MORGENTHAU_Functionalism, Positivism, Int. Law_1940 c

download MORGENTHAU_Functionalism, Positivism, Int. Law_1940 c

of 26

Transcript of MORGENTHAU_Functionalism, Positivism, Int. Law_1940 c

  • 8/10/2019 MORGENTHAU_Functionalism, Positivism, Int. Law_1940 c

    1/26

    Positivism, Functionalism, and International LawAuthor(s): Hans J. MorgenthauReviewed work(s):Source: The American Journal of International Law, Vol. 34, No. 2 (Apr., 1940), pp. 260-284Published by: American Society of International LawStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2192998.

    Accessed: 15/12/2011 12:19

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    American Society of International Lawis collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to

    The American Journal of International Law.

    http://www.jstor.org

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=asilhttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2192998?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2192998?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=asil
  • 8/10/2019 MORGENTHAU_Functionalism, Positivism, Int. Law_1940 c

    2/26

    POSITIVISM,

    FUNCTIONALISM,

    AND

    INTERNATIONALLAW

    BY

    HANS

    J. MORGENTHAU

    AssistantProfessor f Law and

    Political

    Science, Universityf

    Kansas

    City

    If

    an event

    in the physicalworld

    contradicts

    ll

    scientific orecasts, nd

    thus

    challenges he assumptions

    n

    whichthe forecastshave been

    based,

    it

    is the natural

    reactionof

    scientificnquiry o reexamine he

    foundations f

    the specific

    cience

    and

    attempt

    o

    reconcile cientific

    indings

    nd

    empirical

    facts. The social sciences do

    not react in

    the

    same

    way. They have

    an

    inveteratetendency to stick to their assumptionsand to suffer onstant

    defeatfrom xperience ather

    han to change

    their

    ssumptions

    n

    the

    light

    of

    contradicting acts.' This

    resistance o change

    s

    uppermost

    n

    the

    his-

    tory

    of

    international

    aw.

    All

    the schemes

    and

    devices

    by

    which

    great

    humanitarians

    nd shrewdpoliticians

    ndeavored o reorganize he relations

    between tates on the basis

    of

    aw,

    have

    not

    stood the trial

    of

    history.

    In-

    stead

    of

    asking whether he

    devices

    were

    adequate

    to the

    problems

    which

    they were

    upposed to solve, t

    was

    the general

    ttitude

    of

    the

    nternational-

    ists to take the

    appropriateness fthe devices

    forgranted

    nd

    to blame

    the

    factsforthe failure.2 Whenthe facts behave otherwise han we have pre-

    dicted, heyseem to say, too

    bad

    for

    he facts.

    Not unlike

    thesorcerers f

    primitive ges, they attempt

    to exorcise

    social evils

    by the

    indefatigable

    repetition f

    magic formulae.

    As the League

    of

    Nations

    was

    a

    failure, et

    us have

    another

    League.

    As the first

    nd

    second Peace

    Conferences

    f

    the

    Hague didnot

    succeed, et us have a

    third

    ne. As

    arbitration ever ettled

    a

    political conflictwhichotherwisewould have led to

    war,

    et

    us

    have more

    arbitration

    for

    the prevention

    of

    war.

    As

    the Disarmament

    Conference

    was a

    senselesswaste of

    intellect

    and

    time, why

    not convoke

    another

    Disarmament

    Conference?

    It is a strange paradox that the lay public has observed a much more

    sceptical

    and

    realistic,

    hereforecientific,ttitude

    toward

    nternational aw

    than

    the scienceof nternational

    aw

    itself.

    The

    laymen

    weremuch

    quicker

    to

    recognize

    he

    gap between he

    rules

    of

    nternational

    aw

    as

    represented

    y

    science,

    nd

    the rulesof nternational

    aw as

    they

    exist

    n

    actual

    experience.

    The

    breakdown f

    the

    main

    bulk

    of

    post-World

    War

    international aw

    has

    altogether

    estroyed ublicconfidence

    n a

    science

    which,

    nmoved

    by what

    'As to this endency,

    ee LancelotHogben, he

    Retreat

    rom eason

    Conway

    Memorial

    Lecture, ondon, 936);

    Lynd,

    Knowledge orWhat?

    Princeton, 939).

    2See Wild,"What Is theTroublewith nternationalaw?" Am. Pol. Sci. Rev.,Vol.

    XXXII

    (1938),p. 479: "Too oftenn the

    past

    he has assumed

    he ttitude hat

    he

    world

    s

    out of tepwith is aw,

    nd tooseldom as he

    considered

    hepoint

    hat

    perhaps is

    cience

    is

    partly oblame."

    260

  • 8/10/2019 MORGENTHAU_Functionalism, Positivism, Int. Law_1940 c

    3/26

    POSITIVISM,

    FUNCTIONALISM,

    AND INTERNATIONAL LAW

    261

    experiencemay show, invariably

    follows ts preconceivedpattern.3

    This

    breakdown mplies

    the

    practical

    refutation

    f

    the

    ideas which have deter-

    mined he development

    f nternational

    aw in the asthalf-century. Hence,

    the science of internationalaw is now confrontedwith the alternativeof

    maintaining

    he traditionalpatternof assumptions,

    oncepts

    nd

    devices

    n

    spite of the teachings

    of

    history,

    r of revising his

    pattern and

    trying

    o

    reconcile he science

    of nternationalaw and its subject-matter,

    hat

    is, the

    rules

    of

    nternationalaw as they

    are actually applied.4 The present

    writer

    has always held

    that only the latter

    way leads to theoretically orrect

    nd

    practicallyuseful

    results. In thefollowing aper the

    attemptwill be made

    to

    reexamine the

    methodological

    ssumptions

    with

    which the traditional

    science of nternational

    aw starts. These assumptions

    re embodied

    n the

    positivistdoctrine f aw.

    THE LEGAL PHILOSOPHY OF POSITIVISM

    Positivistphilosophy

    estricts heobject

    of

    scientific

    nowledge o

    matters

    that

    can

    be

    verified

    y observation,

    nd thus

    excludes

    from

    ts domain all

    matters

    of an

    a

    priori,metaphysical

    nature.5 Juridicpositivism

    ransfers

    this

    delimitation

    nto

    the

    legal sphere.

    The

    juridicpositivist

    delimits

    he

    subject-matter

    f

    his

    research

    n

    a

    dual way.

    On

    the

    one

    hand,

    he

    proposes

    to deal exclusively

    with

    matters egal,

    and for his

    purpose

    trictly eparates

    the legal sphere

    from thics and mores s

    well

    as

    psychology

    nd

    sociology.

    Hence,

    his

    egalism.

    On

    the other

    hand,

    he restricts

    is

    attention

    within

    he

    legal sphere

    to the

    legal

    rules

    enacted by

    the

    state,

    and

    excludes

    all law

    whose

    existence

    annot

    be traced to

    the statute

    books

    or

    the decisions

    f

    the

    courts. Hence,

    his 6tatistmonism.

    This

    "positive"

    law

    the positivist

    accepts

    as

    it

    is,

    without assing udgmentupon its ethical

    value

    or

    question-

    ing its practical appropriateness.

    Hence, his agnosticism. The positivist

    3

    Professor

    uincyWright

    ouldreportn 1930 Research n

    Internationalaw since he

    War, p. 25):

    "Of

    the twenty urists

    withwhom

    he writer

    as corresponded,nly

    two

    betrayed noteofpessimismt the prospects,nd that n both ases was qualified."

    4Such

    reexamination

    s called

    for

    by

    manywriters; ee,

    for nstance, hilip

    Marshall

    Brown, his

    JOURNAL,

    Vol. 33

    (1939),

    p.

    149;

    Djuvara, Recueil es Coursdel'Acadgmie

    e

    Droit nternationalcited

    hereafters Hague

    Recueil),

    Vol. 64 (1938),

    p.

    485;

    Hudson,

    Proceedings

    f he2nd,3rd, nd 5thConferences

    fTeachers

    f

    nternational

    aw (Wash-

    ington, 925,

    1928, 933),

    pp.

    86 et eq., 2, 94,

    95, respectively; acKenzie, roceedings

    f

    the 6th

    Conference

    f

    Teachers

    f

    nternational

    aw (Washington,938),

    p.

    109;

    Friedman,

    "The Disintegration

    f European

    Civilization nd the Future

    of International aw,"

    ModernLaw Review,

    Vol. 2 (1938),

    p.

    213.

    6

    For the

    characteristics

    f positivist hilosophy,ee Comte,

    Discours ur 1'esprit

    ositif

    (Paris, 1844),

    p.

    41

    et seq.; Mill, AugusteComte

    nd PositivismLondon,1866),

    p. 6 et

    seq.; see especially,he

    excellent rticle, Positivism," y Ruggiero

    n Encyclopedia

    fthe

    Social Sciences, ol.12,p. 260.

    The

    most

    penetratingontemporaneousriticism

    f positivist

    cience s to be found n

    Mortimer . Adler,What

    Man Has

    Made

    of Man (New York,1937), specially

    p. 28, 87,

    97, 131, 132,

    158et eq.,192,233,238 et eq.

  • 8/10/2019 MORGENTHAU_Functionalism, Positivism, Int. Law_1940 c

    4/26

    262 THE

    AMERICAN

    JOURNAL

    OF

    INTERNATIONAL LAW

    cherishes

    he beliefthat

    the "positive" law

    is a

    logicallycoherent

    ystem

    which

    virtually ontains, and

    through mere process

    of

    logical deduction

    will

    actually

    produce,

    ll

    rules

    necessary

    or

    he decision

    f

    all

    possible

    cases.

    Hence, his systemworship nd dogmaticconceptualism.6

    The historic

    mportance

    f the positivist

    chool of

    jurisprudence or

    the

    science

    of

    law

    was fourfold.

