Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s...

download Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

of 15

Transcript of Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s...

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    1/36

    Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera Author(s): Rebecca ZorachSource: Critical Inquiry, Vol. 34, No. 1 (Autumn 2007), pp. 190-224Published by: The University of Chicago PressStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/526092 .

    Accessed: 06/06/2015 04:54

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

     .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of 

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

     .

    The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Critical

     Inquiry.

    http://www.jstor.org

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ucpresshttp://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/526092?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/10.1086/526092?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=ucpress

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    2/36

    Critical Inquiry  34 (Autumn 2007)

    2007 by The University of Chicago. 0093-1896/07/3401-0008$10.00.All rights reserved.

    190

    For kind help in gaining access to the EdgarWind Archivein Oxford, I am most grateful to the

    assistanceand advice of Jon Whiteley, Jas’ Elsner,ElizabethSears, and Consolato Latella. Nanci

    Young provided archival materials from Smith College. Thanks are due to the numerous readers

    and interlocutors who have refined my thinking on this essay, in particular, audiencesat the

    College Art Association, DukeUniversity,and the KunsthistorischesInstitut in Florence.Advice

    from LaurenBerlant andthe board of  Critical Inquiry has been especially thoughtful and

    pertinent. I was privilegedto benefit from the commentsand suggestionsof—among others—

    DaisyDelogu, Nicole Lassahn, Lucy Pick, Lisa Voigt,Peter Parshall,Ethan Matt Kavaler, Randi

    Klebanoff, Bob Williams, PatriciaSimons, Michael Cole, JamesG. Turner, Hans van Miegroet,

    PatriciaLeighten,Mark Antliff, Annabel Wharton, Kristine Stiles, Hannah Baader,Gerhard Wolf,

    Darrel Rutkin, Lia Markey,KatherinePoole, Rainbow Porthé, and the students in my neo-

    Platonism seminar.This essayis dedicated to the memory of Margaret Wind, whose careful

    archivingenabled this project to come to fruition.

    Unless otherwise noted,translations from German are my own.

    1.   Erwin Panofsky, “Introductory,” Studies in Iconology: Humanistic Themes in the Art of the 

    Renaissance (Oxford, 1939), p. 8. “Introductory”was revised as Panofsky,“IconographyandIconology:An Introductionto the Study of Renaissance Art,”Meaning in the Visual Arts: Papers in and on Art History (Garden City, N.Y., 1955), pp. 26–54.

    Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; or, WhatEdgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera 

    Rebecca Zorach

    In the middle decades of thetwentieth century, somethingknownas neo-Platonism became a privileged interpretive toolfor thestudyof Renaissance

    art. Associated witha contemplative method of hierarchicalascentto higher

    meaning, it resonated with the iconographic method propounded byErwin

    Panofsky, in which the scholar was to work toward increasing abstraction

    through three layers of interpretation: the pre-iconographic, the icono-

    graphic, and the iconological (or  “iconography in a deeper sense” ).1 Neo-

    Platonism offered historical justification for scholars seeking meaning

    beyond the surface of images; it came to be an emblem of the iconographic

    methodology of the Warburg Institute and its affiliates (including Panof-

    sky), but it stretched much further than that. Art historytextbooksstillbear

    the imprint of what Horst Bredekamp has called a “fashionable trend” of 

    This content downloaded from 62.204.192.85 on Sat, 6 Jun 2015 04:54:15 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    3/36

    Critical Inquiry / Autumn 2007 191

    2.   Horst Bredekamp, “Götterdämmerung des Neuplatonismus,”Kritische Berichte 14, no. 4(1986): 42; hereafterabbreviated“G.” The termin German is Modewelle. Thanks to Ethan Matt

    Kavaler for pointing this article out to me.3.   See, for example, David R. Coffin, “Tintoretto and the MediciTombs,” Art Bulletin 33 (June

    1951): 119–25, and uses of the term in Phyllis Pray Bober and Ruth Rubinstein, Renaissance Artists and Antique Sculpture: A Handbook of Sources (London, 1986).

    4.  As he puts it, Botticelli’s Primavera is one of only three “witnessesfor the prosecution”(Kronzeugen), along with Dürer’s MelencoliaI  and Titian’s so-calledSacred and Profane Love  (“G,”p. 40).

    mid-century scholarship; they invariably make reference to neo-Platonism

    in discussions of Florentine humanism, Botticelli, and Michelangelo.2 In

    that context the phenomenon is synonymous with what medieval and Re-

    naissance commentators might have called allegory:Christianizedreadingsof classical themes in art. The mid-century’s “neo-Platonism” also dema-

    terialized images and, frequently, desexualized them, both indicating and

    masking homoeroticism, especially in the case of Michelangelo. Neo-Pla-

    tonism became a catchall term to characterize the standardintellectual bag-

    gage of medieval and Renaissance Europe to the extent that concepts like

    harmony or the system of the four elements or any Renaissance instanceof 

    the revival of antiquity could be characterized, in a very general way, as

    “neo-Platonic.”3 Because of what we might call its abuse, by the 1970s the

    term had fallen out of fashion. In his 1986 article Bredekamp noted that it

    had lost its signal role in our understanding of the meaning of Renaissance

    art (see “G,” p. 39).

    Bredekamp argues that Panofsky, Edgar Wind, Ernst Gombrich, andothers originally saw iconology and its preoccupation with the classical tra-

    dition as a bulwark against Nazism, but that neo-Platonism was “the wrong

    fortress [die falsche Burg],”  an esoteric dead end (“G,” pp. 39, 40).4 But to

    say this is perhaps to blame these authors unfairly for the assumptionsthat

    grew up in the wake of their work—assumptions that softened and sim-

    plified neo-Platonism, producing a domesticated version of what was ac-

    tually a complicated and often internally conflicting set of esoteric

    philosophical ideas. Neo-Platonism is not a word used in the Renaissance

    or before; what it refers to is, as the founders of the approach knew, a mul-

    tilayeredobject, beginning with late antique Alexandriancommentatorson

    Plato (Plotinus and his following) and extending to a revival of interest in

    their work and in that of Plato in the Italian Renaissance and beyond. In

    R ebecca  Zorach  is an associate professor of art history and the college at the

    University of Chicago. She is the author of  Blood, Milk, Ink, Gold: Abundance and 

    Excess in the French Renaissance  (2005). She is currently working on an exhibitionon early modern prints of Rome and an essay on relations between France and

    Thailand in the late seventeenth century.

    This content downloaded from 62.204.192.85 on Sat, 6 Jun 2015 04:54:15 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    4/36

    192 Rebecca Zorach / Botticelli’s  Primavera

    5.  Edgar Wind, Pagan Mysteries in the Renaissance (1958;New York, 1968),pp. 8, 238; hereafterabbreviated PM. Recent work on Wind includesthe projectof editing his unpublished (oruntranslated) papers (The Eloquence of Symbols and The Religious Symbolism of Michelangelo) aswell as an excellent German collection of essays on him,Edgar Wind: Kunsthistoriker und 

    Philosoph, ed. Bredekamp(Berlin, 1998).6.  E. H. Gombrich, “Botticelli’s Mythologies: A Study in the Neo-Platonic Symbolism of His

    Circle,” Symbolic Images: Studies in the Art of the Renaissance (London, 1972), p. 37; hereafterabbreviated “BM.”

