No Man an Island

download No Man an Island

of 10

Transcript of No Man an Island

  • 8/12/2019 No Man an Island

    1/10

    No Man an Island: Refuting Robert Nozick'sLibertarian Political Philosophy

    Galvin Chia*

    InAnarchy, State, and Utopia, Robert Nozick expounds a property-based

    theory of rights. Fundamental to his philosophy is the claim

    (reminiscent of Kant) that an individual possesses ownership over

    himself, and because of this the individual is inviolable a claim that is

    often heard in contemporary rights discourse. Stemming from this is his

    conception of rights and his entitlement theory, which outlines his

    concept of justice. This results in Nozicks derivation of the minimal

    state a state dedicated only to the protection of property rights and the

    enforcement of fair exchanges. In this form, Nozicks political

    philosophy enshrines the claim of an individual to his rightful property,

    as well as the inalienability of the individual entity itself. Although such

    claims may seem appealing within the liberal western paradigm, this

    paper will show that such Nozicks extreme libertarian approach is

    unsustainable under critical examination. The minimal state that he

    builds upon these values is an altogether unconvincing construction,wrought with both internal inconsistencies and external fallacies.

    I Individualism, Justice and the Minimal State

    Self-ownership is the cornerstone of Nozicks work it is from this

    source that the rights of the individual, and subsequently the minimal

    state, originate. As individuals own themselves, they cannot be treated

    as means and must be seen as ends, in Kantian fashion.1

    Self-ownershipthus accords them this right, which is a fundamental one.2Like Locke,

    he defines rights to be naturalrights: inalienable and inviolable.3This is

    Nozicks categorical imperative what he calls side constraints and

    *Galvin Chia is in his second year of a combined Bachelor of Arts/Bachelor of Economics

    degree at the Australian National University. He is a current resident of Bruce Hall.1Robert Nozick,Anarchy, State, and Utopia(Basic Books, 1974) 105.2G A Cohen, Self-Ownership, Freedom, and Equality(Cambridge University Press, 1995) 67-

    8.3Alan H Goldman, The Entitlement Theory of Distributive Justice (1976) 73(21)Journal of

    Philosophy 833.

  • 8/12/2019 No Man an Island

    2/10

    138 Cross-sections Volume VI 2010

    represents the inviolability of other persons.4 As this conception of

    rights operates on a universal level, it grants moral equality to all

    individuals.

    Following this is his entitlement theory, which defines how individualsmay justly come to possess things. The theory, from which stems his

    conception of justice, is a narrow one that is grounded in the non-

    violation of property rights. There are three aspects to this. First is the

    concept of justice in acquisition, which states that a possession is justly

    held if it was acquired in a just fashion that is, acquired without the

    violation of anothers self-ownership or right to property. Second is

    justice in transaction, in that whatever is justly held can be freely

    transferred. The notion of free in this case would seem to meanfreedom from force, theft, fraud, and so on.5 Third is the method of

    rectification of past injustices, in which if the current distribution of

    property holdings are the result of unjust acquisitions, then a

    distribution which would have arisen had the transaction been just

    must be realised.6 This necessitates a historical approach; unjust

    acquisition in the past must be rectified

    The entitlement theory says nothing about the process of initialappropriation, however. To this, Nozick appeals to a Lockean provisio,

    such that an individual can legitimately claim possession of the natural

    world. Kymlicka summarizes the sentiment succinctly:

    1) People own themselves.2) The world is initially unowned.3) You can acquire absolute rights over a disproportionate share of

    the world, if you do not worsen the condition of others.

    4) It is relatively easy to acquire absolute rights over adisproportionate share of the world.

    4Nozick, above n 1, 105.5Will Kymlicka, Contemporary Political Philosophy(Oxford University Press, 2nded, 2002)104.6Nozick, above n 1, 153.