    First, positivism

    accepted

    the

    breakdown

    of

    the

    greatmetaphysical

    ystems

    f

    theeighteenth

    nd

    theearly

    nineteenth

    centuries nd

    the

    resulting

    ecadence

    of

    metaphysical

    urisprudence

    s

    an

    established fact. It endeavored to save

    the scientific

    haracter

    of

    juris-

    prudenceby

    eliminating

    rom t all

    metaphysical lements,

    hus

    separating

    it

    from

    he

    discredited

    octrines fnatural

    aw.

    In

    the second

    place,

    posi-

    tivism

    recognized hat the

    subject-matter

    f

    urisprudence

    was

    the

    law

    and

    nothingbut the law, and thatneithernon-legal ubjectsnornon-legal on-

    siderations ould have

    anyplace

    in

    t.

    Furthermore,egal positivism

    earned

    from

    he

    positivist

    movement

    n

    philosophy

    nd

    the natural

    sciences

    that

    scientific

    bjectivity

    s

    dependent

    upon

    an

    object

    intelligible

    n

    experience,

    and

    a

    method aimed at

    knowledge,not

    at evaluation.

    Finally,

    the

    great

    legal

    codifications

    f

    the

    European

    continental

    countries

    nd

    the

    Anglo-

    American

    tatutory aw found n

    positivism

    technique

    of

    interpretation

    and

    representation. This

    technique fulfilled ts

    purpose

    satisfactorilys

    long as

    the social

    and political

    philosophy

    of

    the

    statutes,

    eitherdirectly

    expressed

    by

    them or

    indirectly

    erivedfrom

    hem

    by way

    of

    ogical

    deduc-

    tion,

    was

    sufficiento

    meetthe economic

    nd

    social needs as well

    as the

    polit-

    ical

    demands nd ethical

    requirements f

    a

    given

    ociety

    t

    a

    givenhistorical

    moment.

    To be

    sure, his

    correspondence etween

    he statutes

    nd

    the standardsof

    society

    has

    never

    existed

    ompletely; ven

    under

    tationary

    onditions

    here

    will

    always be a marginal

    sphere which

    does

    not

    allow the

    mere

    logical

    subsumption of

    a

    given case under

    statutory

    aw

    without

    violating

    the

    standards of

    society.

    In

    orderto

    satisfy

    he

    positivist

    ssumptions

    of the

    logical

    completeness

    f

    the

    egal

    order

    nd

    at the

    same

    time

    meet the stand-

    ards of society, hesestandardswere first o be read intothe statutesfrom

    6

    For the

    characteristicsf uridic ositivism,

    ee Finch,Hague

    Recueil,Vol. 53

    (1935),

    p. 557,and

    The Sources f

    Modernnternational

    aw

    (Washington,

    937),p. 20;

    Oppen-

    heim, The

    Scienceof nternational

    aw: Its

    Task and Methods," hisJOURNAL,

    Vol.

    2

    (1908), p.

    333 et seq.;

    Bergbohm,

    taatsvertraege

    nd Gesetze

    ls

    Quellen

    es

    Voelkerrechts

    (Dorpat,

    1876),p. 40 et

    seq.; andJurisprudenz

    ndVoelkerrechtLeipzig,

    892),pp.

    51, 52;

    Kelsen, Die

    philosophischen

    rundlagen

    er

    Naturrechtslehrend

    des

    Rechtspositivismus

    (Berlin,

    928); Pound,"Mechanical

    Jurisprudence,"olumbia

    Law

    Rev.,

    Vol.

    8 (1908),

    p.

    605;

    MorrisCohen,

    "The Concepts f Juridical nd

    Scientific

    aw," Politica,

    Vol.

    4

    (1939),p. 8 et

    eq.;

    Ripert, Droitnaturel tpositivisme

    uridique,"

    nnales

    e a

    Faculte

    e

    Droit 'Aix,nouvelle 6rie,

    No. 1 (Marseilles,

    918),pp. 19,

    20, 32

    et

    eq.;Anzilotti,

    ours e

    Droit nternational,ol. 1 (Paris,1929),p. 18 etseq.;Waline, Positivismehilosophique,

    juridique t

    ociologique,"

    elanges

    arre

    e

    Malberg Paris,1936),p.

    519; G6ny, cience t

    Techniquen

    Droit rivFositifParis,

    915),Vol.2, pp. 15et

    eq., 1,37, 38.

    A

    good urvey

    is tobe found

    n Erim,Le Positivisme

    uridique

    t e Droit

    nternational

    Paris,1939).

  • 8/10/2019 MORGENTHAU_Functionalism, Positivism, Int. Law_1940 c

    5/26

    POSITIVISM, FUNCTIONALISM, AND INTERNATIONAL LAW 263

    which they then appeared to have been derivedby a mere ogical process.

    Throughthe back door of pseudo-logical nterpretation

    he outlawed com-

    pany of natural law and extra-legalvalue judgmentsreentered he legal

    system. This kindof pseudo-logical egerdemain ecamethe predominating

    interpretative echnique of legal positivism n the

    period of its decadence.

    In the last decades of the nineteenth entury he standardsof societywent

    far

    away from he economic, ocial, political, nd

    ethical assumptionsfrom

    which the systemsof statutory aw had started.7 Hence, the positivists

    were compelled o resort o a seriesof pseudo-logicalmakeshiftsn order o

    maintain

    the fiction

    f

    "legal self-sufficiency,"on

    which positivist uris-

    prudencehad founded ts theoretical ystem.

    From three ides thisfictionwas, and still s, under

    ttack. From the one

    side, sociologicaland realist urisprudence, nspiredpartly and indirectly

    by

    the

    original ociologicalpositivism

    f

    Comte,

    does away with he

    artificial

    barriers

    y whichpositivism

    has

    separated the legal

    spherefrom he

    whole

    domain of

    the social sciences o which t actually belongs.

    Thus it destroys

    the positivist ssumptions ogetherwith the positivist

    onclusions.

    From

    the other side, the neo-positivism

    f

    Kelsen's puretheory

    f

    law

    maintains

    the

    basic assumptions

    f

    positivism ut undertakes

    o achieve the positivist

    ends

    by purifying

    he

    egal

    sciencefrom

    ll

    material,

    on-legal lements,

    hus

    eliminating he subject-matter

    f

    positivist rypto-metaphysics.

    Several

    schools

    of

    revived natural

    law,

    as

    well

    as the

    politico-ideological

    power

    of

    totalitarianism, ave joined

    in

    this

    dual

    scientificttack.

    Totali-

    tarianism has ostracized positivist urisprudence

    as a manifestation

    f

    liberalistic ecadence n Germany nd Italy, where

    he domination f uridic

    thought y positivism

    as

    been

    at

    timesalmost

    undisputed,

    nd

    whereposi-

    tivismhas

    exerted

    ts

    most far-reaching

    nd

    fertile

    nfluence

    n

    the develop-

    ment f he

    egal

    science.

    Deprived

    of ts

    traditional

    trongholds y political

    suppression

    nd

    undermined

    y

    scientific

    riticism,

    ositivism

    s no

    longer

    guiding nfluence

    n

    modern

    egal thought.

    POSITIVISM AND INTERNATIONAL LAW

    In

    international

    aw,

    unlike he other

    branches

    f

    egal science,positivism

    is

    still

    a

    determining

    nfluence.

    Ever since

    the

    turn

    of

    the century,

    nterna-

    tionalistshave started with

    positivist ssumptions,

    have followed

    he

    posi-

    tivist

    method,

    nd have

    professed

    dherence

    o

    the

    principles

    f

    positivism.9

    7

    An excellent nalysis f thisdevelopments to be

    found n Bonnecase's istory f

    the

    French kcolede l'Ex6gese."

    a PensFe uridique ranQaise

    e 1804 d l'heure r6sente,ol.

    1 (Bordeaux, 933).

    8

    Roscoe Pound,

    An

    Introduction

    o

    the Philosophy

    f

    Law (New Haven, 1937),

    p. 57.

    9

    Cavaglieri ould write

    n

    1911 ("La Conception

    ositive

    e la

    sociWtdnternationale,"

    Revue 6n. r. pub.,Vol. 18 (1911),p. 260): "Parmi ceuxqui s'adonnent ux 6tudes e droit

    international,l n'est ujourd'hui ersonne ui ne fasse

    pas solennellementrofession'ad-

    h6rerA a nouvelle onception

    ositive u droit. . ."

    Someyears aterRipert ould ay

    (Annales,

    bc.

    it., . 18):

    ". . . cette

    generation

    rofesse

    n positivismeuridique bsolu."

  • 8/10/2019 MORGENTHAU_Functionalism, Positivism, Int. Law_1940 c

    6/26

    264

    THE

    AMERICAN JOURNAL

    OF

    INTERNATIONAL

    LAW

    Neither

    heopposition f

    natural

    aw,'0norKelsen's

    neo-positivist

    riticism,"

    nor,finally, he

    rather mplicit

    riticism f

    egal sociologists,'2

    as been able

    to

    affect

    he

    predominance f

    positivist hought ver

    the

    science of nterna-

    tional law. The PermanentCourtof InternationalJustice till follows he

    time-honored

    seudo-logical method of

    traditionalpositivismwhich

    pre-

    vailed

    in

    the

    jurisdiction f

    the domestic

    upremecourts t

    the turn of

    the

    century. The

    annals of

    hishighest

    nternationalribunal ecord

    no

    nstance

    where

    an

    advocate, like

    Brandeis in Muller v.

    Oregon,13

    dared

    to

    break

    throughthe

    networkof

    positivistformulae,nor of

    any

    majority opinion

    which

    would

    not

    have clung,on a

    veryhigh evel of

    technical

    perfection,o

    the

    traditional

    pattern

    of

    positivist

    rgumentation. When

    Judge Hudson

    looks for

    realistic

    decisionwithrespect o

    international aw

    he has to

    turn

    to the Court of Appeals of the State of New York.14 Compared to mu-

    nicipal

    law,

    internationalaw is in

    a

    retarded stage of

    scientific evelop-

    ment. As

    represented y its

    sanest

    elements, he science

    of

    international

    law still

    tands where he

    scienceof

    municipal aw stoodin

    1910;

    in

    terms

    f

    its

    post-World

    War development, ts

    mostspectacular

    branches,nvaded by

    the

    political

    deology

    of

    Geneva,have gone

    back at least to the

    point

    from

    which

    positivism tarted

    n

    the last decades

    of the

    nineteenth

    entury.

