallypartitive:

(44) a. MattiMatti

koett-itry-Pst-3Sg

tappa-akill-Inf

karhu-nbear-SgAcc

‘Matti tried to kill a/thebear’

b. MattiMatti

koett-itry-Pst-3Sg

tappa-akill-Inf

karhu-abear-SgPart

‘Matti tried to kill a/thebear’

Thiscasevariationcanbeobtainedby assigningcaseeitherat thelevelof thelowerVP or at the level of thehigherVP. Thelower VP ‘kill thebear’ is bounded(cf. *killthebearsomemore), if thecaserule (41) appliesto it theobjectgetsaccusativecase;thehigherVP ‘try to kill thebear’is bounded(cf. try somemoreto kill thebear), if thecaseruleappliesto it is assignspartitivecaseto theobject.

Negatedverbsassignpartitivecaseto theirobjectsobligatorily(see(45a)),andop-tionally to certainmeasurephrases(adverbialsof timeandextent)whichareotherwiseaccusative(see(45b,c)).

(45) a. MattiMatti-SgNom

e-inot-3Sg

myy-nytsell-PstPart

talo-ahouse-SgPart

(#talo-n).(house-SgAcc)

‘Matti didn’t sell the/ahouse’

20

Page 21: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

b. MattiMatti-SgNom

odott-iwait-Pst-3Sg

#tunti-ahour-SgPart

(tunni-n)(hour-SgAcc)

‘Matti waitedanhour’

c. MattiMatti-SgNom

e-inot-3Sg

odotta-nutwait-PstPrtc

tunti-ahour-SgPart

(tunni-n)(hour-SgAcc)

‘Matti didn’t wait anhour’

Thecasechange“goesdown” arbitrarily far into nonfinitecomplements:

(46) a. AkiAki(Nom)

sa-iget-Past(3Sg)

Jari-nJari-Acc

pakotta-ma-anforce-Inf-Ill

Sake-nSake-Acc

lukema-anread-Inf-Ill

kirja-nbook-Acc

(loppu-un)(end-Ill)

‘Aki gotJarito forceSakereadthebook(through).’

b. AkiAki(Nom)

e-inot-3Sg

saa-nutget-PP

Jari-aJari-Part

pakotta-ma-anforce-Inf-Ill

Sake-aSake-Part

lukema-anread-Inf-Ill

kirja-abook-Part

(loppu-un)(end-Ill)

‘Aki didn’t getJarito forceSaketo readthebook(through).’

It is not only overt negationthat selectspartitive case. Like a negativepolarityitem,partitivecasecanappearin implicitly negativecontexts.For example,a speakerexpectinga negativeanswer,or trying to bepolite,mightprefer(47b)to (47a).

(47) a. On-koBe-Q

sinu-llayou-Adess

kyna?pencil-Nom

‘Do youhaveapencil?’

b. On-koBe-Q

sinu-llayou-Adess

kyna-a?pencil-Part

‘Do youhaveapencil?’

6 Coercion

Both partitive and imperfectivemorphologycanmark different semanticvariantsofunboundedness.Although theserun parallel in Finnish and Russianin many cases(recallthediscussionaround(11)) this is not alwaysthecase.Differencesin how lan-guagesinterpretunboundednessresultfrom differentcoercionof boundedexpressionsinto unboundedexpressionsandviceversa.

We haveseenthatexpressionsdenotingboundednonpunctualevents(accomplish-mentssuchasshootthebear) haveunboundedcounterpartsthatdenoteprocessescon-stitutingsuchevents(suchasshootat thebear). Punctualevents(achievements,suchasdrop theball) areatomic(i.e., not constitutedby processes,Pinon1995,p. 91), sotheirunboundedcounterpartscannotdenotesuchprocesses.Theycan,however,denoteprocessesthatarecomposedof punctualevents.With imperfectiveaspector partitive

21

Page 22: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

caseon theobject,drop theball canthusdenotea processof repeatedball-droppings,i.e.aniterative:

(48) Taitamatonunskilled

koripalloilijabasketballplayer

pudott-idrop-Past3Sg

jatkuvasticontinually

pallo-a.ball-Part

‘The unskilledbasketballplayerkeptdroppingtheball.’

Similarly, an intrinsically boundedpredicatecanget a secondarydurativeinterpreta-tion, asanongoingactivity, againwith partitivecaseon theobject:

(49) a. Tapo-i-nkill-Pst1Sg

juurijust

karhu-a.bear-Part

‘I wasjust killing thebear.’

b. MattiMatti

ost-ibuy-Pst3Sg

(juuri)(just)

auto-a,car-SgPart,

(kun.. . )(when.. . )

‘Matti was(just)buyinga car,(when.. . )’

In additionto the iterativeanddurativeinterpretations,basicallyboundedpredi-catescanget a rangeof otherunboundedinterpretations,dependingon whetherthelanguageexpressesVP unboundednessby aspectualmorphologyon the verb or bycasemorphologyon theobject.Thegeneralizationseemsto beasfollows:

(50) a. Aspectcancoerceshiftsin thelexicalmeaningsof verbs.

b. Casecancoerceshiftsin thelexicalmeaningsof nouns.

An exampleof aspectualcoercionin the lexical meaningof verbsis that theRussianimperfectivevyigryvat’, like theEnglishprogressivebewinning), candenote(in addi-tion to asequenceof winningevents,i.e. theiterativemeaning)aprogressivestateof aprocessthatprecedesthepunctualeventof winning, i.e. “be ahead”.PartitivecaseinFinnishdoesnot inducethis meaning:in a VP headedby thecorrespondingverbvoit-taa “win”, a partitiveobjectcannotcoercethemeaning“be ahead”;Finnishrequirestheprogressiveverbconstructionin (51b)“be (in theprocessof) winning” to conveyit.

(51) a. #MattiMatti

voitt-iwin-Past3Sg

kilpajuoksu-a.race-Part

‘Matti waswinning therace.’

b. MattiMatti

ol-iwas

voitta-ma-ssawin-Prtcpl-Iness

kilpajuoksu-a.race-Part

‘Matti waswinning therace.’

Anotherinterpretationof imperfectivizedpunctualtelic predicatesin Russian,un-availablein English,is conative(“try”):

(52) a. OnHe

da-va-l(Impf.)give-Pst3SgM

mneme

den’gi,money,

abut

jaI

nenot

vzja-l (Perf.)take-Pst3SgM

‘He wastrying to givememoney, but I refused.’ (Leinonen1984)

22

Page 23: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

b. JaI

vasyou

obman-yva-l(Impf.) ,deceive-Pst3SgM,

nobut

mogcould-Pst3SgM

liQ

obman-u-t’deceive-Inf

(Perf)?