    7.  See Raimond van Marle, The Developmentof the Italian Schools of Painting, 19 vols. (TheHague, 1923–38),12:76.

    8.  The painting is painted in tempera overa gessoground on a support made of sevenpoplarpanels, approximatelysix by ten feet (the scaleof a tapestry!). Twenty-oneplant species are

    identifiable on the ground; the trees include orange, laurel and myrtle; see Mirella Levi d’Ancona,Botticelli’s Primavera: A BotanicalInterpretation Including Astrology, Alchemy, and the Medici (Florence, 1983).

    fifteenth-century Florence a group of scholars, principally Marsilio Ficino

    and Giovanni Pico della Mirandola and their circle, devoted substantialat-

    tention to these lateantiquecommentators. TheAlexandrianGreekauthors

    and the Italians (who wrote mainly in Latin) are now referred to as neo-Platonists. We tend to assume that part of their intention was to reconcile

    classical philosophy with Christian belief. But with this commentary tra-

    dition also came a heady mix of mysticism and esoteric knowledge that are

    distinctly un-Christian. Ficino’s writings—the main body of Florentine

    Platonism—are rich and complex; they are full of references to Plato and

    Aristotle and their commentators, but also to medicinal formulae based on

    herbs, minerals, and the stars. Wind, in his 1958 book  Pagan Mysteries in 

    the Renaissance, cites Pico’s description of ancient writings possessing “co-

    piousness of matter and . . . multiformity of religion . . . occult philosophy 

    and strange foreign mysteries.” Wind concludes by characterizing Renais-

    sance neo-Platonism as a “manifest eccentricity” thatnonethelessproduced

    great art.5

    There may be a no more extensively examined case of neo-Platonism

    than Sandro Botticelli’s tapestry-like Primavera  (fig. 1). Its sculpted forms

    and hauntingly impassive faces, set within a forest glade, have likelyinspired

    moreinterpretive labor thananyother quattrocentopainting. AsGombrich

    put it in 1945, “Anyone interested in problems of method can do no better

    than to study the conflicting interpretations of the ‘Primavera’ and the dis-

    cussions which centredround them.”6 Already in 1931, a scholar hadreacted

    with irritation to the quantity of ink spilled about the painting.7 It depicts

    Venus at the center of a dance of figures: from left to right, Mercury, the

    three Graces, Venus (with Cupid floating above her), and Flora, Chloris,

    and the wind-god Zephyr. Interpreters have connected the painting to nu-

    merous classical literary texts, to contemporary love poetry, and,especially,

    to festivals—as well as to neo-Platonic ideas.8 It is now assumed that it was

    This content downloaded from 62.204.192.85 on Sat, 6 Jun 2015 04:54:15 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    5/36

         f     i     g     u

         r     e

       1 .

         S   a   n

         d   r   o

         B   o    t    t     i   c   e

         l     l     i     (   1   4   4   4  –   1   5   1   0

         ) .     P    r     i    m    a    v    e    r    a     (   p   o   s    t   r   e   s    t   o   r   a    t     i   o   n

         ) .     U     ffi   z     i .

         P     h   o    t   o   :

         S   c   a

         l   a     /     A   r    t

         R   e   s   o   u   r   c   e

     ,     N     Y

     .

    This content downloaded from 62.204.192.85 on Sat, 6 Jun 2015 04:54:15 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    6/36

    194 Rebecca Zorach / Botticelli’s  Primavera

    9.  See Aby Warburg, “Sandro Botticelli’s Birth of Venus and Spring: An Examination of Concepts of Antiquity in the Italian EarlyRenaissance,”The Renewal of Pagan Antiquity:Contributions to the Cultural History of the EuropeanRenaissance, trans.DavidBritt(1893; Los

    Angeles, 1999), pp. 88–156.See alsoMatthew Rampley, “From Symbol to Allegory: Aby Warburg’sTheory of Art,”Art Bulletin 79 (Mar. 1997): 41–55, and Georges Didi-Huberman,Devant le temps:Histoire de l’art et anachronismedes images (Paris, 2000) and L’Image survivante: Histoire de l’art et temps des fantômes selon Aby Warburg (Paris, 2002).

    10.   See Creighton Gilbert, “On Subject and Not-Subject in Italian Renaissance Pictures,”Art Bulletin 34 (Sept.1952): 202–16.

    11.   Charles Dempsey,The Portrayal of Love: Botticelli’s “Primavera”and Humanist Culture at the Time of Lorenzo the Magnificent (Princeton, N.J., 1992), p. 7. Dempseyargues that Botticelli’s

    painting constitutes a pictorial analogue to a new form of humanist literaturein which vernacularforms(for example, praise of the beloved as in medieval love poetry)are broughtto the level of universality (here, a generalized principleof love, Venus Physica ) through classicalreferences.Ivan

    painted in the late 1470s or early 1480s and that it was commissioned either

    by or for Lorenzo di Pierfrancesco de’ Medici, the older of the two younger

    second cousins of Lorenzo di Piero de’ Medici, called the Magnificent, who

    served as theguardianof hiscousinsandadministratorof their considerablefortune. The Primavera  (along with the Birth of Venus ) was the subject of 

    Aby Warburg’s doctoral dissertation, in which he argued for strong con-

    nections between the painting and Agnolo Poliziano’s Stanze. More than

    this, though, he suggested that artists and writers of the fifteenth century 

    looked to antiquity for thedepictionof movement—arguing thisin contrast

    to the prevailing Winckelmannian notion that associated Renaissance clas-

    sicism with static harmony.9 Warburg’s interpretation was literary and, in

    a sense, formal, with form understood not in a surface or stylistic sense but

    as a deeply rooted cultural resource. Those who followed in his footsteps—

    Wind, Panofsky, Gombrich—added neo-Platonism, specifically Ficino’s

    writings, to help understand the painting’s iconography.

    Gombrich, for his part, collected fifteen different readings of the paint-ing’s affective portrayal of Venus as part of his argument that there was

    something inexhaustibly haunting about the painting: “These puzzlingand

    wistful faces give us no rest until we have built around them a story which

    seems to account for their enigmatic expression” (“BM,” p. 38). But, as

    Creighton Gilbert argued, Gombrich never actually explained thisaspect of 

    the work.10 I will argue in what follows that the painting’s haunting quality 

    may instead be the result of a formal asymmetry that bears an equivocal

    meaning—if not of the accumulated ghosts of so many pastinterpretations.

    Among these, Wind’s, in Pagan Mysteries in the Renaissance, has been one

    of the most tenacious of the neo-Platonic camp. I am not alone in consid-

    ering his treatment of the painting compelling (if not entirely complete);

    Charles Dempsey, author of the most prominent recent scholarly treatment

    of the painting, The Portrayal of Love, acknowledges thatamong thevarious

    neo-Platonic readings Wind’s “certainly deserves primacy.”11 As Dempsey 

    This content downloaded from 62.204.192.85 on Sat, 6 Jun 2015 04:54:15 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    7/36

    Critical Inquiry / Autumn 2007 195 

    Tognarini focuses on the “muse” to whom Warburg drew attention, SimonettaVespucci, and on

    the bride of Lorenzo di Pierfrancesco,Semiramide Appiani. See Ivan Tognarini,L’identità e l ’oblio:Simonetta, Semiramide, e Sandro Botticelli (Milan, 2002). Giovanni Reale, Botticelli: La “Primavera”o le “Nozze di Filologia e Mercurio”? (Rimini, 2001), proposesa philosophicalallegory.An argument that the painting represents politicalharmonyamong different Italian cities has

    been proposed by Enrico Guidoni, La “Primavera” di Botticelli: L’armonia tra le città nell’Italia di Lorenzo il Magnifico (Rome, 2005). Lilian Zirpolo sees the painting as addressedto Semiramideherself as does Michael Rollmann,who does not cite Zirpolo.See Lilian Zirpolo,“Botticelli’sPrimavera : A Lessonfor the Bride,”in The Expanding Discourse: Feminism and Art History, ed.

    Norma Broude and Mary Garrard (New York, 1992), pp. 101–9, and Michael Rohlman, “Botticellis‘Primavera’:Zu Anlaß, Adressat und Funktion von mythologischenGemälden im FlorentinerQuattrocento,”Artibus et Historiae, no. 33 (1996): 97–132.

    notes, it is to Wind that we owe the essential insight that identifies the triad

    of figures to the right of the panel. Zephyr, by raping the virginal nymph

    Chloris, transforms her into the fecund Flora, nymph of flowers and fields.

    In this paper I propose what I believe is a compelling new interpretationof Botticelli’s famous painting. Suspicious of the impulse to find answers

    to a picture’s mysteries in a single detail, however, I use my interpretation

    as a point of departure to aska new setof questions—aboutthe relationship

    of art to philosophy, of eros to power, and about the gaps that remain when

    we reduce art-historical methods to a conflict between formalism and his-

    toricism or between iconology and social history. The seeds of my inter-

    pretation appear in the works of thosemid-twentieth-century scholars who

    made the painting into an object lesson in iconological interpretation. Be-

    fore addressing the painting directly, however, I begin with a case study of 

    a different sort, drawn from the context in which these same interpretive

    methods developed. In contrast to the apparent beauty and harmonyof the

    Primavera, this will be a case study in conflict: specifically, that of Wind’sdebates with “Chicagoschool” critics and Great Booksadvocates in hisbrief 

    stay at the University of Chicago in the 1940s. Wind will also be my chief 

    interlocutor in considering Botticelli’s painting. The lectures that were to

    form his Pagan Mysteries of the Renaissance  were given across the U.S., and

    at Chicago they became part of a controversy whose details highlight

    broader issues at stake in midcentury debates inAmericaneducation.I hope

    to show here how these pedagogical issues can illuminate the “mysteries”

    Wind studied in his 1958 book. The painting, in turn, prompts a reconsid-

    eration of the status of the early modern image and the quandary of art

    history’s own complicity with the power and violence that produces, some-

    times, things of beauty.