    The collapse of

    the

    nternationalaw of

    Geneva, when

    for

    he first ime ts

    fictions

    were

    confronted

    ith the

    full

    reality,meant

    of

    necessity

    he

    break-

    down

    of

    the science which

    had been only

    its

    ideological

    reflection.

    The

    10

    Professor auterpacht

    Private Law Sources and

    Analogiesof

    International aw

    (London, 927),p. 27, note

    5; p. 58, note 7;

    Oppenheim-Lauterpacht,

    nternationalaw,

    Vol.

    1

    (1937, p. 100)

    defends he opinion hat positivism o

    longer

    dominates he

    science f nternationalaw,

    but has beenreplaced y a new

    doctrine f

    moderate atural

    law. It

    is

    difficulto share hisopinion.

    Natural aw and thepost-warcience f

    nterna-

    tional awhave only his n

    common,hat hey verstep he

    imits f xperience.

    However,

    one woulddo njustice o the

    great

    metaphysicalystems fnatural aw by

    dentifying

    hem

    with

    the

    post-war cience f nternational

    aw. Whereas uarez and

    Grotius

    were

    fully

    awareof the

    aprioristic,

    etaphysicalharacter f their

    ropositionsnd

    had

    good philo-

    sophical easons or dhering

    o them, ost-war ositivism

    elplessly

    onfuses

    eality ndimagination, ish and fact,because no longer oes t possess he scientific eansofdis-

    tinguishing

    etween oth.

    Cf., lso, Laski,The State in

    Theory nd PracticeNew York,

    1935), p. 198; Wild,

    oc.

    cit.,

    . 483 et eq.

    11

    See,

    especially, as

    Problem er ouveraenitaetnd

    die

    Theorie

    es

    Voelkerrechts

    1928).

    12See,

    especially,Max

    Huber,

    Die

    soziologischen

    rundlagen

    es Voelkerrechts

    Berlin,

    1928); Ray,

    Hague

    Recueil,

    Vol. 48 (1934), p.

    631 et seq.;Schindler,bid.,Vol. 46

    (1933),

    p. 229 et eq.;Morgenthau,a

    Notion

    u

    "

    politique"

    t a

    thgorie

    es

    diffgrends

    nternationaux

    (Paris,1933),pp. 37 et eq., 5

    et eq., nd La RkalitMes

    normes,

    n

    particulier

    es

    normes

    u

    droitnternationalParis,

    1934),pp. 139, 140,

    215.

    13

    208 U. S. 412

    (1908).

    An

    excellent ppraisal

    f

    the

    theoretical

    mportance

    fthis

    ase

    is to be

    found n Frankfurter,Hours of

    Labor and

    Realism

    n

    Constitutional

    aw,"

    HarvardLaw Rev., Vol. 29 (1916),p. 353.

    14

    See the

    referenceo

    Cardozo'sopinion

    n Techt v.

    Hughes,

    29 N. Y.

    222,

    241

    (1920),

    in

    Hudson,

    International aw in the

    Twentieth entury,"

    ornell

    aw

    Quarterly, ol.

    10 (1925),p.

    435,note75.

  • 8/10/2019 MORGENTHAU_Functionalism, Positivism, Int. Law_1940 c

    7/26

    POSITIVISM, FUNCTIONALISM, AND

    INTERNATIONAL

    LAW 265

    post-WorldWar science

    of

    nternational

    aw

    sharedthe short-lived

    nd delu-

    sive splendor

    f ts

    politicalmaster,

    nd now shareswithhimthe finaldetec-

    tion

    of

    their

    ommon hamexistence s well as the

    resulting isrepute.

    The

    helplessness f the science of nternational aw in thefaceof those dangers,

    its very

    unawarenessof

    them,

    ts

    sincere self-deception

    s to its scientific

    character,

    re

    perhapsthe gravest

    ndictmentswhich an

    be

    brought gainst

    the scientific

    alue of

    thepositivist

    doctrine

    f

    nternationalaw.'5 The

    fail-

    ure

    of he

    post-World

    War science

    f

    nternational

    aw s not due to

    personal

    r

    accidental circumstances;

    t

    grows

    ut

    of

    the

    very ssumptions

    nd

    methods

    whichhave led

    juridicpositivism

    o

    defeat

    n

    the

    domestic ield.

    Yet, in

    the

    international ield he disastrous onsequences fthe genuineweakness fthe

    positivist

    doctrine

    re doubled

    by

    the absence

    of

    the conditionswhich

    n

    the

    domesticdomain made juridicpositivism t least a temporarynd apparent

    success.

    Juridic

    positivism

    tarts

    with the

    assumption

    that

    its

    subject-matter

    s

    to

    be found

    exclusively

    n the writtenaw of the state.

    Only

    the rulesof

    law,

    and all

    the

    rules

    of law which

    statutes

    and

    court

    decisions

    present

    s

    such,

    are

    the

    material

    with

    which

    the positivist

    doctrine

    has

    to deal. The

    criterion

    f

    the

    existence,

    hat

    is,

    the

    validity

    of

    a

    legal rule, s, then,

    ts

    incorporationnto the written aw

    of

    the state. We do not repeat herewhat

    we have said elsewhere

    f

    the scientific

    alue

    of

    this

    uridic

    monism,16

    nd

    consider nly

    the results

    f

    ts

    being pplied

    to

    the

    rules

    of

    nternational

    aw.

    This criterion or the validity of legal rules means,

    if

    transferred

    o the

    international ield, hat the only

    valid

    rules of international

    aw are those

    which

    re revealed

    by

    the decisions

    of

    courts

    nd

    international reaties

    duly

    ratified

    nd

    not formally evoked. Yet this concept

    s

    at

    once confronted

    with two problems

    for which

    the positivist doctrine

    of

    international aw

    has

    no

    solution. On the

    one

    hand, all rules embodied

    n

    written

    ocuments

    are

    not

    valid

    internationalaw, and,

    on

    the

    other

    hand,

    there

    re valid

    rules

    of international

    aw other than

    the rules

    embodied

    n

    written

    documents.

    The

    positivist

    ormula s

    applied

    to

    international

    aw

    is

    at once too narrow

    and too broad."7

    15

    or criticismfpost-warnternational

    aw, ee especially, eckett, Internationalaw

    in England, Law Quarterly ev.,Vol. 55 (1939),pp. 261, 62, 66; Borchard,his

    OURNAL,

    Vol. 27 (1933),p. 518,Vol. 28 (1934),p.

    108; Hill, bid.,Vol. 23 (1929),p. 617; John assett

    Moore, bid.,Vol. 27 (1933),p. 607; the ame,

    nternationalaw and SomeCurrentllusions

    (New York,1924);

    the

    same,

    "An

    Appeal

    toReason,"ForeignAffairs,ol.

    11

    (1933), ee

    especially p. 548,585;

    the

    ame, Post-War

    nternationalaw," Columbia aw Rev.,

    Vol.

    27 (1927), ee especially . 412.

    16

    See Morgenthau,

    a

    Rgalitg

    es

    Normes,. 106et eq.;

    cf.

    lso, herather nalytical

    han

    critical emarks y Edwin

    D.

    Dickinson,Hague Recueil,Vol. 40 (1932), pp. 337,

    344;

    Siotto-Pintor,bid.,

    Vol.

    41

    (1932),pp. 265,266; Verdross,bid.,Vol. 30 (1929),p. 276.

    17

    To the following iscussion, ee Morgenthau, Positivismemal compris t thgorie

    rgaliste u Droit nternational," glangesAltamira Madrid,1936), p. 3 et seq.; see also,

    Affolter,

    Der

    Rechtspositivismusn der

    Rechtsuissenschaft,"

    rchiv uer

    effentliches

    echt,

    Vol.

    12

    (1896/97), p. 40,

    41.

  • 8/10/2019 MORGENTHAU_Functionalism, Positivism, Int. Law_1940 c

    8/26

    266 THE AMERICAN

    JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW

    The science of international

    aw has not developed a criterion o distin-

    guish,

    n an

    objective

    way, between seeminglynd actuallyvalid rules

    of

    international aw. "One can assert that nine-tenths

    f the traditionaldoc-

    trinesof nternationalaw are not actual internationalaw," said Professor

    GeorgeJellinek

    s farback as

    1905.18

    Declared Professor ppenheim

    few

    yearslater:

    It

    is

    also indispensable

    hat the scienceshould free tself from

    the

    tyranny fphrases.

    As

    things re, there s

    scarcely doctrine f he aw

    ofnationswhich s wholly ree rom hetyranny

    fphrases. . . . Anyone

    who s in touch with the application of nternational

    aw in diplomatic

    practicehears from tatesmen very day the

    complaint hat booksput

    forth anciful octrinesnsteadof he actual rules f

    aw. Now it s

    often

    not difficulto push

    the rrelevant o one sideand to extractwhat s egally

    essential romhewaste ofphrase-ridden iscourse. But there reentire

    areas

    in

    which he tyranny f phrases o turns

    he head thatruleswhich

    absolutely

    never

    were

    rules of aw are represented

    s such.19

    "On no

    subject

    of

    human

    nterest, xcept theology,"

    aid

    JohnChipman

    Gray at about the same time, "has there been

    so much loose writing

    nd

    nebulous

    speculations

    s on

    international

    aw."

    20

    If

    these statements

    were true

    in

    the firstdecade

    of

    the century,

    he

    development

    f

    the post-World

    War

    science

    of

    international aw

    has

    only

    added

    to their significance.