‘I tried to deceiveyou,butcouldI deceiveyou?’ (Unbegaun1969)

Theconativeshadesinto a varietyof otherrelatednuancesof incompleteaction:

(53) a. CtoWhat

zeso

delaldid-IpfPstM

Bel’tovB.

vin

prodolzeniecourse

etixthese

desjatiten

let?years?

VseEverything,

ilior

poctialmost

vse.everything.

CtoWhat

onhe

sdelal?did-PrfPstM?

Nicego,Nothing,

ilior

poctialmost

nicego.nothing

‘So what did B. do in the courseof theseten years? Everything,or al-mosteverything.What did he accomplish?Nothing,or almostnothing.’(Forsyth1970:71)

b. KolumbColumbus

by-lbe-PstM

scastlivhappy

nenot

togda,then,

kogdawhen

otkry-l Prfdiscover-Impf-PstM

Amerik-u,America-Acc,

abut

kogdawhen

otkry-va-l(Impf )discover-PstM

eeit-Acc

‘Columbuswashappynot whenhediscoveredAmerica,but whenhewasaboutto discoverit (in theprocessof discoveringit)’ (Unbegaun1969)

Further,in the pasttensethe Russianimperfectivecanalsobe usedto asserttheoccurrenceof a pastevent,with currently relevantconsequences.For example,Onpisa-l pis’m-a(imperfective)couldhaveroughlythesenseof English“He haswrittenthe letter (already)”. This is the “simple denotation”or “statementof fact” meaning(Forsyth1970:82,Smith1991:312).

Suchaspectual/temporalmeaningshiftsinducedonverbsby imperfectiveaspectinRussianhaveno counterpartsin theaspectualuseof theFinnishpartitive. In Finnish,on the otherhand,the accusative/partitiveoppositionis exploitedto yield a rangeofspecialNP-relatedinterpretations,which in turncannotbereplicatedby aspectin Rus-sian.

Thus,partitivecasecancoerceacountnouninto amassnoun,whichis notpossiblein Russian,in spiteof thefact thatthedistinctionbetweenperfectiveandimperfectiveaspectcaneffectivelymarkthedefinitenessof NPobjectsin caseslike [10] (Larjavaara1991:382):21

(54) SitaThat-Part

kasikirjoitustamanuscript-Part

olibe-Past3Sg

sangy-nbed-Gen

alla-kinunder-even

‘(Partsof) thatmanuscriptwereevenunderthebed.’

A pervasivephenomenonis the coercionof a telic meaning. BoundednessinFinnishcanbelicensedby resultativitythroughexplicit or implicit locativeor resulta-tive predication.For example,potkaista“kick” takesa partitiveobjectin themeaning

21Larjavaaranotesthat thecorrespondingusageis impossiblewith theLatviangenitive,which otherwisehasfunctionssimilar to that of the Finnishpartitive (bareplural andmassnounobjectsandobjectsundernegation),or with theFrenchde-partitive construction.TheRussianpartitive (secondgenitive)alsocannotbeusedin this way.

23

Page 24: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

“kick at”, andan accusativeobjectwhena directionalcomplementis added,or evenimplied. In (55b),theverb“rub”, atelicin (55a),takesanaccusativeobjectlicensedbythe(explicit or implicit) resultativepredicate.A particularlycreativeusageof thiskindare(55j), wheretheatelicintransitive“love” is construedasresultative.22

(55) a. Hiero-i-nrub-Pst-1Sg

si-tait-Part

‘I rubbedit’

b. Hiero-i-nrub-Pst-1Sg

senit-Acc

pehmea-ksisoft-SgTrnsl

‘I kneadedit soft’

c. Ravist-i-nshake-Pst-1Sg

mato-ncarpet-SgAcc

(#kade-n)(hand-SgAcc)

‘I shook(out) thecarpet(my hand)’

d. Aitimother-SgN

makas-ilie-Pst-3Sg

lapse-nsachild-SgAcc-3Sg

kuoliaa-ksidead-SgTransl

‘The motherlay herchild dead(i.e.killed it by lying ontopof it)’

e. JussiJussi(NOM)

maalas-ipaint-Pst3Sg)

talo-nhouse-Acc

(punaise-ksi)(red-Transl)

‘Jussipaintedthe(a) [whole] house(red)’

f. JussiJussi(NOM)

maalas-ipaint-PAST(3SG)

talo-ahouse-Part

(punaise-ksi)(red-Transl)

‘Jussiwaspaintingthe(a)house(red)’

g. Luinread-PAST-1SG

kirja-nbook-Acc

(loppu-un)(end-Illat)

//(repale-i-ksi)(shred-Pl-Transl)

‘I readthebook(to theend)/ (to shreds)’

h. Luinread-Pst-1sg

kirja-abook-Part

‘I wasreadingthebook.’

i. Rakast-i-nlove-Pst-1Sg

tei-tayou-PlPart

‘I lovedyou’

j. Rakast-i-nlove-Pst-1Sg

te-i-da-tyou-PlAcc

rappio-lleruin-Adess

‘I lovedyou into ruin’ (EinoLeino)

The upshotis that the aspectualuseof partitive casein Finnish,while certainlyforming oneof its two corefunctions,is not asrichly elaboratedasthatof theverbalcategoryof aspectin Russian.Conversely, theNP-relateduseof aspectin Russianisnot asrichly elaboratedasthatof thenominalcategoryof casein Finnish.Thegener-alizationseemsto bethata morphologicalfeatureinducesextendedinterpretationsonthecategoryonwhich it is marked.

22It is aquotefrom thepoetEinoLeino. Example[55c] is from Leino(1991).(55d)is astandardexamplewhich appearsin Finnishgrammarsfrom Setala 1884onwards.

24

Page 25: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

If the languagepossessescorrespondingovert morphologicaldistinctions,theseextendedinterpretationswill not develop,presumablyin consequenceof the princi-ple thatspecificmorphologicalelementsblock generalmorphologicalelementsin theoverlappingdomain.Forexample,in modernGreek,imperfectiveaspectseemsto haveno NP-relatedfunctionat all, thedistinctionsin questionbeingexpresseddirectly bymeansof thechoiceof thedefiniteor indefinitearticle,whichRussianlacks.Thus,cor-respondingto thetwo sentencesin [10], of which thesecondis threewaysambiguous,Greekhasthefour unambiguoussentencesin (56).