  • 8/12/2019 No Man an Island

    3/10

    No Man an Island Galvin Chia 139

    5) Therefore once people have appropriated private property, afree market in capital and labour is morally required.7

    The minimal state, in Nozicks opinion, follows naturally from these

    claims. It is one, which, through a monopoly of force, enforcesNozickian rights and maintains the inviolability of the individual, but

    nothing more. Whilst conventional conceptions of the state usually

    imply functions such as the provision of public goods, arbitration and

    taxation, Nozick sees these as incompatible with our fundamental

    rights. The funding of such state functions more often than not requires

    taxation, which Nozick sees as a state violation of a citizens right to

    property. Public services, such as the provision of defence and

    healthcare, are seen as unjust redistributive efforts, again on thegrounds of violating property rights.8As such the minimal state is the

    most extensive state that can be justified.9The processes through which

    the minimal state emerges from an optimistic Nozickean state of

    nature to the development of protection agencies will not be

    discussed here, for the sake of brevity.

    II Internal Critique

    Nozicks approach to justifying the minimal state can therefore be

    summarised as:

    1) Self-ownership is fundamental, and from this stems conceptionsof rights and justice.

    2) On the basis of these principles, the minimal state is constructedand is the most extensive state that can exist.

    Since the validity of 2) relies on the strength of the premise 1), the

    critique will target the premise to not only show that Nozicks

    conception of the minimal state is invalid, but that its foundations are

    flawed. This first part will consider arguments against Nozick, ad

    hominem.

    7Cohen in Kymlicka, above n 5, 116.8Nozick, above n 1,101.9Ibid 106.

  • 8/12/2019 No Man an Island

    4/10

    140 Cross-sections Volume VI 2010

    There are serious questions that can be raised concerning justice in

    initial acquisition. In a historical context, there have been many

    instances in which the appropriation of property has been carried out

    through force, coercion or in an otherwise unjust (by Nozicks

    standards) fashion. The violent appropriation of land in North Americaand Australia by early European settlers, for instance, is a clear case in

    which initial acquisition was unjust, and has remained unrectified to

    this day.

    However Nozicks model does call for the rectification of these past

    transgressions of indigenous property rights. Though this is currently

    achieved in some cases through fiscal compensation or affirmative

    action schemes, under Nozicks system of rights this would beillegitimate not simply because they would be services provided for

    by an illegitimate, more-than-minimal state, but also because they

    would require funding through taxation, which is in itself a violation of

    the property rights of the taxed.10 The only available option would be

    nothing short of returningall the land unjustly claimed from indigenous

    peoples this would include much of North America, and almost all of

    Australia. What, then, of the Australian property owner who has justly

    bought what was initially unjustly appropriated land? Would not his

    right to property be violated as well? These two tensions remain

    unresolved by Nozick it is unclear how historical injustices such as

    these could be resolved.

    Cohen notes that as long as historical injustice is unresolved, Nozicks

    entire position on rights and the minimal state is rendered nigh invalid.

    As noted, historical injustice violates property rights. If property rights

    are allowed to remain compromised, then there is no moral objection to

    further infringing property rights for instance, through taxation.11The

    minimal state would cease to be the most extensive state that can be

    justified a Rawlsian welfare state or Hobbsian leviathan would be

    made morally justifiable.

    10Kymlicka, above n 5, 112.11Cohen in Kymlicka, above n 5, 111.

  • 8/12/2019 No Man an Island

    5/10

    No Man an Island Galvin Chia 141

    Next is an issue of Nozicks justice in transfer. Nozick claims that just

    situations result from just actions, but this is not always the case.

    Consider the case where an individual willingly sells himself into

    slavery. No justice in transfer principles are violated, but in effect the

    free individual an ends is subsumed as a means, and self-ownershipis violated.12 Nozicks firm stance against slavery and belief in the

    necessity of self-ownership is clearly expressed in his Tale of the Slave

    in which a slave with a plethora of rights and benefits, but not

    freedom, is still in a morally unacceptable position.13This is indicative

    that Nozicks model does not necessarily remain just in all cases. How

    would the minimal state react in this case? There appears to be no case

    on which it could act the new slave has not violated any principles,

    and to take the slave away from his owner would be to violate theowners rights to owning the slave. That there is no solution to this

    significant contradiction goes to show, again, that the principles on

    which Nozick bases his minimal state on are not entirely sound.