    Pagan Mysteries in Chicago

    Wind is most often associated with Warburg’s intellectual legacy and

    with his years as the first professor of art history at Oxford in the 1950s and

    This content downloaded from 62.204.192.85 on Sat, 6 Jun 2015 04:54:15 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    8/36

    196 Rebecca Zorach / Botticelli’s  Primavera

    12.   LikePanofsky, Winddrew his conceptionof the symbol largely fromErnst Cassirer’s theory of “symbolic forms,” produced in dialoguewith Warburg. See Ernst Cassirer, The Philosophy of  Symbolic Forms, trans.Ralph Manheim and John Michael Krois, 4 vols. (New Haven, Conn., 1953–

    96).13.   Wind and Gombrichwere to differ on the statusof the irrational in Warburg’s work. See

    Wind, “On a Recent Biography of Warburg,” in The Eloquence of Symbols: Studies in Humanist Art, ed. Jaynie Anderson (Oxford, 1993), pp. 106–13.

    14.  See EdgarWind, “Heı̂oyUóby (Laws, II, 671D): On Plato’sPhilosophy of Art,” The Eloquence of Symbols, pp. 1–20.

    15.  Ibid., p. 9.16.   NicholasXenos has recently argued that Leo Strauss’s sympathywith fascism (apart fromits

    anti-Semitism)alreadyappears in writings frombefore he left Germany. See NicholasXenos, “LeoStrauss and the Rhetoricof the War on Terror,” Logos  3 (Spring 2004), www.logosjournal.com/issue_3.2/xenos.pdf 

    1960s, where his lectures created a sensation and packed theaters. Trained

    as a philosopher before becoming an art historian, he waged a long battle

    in his work in aesthetics and intellectual historyand in hishistoricalstudies

    of Renaissance art on behalf of the symbol and against formalism in boththeoretical and pragmatic terms.12 Following Warburg and mindful of 

    Plato’s “divine fear” of the power of art, he insisted on the complexity of 

    symbols and a constant, vital, and sometimes risky tension between reason

    and ritual (with Warburg, he believed ritual and magic tapped into pow-

    erful, irrational forces within the human psyche).13 In his inaugural lecture

    as a Privatdozent  at the University of Hamburg in 1932, he explainedPlato’s

    rejection of the plastic arts not as a rejection of a degraded copy of a copy 

    (as it appears in the Republic ) but as a recognition of the dangers posed to

    theutopian republicby thepower of artto move humanhearts and minds.14

    Running throughout Wind’s work is an insistence that some conflicts of 

    values are nontrivial, that legitimate values may come into conflict in ways

    that cannot be resolved by a simpleevaluation of priorities. Inthe Hamburglecture, he raised the question of “whether everyone who is confronted by 

    conflicting values must not decide to make a sacrifice in one direction or

    another—a sacrifice through which he defines the form of humanity in

    which he believes and to which he commits himself.”15 That is, one legiti-

    mate value may need to be sacrificed to another. This position reflects the

    increasingly dire political situation, the rise of Nazism, met with compla-

    cency or support by some of Wind’s intellectual contemporaries.16

    Wind had been Panofsky’s first dissertation student in Germany. After

    finishing his dissertation, he took the unusual step of spending three years

    in the United States, first in New York and then at the University of North

    Carolina. He returned to Germany in 1927 to complete his Habilitation and

    soon met Warburg. His time in the U.S. accounts for the fact that he con-

    sidered C. S. Peirce along with Warburg as his two great intellectual influ-

    This content downloaded from 62.204.192.85 on Sat, 6 Jun 2015 04:54:15 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    9/36

    Critical Inquiry / Autumn 2007 197 

    17.  Hutchins intervened withthe draft board to preventWind from being drafted. See Wind,letterto Robert Maynard Hutchins,5 Dec. 1942,and Hutchins, letterto Wind, 7 Dec. 1942, folder2, box 2, Presidents’ Papers, 1940–46,University of Chicago Archive,University of Chicago,

    Chicago (UCA).18.   Anne Stevens alludes to this problem in her“The Philosophy of GeneralEducation and Its

    Contradictions: The Influence of Hutchins,” Journal of General Education 50, no. 3 (2001): 182.

    ences. In 1933 Hitler’s racial laws cost him his university appointment, and

    he moved with the Warburg Institute to London, becoming its deputy di-

    rector under Fritz Saxl. In 1939, he undertook what was intended as a short

    trip to the United States; with war intervening and then a falling-out withhisWarburg colleagues, he wasto live there more or less full-timeuntil 1955,

    spending the last ten years as a research professor at Smith College before

    moving on to Oxford.

    In the U.S. in 1939 Wind quickly fell into an alliance with men involved

    in a revolution in American higher education—among them Robert May-

    nard Hutchins, the young president of the University of Chicago. War was

    on everyone’s minds—especially as professors as well as students began to

    be drafted—and therefore the issue of defining “the form of humanity in

    which [they] believe[d]” was particularly charged.17 The often-heated de-

    bates over educational philosophy were concerned with nothing less than

    the fate of modern civilization. Hutchins and his allies were in the process

    of establishing undergraduate curricula in Great Books, which were in-tended to counteract disciplinary overspecialization and lack of attention

    to philosophical issues that, theybelieved, should equip young mento shape

    society. They took aim in particular at the empirical social sciences and in

    general at pragmatism and professionalization. Despite initial friendly re-

    lations, it may have been inevitable that with Wind’s interest in American

    pragmatism he would come into conflict with the architects of the reaction

    against it in American universities. There is, as many have observed, a ten-

    sion at theheart of theGreat Books philosophy: to itsproponents, theGreat

    Books represented ideas, not history. And yet these books are treated as a

    set of sacred texts authorized by tradition.18 For Wind, as a Jewish intellec-

    tual exiled from Nazi Germany, the new curriculum’s rejection of articu-

    lated historical understanding coupledwitha covert appeal to traditionmay 

    not have seemed such a promising way of addressing the state of Western

    civilization.

    To the Great Bookspartisans, I think, Wind simply represented a classical

    European education. In 1939, at the instigation of Stringfellow Barr and

    Scott Buchanan, who were then in theprocessof revamping thecurriculum

    of St. John’s College in Annapolis, Wind lectured there for a semester on

    Renaissance art. Early warning signs of incompatibility with the exponents

    This content downloaded from 62.204.192.85 on Sat, 6 Jun 2015 04:54:15 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    10/36

    198 Rebecca Zorach / Botticelli’s  Primavera

    19.  Margaret Wind, note,folders i–iii, boxI, 7, EdgarWind Archive,BodleianLibrary,

    Universityof Oxford, Oxford (EWA).20.   Wind developed a group of American friends of the Warburg Institute, eventually securing

    various offers of a temporary home, which forced the hand of the University of London and

    enabled the institute to find a permanent homethere. From 1939 to 1945, he reported to theWarburg Institute;in addition to giving numerouslectureseries, he gave seventy-threeindividuallectures at a wide variety of locations.

    21.  Wind had met McKeon at Columbia in his first American visitin the 1920s andrecommended McKeon to Panofsky when he moved to the U.S. Buchanan and Barrwarned that

    he wouldnot get alongwith McKeon at Chicago.See Wind, letter to Saxl,10 Apr. 1943, folder ii,box I, 5, EWA.

    22.  See Richard McKeon, letters to Wind, 3 Dec. 1941and 10 Dec. 1941,and letter to Hutchins,10 Dec.1941, folder 11 “[Correspondence regarding] Wind, Edgar1937–1944,”box 68, Richard

    McKeon Papers, UCA.23.   See Secretary of the Board of Trustees, letter to Wind, 24 Feb. 1942, folder i, box I, 8, EWA.24.   Hutchins’s proposalhad been accepted, but a motion to rescindit failed narrowly, 58–58,

    with Hutchinscasting the 58th vote. See Milton Mayer, Robert Maynard Hutchins: A Memoir 

    (Berkeley, 1993), p. 241. See also James SloanAllen, The Romance of Commerce and Culture:Capitalism, Modernism, and the Chicago-Aspen Crusade for Cultural Reform (1983; Boulder, 2002),p. 105.

    of Great Books came when he found that, as Margaret Wind later put it,

    “Buchanan, enamoured of the Platonic Idea, wished him to talk about art

    without contaminating thought by showing pictures on a screen.”Presum-

    ably while waiting for St. John’s to acquire a lantern slide projector, he“spent some peaceful afternoons eating oysters on Chesapeake Bay.”19

    Wind’s initial plan had been, as he put it, “spreading the gospel” of the

    Warburg Institute, its scholarly projects, its dire financial circumstances,

    and its need for a permanent home. After the stint at St. John’s he lectured

    incessantly for three years, all over the U.S., as the institute’s ambassador.20

    Constant travel took a toll, and he wrote in the fall of 1941 to Richard

    McKeon, dean of Chicago’s humanities division, to take him up on an offer

    to teach there.21 McKeon’s initial response was equivocal (he cited a budget

    crisis), but it was quickly followed by another, more favorable, letter.22 By 

    February 1942, Hutchins had formally invited Wind to take up a position

    at Chicago.23

    Wind arrived at a contentious time. Hutchinsbelieved thatby reformingundergraduate education at Chicago he could help guide American edu-

    cation toward the pursuit of values rather than the accumulation of facts.