(56) a. e rap-s-e (Perf.)write-Pst.3Sg

tathe

rama-taletter-PlAcc

‘He wrotetheletters’(. . .andleft) (telic V, def. NP)

b. e rap-s-e (Perf.)write-Pst.3Sg

(merika)(some)

rama-taletter-PlAcc

‘He wrote(some)letters’(. . .andleft) (telic V, indef. NP)

c. e raf-e (Imperf.)write-Pst.3Sg

tathe

rama-taletter-PlAcc

‘He waswriting theletters(. . .whenI came) (atelicV, def. NP)

d. e raf-e (Imperf.)write-Pst.3Sg

rama-taletter-PlAcc

‘He waswriting letters(. . .whenI came) (telic V, indef. NP)

Morphologicaleconomy(No VacuousAffixation, Marantz1984)would precluderedundantaspectualmarkingby partitive case,andredundantmarkingof NP-relatedfunctionsby aspect. In fact, when [–B] is morphologicallymarkedon the verb inFinnish,theobjectneednot bepartitive.Thus,frequentativeverbscantakeaccusativeobjectsin Finnish. Eventhoughthe VP is [–B] in virtue of the frequentativeverb,that featureis licensedby the verbalaffix andthereforeneednot be licensedby thepartitive. In this context,thepartitive/accusativecase-markingdistinctionrevertsto itspurelyNP-relatedfunction:

(57) Lue-skel-i-nread-freq-Past-1Sg

senthat-Acc

kirja-nbook-Acc

(loppu-un)(end-Ill)

‘I readthatbookoff andon (through).’

By thesametoken,we would expectthat in caseswhere[–B] is morphologicallymarkedonthenoun,theRussianperfective/imperfectivedistinctionwould revertto itspurelyaspectualfunction. Russianconfirmsthis prediction,but with a curioustwist.Theevidencecomesfrom thequantificationalgenitive,a casemostlyusedwith massnouns,which in certainparadigmsis morphologicallydistinct from the regulargen-itive. This so-called“secondgenitive” casehasbeenarguedto be a partitive case(Jakobson1936,Neidle1988,Franks1995). ThusRussianhas,undercertaincondi-tions, two morphologicalmeansof marking[–B] at its disposal:imperfectiveaspectfor aspectualfunctions,andpartitivecasefor NP-relatedfunctions.And indeed,in justthosecaseswherethenominal[–B] featurecanbemarkedby partitivecase,theverb

25

Page 26: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

appearsin the perfectiveaspect,ratherthanin the imperfective,as it would with anaccusativeobject(Klenin 1978).Thepattern,asI havebeenableto reconstructit fromtheciteddiscussions,is shownin (58),with thetabulardisplayin (59); theseshouldberespectivelycontrastedwith (10)andwith (42),illustratingthepatternwithoutpartitivecase.

(58) a. OnHe/she

kupi-l (Perf.)buy-PstM3Sg

cajtea-Acc

(Acc)

‘He boughtthetea’ (. . .andleft) (telic, def.)

b. OnHe/she

kupi-l (Imperf.)buy-PstM3Sg

caj-utea-Part

(Part)

‘He bought(some)tea’ (. . .andleft) (telic, indef.)

c. OnHe/she

pokupa-l(Imperf.)buy-PstM3Sg

cajtea-Acc

(Acc)

(1) ‘He wasbuyingtea(. . .whenI came) (atelic,indef.)(2) ‘He wasbuyingthetea(. . .whenI came) (atelic,def.)

(59)[+B] object [–B] object

[+B] verb(telic) kupil (perf.) caj (acc.) kupil (perf.) caj+u(part.)[–B] verb(atelic) pokupal(impf.) caj (acc.)

The unexpectedwrinkle, however,is that partitive casenormally appearsjust onobjectsof perfectiveverbs,not on objectsof imperfectiveverbs(Dahl andKarlsson1976:44,Klenin 1978).23 We might haveexpectedthepartitive/accusativedistinctionto be fully exploitedto yield a four-wayparadigmwhereunboundedreferencein thenominalandverbaldomainareseparatelymarked.

The generalizationin (50) seemsto be confirmedby aspectuallyinterpretedcasealternationsof Warlpiri andseveralPolynesianlanguages.

In Warlpiri, a classof verbshaveabsolutive(i.e. nominative)objectswhentheydenoteatelic event,anddativeobjectsotherwise,in whathasbeendubbedtheconativeconstruction(Hale1982,Laughren1988,Simpson1991):

(60) a. Ngarrka-ngkuka marlu luwa-rniman-Erg Pres kangaroo(Nom)shoot-Nonpast‘The manis shootingthekangaroo’

b. Ngarrka-ngkuka-rla-jinta marlu-ku luwa-rniman-Erg Pres-rla-jintakangaroo-Datshoot-Nonpast‘The manis shootingat thekangaroo’

Theconativealternationis foundwith verbsof impact(“strike”, “chop”, “carve”,“cut”,“”dig”, “pierce”, “grind”) andwith perceptionverbs(“see” vs. “look for”). Thereisalso a classof verbswith an inherentErgative-Dativecaseframe and with the ex-pectedatelic meaning(“seek,dig for”). This indicatesthat the meaningshouldbe

23Exceptthat,mysteriously,imperfectiveverbsseemto behavelike perfectivesundernegation.

26

Page 27: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

associatedwith thecaseframeitself, ratherthanwith a putativederivationalprocess.It seemsthat this casealternationshouldbe analyzedalongthe lines of the Finnishpartitive/accusativealternation,ratherthanasa lexical rule24 (Laughren1988)or by atransformationalprocessin thesyntax(BittnerandHale1993).25

TonganandSamoan‘middle verbs’(‘describinganeventwhichdoesnotaffectthedirectobjectimmediately’)marktheirobjectswith adativeprefix(Chung1978,47ff.,216ff.). Theyincludeperceptionverbs(‘see’, ‘listen to’), verbsof emotionandotherpsychologicalstates(‘love’, ‘want’, ‘understand’),verbsnormally selectinganimatedirectobjects,includingsomecommunicationverbs(‘meetwith’, ‘help’, ‘call’), andverbssuchas‘follow’, ‘wait for’, and‘visit’.