    Thirdly, there are issues with Nozicks use of the Lockean provisio.

    Recall that it is just to acquire a disproportionate share of the world for

    yourself to prevent the tragedy of the commonsprovided nobody

    is made worse off. On a more general level, this conflicts with the

    themes of moral equality expressed in Nozicks categorical imperative.

    Goldman notes that recognition of the moral equality of others

    generates a presumption of equality of conditions, which obviously

    does not hold if one is justly allowed to own disproportionate shares of

    the world.14

    The provisio is not impervious to what could essentially be seen as

    coercion, either. Take Jake, who, after having the commons on which he

    subsisted on appropriated by an entrepreneurial individual, faces the

    option of either working for a minimal wage, option A, or starving,

    option B. Assuming the transactions that led to this situation were

    entirely legitimate, then, according to Nozick, if [Jake] is forced to do A

    or B, and A is the only thing it would be reasonable for him to do, and

    12Cohen, above n 2, 21.13Nozick, above n 1, 290-3.14Goldman, above n 3, 835.

  • 8/12/2019 No Man an Island

    6/10

    142 Cross-sections Volume VI 2010

    [Jake] does A, then [Jake] is forced to do A.15Because we may construe

    the case as a transaction of labour, the transaction has been indirectly

    rendered unjust by the fact that action was forced.

    Although Jake may have technically given consent to do A, it cannot besaid that he exercised his freedom to decide. Nozick believes otherwise:

    that the choice of a feasible over an unfeasible action does not render the

    choice illusory.16 Semantics aside, it is clear from a commonsensical

    approach that Jakes choices were indeed limited. Within the realm of

    Jakes abilities or sensibilities, B is a distinctly infeasible option; thus the

    choice is not really a choice at all, and Jake was indeed forcedto do A. It

    is as if one were presented with the option of either walking across the

    street or burrowing under it to get to the other side; the latter is notreally a choice at all, within our ability or sensibility, and we are

    necessarily limited to choosing the former.

    This then suggests that acting on the provisio can violate Nozicks

    theory of rights. Having this problematic provisio so closely intertwined

    with his theory of rights paints in contrast to the sentiments of the

    morally egalitarian imperative a distinctly inegalitarian picture of the

    minimal state. It unclear how the minimal state would react to this clashbetween individual liberty and the acquisition of property rights.17

    Finally, it should be noted that whilst Nozick intended the provisio to

    be a method with which to escape the tragedy of the commons, he has

    failed to show exactly why it is the best system to adopt. As Kymlicka

    states, given the tragedy of the commons, any system of property-

    ownership would pass this test, including state ownership

    *or+

  • 8/12/2019 No Man an Island

    7/10

    No Man an Island Galvin Chia 143

    III External Critique

    From an external perspective, it is unclear how Nozick derives his

    fundamental conception rights. Unlike Locke, who arguably adopts a

    religious, God-given origin to his conception of fundamental rights,Nozick presents no such fundamental derivation.19His specific selection

    of property rights as the basis of his categorical imperative relies heavily

    on the presupposition of the Lockean state of nature. This is an

    optimistic assumption, in which individuals are in a state of perfect

    freedom, and bound by natural rights.20Nozicks adoption of Lockes

    position is an axiomatic one, and is simply treated as a given at the start

    of his work. The sensibilities of taking this state of nature to be

    descriptive of the true state of nature is problematic there is noevidence to suggest why this is necessarily the case, or why, say,

    Hobbes pessimistic views on the state of nature may instead be the

    case.21

    It is also an issue of how Nozick has managed to single out his branch of

    property rights from moral discourse as a whole. Nozick admits that an

    individual is allowed to maintain his own moral considerations: for

    instance, a Singeresque responsibility to others and desire to donatecharitably (though he scorns that such action is irrational).22 Provided

    that these actions do not violate his side constraints, they are legitimate.

    Thus these sets of moral considerations can coexist, and both are equally

    valid Nozick only defends his account on grounds of rationality. It

    seems reasonable enough to extend this condition to a whole host of

    other moral considerations, such as welfare or equality of opportunity.