    The

    Covenant

    of

    the League

    of

    Nations,

    for

    instance, s a duly ratified ocumentwhich has never been repealed. But

    has it everbeen valid internationalaw as a whole?

    If not, whichprovisions

    never

    had the quality

    of

    valid legal rules,

    and

    which

    ones lost

    this quality

    in

    the course

    of

    the

    gradual collapse of the institution f Geneva?

    No

    treatise

    of

    the

    law of nations offers

    ny general

    criterion o

    answer

    these

    questions,

    nor do the concrete nswers

    given

    with

    reference

    o

    the

    actual

    validity

    of

    Article

    16

    of

    the Covenant

    reveal

    any

    such

    underlying bjective

    criterion.

    The

    absolute

    denial

    of

    any validity,

    he

    assertion

    of a so-called

    "de facto

    revision,"

    and

    the defense

    of full

    validity,

    re advanced side

    by

    side.21

    Similar

    problems

    rise with

    respect

    o theBriand-Kellogg

    Pact

    and

    the

    Peace Treaties

    of

    1919,

    as

    well

    as

    to

    other

    political treaties,

    uch

    as the

    Pact

    of

    the

    Little Entente,

    alliance

    treaties,

    the

    concepts

    of

    aggression,

    independence,

    ntervention, overnment,

    nd so

    forth.22

    They

    are em-

    18

    System

    er

    ubjektiven

    effentlichenechteTuebingen,905),p. 321; see also

    the even

    strongerriticismyBergbohm,taatsvertraege,.

    8.

    19

    The Future f nternational

    aw (Oxford, 921;firstn German, 911),pp.

    58, 59; see

    also, The Science

    f

    ntemational aw, pp. 315,

    334.

    20

    Nature nd Sources

    f

    the Law (New York,1927;

    first dition, 909),p. 127.

    21

    Cf.,

    for

    nstance, chwarzenberger,

    n The New Commonwealth uarterly, ol.

    3

    (1937/38), p. 263, 360

    et seq.; bid.,Vol. 4 (1938/39), . 60 et eq.;for n excellent

    tate-

    ment ftheproblem,eeKunz, d.,p. 131, ndthis

    JOURNAL,

    ol. 33 (1939),p. 33.

    -'

    An excellent ontribution

    o the understandingfthisproblems to be found

    n

    Baty,

    "The

    Trend

    f

    nternational

    aw," thisJOURNAL, ol.

    33

    (1939),p.

    653 et

    seq.,

    nd

    "The

    Abuse

    of

    Terms," bid.,

    Vol. 30 (1936),p. 377.

  • 8/10/2019 MORGENTHAU_Functionalism, Positivism, Int. Law_1940 c

    9/26

    POSITIVISM,

    FUNCTIONALISM,

    AND INTERNATIONAL

    LAW

    267

    bodied

    n

    written

    ocumentswhichwere duly

    ratified nd

    never

    nvalidated.

    Have they

    ever beenvalid law from

    he beginning,nd what

    has become

    of

    them

    n

    the years

    of

    theirviolation? Are they

    still valid?

    If

    they

    are

    not,

    what destroyed heirvalidity? These are questionswhich he nterpreterf

    domestic tatutes, ubject

    to a rational

    process fvalidation

    nd nvalidation,

    is not likely

    to be asked,

    and hencethe positivist

    doctrine

    f international

    law,

    following he pattern

    of

    domesticpositivism,

    as nothingwithwhich

    o

    answer them.23

    The basic assumption

    of juridic positivism,

    hat its

    exclusive subject-

    matter

    s

    the written

    aw of

    the

    state, eads legal science

    not only to the

    in-

    clusion

    of

    alleged egal

    rules which

    no longerhave

    or

    never

    have had

    legal

    validity,

    but

    also

    to the exclusion

    of undoubtedly

    valid rules of aw.

    Posi-

    tivist jurisprudence, tartingwith the axiom of "legal self-sufficiency,"

    separates

    the aw

    from

    he othernormative

    pheres,

    hat s, ethics nd

    mores,

    on

    the

    one hand, and from he

    social sphere,

    comprehendinghe psycho-

    logical,

    political,

    and

    economic

    fields,on the

    other hand. By

    doing so,

    positivism

    evers

    he

    actual relations etween he

    aw and the

    otherbranches

    of

    the

    normative

    nd social sphere. It proceeds

    on theassumption hat

    the

    law,

    as

    it really s, can

    be understood

    without he normative

    nd social con-

    text

    n

    which t actually stands.24

    From theapplication

    of this assumption

    to international

    aw

    there results

    threefold elimitation

    f

    legal

    research,

    contrary

    o theexigencies

    f

    the

    reality,

    nd hence a threefold

    misconception

    of whatinternationalaw really s.

    1.

    The

    normative

    phere,comprehendinghe

    totalityof rules governing

    a

    given

    society, s one whole with

    regard o thebasic precepts

    t contains.25

    23

    This

    absence f any scientific

    est for

    he validity f the rules

    of nternationalaw is

    responsible

    or he perplexitynto

    which ome

    ofthe foremostepresentatives

    fthe nter-

    national

    awofGenevahavefallen

    nrecent

    ears. Professorcelle,whohadfounded whole

    system

    f

    "positive"

    internationalaw upon

    "international

    olidarity," international

    federalism,"

    nd ike

    "social facts,"n 1937

    rrives t the conclusion

    hatthere s

    no

    such

    thing s

    internationalaw at all.

    "I1

    n'y a plus en Europe

    de droit

    es gens,"he writesn

    theJournal esNations

    No. 1665,

    eb. 28and March1,

    1937). "Il n'y a plusdes

    trait6s."

    "The conclusioneemsunescapable," aysProfessor immern"The Declineof nterna-

    tionalStandards,"nternational

    ffairs,ol.

    17 (1938),

    p. 12), "that positive nternational

    law,

    so

    called,

    as

    no

    claim o thename f aw."

    (See also the ame,The League

    ofNations

    and the Rule

    of

    Law

    1918-1935

    London,1936),p. 94.)

    These scholars, ho

    never ared

    for uch

    "abstract"

    problems s thecriterion

    fthevalidity

    f rule f aw, now

    fallfrom

    one

    error

    nto he

    ther. First, hey ccepted

    he ssumed

    alidityfpost-war

    nternational

    law

    without

    uestion; ow, ince

    t is obvious

    hatthemainbulk

    ofthis o-called

    nterna-

    tional aw never asbeenvalid aw

    at all,they

    dentifyhis roduct

    f heirmaginationith

    the

    mainbulkofpre-warnternational

    aw,which oday

    s as valid

    as it has everbeen,

    nd

    declare hat nternational

    aw simply oesnot

    exist

    24

    "Can we evenunderstand

    nglish aw without oing

    beyond

    he actualrules them-

    selves?"asks Paton n his interestingaper,"WhitherJurisprudence,"olitica,Vol. 4

    (1939),

    p.

    16.

    25

    To

    thefollowing

    iscussion,

    ee Pound, The Partof

    Philosophyn nternational

    aw,"

    Proceedings

    f

    the

    6th nternationalongresss

    f PhilosophyNew

    York, 1927),

    p. 374

    et

  • 8/10/2019 MORGENTHAU_Functionalism, Positivism, Int. Law_1940 c

    10/26

    268

    THE

    AMERICAN

    JOURNAL OF

    INTERNATIONAL

    LAW

    Although

    here

    may be

    in a

    given

    societyparticular

    egal rules

    which

    con-

    tradict

    particular

    thical

    rules

    or

    mores,

    nd vice

    versa,

    he

    main

    bulk of

    basic

    ideals to

    be realized,of ends

    to be

    achieved,and of

    nterestso

    be protected,

    is generally he same in the different ranchesof a givennormative rder.

    Law,

    ethics,

    and

    mores

    upport

    each

    other

    in

    the

    pursuit

    of

    these

    aims.

    Legal rules refer o ethics

    and mores

    or

    he

    determination

    f

    their

    meaning

    and vice

    ersa.26

    The

    guiding

    nfluence,

    owever,

    s

    to

    the

    ideals,ends, and

    interests o be

    pursued by the norms

    under

    which

    a

    given

    society

    lives,

    emanatesfrom

    he

    ethical

    phere.

    From

    t

    law and mores

    eceive

    hefunda-

    mental

    distinctions etween he

    good

    and

    the

    bad,

    the ends

    to be

    advanced

    and

    the

    ends

    to be

    opposed,

    the

    interests

    o

    be

    protected

    nd

    the

    interests

    to be

    repudiated. At the

    base

    of

    any legal system

    here ies

    a

    body

    of

    prin-

    ciples whichincorporate he guiding deas of justice and orderto be ex-

    pounded

    by the

    rules

    of

    aw. The

    intelligibility

    f

    any egal system

    depends

    uponthe

    recognition

    f

    uch

    a

    set

    of

    fundamental

    rinciples

    which

    onstitute

    the

    ethical

    substance

    of

    the

    legal system,

    nd

    shed

    their

    lluminatingight

    upon each

    particular

    ule

    of aw.

    This

    recognition

    s

    relatively asy

    to

    perform

    n

    the

    domestic

    field,

    where

    the

    constitution odifies

    he

    main

    bulk of

    those

    fundamental

    rinciples, nd

    a

    highly

    ntegrated ublic

    opinion provides

    upplementary

    moral

    guidance.

    The task s

    muchmore

    difficult ith

    espect

    o

    nternational

    aw.

    Here

    there

    is

    no body of such

    principles

    eparate

    from

    he

    ordinary

    ulesof

    aw.

    Some

    of thoseprinciples

    may

    be

    only

    partlyexpressed

    n these

    rules;

    others

    may

    not be

    expressed at

    all,

    and

    hence have to

    be

    detected,

    n

    a

    dangerously

    uncertain

    rocedure,

    n

    the

    general

    moral deas

    underlying

    he

    international

    law of

    a

    certain

    ime,

    a

    certain

    civilization,

    r even

    a

    certain

    nation.