(62) a. Na’ePast

taa’ihit

’eErg

MeleMary

’aAbs

Sione.John

‘Mary hit John.’

b. ’OkuProg

manakolike

iahe

’iat

hethe

ta’ahine.girl.’

‘He likes thegirl.’ Tongan(Chung1978,53-54)

Like theWarlpiri conative,theTonganmiddle is transitive,andthedativeobjectsin this constructionaresyntacticallyfull-fledgeddirectobjects,undergoingprocesseswhich are restrictedto direct objects(incorporationand passivization),or to directarguments(quantifierfloat),andthatanumberof constraintsvalid for transitiveclausesapplyto middleclausesaswell (Chung,p. 216-234).Chungargueson this basisthat

24Laughrenproposesthat the conativeform of the verb (the atelic one,which takesa dative object) isderivedby thefollowing rule:(61) (x produceeffect on y) by ((entity comeinto contactwith y) by (x manipulateentity))→ ((x ma-

nipulateentity) in order that (entity comeinto contactwith y)) in order that (x produceeffect ony).

This rule could becontestedon severalgrounds.First, the conativealternationis not associatedwith anaffix on theverb. (Conceivablyit couldbeonethesuffixeson theauxiliary. However,thatseemsdoubtful,asneitherof themseemsto bespecialto theconativeconstruction.-rla “registers”thepresenceof anydativeobject whatever,while -jinta marksa third singulardative object (Hale 1982).) We would either havetoassumea “spontaneous”lexical derivationalprocess,or postulatea triggering morphemewhich is alwaysnull (cf. Pesetsky1995). Secondly,by erasing/respecifyinginformation in lexical conceptualstructure,thederivationalprocessin [61] violatesa basicpropertyof monotonicitythat canotherwisebe maintainedforlexical processes.In general,derivationalruleseitheraddpredicatesor featuresto thebase(e.g.causatives,diminutives),or specifytheway theargumentsaresyntacticallyexpressed(e.g.passives,antipassives).Theproposedlexical rule would not do either of thesethings. Third, the rule doesnot expressany intrinsicrelationbetweentheconativemeaningof the“derived” verbandthedativecasethat it governs.

25Bittner andHaletaketheconativeconstruction[60b] to beanantipassive,i.e.aninstanceof theprocessusually analyzedasdemotionof the direct object. The absenceof a morphologicaltrigger is if anythingevenmoreof a problemfor theantipassiveaccountthanit is for thelexical rule account,because“relation-changing”processesalmostalwaysdependon diathesis-changingverbalaffixes, indeed,as far asI knowthereareno casesof systematic“spontaneous”antipassivization.Moreover,theWarlpiri conativeconstruc-tion is transitive.(Theevidenceincludesthefollowing: (1) thesubjectbearsergativecase,(2) thereis objectagreementin theAUX (see[60b]), and(3) thedativeobjectcancontrol -kurra clauses,which musthaveanobjectcontroller.) But transitiveantipassivesareotherwiseunattestedin languages;their absencefollowsfrom a principledtheoryof valencychange(demotionandadditionof argumentsastheonly mechanisms).

27

Page 28: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

these‘middle’ verbsarenotantipassives,andproposesarulewhichassignsdativecaseto theobject.

The translationalequivalentsof all Warlpiri conativeverbsmentionedby Laugh-ren,Hale,andSimpson,of all Tonganmiddleverbslisted by Chung(e.g.[62]), takepartitiveobjectsin Finnish(with theexceptionthatperceptionverbslike ‘see’ takeac-cusativeobjectsin Finnish). Theconverse,of course,is not true: partitiveobjectsareusedmuchmorewidely in Finnish.

It seemsclearthat theWarlpiri conativeandTonganmiddlecasealternationsareessentiallyaspectual,andakinto theFinnishpartitive/accusativealternation.However,no analogto the Finnish NP-relatedfunction of partitive caseis reportedfor theselanguages,seeminglycontradicting(50b).

But in both languages,theNP-relatedfunctionof thecasealternationis arguablyblockedby explicit morphology, asdiscussedabove.This is clearestin Tongan,wheredefinitenessis morphologicallymarkedby thearticlehe. ThusTonganwould be liketheGreekcasementionedaboveunder(56). As for Warlpiri, it hasa specialdefiniteplural suffix -patu (Nash1980:167).This suffix would presumablymakethedefinite-nessdistinctioncorrespondingto (56a,c)vs. (56b,d).26 Nevertheless,it is not clearto me why the conativecaseoppositionshouldnot distinguishbetweendefiniteandindefinitereadingsof singularmassnounsin Warlpiri.27

Thematerialdiscussedin thissectionsuggeststhatcoercionis in mostcasesalocalaccommodationof aV or NPto therespectivemorphologythatit bears(generalization(50)). In thiswayit differsfrom thebasicdeterminationof boundedness,whichis doneat theVP levelasdiscussedin earliersections.

7 Partitive subjects

In additionto partitiveobjects,Finnishalsohaswhataretraditionallycalledpartitivesubjects.Theyshowonly theNP-relatedfunctionof partitivecase,nevertheaspectualfunction.Thus,only bareindefinitepluralsandmassnounscanbepartitivesubjects:28

(63) a. Karhubear-SgNom

kuol-idie-Pst-3Sg

‘The beardied’

b. #Karhu-abear-SgPart

kuol-idie-Pst-3Sg

26Thanksto Mary LaughrenandDavid Nashfor pointingout this crucial fact.27TheScottishGaelicsystemstudiedby Ramchand(1993)is alsointerestingin this respect.Ramchand

arguesthatScottishGaelicusesgenitivecaseto markbothananindefiniteobject,anda definitepostverbalobjectof anirresultativeverb.Thegenitivethusdeterminestheinterpretationof theVP asin Finnish.UnlikeFinnish,however,ScottishGaelichasamorphologicaldistinctionbetweendefinitesandindefinites.

28Allowing againfor coercion,asin (54).