    In April 1942, Hutchins cast a tiebreaking vote in the university senate to

    pursue changes in the college, giving it greater autonomy and allowing it to

    award a four-year BA based on “general education,” in other words, the

    Great Books.24 Basic humanities courses were promptly revamped. While

    a 1940 humanities textbook provided historical context organized chron-

    ologically and included such chapter titles as “TheMacedonianEmpire and

    the Hellenistic Age” and “The Spread of the Protestant Reformation,” the

    This content downloaded from 62.204.192.85 on Sat, 6 Jun 2015 04:54:15 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    11/36

    Critical Inquiry / Autumn 2007 199

    25.  See University of Chicago, Introductory General Course in the Humanities, Syllabus, ed.Hayward Keniston, FerdinandSchevill, and Arthur P. Scott (Chicago,1940); Universityof 

    Chicago, the College, Humanities 2: Suggestions for the Analysis of Drama and Fiction (Chicago,1944); and University of Chicago, the College, Humanities 2: Syllabus and Selected Readings (Chicago,1945). Humanities1, 2, and 3 replaced the general introductory course; of the three,Hum 2 is the closest analogue to it.

    26.   EdgarWind, “Statementby Wind on the McKeon trouble, possibly to be submitted to theCommitteeon Policy,”p.3, cover sheet dated6 Sept. 1943, folder 17, box 46, John U. Nef, Jr. Papers,UCA. In the same folder, see alsoMcKeon, letterto John Nef, 31 July 1943.

    27.   Wind, “Statementby Wind on the McKeon trouble,possiblyto be submitted to the

    Committee on Policy,” p. 4.28.  Nef dealsdirectly with what he calls the “pagantradition” in Germany in his The United 

    States and Civilization (Chicago, 1942), pp. 102–3.

    analogous book in 1944 consisted of literary texts organized by genre and

    supplemented by brief methodological essays.25 The philosopher and clas-

    sicist McKeon was the architect of the new course, Humanities 2 (Hum 2),

    which contributed to Wind’s dissatisfaction at Chicago. McKeon was him-self a contentious figure. While intermittently a Hutchins ally, he also pub-

    licly opposed some of Hutchins’s schemes for the university. McKeon

    argued for a neo-Aristotelian rationalist approach based on a notion of the

    universality of the rational soul, which in pedagogical terms might be char-

    acterized with the single word method.

    From the perspective of Renaissance art history, Wind clashedmostcon-

    spicuously with McKeon over the title of a series of public lectures he was

    to give. As dean of the humanities division, McKeon had invited Wind to

    lecture on “something in Renaissance art and culture,” suggesting that

    Wind supply the specific title. Wind agreed and gave his title: “Pagan and

    Christian Mysticism in the Art of the Renaissance.” McKeon, ever the ra-

    tionalist, replied that the word mysticism displeased him and that he wouldprefer   elements  or   influences.26 When Wind would not budge, McKeon

    claimed that Wind was trying to substitute other lectures entirely for the

    ones he had asked for. Wind later wrote,

    I did not think that I needed to explain to Mr McKeon what I intended

    to explain to the audience, namely, that I was using the word ‘mysti-

    cism’ in the strict technical sense employed by Renaissance authors and

    artists when they contrast a ‘mystical image’ with a ‘literal statement’ . . .

    Since this is, in my opinion, the common denominator between such

    varied expressions of Renaissance art as are to be found in the works of 

    Botticelli, Mantegna, Raphael, Michelangelo, Titian, Tintoretto and

    even El Greco, it seemed to me a suitable subject for a general course of public lectures.27

    On a basic level any whiff of paganism or mysticism must have called up

    fears of the nationalism of Hitler’s Germany.28 But McKeon and his allies,

    This content downloaded from 62.204.192.85 on Sat, 6 Jun 2015 04:54:15 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    12/36

    200 Rebecca Zorach / Botticelli’s  Primavera

    29.   Fora Hegelian reading of abstractionin modernpainting,see Robert Pippin, “What WasAbstract Art? (From the Point of View of Hegel),” Critical Inquiry  29 (Autumn 2002): 1–24.

    30.   See Gilbert, “On Subject and Not-Subject in Italian Renaissance Pictures,”p. 211.

    31.   See “InstructionsConcerning Lectures,Readings,and Discussions for the General Coursein the Humanities(Humanities 2),” Sept. 1942, folder 17 “Humanities 2,” box 38, Richard McKeonPapers, UCA.

    I think, liked the idea  of the Renaissance better than they liked the Renais-

    sance itself. What was it that mid-twentieth-century educators saw in the

    Renaissance? It sometimes seems that the Renaissance carries no other cul-

    tural content than an assertion that change happens; it is a paradigm forhistorical change that can be mobilized to support the values any particular

    writer seeks to propound. In the mid-century U.S. it signified the much-

    vaunted “rise of the individual.” Accompanied, in the world of contem-

    porary (American) art, by the rise of “pure” painting, the Renaissance

    prefigured the ascendancy of painting as medium.29 This is evident, for in-

    stance, in Gilbert’s intelligent but flawed responseto iconography, “OnSub-

     ject and Not-Subject in Italian Renaissance Pictures,” in which he argued

    for the existence of a Renaissance notion of pure (subjectless) painting: Re-

    naissance painting nicely suited to modernist tastes.30 Modern scholarssaw 

    the Renaissance as a period of secularization in which art andthoughtpried

    themselves from the realm of religious ritual as individualspried themselves

    from submersion in collectivity. One edition of the Humanities 2 courseinstructions declared, for instance, that “the humanists of the Renaissance

    conceived themselves to be engaged in an attempt to liberate the study of 

    things human and natural from subjugation to theology and the study of 

    things divine.”31

    From the view then generally held, it would be easy to understand the

    Primavera  and other paintings like it as exemplary of Renaissance sensibil-

    ity. First given the name  Primavera  by Vasari and symbolically indicating

    the springtime of Renaissance revival itself, Botticelli’s pagan dance looks

    far removed from the concerns of Christian representation. For the first

    time, painted images appeared to stand alone and to invite a kind of 

    contemplation not directly connected to religious worship. For twentieth-

    century humanists, Renaissance Italy offered a moment of the reorgani-

    zation of pedagogy much like what they themselves were seeing, and

    sometimes pushing, in education. McKeon’s friend and ally Ronald Crane,

    chair of the English department, had written in 1935 that

    it would be necessary to have properly prepared students as well, and to

    give us these there is required something like a renaissance in general

    education at the level of the high school and junior college. Perhaps

    such a renaissance is coming, bringing with it the revived study of the

    This content downloaded from 62.204.192.85 on Sat, 6 Jun 2015 04:54:15 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    13/36

    Critical Inquiry / Autumn 2007 201

    32.   R. S. Crane,“History vs. Criticismin the Study of Literature,” English Journal 24 (Oct. 1935):666.

    33.  See McKeon, Culture, Education, and the Arts, vol. 2 of  SelectedWritings of RichardMcKeon,

    ed. Zahava K. McKeon and WilliamSwenson (Chicago, 1998), p. 117. A distinctmedievalismpermeatedthe university duringthe Hutchins revolution; Hutchins was a Thomist, and McKeonbelieved in a scholastic systemof educationwith a strongly Aristotelian character.