    The issue then lies in how Nozick has managed to isolate his categorical

    imperative as the most important of moral considerations simple

    assertion is inadequate. Indeed, as Singer notes, Nozicks theory of

    rights does not pronounce on whether the rich ought to give to the

    19Grimes, Alan P., and Robert H. Horwitz.Modern Political Ideologies. 1959 ed. New York:

    Oxford University Press, 69; Goldman, above n 3, 833.20Nozick, above n 1, 10.21Murray N. Rothbard, Robert Nozick and the Immaculate Conception of the State.(1977) 1(1)Journal of Libertarian Studies, 45.22Nozick, above n 1, 268.

  • 8/12/2019 No Man an Island

    8/10

    144 Cross-sections Volume VI 2010

    poor.23 Could not a more-than-minimal state, with welfare functions,

    thus be borne from the philanthropy of individuals like Singer? This

    fundamentally undermines the minimal state; a more extensive state

    could in this way be justified based on the moral consideration of

    others.

    Goldman notes that Nozicks principles place absolute priority of the

    freedom of the individuals over their welfare, and from a

    commonsensical approach this is problematic.24Nozicks lexical priority

    of freedom before welfare suggests, ironically, that we are bound to his

    concepts of freedom. From the Tale of the Slave, this implies that it is

    morally justified if we are free and impoverished, but morally wrong to

    be in slavery and tremendously well off. A system of morals which failsto take into account the welfare of its moral agents is clearly flawed

    how are we to exercise the freedoms that we are entitled to if we are

    physically in no condition to do? By virtue of the definition of freedom

    presented previously, if our condition - in limiting our abilities and

    sensibilities reduces the options available to us from, say, 2 to 1, then

    individual freedom itself has been reduced. What good are your

    property rights, or for that matter, anybody elses, if you are too hungry

    to move? The minimal state, being the unintrusive entity that it is, has

    no answer to this.

    It has been made clear in this paper that Nozicks position on rights and

    the minimal state is an inadequate one. Internally, Nozicks concepts of

    justice in initial acquisition, justice in transfer and the reliance on the

    Lockean provisio have been shown to be inconsistent, and in cases

    contradictory to the themes of individualism and moral equality that he

    sets out in his work. Externally, Nozicks presupposition of the Lockean

    state of nature, the assumption of the paramount importance of

    property rights and the lexical priority of freedom over welfare have

    shown to be problematic, and by and large remain unaddressed. Along

    the way, the minimal state, which was based solely on these shaky

    premises, was shown to be an unconvincing and problematic

    conclusion.

    23Peter Singer, Practical Ethics. (Cambridge University Press, 1979) 173.24Goldman, above n 3, 825.

  • 8/12/2019 No Man an Island

    9/10

    No Man an Island Galvin Chia 145

    Acknowledgments

    I would like to thank Joel Chow for his invaluable ideas and advice

    during the writing process, as well as John Shellard for his time and

    effort in editing the essay.

  • 8/12/2019 No Man an Island

    10/10

    146 Cross-sections Volume VI 2010

    References

    Cohen, G.A, Self-Ownership, Freedom, and Equality(Cambridge

    University Press, 1995).

    Goldman, Alan H, The Entitlement Theory of Distributive Justice.

    (1976) 21Journal of Philosophy73.

    Grimes, Alan P, and Robert H. Horwitz,Modern Political Ideologies

    (Oxford University Press, 1959)

    Kymlicka, Will, Contemporary Political Philosophy(Oxford University

    Press, 2nded,2002)

    Nozick, Robert,Anarchy, State, and Utopia(Basic Books, 1974)

    Rothbard, Murray N., Robert Nozick and the Immaculate Conception

    of the State (1977) 1Journal of Libertarian Studies1

    Singer, Peter, Practical Ethics(Cambridge University Press, 1979)

    Wolff, Jonathan, Robert Nozick, Libertarianism, and Utopia Critiques of

    Libertarianism. . (25

    October 2007) accessed 28 April 2010