28

Page 29: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

c. Karhu-tbear-PlNom

kuol-i-vatdie-Pst-3Pl

‘The bearsdied’

d. Karhu-j-abear-PlPart

kuol-idie-Pst-3Sg

‘Bearsdied’

Partitivesubjectscanbeeitherpreverbalor postverbal.Theirbasicpositionis VP-internal.Theyonly occurwith intransitiveverbs(see(64a)),andonly with thesubclassof so-calledPRESENTATIONALVERBS(EXISTENTIAL VERBS, in thetraditionaltermi-nologyof Finnishgrammarians).Thus,“play” (see(64b,c))is a presentationalverb,but “smile” (see(64d,e))is notapresentationalverb.29

(64) a. #Karhu-j-abear-Pl-Part

so-ieat-PAST-3Sg

hunaja-ahoney-SgPart

‘Therewerebearseatinghoney’(transitiveverb)

b. Piha-llacourtyard-Adess

leikki-iplay-3Sg

laps-i-achild-Pl-Part

‘Therearechildrenplayingin thecourtyard’

c. Laps-i-achild-Pl-Part

leikki-iplay-3Sg

piha-llacourtyard-Adess

‘Therearechildrenplayingin thecourtyard’

d. #Piha-llacourtyard-Adess

hymyile-esmile-3Sg

laps-i-achild-Pl-Part

‘Therearechildrensmiling in thecourtyard’

e. #Laps-i-achild-Pl-Part

hymyile-esmile-3Sg

piha-llacourtyard-Adess

‘Therearechildrensmiling in thecourtyard’

Examplesof presentationalintransitiveverbsarelistedin (65). All theseverbsal-low partitivesubjects,regardlessof whethertheyarebounded,asin (65a),unbounded,asin (65b),or bounded/unbounded,asin (65c).

(65) a. [+B]: kuolla ‘die’, syntya ‘be born’, ilmaantua ‘appear’,karata ‘escape(run away)’, tunkeutua‘intrude’, pelastua‘escape,be saved’, luhistua,sortua ‘collapse’, syttya ‘catch fire’, valahtaa ‘flash’, kuoriutua ‘hatch’,hukkua‘drown’, haaraantua‘branch’, ehtia ‘get (somewhere)on time’,lohjeta,katketa‘breakoff ’, naantya ‘die from deprivation’,takertua‘getstuck’,sarkya ‘break’,pysahtya ‘stop’, tarttua ‘stick’.

b. [–B]: asua‘dwell’, kasvaa‘grow’, kiehua‘boil’, kilpailla ‘compete’,kokoon-tua ‘gather’, lymyilla, piill a ‘lurk’, mahtua‘fit’, opiskella‘study’, leikkia‘play’, riitt aa ‘suffice’, seista ‘stand’, tapahtua‘happen’, tippua ‘drip’,tyoskennella ‘work’, vaeltaa‘wander’,hiipia ‘sneak’,roikkua,riippua ‘hang’,

29Presentationalverbsareoftencalled“unaccusatives”,but thetwo classesarequitedistinct.

29

Page 30: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

kiehua, ‘boil’, liikkua ‘move’, madella‘crawl’, riitt aa ‘suffice’, sijaita ‘belocated’,vilkkua,valahdella ‘flash (repeatedly)’,puuttua‘be lacking’, is-tua ‘sit’, kellua ‘float’, kiipeilla ‘climb’, kokoontua‘gather’,vaeltaa‘wan-der’.

c. [±H]: kukkia ‘(comeinto) blossom’,havita ‘disappear’,roiskua ‘splash’,aueta‘open’, selvita ‘becomeclear(er)’,kiiveta ‘climb’, hajota ‘disinte-grate’.

Non-presentationalintransitivesdo not takepartitivesubjects,againwhethertheyaretelic, asin (66a),or atelic,asin (66b).

(66) a. [+B]: voittaa ‘win’, suuttua‘get angry’, tehota ‘have an effect’, loppua‘end’, pettya ‘get disappointed’,pelastya ‘becomescared’.

b. [–B]: kelvata‘to begoodenough’,hymyilla ‘smile’, neuvotella‘negotiate’,naureskella‘chuckle’, jutella, keskustella‘converse’,riemuita ‘rejoice’,hallita ‘reign’, suostua‘agree’.

c. [±H]: sulaa ‘melt’, puhdistua‘get clean(er)’,pieneta ‘get small(er)’, ly-heta ‘get short(er)’,vanheta‘get old(er)’.

Syntactically, partitivesubjects(andpresentationalsubjectsin general)differ fromregularsubjectsin their word order. Theyappeareitherpostverbally((67a,b),contrast(68a,b)), or preverballyin Spec-VPposition((67c,d)).If theyareplacedpostverbally,andthesentencebeginswith alocativeadverbial,theSpec-VPpositioncanbeoccupiedby aclitic pronounsita “it” in thepartitivecase((67e),contrast(68e)).

(67) Presentationalintransitives:

a. Nytnow

onbe-3Sg

synty-nytborn-PP

lapsichild-SgNom

(lapsi-a)(child-PlPart)

‘Now achild hasbeenborn’

b. Sytty-ibreakout-Pst-3Sg

sotawar-SgNom

‘War brokeout’ (Vilkuna1989,165)

c. Lapsichild-SgNom

(lapsi-a)(child-PlPart)

onnow

nytbe-3Sg

synty-nytborn-PP

‘The/achild (children)has(have)beenbornnow’

d. Sotawar-SgNom

sytty-ibreakout-Pst-3Sg

‘War brokeout’

e. Siellathere

si-tathat-Part

synty-ybeborn-Pst-3Sg

(lapsi-a)child-PlPart

‘Therechildrenarebeingborn(all thetime)’

Non-presentationalintransitives:

30

Page 31: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

(68) a. #Hymyil-ismile-Pst-3Sg

lapsichild-SgNom

(lapsi-a)(child-PlPart)

‘The/achild (children)smiled’

b. #Voitt-i#win-Pst-3Sg

ruotsalainenSwede-SgNom

(ruotsalaisia)(Swede-PlPart)

c. Lapsichild-SgNom

(#lapsi-a)(child-PlPart)

hymyil-ismile-Pst-3Sg

‘The/achild (#children)smiled’

d. RuotsalainenSwede-SgNom

(#ruotsalais-i-a)(#Swede-PlPart)

voitt-iwin-Pst-3Sg

‘The/aSwede(#Swedes)won’

e. #SiellaThere

si-tathat-Part

hymyile-esmile-3Sg

laps-i-achild-SgNom(child-PlPart)

‘Therechildrenaresmiling (away)’

Thesedatacan be accountedfor on the following assumptions.First, partitivecaseis assignedonly inside VP; NPs in Spec-Inflget nominativecaseobligatorily.By the basicconstraintof Finnishsyntaxthat a VP cancontainonly a singledirectinternalNP argument(Siro’s Law, seep. 10 above),VP-internalsubjectsoccuronlywith intransitiveverbs.Therefore,partitivesubjectsarerestrictedto intransitiveverbs.