    34.   Once the committee became a degree-grantingunit, its brochure describedits mission as

    follows: “Thesubject matter for considerationis the broad general conceptionswhich have beenoffered as to the nature of manin society, as to the course of historical change, as to the majorendsof living and the circumstancesunder which groups of men definesuch ends,and as to methods of social action chosen or advocatedfor realizing those ends.”The fields represented included

    anthropology and sociology; politics, economics, jurisprudence, and ethics; and education,psychology, and human development (Wind, “Report 1939–1945”to the Warburg Institute, folderi, boxI, 5, EWA; see alsofolders i and vi, box I, 7).

    classics in some form or other, bringing with it also the renewed cultiva-

    tion of those ancient arts of reading and writing upon which any criti-

    cism of literature worthy of the name must be firmly based.32

    To many Great Books sympathizers, the Renaissance had stripped away 

    the outmoded baggage of scholasticism and established rhetoric and ver-

    nacular literatures as suitable subjects of study. McKeon’s position, how-

    ever, was more ambivalent. On the one hand, the revolution in education

    at Chicago was largely a return to “classics.” Understood in this way, the

    Renaissance might provide an analogy for the pedagogical project upon

    which the university had embarked. On the other hand, McKeon saw in the

    Renaissance the lossof something significant aboutmedieval educationand

    specifically scholasticism: method. He believed that a primary weakness of 

    modern education stemmed directly from the Renaissance—the replace-

    ment of knowledge as method (the medieval trivium andquadrivium) with

    knowledge as content, in other words, subjects of specialized study (liter-ature, natural sciences, history).33 McKeon took an approach that, in a sub-

    stantial way, reversed rather thanimitated “theRenaissance”:it reinstituted

    method. For a series of public lectures, he might simply have wanted a cele-

    bration of the rebirth of learning, illustrated with pictures.

    Similar conflicts emerged in the design of Ph.D. fields in the Committee

    on Social Thought. Social Thought was a new entity that corresponded,on

    the divisional level, to the changes Hutchins was making in the College. It

    had been established to enable cross-disciplinary work in social theory; its

    driving force was John U. Nef, an economic historian who became Wind’s

    closest friend at Chicago. Later, Social Thought would be associated with

    Leo Strauss (who arrived in 1949) and would become the refuge for the

    Great Books philosophy after the College curriculum shifted away from it.But in 1943 it was an elite group that embodied, in polite form, many of the

    university’s debates.34

    This content downloaded from 62.204.192.85 on Sat, 6 Jun 2015 04:54:15 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    14/36

    202 Rebecca Zorach / Botticelli’s  Primavera

    35.   It was approved by the committee in December1942. See Nef, letterto Wind, 29 Dec.1942,

    folder17, box 46,JohnU. Nef, Jr. Papers, UCA.36.   Wind, “Renaissance Studies,” folder ii, box I, 8, EWA.37.   Concernedprimarily with the survival of antiquity in its very aliveness, movement,and

    formal-empatheticeffects, Warburg did not focuson the issueof a purported but spurious

    genuineness of that or any othertradition. The conflict most crucial for Warburg’s reading of Renaissance classicism is the internaltension that we can characterizein a shorthand way asDionysian-Apollonian.

    Wind was asked to join the committee upon his arrival at Chicago and

    produced a memorandum on how the study of art might be integrated into

    the program of study in Social Thought. In it he discussed at length the

    philosophicalquestion of the existence of aesthetic universals andproposeda range of topics that clearly derive from the preoccupations he shared with

    Warburg: “the relation of the ‘fine arts’ to folklore and magic”; “the tradi-

    tional veneration and fear of the artist”; “origins and history of the term

    ‘genius’ as applied to the artist”; “origins andhistory of theterm‘aesthetics’

    as applied to art”; “the evolution of canons” for different styles and genres

    of art—wherein he refers to a “growing distrust [one shared by him] in the

    dismissal of whole periods of art as ‘decayed’ or ‘undeveloped’”—and sev-

    eral others. While this discussion was not incorporated into Social

    Thought’s published program—and it is not clear what reception it got—

    Wind’s description of the field of Renaissance studies did become part of 

    the official program.35 It promptly provoked controversy. In it, he wrote,

    The student will be expected to form an idea of the general problem of 

    cultural revivals, of which the historical period called the Renaissance is

    only one among many examples. The common characteristic of these

    revivals is that the revolt against a given tradition is coupled with the at-

    tempt to re-instate an older, supposedly more “genuine” tradition, so

    that revolutionand restitution go hand in hand. To trace the manner in

    which the traditional and novel features interpenetrate and reinforce

    each other, is the central problem of Renaissance studies.36

    Wind’s description of the Renaissance thus takes it as an instance of a

    more general problem of history and insists upon a dispassionate view of 

    what he calls the“supposedlymore‘genuine’ tradition.” This isnot a simple

    transposition of Warburgian ideas; it is, I think, a more skeptical formu-

    lation than Warburg would have used.37 It’s tempting, therefore, to read

    Wind’s comment as a subtle digat the GreatBooksapproach, oneinformed

    by his reactions to the rise of German nationalism and its uses of history to

    construct a notion of authentic, “Aryan” Germanness. Of course, Wind

    would not, in anyfacile way, have equatedtheAmericanpreoccupationwith

    the Great Books with the Nazis. Yet he clearly shows an inclination to cast

    This content downloaded from 62.204.192.85 on Sat, 6 Jun 2015 04:54:15 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    15/36

    Critical Inquiry / Autumn 2007 203

    38.  Crane, letterto Nef, 18 Feb. 1944, folder ii, box I, 8, EWA.39.   In the case of the New Critics the generalization would be about the nature of poetry,for

    example, irony as a master trope. Cranedivides criticisminto two modes, to the first of which“belong all the criticalsystems that find it necessary, in order to givean understandingof artisticworks or to account for the valuesthey contain, to place them in a context of some kind inclusiveof morethan the works themselves.” The second seeksthe poem’s individuality; its content arises

    “from the embodiment in the medium of an individualform” (Crane, “TheTwo Modes of Criticism,” Dec. 1937, typescript,pp. 2, 12, folder6, box 1, R. S. Crane Papers, UCA).The sameargument with respect to the New Criticsappears,for instance, in his “Prefatory Note” to twoessays by Maclean and Charles Olsonin The University Review [University of KansasCity] (Spring

    1942): 199–202 and in his “Cleanth Brooks; or, the Bankruptcy of Critical Monism,”Modern Philology 45 (May 1948): 226–45.

    40.  Crane, letterto Nef.

    a critical and historically complex eye on the interpenetration of old and

    new. Wind’s views appeared, to some of his colleagues, to overdetermine

    questions of method. On seeing the program description Crane wrote to

    Nef, labeling Wind’s approach “obscurantist”:

    What you are really proposing, therefore, is a kind of a priori history in

    which one and only one among many possible—and equally plausi-

    ble—formulae for the Renaissance period is to be imposed on the inter-

    pretationof the intellectual and artistic works the student considers. . . .

    [In] the absence from your program of any of the basic arts of interpre-

    tation and criticism, the students who are exposed to such a course of 

    historical study are likely to come out with a great many general conclu-

    sions which they will be unable either to defend intelligently or to relate

    to the conclusions of other scholars working with different principles of 

    explanation.38

    “A priori” is an important term for Crane, who used it to characterizeevery critical method other than his own. Though the methods of Chicago

    critics themselves bear some resemblance to New Criticism, Crane lumped

    the latter together with historicism. He believed they both fell into the trap

    of beginning with a generalization or a “monism” and from it moving to

    the particular, rather thanbeginning withan individual caseand proceeding

    inductively.39 Wind, he thought, was imposing content that would over-

    determine the process of interpretation. Instead, method should follow the

    “basic arts of interpretation and criticism” (then called, for literature as for

    art, “formal analysis”). Crane goes on to say that the Renaissance “has suf-

    fered peculiarly (witness the tradition of Burckhardt) from this mode of 

    ‘Geistesgeschichte’ and I can therefore understand the difficulties your

    Committee has faced in attempting to evolve a fresher and more genuinely critical approach; but I should hope that it is not part of your intention to

    carry over the same or a similar method to the study of the other historical

    fields.”40

    This content downloaded from 62.204.192.85 on Sat, 6 Jun 2015 04:54:15 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    16/36

    204 Rebecca Zorach / Botticelli’s  Primavera

    41.   See Wind, introduction, trans. Richard Newald, KulturwissenschaftlicheBibliographie zumNachleben der Antike, in A Bibliography of the Survival of the Classics, ed. Hans Meier, Newald, andEdgarWind (London, 1934), pp. vii–viii. The second section of the introduction is entitled “Kritik 

    der Geistesgeschichte.”42.   Gombrich, Art and Illusion: A Study in the Psychology of Pictorial Representation (1960;

    Princeton,N. J., 1972), p. 20. Jas’ Elsner points this out in his “From EmpiricalEvidenceto the BigPicture: SomeReflections on Riegl’s Concept of  Kunstwollen,” Critical Inquiry  32 (Summer 2006):

    741–66.43.   “TheField of Renaissance Civilization,”folder ii, box I, 8, EWA. A later version of the same

    prospectusincorporatedCrane’s points. See folder 1, box 61, John U. Nef, Jr. Papers, UCA.