    Yet

    the successful earch

    for these

    principles

    s

    as

    essential for the

    scientific

    understanding

    f

    nternational

    aw as of

    any legal system.

    Legal positivism

    s

    unable

    to

    grant

    this

    recognition;

    or

    at

    its basis

    there

    is

    the

    hostility

    o

    all

    matters

    metaphysical,

    hat

    is,

    those

    which

    cannot

    be

    ascertained

    by

    actual

    observation.

    Since

    non-legal

    rules

    have

    generally

    entered hehorizonof the positivist uristas metaphysical ules ofnatural

    law,

    the

    positivist

    s

    inclined o

    identify

    atural aw

    and

    ethics

    as

    such,

    and

    to

    repudiate

    both

    as

    metaphysics.

    However,

    to exclude

    a

    priori

    a

    certain

    subject-matter

    rom cientific

    esearch

    by calling

    t

    metaphysical,

    nstead

    of

    impartially

    xamining

    ctual

    experience,

    s

    to blindoneself o

    a

    preconceived

    idea

    originating,

    ot

    in

    experience,

    ut

    in

    mere

    reasoning,

    nd

    thus

    to

    do

    violence

    o the facts.

    Hence,

    the

    positivist

    oncept

    of

    the normative

    phere

    seq.; Bentwich,

    he

    Religious oundations

    f

    nternationalismLondon, 933), specially

    p. 262 et eq.; Zimmern,

    International

    aw

    and

    Social Consciousness,"ransactionsf he

    Grotius ociety, ol. 20 (1934),p. 25 et eq.; cf., articularly,hebrilliantaperby Schwar-

    zenberger,

    The Rule

    of

    Law and the

    Disintegration

    f the

    International

    ociety," his

    JOURNAL,

    Vol.

    33

    (1939),p.

    56.

    26

    We have dealtwith hisproblemn La RMalitWesNormes, .

    155.

  • 8/10/2019 MORGENTHAU_Functionalism, Positivism, Int. Law_1940 c

    11/26

    POSITIVISM, FUNCTIONALISM,

    AND INTERNATIONAL

    LAW

    269

    itself reveals

    a

    metaphysical

    attitude,

    a kind

    of

    negative

    metaphysics

    which plainly

    contradicts he

    very

    assumptions

    f a positive

    science.27

    Yet positivismhas

    never been quite able

    to live up

    to its legalisticand

    anti-metaphysicalssumptions. The verynature of ts subject-matter as

    compelled t time

    and

    again

    to

    violate

    ts

    own

    assumptions

    nd make

    use of

    fundamental rinciples

    ot

    revealed

    by

    "

    positive

    law. In order

    o give

    at

    least apparentsatisfaction

    o

    these

    assumptions,

    ositivism

    dares to make

    use

    of

    such principles

    only

    under

    the

    disguise

    of

    positivist

    concepts,

    and

    therefore evelops

    a

    fictitious

    method which tries

    by

    pseudo-logical rgu-

    ments to

    derive from"positive,"

    that is,

    written, ules of international

    law

    something hat

    those rules

    do

    not contain.

    The

    interminable nd

    quite

    sterile

    discussions

    on the

    foundation

    f

    the binding

    force

    of

    international

    law are evidence of this word-juggling,ince this is a problemwhich,as

    defined

    n

    the positivist

    erms of

    mutual consent

    and the

    like,

    is

    contra-

    dictory

    n

    itself,

    nd

    hence insoluble

    withinthe

    framework f

    positivism.

    The

    foundation

    f

    the

    binding

    orce

    f

    "

    positive

    law can

    logically

    be

    found,

    not in

    this

    "positive"

    law

    itself,

    ut

    only

    outside

    t.28

    Another xample

    s

    the

    problem

    of

    sovereignty

    s defined and

    solved

    by positivism.

    Here

    again

    a

    fundamental rinciple

    which,by

    its

    very

    nature,

    cannot be derived

    from positive"

    law,but

    fromwhich

    "positive"

    law itself atherderives ts

    meaning,

    s

    to

    be dealt

    with

    as if

    t were

    a

    rule

    of

    "positive"

    international

    law.

    It

    is

    for hese helpless ttempts

    o conciliate ts

    legalistic

    ssumptions

    with actual

    juridic

    experience

    hat the

    positivist

    doctrine

    of

    international

    law

    is

    bound to

    misrepresent

    he

    reality

    of international aw

    and

    to

    fail

    to

    do justice

    to its actual content.29

    2.

    The precepts

    f nternational

    aw

    need not

    only

    to be

    interpreted

    n

    the

    lightof the

    deals

    and

    ethico-legal

    rinciples

    which re at theirbasis. They

    need also to be

    seen within

    he

    sociological

    context of

    economic nterests,

    social

    tensions,

    nd

    aspirations

    or

    power,

    which re the

    motivating

    orces

    n

    the international

    ield,

    nd

    which

    give

    rise to

    the factual

    situations

    forming

    the raw material

    for

    regulation

    by

    international aw.30 The

    correctness f

    27

    or this

    point, ee Liard,

    La

    Science ositive

    t

    a

    m6taphysique

    4th ed., Paris, 1898),

    pp. 38, 57, 72.

    See also

    Ruggiero,

    oc. cit.,p. 261:

    "Not

    only

    the

    extreme

    ifficulty

    f

    maintaining

    tselfn a level trictly ositive

    nd not

    exceeding

    he imits f

    experience

    ut

    also thetendency

    .

    . to

    dentifybjectivity

    ithmateriality,

    ave

    often ausedpositivism

    to range ver

    nto

    materialism,

    hat s,

    nto

    metaphysics,

    n contradictiono

    its own

    pre-

    mises." As

    to the

    pecificegal

    phenomenon

    f

    "positivismnding

    n

    disregard

    f

    positive

    law," ee Lauterpacht,

    n Modern

    heories

    f

    Law

    (London,

    933), p. 132, 33;

    nd

    Morgen-

    thau,Positivisme

    al

    Compris, p.

    3,

    4.

    28

    Strupp,

    Hague Recueil,

    ol. 47 (1934),p. 298; Brierly,

    he

    Law

    of

    Nations London,

    1936),p.

    45.

    29

    Brierly,

    he

    Shortcomings

    f

    International

    aw, p.

    4

    et

    seq.;

    Morgenthau,

    The

    Problem fNeutrality," niversityf Kansas CityLaw Rev., Vol. VII (1939), p. 110;

    Wild,

    oc.

    cit.,

    .

    478

    et

    eq.

    30

    For

    this

    point, ee Brierly,p. cit.,pp. 5, 16;

    Kenneth

    Colegrove,

    roceedings

    f

    the

    5th

    Conference

    f

    Teachers

    f

    nternationalaw, p. 97; Ray,

    Annales

    ociologiques,

    6rie

    ,

  • 8/10/2019 MORGENTHAU_Functionalism, Positivism, Int. Law_1940 c

    12/26

    270 THE

    AMERICAN

    JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW

    thispostulate forthe

    interpretation f municipal aw is today

    self-evident.

    Nobody

    would evertry

    o

    interpretocial egislation

    without eferenceo the

    conflicting

    ocial interests o be evaluated

    and

    the social relationsto

    be

    settled. Nobody would ever endeavorto grasp the legal meaning of eco-

    nomic

    egislationwithoutmaking conomic nterests

    nd conflicts art of the

    reasoning. Even where hereference o the

    underlying conomic nd social

    forces

    nd

    relations

    s not

    always explicit,

    s

    in

    the fieldof

    contracts, he

    sociological

    context s nevertheless

    lways

    referred

    o

    by implication. It

    is

    only

    because

    of

    he

    highly ypical

    character

    f

    the

    factual

    ituations nd

    their

    social

    and

    economic

    significance,

    with which

    everybody

    s

    familiar,

    and

    which are

    completely

    nd

    adequately expressed

    n

    the

    legal rules,

    that the

    merereferenceo

    those

    egal

    rules

    mplies

    he

    consideration

    f

    the social

    and

    economicfactorswhichare at theirbasis.

    It

    was, historically,

    he

    most disastrous error

    of

    positivism

    to

    mis-

    understand

    completely

    this

    implicit

    reference o

    the

    sociological

    context

    which

    every egal

    rule contains. This error an

    be traced back to the tradi-

    tion of the

    pandectists,

    who

    had in

    the

    Roman

    law the

    classical model

    of

    a

    highly

    typified egal systemwhich expressedwith

    perfect ppropriateness

    the fundamental

    nterests

    nd

    relationships

    which can

    arise

    from

    hesocial

    activitiesof men. So

    perfectly

    was

    this sociologicalcontext

    represented

    n

    the abstractions

    f

    the

    Roman

    law,

    that the

    pandectistswere

    only

    too

    prone

    to forgetts veryexistence nd to deal withthose abstractions s with n-

    dependent ogical

    entities.

    So

    did

    the positivists,both

    in

    the municipal

    and

    international

    fields.3' This

    methodologicalerror was of minor im-

    portance

    where

    he

    legal

    concepts

    were

    true abstractions rom

    he interests

    and

    relations

    which

    hey

    were

    upposed

    to

    regulate. When,however,

    hose

    legal

    rules were

    applied

    to

    interests

    nd

    relationsto

    which some

    of

    them

    referred

    nly partly,

    thers

    not at all, that

    methodological rrorwas bound

    to

    have

    a

    disastrous

    nfluence

    pon

    the

    scientific alue

    of

    positivist uris-

    prudence.

    In

    the domestic

    field,

    t

    became instrumental

    n

    distorting he

    legal realityand originating hat positivistconceptualismwith which a

    decadent

    egal

    science

    ttempted

    o

    adapt

    the

    old

    legal

    rules

    o

    new

    economic

    and

    social

    needs,

    but

    at

    the same time

    maintained he

    fictitious

    ssumption

    that the written aw

    already contained, ogically,

    ll

    the rules

    necessary

    for

    the

    solution fthose new

    problems.