The secondassumptionto be madeis that VP-internalsubjectsare licensedbylocativearguments,whichmaybeexplicit or implicit. Verbswhichhavesuchlocativeargumentsconstitutethe classof “presentationalverbs”. Therefore,VP-internalsub-jects,andpartitivesubjectsin particular,arerestrictedto presentationalverbs,andcanalwaysco-occurwith locatives.

Thesubjectof a presentationalverbis partitiveif it is unbounded:

(69) a. PoikaBoy (Nom)

saapu-iarrive-Pst3Sg

‘The/aboy ([+B)] arrived([+B]).’

b. Poik-i-aBoy-Pl-Part

saapu-iarrive-Pst3Sg

‘Boys ([–B]) arrived([+B]).’

Partitivesubjectsdiffer from partitiveobjectsin oneimportantrespect:theydonotmark unboundednessat the VP level. Eventhoughthe VP in (70) is unbounded,invirtueof theverbalpredicate,thisdoesnot licensea partitivesubject:

(70) a. KarhuBear

lymyile-e(Nom) lurk-3Sg

‘A bear([+B]) is lurking ([–B]).’

b. *Karhu-aBear-Part

lymyile-elurk-3Sg

‘A bear([+B]) is lurking ([–B]).’

31

Page 32: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

On subjects,partitivecasemarkstheunboundednessof theNP itself. In otherwords,subjectsof all presentationalintransitivespatternlike objectsof boundedverbalpredi-cates,in thatpartitivecaseonthemhasonly theNP-relatedfunction.

8 The evolution of the aspectualpartitive

Thepartitivecasewasoriginally a spatialcasewith separative(“from”) meaning.Itsunboundedness-markingfunctionsdevelopedwithin Balto-Finnic. The original nu-cleusof the innovationhasbeenthoughtto bea classof intensionalverbsthatgovern“quirky” lexical partitivein Mordvinianandin certaindialectsof Lappish(E. Itkonen1972,1973,T. Itkonen1976). It hasalso beenarguedthat the usesof the partitiveareborrowedfrom the Baltic genitive(Larsson1983,1984). Larjavaara(1991)hasproposeda hypotheticalscenarioof theevolutionfrom separative(“from”) case,via aquantificationalmeaning(similar to Frenchdeasin mangerdupain ‘to eatbread’),totheaspectualfunctionof Finnishandits closerelatives.

Outsideof theBalto-Finnicsubfamily, limited aspectualfunctionsof partitivecaseareattestedin theearliestrecordsof thenow extinctSoutherndialectof Lappishoncespokenin Sweden(E. Itkonen1972,1973).30 But by far themostimportantevidenceevidencefor theoriginal systemcomesfrom Mordvinian(Itkonen1972:166,Larsson1983:124).

Mordvinianhasarich systemof inflectionalcategories.Nounsmaybeinflectedforeitherpossessionor definiteness.Verbsagreein personandnumberwith thesubject,andmayagreealsowith anaccusativeobject(the“objectiveconjugation”);verbswithinessiveandpartitiveobjects(andof courseintransitiveverbs)showsubjectagreementonly (the“subjectiveconjugation”).Objectsinflectedfor possessionarenormallyas-signedaccusativecase,31 andtheyshowobligatoryobjectagreement.

(71) MasajtWhy

simendadrink-Past2Sg3Sg

sapamstrong

vinanenvodka-AccSg-1Sg

‘Why did youdrink my strongvodka?’

Objectsinflectedfor definitenesscanalsogetaccusativecase;if thesentencehasa atelic (resultative)interpretation,thereis thenoptionalobjectagreement(Itkonen1972,166).

(72) a. vede-ntwater-Acc-Def

kand-i-jabring-Pst-1SgSubj3Obj

‘I broughtthewater’

30In modernLappish,theold partitive formsnow serveasaccusativein theplural; theaccusativeendingshavebeenretainedin thesingular(Korhonen1981:214-215).

31Accusativecaseis morphologicallyidenticalwith thegenitive. In somedialectsa possessedobjectcanalsobealsonominativeif it is inanimateandthepossessoris third person(Itkonen1972:167).

32

Page 33: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

b. vede-ntwater-Acc-Def

kand-i-nbring-Pst-1SgSubj

‘I broughtthewater’, ‘I (always)broughtwater’

Objectswhichareinflectedneitherfor possessionor definitenessdonotagreewith theverb.32 Theyarenormallyaccusative,and(if indefinite)canalsobenominative.

In additionto accusativeandnominativecase,objectsmayalsobearpartitivecase33

or inessivecase.TheMordvinianpartitivecaseending-da is cognatewith theFinnishpartitive-ta, andits syntaxoffersaglimpseof theancestralsystemto whichtheFinnishusescanbe traced.Mordvinianpartitive objectscanbe morphologicallyandseman-tically eitherdefiniteor indefinite,andtheydo not triggerobjectagreement.Partitiveoccursasa “quirky” caseon the objectsof certainintensionalverbssuchas “fear”,“be ashamed”,“mourn”, “see”, “hear”, “listen to”, “notice”, “know”, “need”, “want”,“think about”, “talk about”, “avoid”, “promise”, “escape”(see(73a)). Some,but notall, of theseverbsgovernpartitivecasein Finnishaswell. As in Finnish,thecomple-mentof certainmeasurephrasesis partitive(see(73b)).

(73) a. ilanot-Imper2Sg

pelefear

dusman-do-t,enemy-Part-2Sg,

sexrather

pel-tfear-Imper2Sg

esi-town

pola-do-tspouse-Part-2Sg(quirky

partitive)

‘Don’t fearyourenemy, ratherfearyourownspouse.’ (Zorin 220)

b. tasa‘here

lamalot

penga-dafirewood-Part

‘there’sa lot of firewoodhere’

Most revealingly, partitiveoccurson indefinitebareplural or massnounobjectsof asmallclassof verbs,mostcommonly“eat”, “drink”, and“smoke”, lessoftentransferverbslike “give”, “bring”, “take”, and“steal” (Itkonen1972:170,Larsson1983:125ff.):

(74) a. jarsa-neat-1SgSubj

kal-do.fish-Part

sima-ndrink-1SgSubj

vet-te.water-Part.

mon,OK,

ada,fine,

sim-t-tandrink-caus-1SgSubj/2SgObj

vina-do.vodka-Part

‘I’m eatingfish. I’m drinkingwater. OK, soI’ll let youdrink vodka.’

b. jarsa-keat-Imp

praka-do-npie-Part-1Sg

‘eatsomeof my pies’

c. jarsa-mseat-Inf

praka-do-ntpie-PartSg-Def

‘to beeatingthepie’

32Exceptfor personalpronounsandpropernames,which mayremainmorphologicallyindefiniteandstillshowobjectagreementlike definitely inflectednouns(Itkonen1972:164).