    In characterizing Wind’s approach as “Geistesgeschichte,” Crane was

    unaware of the fact that Wind had spent several paragraphs of his intro-

    duction to the Warburg Library’s Kulturwissenschaftliche Bibliographie on a

    “Kritik der Geistesgeschichte.”41

    In the context, Crane’s use of the Germanterm suggests an allusion to Nazi Germany:  Geistesgeschichte  insisted on

    cultural-historicalhomogeneity, a racialism presumedto be mirrored in the

    political realm by Nazism (this despite the fact that Wind was himself a

    refugee). In a similar vein, in Art and Illusion, first published in 1960, Gom-

    brich would complain that art history, in “inculcating the habit of talking

    in terms of collectives, of ‘mankind,’ ‘races,’ or ‘ages’. . . weakens resistance

    to totalitarian habits of mind.”42 The relationship between the particular

    and the general was subtly politicized, such that the imposition of general

    upon particular was a mark of totalitarian thought.

    Crane and McKeon were allied as members of SocialThought’s subcom-

    mittee on “Eighteenth-Century European Civilization.” Within the same

    brochure, the description of the study of the eighteenth century pointedly states that “emphasis will be placed on theinterpretation of importantwrit-

    ingsin their ownterms, aidedby therelevanttechniquesof analysis,without

    undue simplification of their arguments, and without any presupposition

    as to the general character of the age in which they appeared, and without

    commitment to any particular philosophical position.”43 Here, method

    reigns supreme. Writings are to be interpreted in their own terms, without

    regard to historical position. The description of eighteenth-centurystudies

    has nothing to say about the eighteenth century; instead, it is a rebuke to

    the description of Renaissance studies. If Wind takes the period as a whole

    as his object, he does not, however, presuppose a prevailing “spirit of the

    age” specific to the Renaissance but rather emphasizes internal conflicts.

    Crane was not able to see this emphasis, ironically, because he applied a

    generalization about the tenor of Germanic scholarship to the individual

    case of Wind.

    McKeon’s and Crane’s concern with method, with “teaching how to

    read,” could both coincide and conflict with Hutchins’s view of education

    This content downloaded from 62.204.192.85 on Sat, 6 Jun 2015 04:54:15 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    17/36

    Critical Inquiry / Autumn 2007 205 

    44.  See Mayer, Robert Maynard Hutchins, esp. chaps. 31–34.45.   See McKeon, “InstructionsConcerning Lectures,Readings,and Discussions for the

    General Course in the Humanities (Humanities 2),”Sept. 1942, folder17, box 38, Richard McKeon

    Papers, UCA. The “Instructions,” Windwrote, were “wrought with strangefallaciesconcerningthe nature of the humanities,as some of us understand them. . . I think it astonishing that suchstatements should be handed out to the staff as Instructionsin mimeographed form less thantwenty-fourhours before the first classmeets and with the order that they be distributed to the

    students” (Wind, letter to McKeon, 12 Oct. 1942, in “Bill of Particulars in Support of the StatementRegarding the Memorial to the Board of Trustees,” folder ii, box I, 8, EWA).

    46.   Wind, letter to McKeon.47.  Wind stayed at Smith afterfalling out with his Warburg colleagues; he was irritatedat being

    offered a position as Reader rather than Professorby the University of London (which housed theInstitute)and disagreedwith Saxl overthe intellectual and institutional directionof the institute.Wind wrote to Gertrud Bingat the time that despite “the discomfort of being an intellectual

    as facilitating the development of values. McKeon and Crane sought to de-

    velop judgment and critical sensibility and were resistant to crusades, even

    those of Hutchins, that might seem to compromise theintellectualfreedom

    of individuals. Hutchins was under attack in 1944 because of speeches inwhich he proposed a rededication of the university to a moral revolution

    in American life and, along with it, a radical reorganization of the univer-

    sity’s structure that would have abolished rank and made salary commen-

    surate with need rather than (perceived) merit. Unsurprisingly, the latter

    plan appeared “Bolshevist” to many of the faculty, but understanding that

    they could make a case more strongly on the basis of the intellectualhealth

    of the university than on that of personal financialinteresttheyemphasized

    a threat to individual intellectual freedom.44

    In this context, Wind’s counterattack was rather ill-judged; he defended

    Hutchins by attacking McKeon. How could the faculty claim intellectual

    freedom was threatened by Hutchins, he argued, when it was actually 

    McKeon who was exerting undue control over the departments and faculty of theDivision of theHumanities? Oneof thecornerstones of hisargument,

    presented in a “Bill of Particulars,” was the teaching of Hum 2. In the bill,

    Wind inveighed against what he saw as the doctrinaire methods promoted

    by its instructional manual, written by McKeon.45 Wind objectedto thefact

    that the instructions were “ambiguous on the subject of history” by which

    he meant disingenuous (claiming history is unimportant to the interpre-

    tation of texts but then requiring memorization of dates); that they sepa-

    rated form and content and proposed an initial and primary approach of 

    dealing only with form; and that they suggested he should be able to “teach

    [students] in three hours how to read Herodotus or Thucydides or Gibbon

    when every word in these authors is full of connotations which they have

    no equipment to understand.”46

    Wind’s bill of particulars wasdismissed bythe faculty senate, and hesoon

    moved on—expecting an imminentreturn to London—toSmith College.47

    This content downloaded from 62.204.192.85 on Sat, 6 Jun 2015 04:54:15 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    18/36

    206 Rebecca Zorach / Botticelli’s  Primavera

    outcast” it was “today the only honourableposition” (Wind, letter to Gertrud Bing,15 June 1945,folder ii, box I, 5, EWA).

    48.   David Grene, “Statement by Mr. David Grene,” in “Bill of Particularsin Support of the

    Statement Regarding the Memorial to the Board of Trustees.”49.  Leslie C. Warren, letter to Clarence H. Faust,10 July 1945,folder 14 “Humanities Divisionof,

    1940–78,” box38, RichardMcKeon Papers, UCA.

    Others remained who shared his view; a young faculty member in Classics,

    David Grene, joined Wind’s dissent, protesting that expertise was routinely 

    ruled out of order in meetings of Humanities 2 teaching staff. As he tells it,

    the course was “the place where the failure to understand that the assumedobjectivity of the ‘disciplines’ is no objectivity at all, has borne hardest on

    the non-conformists and where the mental attitude of such non-conform-

    ists has most consistently been treated with a sorrowful pity or disciplinary 

    measures or most often by an apparent unwillingness to admit that such a

    disagreement is honestly possible by a fully conscious intellectual oppo-

    nent.”48 Grene described the comical resultsof the dogmaticand indiscrim-

    inate application of Aristotle’s four causes or the theory of tragedy in his

    Poetics  to Aeschylus and Gibbon—against the protestations of those who

    had expertise in Greek. In the next year, Leslie Clare Warren, an instructor

    in the course, expressed similar views. In the humanities course, Warren

    suggested, Aristotelian theory was introduced covertly and repeatedly via a

    series of textual illustrations so that by the time it was explicitly presented,it appeared universal and inevitable. Ironically or not, Warren used the lan-

    guage of pagan mysteries: theHum 2 method is a “technique forintellectual

    conditioning that more closely resembles a priestly rite than an educative

    process” that makes of the humanities “a narrow and useless academic

    cult.”49

    The Concealed GodThe lectures Wind didn’t give at Chicago were published in 1958 as Pagan 

    Mysteries of the Renaissance, and it is in a central chapter of this book that

    he proposes his interpretation of the Primavera. Wind,likeGombrich,drew 

    on Ficino’s neo-Platonic thinking in elucidating the painting, based on Fi-

    cino’s close association with Botticelli and the painter’s patrons among the

    Medici family. Ficino would, in this view, have provided the philosophical

    underpinningsfor the painting (while classical literatureandcontemporary 

    lyric provided much of the overt subject matter). Wind’s approach makes

    more systematic use of neo-Platonism than Gombrich’s does and opposes

    Panofsky’s rationalist reading of neo-Platonic love. For Wind, the divine

    love toward which the Florentine neo-Platonists strove encompassed fren-

    zied ecstasy as well as calm devotion—inseparable, in his view.