    Thus the

    uridical

    pseudo-logic

    ecame

    the artificial

    makeshift

    y

    which

    stationary

    aw

    could

    be reconciledwith

    moving

    ocial

    reality.

    In

    the

    nternational

    ield,

    he

    methodological

    rror

    f

    neglecting

    he

    socio-

    No. 3, p. 14et eq.;cf. specially,heexcellent emarks y Friedman,Modern aw Review,

    Vol.2

    (1938),p. 194;

    nd

    review,bid., .

    81.

    81

    For the nfluencefRoman aw upon ntemational

    aw,

    see Pound,

    oc.

    cit.,pp. 376,

    377; Lauterpacht, rivateLaw Sources,p. 23 et seq.; Alvarez,Nouvelle onception es

    ttudes

    uridiques, .

    47 et

    eq.

  • 8/10/2019 MORGENTHAU_Functionalism, Positivism, Int. Law_1940 c

    13/26

    POSITIVISM, FUNCTIONALISM, AND INTERNATIONAL LAW 271

    logical context f nternationalaw led to even worseconsequences.32 In the

    domestic field, he correspondence etween egal concepts and sociological

    contextwas at least a temporary act, and within his limitthe negligence

    of the sociological contextand the assumptionof the "self-sufficiency"f

    the written aw could be justified.

    In

    the most important branchesof

    international aw this correspondencehas never, and could never, have

    existed.

    The

    sociologicalrelationships nderlying

    hose branchesof

    inter-

    national aw are characterized y their ndividual,non-typical ature.33 A

    political ituation

    n

    the nternational ield s not ikely o repeat tself, ince

    the variety

    f

    factors

    f

    which t is composedmakes for

    n

    indefinite umber

    of

    possible combinations. Hence only

    a

    strictly ndividualized

    rule of law

    will

    be adequate

    to

    t. International aw provides artly

    or

    uch

    ndividual-

    ized rules by restrictinghe application of a rule to one individual case and

    leaving he regulation f imilar uture ases to new egislative fforts. Peace

    treaties are instancesof such individualizedrules

    of

    international

    aw.

    In

    part, however, nternational aw does maintain the

    form

    of

    the general,

    typical

    rule of aw and

    depends

    on

    the

    interpretation

    f the

    rule to

    provide

    the flexible

    meaningwhichthe ever-changing ociological

    context

    requires.

    All political treaties which are intent upon establishingpermanentrights

    and duties between he contracting artiesare of this kind. The same gen-

    erally

    and

    typicallywordedtext may imply quite differentules,according

    to the

    political functionwhich t is supposed

    to fulfill.34Thus one

    is

    able,

    for

    instance, to distinguish hree different eriods

    in

    the history

    of

    the

    Treaties of

    Locarno.35

    Those three periods are characterized by three

    significant hanges

    in

    the normative content

    of

    the rules, resulting

    rom

    changes

    n

    the political context, lthough he wording f the rules remained

    unchanged. The Covenant ofthe League

    of

    Nations,

    as

    a

    whole,

    s

    well as

    particular rovisions, or nstance,Article 6, have been submitted

    o similar

    modifications s

    a

    result of factual sociological developments

    nd not of

    legislative hanges.36

    The same phenomenon ccurs not only

    n

    temporary uccession,

    but

    also

    32

    Reeves,

    roceedingsf he2nd Conference

    fTeachers

    f

    nternational

    aw,pp. 72,

    73.

    33

    This high

    degree f ndividualizations clearly

    ecognized

    y Brierly, ague

    Recueil,

    Vol. 58, p. 16;

    Ray, bid.,Vol.

    48, p. 699; Schindler,bid.,Vol. 46,

    p.

    265.

    34The samephenomenon

    ith egard o municipal

    ocial egislation as been

    xcellently

    described y

    Frankfurter,

    oc.

    cit., p. 369, 370:

    "It is now clearly nough ecognized

    hat

    each case presents

    distinctssue;that ach case

    mustbe determinedy thefacts elevant

    to it; that weare dealing, n

    truth, ot with

    question f aw but the application

    f an

    undisputed ormula

    o a constantly

    hangingnd growing ariety

    f economic

    nd

    social

    facts. Each

    case, herefore,allsfor new nd

    distinctonsideration,

    otonly f hegeneral

    factsof ndustry

    ut the specific

    acts n regard o the employment

    n question

    nd

    the

    specific xigencies

    hich

    alled

    for he specifictatute."

    3

    See Morgenthau,Theoriees anctionsnternationales,"evue e Droit nt. et deLeg.

    Comp.,Vol.

    16 (1935),p. 832.

    36

    See Morgenthau,

    The

    Resurrectionf Neutralityn Europe,"

    Am. Pol. Sci.

    Rev.,

    Vol.33 (1939),p. 473.

  • 8/10/2019 MORGENTHAU_Functionalism, Positivism, Int. Law_1940 c

    14/26

    272

    THE

    AMERICAN

    JOURNAL

    OF INTERNATIONAL

    LAW

    under

    contemporaneous et

    different

    ociological onditions.

    The identical

    text

    of an arbitrationreaty

    r

    non-aggression

    act may

    have quite

    different

    legal meanings,

    ccording

    o the political ituation

    xisting etween

    different

    contracting arties.37 Even one and the same legal rule, as, for nstance,

    Article

    16 of theCovenant,

    ends itself o different

    nterpretations

    ithre-

    spect

    to states living

    under

    different

    olitical

    conditions.38

    The

    positivist

    doctrine

    of

    international

    aw has completely gnoredthis

    particular relationship

    between the

    rules of

    international

    aw

    and

    their

    sociological

    context.

    Positivism transplanted schematically

    the

    highly

    refined ositivist

    method

    of formalist

    nd

    conceptualist

    nterpretation

    nto

    the domain

    of internationalaw.

    This method developed

    under, and

    was

    justified

    by, the specific

    domestic

    conditions

    of

    a

    temporarily

    tabilized

    societywherethere was approximatelyno tension between law and so-

    ciological

    context

    but

    almost

    complete

    rationalization

    nd

    representation

    f

    the sociological

    ontextwithin

    he conceptsofpositive

    aw.

    Schematically

    applied

    to

    a

    law

    and a

    society

    of

    a

    distinctly

    ifferent ature,this method

    was bound

    to

    produce

    entirely nadequate

    results. Wherethe

    experience

    f

    international

    aw showedthat

    an individual ituation

    required

    n

    individual

    interpretation

    f

    the

    legal

    rule,

    the

    positivist

    method

    could not

    fail

    to dis-

    regard

    ll

    individual

    aspects

    of the

    factual

    situation

    and

    concentrateupon

    the

    general

    wording

    f the

    legal

    rule

    which,by

    virtueof ts

    logical

    self-suffi-

    ciency,

    was

    supposed

    to

    contain

    ll

    elements

    necessary

    or

    ts

    understanding;

    and

    to

    thisthe

    referenceo

    the

    sociological

    ontext

    ould

    contribute

    othing.

    An

    arbitration

    reaty

    which

    ubmitted

    ll

    conflicts etween he

    contracting

    parties

    to international

    ribunals

    was

    a

    legal

    documentthat revealed its

    legal significance

    hrough

    ts

    text, .e.,

    another

    step

    towards

    the establish-

    ment

    of

    an

    international

    rder based

    upon respect

    for aw.

    Whether he

    treaty

    was concluded

    between

    Switzerland

    and

    Uruguay,

    or

    Denmark,

    Sweden,

    and

    Norway,

    or Great Britain

    and

    France,

    or

    Germany

    nd

    Poland

    in

    1925, 1935,

    or 1939-these

    were

    "political"

    considerations

    rrelevantly

    lying

    beyond

    the

    scope

    of

    positivist

    nterpretation.39

    3. The positivistdoctrine,by recognizing s internationalaw onlythe

    rules enforced y states,

    excludes

    from

    he

    domain of

    international aw

    all

    rules whose

    validity

    cannot be traced

    to the writtendocuments

    of

    states.

    On

    the

    other

    hand,

    the

    positivist

    doctrine

    annot

    deny

    that

    such

    rules,

    ike

    most rules

    of

    general

    international

    aw, actually

    exist. Confronted

    with

    the

    embarrassing

    ilemma

    of

    violating

    ts

    own

    etatist

    ssumptions

    r of dis-

    37

    Leresche,

    La Crise

    du Droitdes Gens,"

    Rev. nt.

    Franqaise

    u

    Droit

    des Gens,Vol.

    6

    (1938),p.

    303.

    38

    See the

    excellent riticismy

    Barandon,

    as

    System

    er

    politischen

    taatsvertraegeeit

    1918 Handbuch es Voelkerrechts,ol.4), p. 1.

    39

    See author's

    nalysis

    of

    arbitrationreaties

    oncluded

    nderdifferentolitical

    ir-

    cumstances,

    n International urisdiction,

    ts Nature

    and

    its

    Limits in

    German, 929),

    p. 131 et eq.

  • 8/10/2019 MORGENTHAU_Functionalism, Positivism, Int. Law_1940 c

    15/26

    POSITIVISM,

    FUNCTIONALISM, AND INTERNATIONAL LAW 273

    regarding

    n obvious

    part

    of

    legal experience, he positivist doctrinehas

    taken

    refuge

    n a

    concept which

    has

    become

    a

    veritable

    panacea

    for

    its

    theoreticaltroubles. We are

    referring

    o the

    concept

    of

    customary aw,

    whichhas servedfor he traditionaldoctrine f nternational aw as a kind

    of

    collective designation

    or all

    the rules

    of

    international aw the origin

    of

    which cannot directly

    be traced to

    written ources.

    The

    insurmountable

    theoreticaldifficultiesf

    explaining he existence

    of

    a

    so-called

    customary

    law have been

    pointed

    out elsewhere,40nd this is

    no

    place

    to resume the

    discussion. It is sufficiento

    state that

    the

    reconciliationwhich the

    posi-

    tivist doctrine

    s

    able

    to

    establish

    between

    ts

    monist, egalistic ssumptions

    and

    the existence

    of a

    so-called customary aw,

    is

    merely apparent.