33Mordviniangrammarscall it “ablative” case,thoughto avoidconfusionwith theFinnishablativeI willnotusethat termhere.

33

Page 34: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

d. vanalook

kitwho

salcitsteals

monmy

praka-do-npie-PartSg-Indef

‘Look who’sstealingmy pies’

Verbsof thetype“eat”, “drink”, and“smoke”havethepropertiesin (18)and(19).They arethe prototypicalmembersof the verb classwhich is privilegedby Krifka’stheoryof thepartitive(section4). We canin fact saythattheMordvinianpartitivehasthemeaning“part of” asdefinedin (18a).Accordingly, it hasa muchmorerestricteddistributionthat the Finnishpartitive,andin particularis not triggeredby mereirre-sultativity (“shotat a bear”getsaccusative).As a complementto verbsof therelevantclass,it yieldsanindefinitebareplural or massobjector atelic interpretation(processor iteration).

Thedistributionof inessive(sometimescalledinessive-instrumental)objectscon-tributesanotherpieceto the puzzle. Inessiveobjectsaremorphologicallyindefinite,anddo not triggerobjectagreement,but theyaresemanticallyinterpretedasdefinite.Theyareassignedby the atelic versionof verbsthat areintrinsically unspecifiedfortelicity, suchas “carry”, “hit”, “chew”, “seek”, “read”, “wait for”, “send”, “chide”,“suckle”, “bring”:

(75) a. sov-nichide-3Sg

Vana-soIvan-InessSg

‘He chidesIvan’

b. davajSo

cavmobeat

esnendehe-InessSg

‘So, hebeganto beathim’

In the telic version, the sameverbsassignaccusative(or nominative)caseto theirobjects.Thecorrespondingverbsin Finnishalternatebetweenpartitiveandaccusativeobjects,dependingon telicity. This is in effect the Mordvinian instantiationof theconativealternation,involving theaspectualfunctionof objectcasemarking.

Thefact thatpartitiveandinessiveobjectsneveragreewith theverbsuggeststhatunlike the Finnishpartitive, which is syntacticallya structuralcase,the Mordvinianpartitiveandinessivearesyntacticallyinherent(lexical,oblique)cases.Theyalsocan-notbesubjectcasesin Mordvinian(unlikewhatis thecasein Finnish).

ThusMordvinianusesseparatelexicalcasesfor thetwo functionsof Finnishparti-tive case:partitivefor theNP-relatedfunction,andinessivefor theaspectualfunction,eachrestrictedto a lexical subclassof verbs.TheFinnishpartitivecombinesandgen-eralizesthefunctionsof thesetwo Mordvinianlexicalcasesin asinglestructuralcase.

Thefirst stagein theevolutionof theBalto-Finnicaspectualpartitiveobjectwasthepartitive’s changein statusfrom a strictly locative(“from”) caseto casewith quantifi-cationalforce.Thiswasevidentlytriggeredby thedevelopment,earlyin Finno-Ugric,of a systemof six specializedlocal casesfrom combinationsof essive-na, lative -n,andpartitive-ta with -s- “inside” and-l- “outside”.

34

Page 35: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

(76)

internal externalplace s+na (Finnish-ssa) l+na (Finnish-lla)motionto s+en(Finnish-hen,seen) l+ne (Finnish-lle)motionfrom s+ta (Finnish-sta) l+ta (Finnish-lta)

Thenewcompositeelativeandablativecasestook over the local functionsof theoldpartitive-ta. It retainedonly themeaning“part of”, thusbecominga strictly partitivecase(ateapples,ateporridge,ateof theporridge).

Partitivecasemusthavethendisplacedinessivecaseasamarkerof definiteobjectsof atelic(unbounded)verbsin theconativeconstructionshownfor Mordvinianin (75).With this change,the old functionof partitivecaseof markingNPswith unboundedreferencebecamegeneralizedto markingVPs with unboundedreference(carriedthefirewood(aways),hit at theman,chewedon thebone).

Now partitivecasecouldbeextendedto definiteandcountNPsof atelic verbsingeneral(loved the woman,neededa knife, tendedthe reindeer). Thus the partitivecomesto simplymarkunboundednessat theVP level.

Why did the aspectualfunctionof partitivecaseemergeonly in the Balto-Finnicbranch?(Elsewherein Finno-Ugrictheconativeconstructionremainedunchangedorwassimply lost.) AnotheruniqueBalto-Finnicdevelopmentwasthegrammaticaliza-tion of partitive into a structuralcase.34 It is temptingto makea causalconnectionbetweenthesetwo changes.Recall that theFinnishpartitive licensesunboundednessat the VP level, irrespectiveof whetherthe unboundednesscomesfrom the headVor from the object. Let us supposethat a lexical casemustbe interpretedin a local,compositionalfashion.If thatis thecase,thentheBalto-Finnicfunctionof thepartitivecouldnothaveemergedin theotherFinno-Ugriclanguages.Thegrammaticalizationofpartitivecasewouldbeapreconditionto its developmentasamarkerof unboundednessat theVP level.

9 Conclusion

The commonfactor of the aspectualand NP-relatedfunctionsof partitive caseandimperfectiveaspectis markingaVP’sunboundedness.A VP hasthispropertyin virtueof havingeitheranunboundedheadoranunboundedargument.Historical-comparativeevidencesuggeststhat thepartitive’s emergenceasa structuralcaseis a preconditionfor theriseof its aspectualfunction.

34Presumablythis developmentis relatedto the fact that only the Balto-Finnicbranchhaspartitive sub-jects;seesection7.

35

Page 36: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

Bibliography

BITTNER, MARIA AND KEN HALE. 1993.“Ergativity: towardsa theoryof a hetero-geneousclass.” Ms.,RutgersUniversityandMassachusettsInstituteof Technol-ogy, Cambridge,Massachusetts.

CHOMSKY, NOAM. 1981.Lecturesongovernmentandbinding.Dordrecht:Foris.

CHUNG, SANDRA. 1978. Casemarking and grammaticalrelations in Polynesian.Austin: Universityof TexasPress.