    This content downloaded from 62.204.192.85 on Sat, 6 Jun 2015 04:54:15 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    19/36

    Critical Inquiry / Autumn 2007 207 

    50.   Gombrich, “Botticelli’s Mythologies: A Study in the Neo-Platonic Symbolismof HisCircle,” Journal of the Warburg and CourtauldInstitutes 8 (1945):24. Cupid is a child and alsofunctions as an identifying attributeof Venus.

    51.   With his Medici features,he is sometimes identified with Lorenzo the Magnificent; but theman in the pointed hat and white robes to his left (our right) makes a better match with portraitsof Lorenzo,especially if we consider a date in the later 1470s.

    Following the neo-Platonic fascination with triads, Wind focuses on the

    groups of three in the painting, in particular the three Graces, whichhe saw 

    as the representation of movement between the soul and the divine. The

    divine emanates toward the soul, which receives the emanation and thenturns itself back to the divine; the triad is that of giving, receiving, and re-

    turning. For Wind, the depicted Graces, from left to right, are Pleasure,

    Chastity, and Beauty—not simply a trio of undifferentiated nymphs. With

    her determined gaze, her unbound hair licking like flames, Pleasure’s in-

    terest in the demure Chastity is more passionate than sisterly; Beauty joins

    the two as a mean between extremes.

    If we think about this painting in terms of threes, what happens to the

    arrangement of its figures? On the left, the triad of Graces; on the right, a

    triad of transformation in which Zephyr captures Chloris, making her into

    Flora, who then returns his love. With six figures organized into two triads,

    we are left with two major figures, Venus and Mercury, and one who is, as

    Gombrich put it, “not much of a person.”50

    Long before I knew anything of neo-Platonism or Warburg or Wind, I

    was bothered by something about this painting. The composition looks as

    if it is supposed to be symmetrical, but isn’t. A powerful formal logic—in

    the compositionaltraditionin which Botticelli worked—wouldsuggestthat

    Venus shouldbe at thecenter, butshe standsslightly to the rightof theactual

    mathematical center of the panel. It is perhaps this very fact that caused

    Vasari to give the title of Primavera to thepainting(assuming that thefigure

    we now call “Flora” is the goddess of the springtime). Understood as the

    title figure, “Primavera” seems to upstage Venus. To make Venus the center

    of the panel would require adding slightly less than one figure’s width to

    the right-hand side.

    For comparison, we can look to Botticelli’s Adoration of the Magi  from

    around 1475 (fig. 2). Now in the Uffizi, it was commissioned by Guaspare

    di Zanobi del Lama for his funerary chapel in Santa Maria Novella. Thetwo

    works share a surprising number of features. First, thematic: the three

    Graces have to do with gift-giving, as do the three Magi. Each of the two

    groups of three attends a central figure, Venus and the Virgin respectively,

    who appear in similar positions and resemble each other closely. The pose,

    position, and face of the young man in the lower leftcorner of the Adoration 

    recall the Primavera’ s Mercury.51 The figures leaning forward in the right

    This content downloaded from 62.204.192.85 on Sat, 6 Jun 2015 04:54:15 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    20/36

    208 Rebecca Zorach / Botticelli’s  Primavera

    f igure  2. Sandro Botticelli(1440–1510).Adoration of the Magi. Uffizi.Photo: Scala/ArtResource, NY.

    foreground mimic the movement of Chloris. Reducing the comparison to

    a series of formal parallels, we might see the Adoration  as a triangle and the

    Primavera  as a flattened version of the same triangle—except for the fact

    that theyellow-robed figure at thelower right of the Adoration, a significant

    figure (often thought of as a self-portrait of the painter) corresponds to noformal feature of the Primavera.

    Wind claimed that “the crux of any interpretation of the  Primavera isto

    explain thepart played by Mercury” andthat “the composition ofthe paint-

    ing is therefore not fully understood, nor the role of Mercury quite com-

    prehended, until he and Zephyr are seen as symmetrical figures” (PM, pp.

    121, 124–25). Yet Zephyr is a kind of demigod, more like the nymphs or

    Graces thanlike the stately Olympians Venusand Mercury. Venusis flanked

    by a triad on either side, but only one side has a “major” god to frame the

    scene. Mercury’s and Zephyr’s relations to the female figures are quite dif-

    ferent: Mercury rules over the three Graces; Zephyr, a lesser figure in Greek 

    myth, is the agent of Chloris’s transformation into Flora. He also partici-

    pates fully in the triadic group that corresponds to the Graces on the otherside, part of   a triad rather than ruler over it. The painting is a musical phrase

    missing its final note.

    This content downloaded from 62.204.192.85 on Sat, 6 Jun 2015 04:54:15 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    21/36

    Critical Inquiry / Autumn 2007 209

    52.  See MarsilioFicino, In Plotinum, in Opera omnia, 2 vols. in 4 (1572; Turin,1959–62),2:2:1559.

    53.   Quoted in Gombrich, “Botticelli’s Mythologies,”p. 57. See Ficino, letter to AlbertoVeronensi, 20 Oct. 1481, Opera omnia, 1:2:845. Another lettermentionsthe same three; see Ficino,

    letterto Matthaeo Forliensi, [n.d.], Opera omnia, 1:2:862.54.  See Ficino, The Book of Life,  trans.Charles Boer(Dallas, 1980), p. 3. “There are three planets,

    which we have mentioned before, that are extremely favorable to contemplationand eloquence:the Sun, Venus,and Mercury”(p. 13).

    55.  See Ficino, In Plotinum, 2:2:1561, 1560.56.   Ficino, speech 1, Commentary on Plato’s Symposium on Love, trans. Sears Jayne (Dallas,

    1985),chap. 4.57.  This fact was noticed by Eugenio Marino, who mentions the sun as invisible figurefor the

    Christiangod in his theologicalreadingof the painting. See Eugenio Marino, Estetica, fede, e critica d’arte: “L’arte poetica” di Savonarola,” “L’estetica” di Ficino e “La primavera” di Botticelli (Rome,1997), pp. 193–96, pl. 31.As Marino puts it, Wind’s triadic interpretationrequires him to “double”the figureof Zephyr (p. 162).

    If a figure were missing from thescene, whowould it be?Whatgod might

    flank the scene on the right? An answer is found in the very same writings

    of Ficino cited by both Gombrich and Wind; it is, I think, Apollo. In fact,

    Wind hints at this when he cites a text by Ficino that begins with the triadMercury, Venus, and Apollo and suggests a musical transformation in “the

    key of Apollo” (PM,  p. 130).52 Given his interest in triads, it is surprising

    that Wind did not follow through with the idea of Apollo’s relation to the

    twoothergods.In fact, thetriadof Mercury, Venus, and Apollo (orthesun),

    interpreted in many different ways, reappears insistentlyin theFicinian cor-

    pus. Ficino writesof them, “thesestars are, among thecelestial bodies, those

    which most affect by their favor the human genius.”53 In The Book of Life,

    he declares that the three heavenly guides of scholars are Mercury, Apollo,

    and Venus. A scholar should rise early in the morning when these three

    planets (including the sun) are in force.54 In his commentary on Plotinus’s

    Ennead I.3, which deals with the means for the soul to ascend to the heavens

    through contemplation, Ficino takes the three gods as figures of the threetypesof humans who canfollow paths of ascent:the philosopher(Mercury),

    the lover (Venus), and the musician (Apollo). From that starting point, Fi-

    cino works analogically and piles interpretation on interpretation. He

    equates the gods with the senses: Venus with sight,Apollo with hearing,and

    Mercury with the imagination. These are the three highest of the six senses

    of humans, which included the imagination; they contrast with smell,taste,

    and touch, the lower and more bodily senses.55 In his commentary on the

    Symposium Ficino states thatthese higher sensesarethe onlysensesrequired

    for love.56 Further, Mercury is the good, Venus theintellect,Apollo thesoul.

    Mercury is truth, Venus beauty, Apollo concord. Whatever variety there

    may be in these interpretations, it is clear that the three gods persistently 

    form a triad.57

    This content downloaded from 62.204.192.85 on Sat, 6 Jun 2015 04:54:15 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    22/36

    210 Rebecca Zorach / Botticelli’s  Primavera

    58.  Ficino, “In Praise of Matrimony,”The Letters of Marsilio Ficino, trans.membersof theLanguage Departmentof the School of EconomicScience, London, 7 vols. (London, 1981), 3:70.