    In

    orderto save these assumptions s well as thosefacts, t resorts o a series

    offictions,ike tacit consent,recognition,udicial admission, nd so forth,

    which

    indirectly

    ndeavor to

    attribute

    the

    existence

    of the

    so-called cus-

    tomary

    rules

    of

    nternationalaw to

    the

    egislative

    will of

    states.

    PREFACE TO A FUNCTIONAL THEORY OF

    INTERNATIONAL LAW

    The fundamentalweakness

    of

    the positivistdoctrine

    f

    nternational aw

    lies in its

    inadequacy

    to

    international

    aw

    as it

    really

    s.

    Unfaithful o its

    own

    assumptions,

    t contains t

    the same time more

    nd

    less than

    the actual

    rules

    of

    nternational

    aw,

    which t

    furthermoreubmits o subjective valua-

    tion nthe ight fethical nd politicalprinciples fassumedlyuniversal,yet

    doubtful, alidity.

    A

    truly

    cientific

    heory

    f

    nternational

    aw

    must

    avoid

    these mistakes

    n

    order

    o

    come closer

    o the

    reality.

    It seemsto be a

    logical

    choice

    to call such a

    theory

    by

    the name of realist. There

    are,

    however,

    two

    objections

    to this

    choice.

    On

    the

    one hand,

    the

    increasingdisrepute

    of

    the

    traditional

    doctrine

    f international

    aw

    has

    led

    no

    few

    practitioners

    of this doctrine o demonstrate

    heir loseness

    o the

    reality

    f

    nternational

    law

    by calling

    hemselves realists.

    41

    This misuse

    has

    deprived

    he term

    of its

    distinctive

    haracter

    n

    the international ield.

    On

    the other

    hand,

    realismhas

    become

    a

    collective

    designation

    or

    everal tendencies

    n

    modern

    jurisprudence, ll aiming at replacing,by differentmeans, the fictitious

    legalism

    of

    traditional urisprudencewith

    conception

    nearer o the

    realities

    of the

    law.

    All

    these tendencieshave

    this

    n

    common:

    They

    do

    not

    regard

    the

    legal

    rules

    as

    definitely

    etermined

    by

    their

    legislative

    or

    judicial

    formulation, ut search

    for he

    psychological, ocial, political

    and

    economic

    forceswhich

    determine

    he actual content

    and

    working

    f

    legal rules

    and

    40

    La

    R&UlitM

    es

    Normes, . 89 et eq.;

    for

    riticism

    f the

    doctrine

    f

    customary

    nterna-

    tional aw, seealso,Brierly, ague Recueil, ol.

    58, p. 29; Ray, bid.,

    Vol.

    48, pp. 697,698.

    41

    ee,

    for

    nstance, aufmann, ague Recueil, ol.

    54 (1935),pp.

    319,

    320;

    Scelle, bid.,

    Vol. 46 (1933), p. 691; Verdross,bid.,Vol. 30 (1929), p. 277; Le Fur, n RevuedeDroit

    International,ol.

    17 (1936),p. 7-authors who

    have certainly ot verymuch

    n

    common

    besides

    he

    laim

    f

    being realists." Cf. lso,

    Lundstedt ho, ccording

    o

    Pound,oc. cit.,

    p. 145,qualifies ound,Kelsen, nd Duguit s

    "realists"

  • 8/10/2019 MORGENTHAU_Functionalism, Positivism, Int. Law_1940 c

    16/26

  • 8/10/2019 MORGENTHAU_Functionalism, Positivism, Int. Law_1940 c

    17/26

    POSITIVISM, FUNCTIONALISM, AND INTERNATIONAL LAW

    275

    can be drawn rom hisrecognitionf the functionalelationshipetween

    socialforces nd nternationalaw.44

    I.

    A

    functionalheoryf nternationalawhasto startwith he ecognition

    of the particularlyntimate ature f thisrelationship.45n the domestic

    field,egalrules an be imposed y the groupwhich

    olds he

    monopoly

    f

    organized hysical orce,hat s,theofficialsf he tate. The nternational

    sphere s characterizedy the absence f such group. Internationalaw

    owes ts existenceo identical r complementarynterestsf tates, acked

    by power s a last resort, r,where uch denticalnterests o not exist, o

    a

    mere alance

    f

    powerwhich revents state

    from

    reakinghese ules

    f

    internationalaw. Wherethere s neither ommunityf interests or

    balance

    f

    power, here

    s

    no

    nternationalaw. Whereas

    omestic

    aw

    may

    originaten the arbitrary illof the rule-makinggencies f the state,

    internationalaw s usually he result f objective ocialforces. When,

    n

    the nternational

    ield,

    n

    arbitraryule-makingower ries

    o

    impose

    ules

    supported

    either

    y

    commonnterests or

    by

    a

    balance

    of

    power,

    hese

    rulesnever

    ecome

    alid

    aw,

    or

    gain only phemeralxistence

    nd

    scant

    efficacy;

    he

    history

    f

    herules mbodied

    n

    the

    Treaty

    f

    Versailles

    nd the

    Covenant

    f he

    League

    ofNations s a

    strikingxample

    fthis.

    It is also due to this ntimate elationshipetween ocialforces

    nd

    egal

    rules

    hat

    n

    the nternationalield undamentalhanges

    f

    the

    ocial

    forces

    and, hence, fthe egalrules, ollow ach other t frequentntervalsnd nan

    abrupt, ftenviolent,manner.

    In

    the domestic ield he regulative

    social force ominatingll others

    s

    the

    state. It has

    developed

    ot

    only

    an

    overwhelmingower pparatus, ut

    also

    highly

    efined

    echanisms

    f

    legislative

    nd

    udicial eadjustment,

    hichead

    the

    ocial orces

    nto ertain

    channels

    without isrupting

    he

    legal

    and

    social continuity.Here,

    the

    state

    elects

    n

    authoritativeecisions he socialforces o be recognizedy

    the law. It

    decides o whatextent he

    existingegal

    rules hall

    yield

    o

    changingonditions,o what xtent hey

    hall

    esist hem,

    nd

    n

    what

    ways

    they hall ry o transformhem. In the nternationalield he uthoritative

    decision s replaced y the free nterplay f political ndmilitaryorces.

    This

    makes gradual eadjustment

    f

    the

    aw

    to changing

    ocial

    onditions

    extremely

    ifficult.

    ny

    undamental

    hange

    f

    he ocial

    orces

    nderlying

    a

    system

    f

    nternationalaw

    of

    necessity

    nduces he

    prospective

    enefi-

    ciaries f

    he hange

    o

    try

    o

    bring

    bout

    correspondinghange

    f

    he

    egal

    rules,whereashebeneficiariesf he egal

    tatus uo

    will esist ny hange

    f

    the old

    order. Here

    a

    competitiveontest

    or

    power

    will determine

    he

    44These consequencesan be statedwithin

    he

    imits f this

    paper only

    n

    very

    general

    terms,nd other onsequences aybe revealed hroughpplication ftheprinciples evel-

    oped n the text o special

    problems; ee theenumerationfpossible urther

    onsequences,

    in

    Positivisme alcompris,. 20.

    45

    This relationships clearly

    ecognized y Huber, p. cit., . 9 et eq.;

    Schindler,

    oc.cit.,

    p. 237 et eq.; see also,La

    R6alit6

    esNormes, p. 139, 140,215.

  • 8/10/2019 MORGENTHAU_Functionalism, Positivism, Int. Law_1940 c

    18/26

    276

    THE

    AMERICAN

    JOURNAL

    OF

    INTERNATIONAL

    LAW

    victorious

    ocial

    forces, nd

    the

    change of

    the

    existing

    egal

    order

    will

    be

    decided,not

    through

    legal

    procedure

    rovidedfor

    bythis

    same

    legal

    order,

    but

    through

    conflagration

    f

    conflicting

    ocial

    forces

    which

    challengethe

    legal order s a whole.46

    Where uch

    a

    conflict

    etween

    ocial

    forces nd

    the rulesof

    aw

    exists, he

    character nd

    function f

    the

    whole

    legal

    order

    undergo

    transformation.

    We have

    proposed to call

    this

    relationship

    y

    the

    name of

    "tension,"

    and

    have dealt

    with ts

    legal

    consequences

    lsewhere.47

    II.

    This

    recognition f

    thepeculiar

    relationship

    etween

    ocial

    forces

    nd

    rules

    of

    nternational

    aw

    provides

    he

    clue

    for

    restating,n

    functional

    erms,

    the doctrine f

    the

    validity

    of

    international

    aw.48

    A

    rule

    of

    international

    law

    does

    not, as

    positivism

    was

    prone to

    believe,

    receive

    ts

    validity

    from

    its enactment nto a legal instrument, s, for instance, an international

    treaty.

    There

    are rules of

    nternational

    aw

    which

    are

    valid,

    althoughnot

    enacted

    in

    such

    legal

    instruments,

    nd

    there are rules of

    international

    aw

    which

    are not

    valid,

    although

    enacted

    in

    such

    instruments.

    Enactment,

    therefore,

    s

    no

    objective

    criterion or

    he

    alleged

    validity

    of a

    rule of

    inter-

    national

    aw.

    A

    rule, be

    it

    legal,

    moral,

    or

    conventional,

    s valid

    when

    ts

    violation

    s

    likely

    o

    be

    followed

    y

    an

    unfavorable

    eaction, hat

    is,

    a

    sanc-

    tion

    against

    its

    violator. An

    alleged

    rule,

    the violation of

    which is

    not

    followed

    by

    such a

    sanction,

    s a

    mere

    dea,

    a

    wish,

    a

    suggestion,

    ut

    not a

    valid

    rule. An

    alleged

    rule

    of

    international aw, against the violationof

    which

    no

    state

    reacts,

    nd

    is

    likely

    o

    react,

    s

    proved,

    by

    this

    very

    absence

    of

    probable

    reaction,not to

    be

    a valid

    ruleof

    nternational

    aw.