DAHL , OSTEN. 1985.Aspect.Cambridge:UniversityPress.

DAHL , OSTEN AND FRED KARLSSON. 1976.“Verbienaspektitjaobjektinsijamerkinta.”Sananjalka18:28-52.

DOWTY, DAVID R. 1979. Word meaningandMontaguegrammar. Dordrecht:Rei-del.

FORSYTH, J. 1970.A grammarof aspect.Cambridge:UniversityPress.

FRANKS, STEVEN. 1995.Parametersof Slavicmorphosyntax.Oxford: Oxford Uni-versityPress.

HAKULINEN , AULI AND FRED KARLSSON. 1979.Nykysuomenlauseoppia.Helsinki:SuomalaisenKirjallisuudenSeura.

HALE, KENNETH. 1982.“Someessentialfeaturesof Warlpiri grammar.” In S.Swartz,(ed.) Papersin Warlpiri grammar: in memoryof Lothar Jagst. Work PapersofSIL-AAB, SeriesA, Vol. 6. Darwin: SummerInstituteof Linguistics,AustralianAboriginesBranch.

HEINAM AKI , ORVOKKI . 1984. “Aspectin Finnish.” In CasperdeGrootandHannuTommola,(ed.)Aspectbound. Foris: Dordrecht.

DE HOOP, HELEN. 1992.Caseconfigurationandnounphraseinterpretation.Gronin-gen:Grodil.

IKOLA , OSMO. 1961.Lauseopinkysymyksia. Tietolipas26. Forssa.

ITKONEN, ERKKI . 1972. “ Uber dasObjekt in denfinnisch-wolgaischenSprachen.”Finnisch-UgrischeForschungen39:153-213.

ITKONEN, ERKKI . 1973.“Zur GeschichtedesPartitivs.” Finnisch-UgrischeForschun-gen40:278-339.

ITKONEN, TERHO. 1976.“Eraansijamuodonongelmia.” OpusculaeInstituti LinguaeFennicae,UniversitasHelsingiensis53.

JAKOBSON, ROMAN. 1936/1962. “Beitrag zur allgemeinenKasuslehre.” Selectedwritings,2. TheHague:Mouton.

KLENIN, EMILY. 1978. “Quantification,partitivity, and the genitiveof negationinRussian.” In BernardComrie (ed.) Classificationof grammaticalcategories.Edmonton:LinguisticResearch.

KORHONEN, MIKKO . 1981.Johdatuslapin kielenhistoriaan.Helsinki: SuomalaisenKirjallisuudenSeura.

36

Page 37: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

KRIFKA, MANFRED. 1989.“Nominal reference,temporalconstitution,andquantifi-cation in eventsemantics.” In RenateBartsch,Johanvan Benthem,andPetervanEmdeBoas(edd.)Semanticsandcontextualexpressions. Foris:Dordrecht.

KRIFKA, MANFRED. 1992. “Thematicrelationsaslinks betweennominalreferenceandtemporalconstitution.” In Ivan A. SagandAnnaSzabolcsi(edd.) Lexicalmatters. Stanford:CSLI.

KURYŁOWICZ, JERZY. 1964. Theinflectionalcategoriesof Indo-European.Heidel-berg:Winter.

LARSSON, LARS-GUNNAR. 1983.StudienzumPartitivgebrauchin denostseefinnischenSprachen.Uppsala:ActaUniversitatisUpsalensis.

LARSSON, LARS-GUNNAR. 1984.“The role of Baltic influencein theaspectualsys-temof Finnish.” In CasperdeGrootandHannuTommola,(ed.) Aspectbound.Foris: Dordrecht.

LAUGHREN, MARY. 1988. “Towardsa lexical representationof Warlpiri verbs. InW. Wilkins (ed.) Syntaxand semantics21: Thematicrelations. SanDiego:AcademicPress.

LEINONEN, MARJA. 1984.“Narrativeimplicationsof aspectin RussianandFinnish.”In CasperdeGrootandHannuTommola,(ed.)Aspectbound. Foris:Dordrecht.

LARJAVAARA , MATTI . 1991.“Aspektuaalisenobjektinsynty.” Viritt aja 95:372-408.

LEINO, PENTTI. 1991. Lauseetja tilanteet. Helsinki: SuomalaisenKirjallisuudenSeura.

MALING , JOAN. 1993. “Of nominativeand accusative.” In AndersHolmbergandUrpo Nikanne. (edd.),Caseandother functionalcategoriesin Finnish syntax.Berlin: MoutondeGruyter.

NASH, DAVID . 1980.Topicsin Warlpiri grammar. Ph.D.dissertation,MIT.

NEIDLE, CAROL. 1988.Therole of casein Russiansyntax.Dordrecht:Kluwer.

NIKANNE , URPO. 1990.Zonesandtiers. Helsinki: FinnishLiteratureSociety.

PESETSKY, DAVID . 1995.Zerosyntax.Cambridge:MIT Press.

PINON, CHRISTOPHER. 1995.A mereologyfor aspectuality. Ph.D.dissertation,Stan-ford University, Stanford,California.

SETAL A, E.N. 1884.Suomenkielenlauseoppi.Helsinki: Holm.

SIMPSON, JANE. 1991.Warlpiri morpho-syntax.Dordrecht:Kluwer.

SMITH , CARLOTA S. 1991.Theparameterof aspect.Dordrecht:Kluwer.

UNBEGAUN, BORIS. 1969.RussischeGrammatik.Gottingen:Vandenhoeck& Ruprecht.

VAINIKKA , ANNE. 1993. “The threestructuralcasesin Finnish.” In AndersHolm-bergandUrpoNikanne.(edd.),Caseandotherfunctionalcategoriesin Finnishsyntax.Berlin: MoutondeGruyter.

VENDLER, ZENO. 1967.Linguisticsin philosophy. Ithaca:CornellUniversityPress.

VILKUNA , MARIA . 1989.Freeword order in Finnish: its syntaxanddiscoursefunc-tions.Helsinki: SuomalaisenKirjallisuudenSeura.

37

Page 38: Partitive Case and Aspect - user.phil.hhu.defilip/kiparsky.1998.pdf · Partitive Case and Aspect Paul Kiparsky Stanford University 1 Partitive case as a syntactic and semantic problem

ZORIN, IGNATIJ. 1977.MordwinischeVolksdichtung,VI. Helsinki: Suomalais-UgrilainenSeura.

38