    The

    gradual

    invalidationof

    the

    territorial

    rovisions f

    the

    Treaty

    of

    Versailles,

    nd

    of

    most

    articles f

    the

    Covenant of

    the

    League

    of

    Nations,

    by

    violation nd

    non-

    interventionf

    sanctions

    against

    these

    violations,

    re experimental

    roof

    of

    the correctness f

    this

    concept

    of

    validity.49

    How,

    then, are

    we to

    know

    beforehandwhen

    such sanctions

    re

    likely

    to

    intervene

    n

    behalf f

    a

    violated

    norm,

    nd

    when

    not,and,

    hence,how

    are

    we

    46

    Thisproblem, hich efersothevalidity f nternationalawand tsdynamicspects,

    should

    be

    clearly

    istinguishedrom

    he

    problem

    iscussed

    upra,

    under

    ar.

    2.

    There

    we

    had

    to do

    with

    hequestion

    s to

    how n

    the

    nternationalield

    he

    particular

    haracter-

    istics f

    the

    social

    context

    re

    representedn

    the

    material

    oncepts

    f

    the egal

    rules.

    47

    On

    the

    theoryf

    ntemational

    tensions,"

    ee

    Morgenthau,

    nternational

    urisdiction,

    p.

    59 et eq.;

    andLa

    Notion

    u

    "Politique," .

    37 et

    eq. This

    theory as

    been

    thoroughly

    discussed y

    Ray,

    Annales

    ociologiques,6rie

    , No.

    1

    (1935),p. 163et

    eq.

    48

    As to

    the

    problem f

    the

    validity

    f

    nternationalaw,

    see

    Morgenthau,

    a

    R6alit6

    es

    Normes,p.

    28 et

    eq., 12 et

    eq.

    Professor

    imasheff,

    n

    ntroduction

    o

    the

    Sociologyf

    Law

    (Cambridge,939),

    p. 271,

    alls

    he heory

    eveloped here n

    "artificial

    onstruction."

    However,t

    seems

    o usthat

    he

    rtificiality

    fthis

    heorys

    only he

    reflex f

    he

    artificial

    character f nternationalaw tself; s tothis heoryfvalidityngeneral, ee hisremarks,

    ibid., p.

    142,

    166, 99,

    300. The

    psychological

    echanism

    nderlyinghe

    validity

    f

    nter-

    national

    aw is

    well

    described y

    Baty n

    thisJOURNAL,

    ol. 33

    (1939), p. 653.

    49

    For the

    relationship

    etween

    anctions

    nd

    validity,ee

    also,

    "

    Th6orie es

    Sanctions

    Internationales,"

    oc.

    cit., p. 474

    et

    eq., 09 et

    eq.

  • 8/10/2019 MORGENTHAU_Functionalism, Positivism, Int. Law_1940 c

    19/26

    POSITIVISM,

    FUNCTIONALISM, AND

    INTERNATIONAL LAW 277

    to

    say,

    in

    an

    objective,

    cientific ay,whichnorms

    re valid and

    which re

    not?

    The

    consideration fthe functional

    actorwill give the

    answer.

    1.

    The commonest nd

    simplest est for

    hevalidityof an

    alleged

    rule of

    international aw is this: State A has, in the past, requestedState B to per-

    form ertain

    ctions correspondingo the

    rule,

    whereasState B, inturn,has

    requested State A

    to performertain

    ctions

    corresponding o the same or

    another rule.

    Where these

    identical or

    complementary nterests

    n

    the

    mutual observance of these

    rules did

    not suffice o guarantee the actual

    observance,both

    states were

    willing o enforce

    ompliancewith the

    rule

    by

    protest, eprisal,

    r military ction.

    Wherethere

    was, in thepast, a recog-

    nized

    identicalor

    complementarynterest

    n a certain ction on

    the part of

    two or

    more

    tates, ogetherwith he

    willingness o enforce his

    action,

    here

    exists he ikelihoodhat thesamesanctions or hesake ofthesame nterests

    will also

    be

    performed

    n

    thefuture.

    Respect forthe status of

    diplomatic

    representativesas been, n

    the past, an

    interest ecognized nd

    guaranteed

    with anctions

    by

    all

    states;therefore,he

    forecast s justified hat the

    states

    will

    follow he same

    courseof

    action in the future.

    The

    enactment f rules

    corresponding

    o such interests n international

    treatiesmay indicate

    thepermanent

    ature of those nterests, ut this

    s

    an

    assumptionwhichneeds

    supportfrom he facts and

    whichcan be

    disproved

    by

    them.

    Another

    ndication

    of the permanenceof

    such interests s

    their

    sublimation nto

    moral principles,which

    pretenduniversalvalidity and

    endeavor

    to give

    certain nterests f

    exceptional mportance

    justification

    superior

    to that

    which theycould derive

    from he law.

    2.

    The situation,however,

    s not

    always so simple. Three

    possible situ-

    ations

    present

    hemselves or-

    xamination. It can be

    that:

    (a)

    Identicalor

    complementarynterestsurvive he

    willingness

    o

    enforce

    the

    actions

    corresponding o

    them. The

    provisions of the

    Treaties

    of

    Locarno were the

    function fidentical

    and

    complementarynterests f

    the

    contracting arties.

    When

    Germanyviolated these

    treatiesby

    remilitariz-

    ing the Rhineland,

    the interests f the

    signatories n

    the demilitarization

    survived theirwillingness o enforce an attitude corresponding o their

    interests, nd thus

    the respective rules

    of international aw

    lost their

    validity.

    (b)

    The

    willingness

    o

    enforce ertain

    actions corresponding

    o identical

    or

    complementarynterests

    urvives the

    interests hemselves. The

    provi-

    sions of the

    Treaty of

    Versailles

    establishing he German-Polishfrontier

    fromthe outset

    did not correspond o

    the interestof

    both states. These

    provisionswereobservedfor

    period of twentyyears

    because thereexisted

    a

    balance of

    power between

    both nations

    and theirrespective

    llies,

    which

    prevented ither f themfromviolating he law.

    (c)

    The

    interests nd

    thewillingness o

    enforce heactions

    corresponding

    to

    them

    disappear

    altogether. In this

    categorybelong the

    French-Russian

    and

    German-Italian

    military lliances, the

    Pact of the Little

    Entente,

    the

  • 8/10/2019 MORGENTHAU_Functionalism, Positivism, Int. Law_1940 c

    20/26

    278

    THE

    AMERICAN

    JOURNAL

    OF INTERNATIONAL

    LAW

    political

    provisions

    f the

    Covenant

    of the

    League of Nations, and

    numerous

    provisions

    fthe

    Peace

    Treatiesof

    1919.

    What

    does

    the

    analysis

    of

    these

    cases

    show withregard

    o the

    validity

    of

    internationalaw? In the cases (a) and (c) the rules of international aw

    become

    invalid according

    o

    the functional oncept

    of validitybecause

    no

    longer

    does there

    exist

    a likelihood

    of sanctions

    being

    performed,

    hould

    those

    rulesbe

    violated.

    In

    case

    (b)

    thevalidity

    ofthe rules depends

    upon

    a

    balance ofpower,

    which

    may

    be

    stable

    for certain

    ime,

    nd then uddenly

    become

    unstable,

    but

    which

    n

    our

    time s

    of a ratherpermanently

    nstable

    and precarious

    nature.

    All cases have

    this in common,

    that

    they

    make

    forecasts

    s to

    the likelihood

    f sanctions

    extremely

    ncertain.

    The

    enact-

    ment of the

    rules

    n

    international

    reaties

    s here of

    no

    avail, and,

    as con-

    temporaneousexamples have amply shown,is rather misleading. Their

    conformity

    ithmoral

    principles

    s scarcely

    more lluminating

    ecause

    of

    the

    aforesaiddifficulty

    f

    ascertaining

    he exact

    moral natureof such

    principles.

    Where

    the

    functional

    elationships etween

    sociological

    forces

    nd

    inter-

    national

    aw

    is

    in a

    state

    of

    transition

    rom 1) to

    one of the situations

    nder

    (2)

    the development

    may as

    well stop

    at an

    intermediate

    oint between

    (1),

    on

    the one

    hand,and (2

    a)

    and (c), on

    the other;proceed

    to (2 b); or,

    finally, ome

    to an end

    at (2

    a) or (c).

    Here,the validity

    of the respective

    rules

    of international

    aw is,

    so to

    speak,

    in

    suspense,

    and

    may be

    as well

    maintainedor destroyed. Withrespectto such rules the scienceof inter-

    national

    aw becomes

    system

    f guesses,

    njoying

    greater r esser

    chance

    of

    being proved

    true according

    o the

    factual

    development

    f the

    functional

    relationship

    etween

    he

    social forces

    nd

    the rules

    of nternational

    aw.50

    III.

    It

    follows

    rom

    his

    analysis

    that

    thereexist

    two

    obviously

    different

    types

    of international

    aw,

    one founded upon

    the

    permanent

    and stable

    interests,

    he

    other based upon

    the temporary

    nd fluctuating

    nterests

    f

    states.5"

    This differentiation

    s

    not only

    of fundamental mportance

    or he

    understanding

    f the

    validity

    of

    nternationalaw;

    it

    leads

    to

    yet

    more

    far-

    reaching onsequences s to thesubject-matter,

    he

    methods,

    nd

    the

    scien-

    tific

    haracter

    f the

    science

    of nternational

    aw. One

    might

    ven

    say

    that

    it leads

    to the recognition

    f

    two

    different

    ciences

    of

    nternational

    aw

    which

    deal

    with different

    ubject-matters,

    nd

    apply,

    or

    rather

    ought

    to

    apply,

    different

    ethods

    f res