    59.  See Ficino,“Apologus: In traductionem libride amore missam ab Alamanno Donato ad

    LaurentiumMedicem” and “Apologus: Quod malese habet Lucilia, id est, anima, quandoàPhoebo, id est, à Deo, discedit,” Opera omnia, 1:2:848–49.

    60.  Gombrich alsopoints out that Alberti recommended nine or ten figures as the maximumfor a painting;here we have eight or nine, depending on whether Cupidis counted,and Apollowouldgive us nine or ten. Archival documents equivocate about the number of figures. John

    Shearman has published archivaldocuments relating to the Medicicollections in whichadiscrepancy appears between two copies (from1499 and 1503) of a 1498 document:in the first,there are nine figures, in the second, eight. See John Shearman,“The Collections of the YoungerBranch of the Medici,” Burlington Magazine 117(Jan.1975): 17.

    61.  See Stephen Campbell, The Cabinet of Eros: Renaissance Mythological Paintingand the “Studiolo” of Isabello d’Este (New Haven, Conn., 2006), chap. 4, and also Wind, Bellini’s Feast of  the Gods: A Study in Venetian Humanism (Cambridge, Mass., 1948).

    62.  The surface has been stripped down to the barepanel (it appears) in two narrow areas on

    the lower half of the far right-hand side.Umberto Baldini, “La Primavera” del Botticelli: Storia di un quadro e di un restauro (Milan, 1984)does not address this issue, instead showing a preferencein illustrations for cropping the painting severely on the right.

    Were Apollo positioned to the right of Zephyr, he would produce a more

    satisfying formal symmetry, according to typical Renaissance conventions.

    Such positioning is suggested in a letter by Ficino to Antonio Pelotti, in

    which the philosopher praises marriage by saying that “there Phoebus, lordof the Muses, and their companion Mercury, move as escorts on either side

    of Venus, mother of love and of music, and walk with her almost step for

    step, soto speak, and never gofar from her.”58 To Wind, the figure of Zephyr

    appeared sufficient to provide completion to the group on the right. But

    Apollo might also play a role here. In another letter by Ficino, he makes an

    appearance as the father of Flora. In the springtime she wanders into the

    realm of Venus where she discovers bodily pleasures but also pains—from

    which she returns to her father, “author of life-giving medicine,” to seek 

    healing (quoted in “BM,” p. 61).59 As father of Flora, herself the namesake

    of the city of Florence, Apollo would appropriately govern thegroupon the

    right. With Apollo and Mercury flanking the scene, we would have two tri-

    ads ruled over by Olympians, a total of nine figures in three groups of three.60 Were Apolloto appearin thepicture itwouldalsomakethis painting

    a precursor, in reverse, of Mantegna’s morecomplicatedlycomposed paint-

    ing usually known as the Parnassus  (fig. 3). Here the triad appears very ex-

    plicitly: Apollo to the left, Venus in the top center (with Mars as her

    accessory), and Mercury at the right.61

    I am not claiming that the painting has been cut down—though there

    are some peculiarities at its rightmost extremity, and Chloris and Zephyr

    aretheonlytwofigureswhosebodiesarecutoffbytheedgeofthepainting.62

    I suggest, however, that the painting would have raised the  question  of 

    This content downloaded from 62.204.192.85 on Sat, 6 Jun 2015 04:54:15 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    23/36

    Critical Inquiry / Autumn 2007 211

    f igure  3. Andrea Mantegna (1431–1506). Venusand Marswith Vulcan, Apollo, and Mercury (“Parnassus”). Louvre. Photo: Erich Lessing/ArtResource, NY.

    63.  See Charles M. Rosenberg, The Este Monuments and Urban Development in Renaissance 

    Ferrara (Cambridge, 1997), p. 102. See alsoRosenberg, “The Iconographyof the Saladegli Stucchiin the Palazzo Schifanoia in Ferrara,” Art Bulletin 61 (Sept. 1979): 377–84. Rosenberg’sargumentwas brought to my attentionby Iva Olah, “Tarocchiand the Depiction of ChristianPrincely Virtues in the Schifanoia Frescoes” (M.A.thesis, Carleton University, 2005).

    64.   See Angelo Poliziano, “Monodia In LaurentiumMedicem, intonato per ArrighumIsac,”Angeli Politiani Opera, quae quidem extitere . . . (Basel, 1553), pp. 621–22. The same workpp. 594–95, refers to Lorenzoas the “pure brillianceof an Apollinianstar [Purus Apollinei sideris . . . nitor].”

    Apollo’s absence: why was he not in the picture? One might hypothesize

    that the god was “absent” when a particular viewer was absent from the

    room in which the painting hung and present when he was there—that is,

    perhaps Apollo was intended to be embodied in a privileged viewer. A con-

    temporary analogy might be found in the absence, among a series of theVirtues in theSala deiStucchi at thePalazzo Schifanoia inFerrara, ofJustice.

    Charles Rosenberg has argued persuasively that this absence implied that

    Justice was to be embodied by the duke, Borso d’Este.63 Perhaps the “miss-

    ing” god was to be figured by the elder Lorenzo de’ Medici—Lorenzo the

    Magnificent—himself. Angelo Poliziano associates Lorenzo with Phoebus

    in his funeral ode and refers to him as Apollo’s poet in his Stanze; indeed

    the grounds for such an identification are manifold.64 Like Apollo,Lorenzo

    This content downloaded from 62.204.192.85 on Sat, 6 Jun 2015 04:54:15 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    24/36

    212 Rebecca Zorach / Botticelli’s  Primavera

    65.  On absence (mostly in modernart), see studies collected in Figurations de l’absence:Recherches esthe ´tiques, ed. Jean-PierreMourey (St.-Étienne, 1987).

    66.  This asymmetry is madevery apparentin an illustration in Umberto Baldini’s bookon therestoration of the Primavera that splits the painting into its figuralparts. See Baldini, “La 

    Primavera” del Botticelli, pp. 92–93.67.  On this topic, see Mieke Bal and Norman Bryson, “Semiotics and Art History,”Art Bulletin 

    73 (June 1991): 174–208.

    was a musician and poet. Apollo is the inventor of the laurels of poets; a

    common pun, used by Poliziano, connects the name Lorenzo with laurel

    (Lauro). The absent Apollo suggests a kind of secret flattery—a secret un-

    derstood by a larger circle of viewers, by which a distance was closed be-tween the human ruler and the gods of pictorial representation.

    There is in art history a very strong presumption against arguing from

    absence, and the prestige of the painting, the fact that so many eminent

    viewers have seen it as complete, makes it hard to imagine that something

    is “missing” from it.65 When, however, one combines the formal logic of 

    the painting with the pervasiveness of the Ficinian triad—and adds the evi-

    dence of Mantegna’striadic Parnassus—thisabsencebecomespalpable. My 

    suggestion thus depends not only on content but also on form—the lack 

    of symmetry of the painting’s composition.66 And even if iconologists were

    inclined to wring rich meaning from tiny details, they were less ready to

    explain absences. Wind (and Gombrich) thus missed an opportunity to

    combine a focus on form with a complementary focus on iconography. Per-haps this came from a sensitivity to the critique leveled at them by the likes

    of McKeon: that they were already importing too much from outside the

    work. But if iconographers frustrated formalists by assuming that everyde-

    tail possessed extrapictorial meaning, formalists in the mid-century mold

    would have been hard pressed to see the painting as unbalanced or incom-

    plete; they generally viewed works as complete and bounded, possessing

    tensions, to be sure, but tensions that could be resolved internally to the

    object.

    This notion of boundedness is perhaps a necessary prerequisite to the

    idea of art as autonomous. This concept has a hoary pedigree in art history,

    one that dates back to Kant and hassince been revived repeatedly. Thework 

    of art is thus isolated from social life, existing in its own aesthetic sphere.

    Even those art historians who consider objects in historical context make

    an assumption that the work of art (and the working of art) canbe detached

    from something else called a context.67 This detachment presupposes a dis-

    tinction like the one Crane made between the particular and the general.

    The Chicago critics added a soupçon of antitotalitarian liberty to the au-

    tonomy of the art object. But, here as elsewhere, the autonomousart object

    This content downloaded from 62.204.192.85 on Sat, 6 Jun 2015 04:54:15 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    25/36

    Critical Inquiry / Autumn 2007 213

    68.  With the notion of “bewegtes Beiwerk.” See Warburg, The Renewal of Pagan Antiquity, andKurt Forster,introductionto ibid., pp. 13, 65 n. 54. See alsoPhilippe-AlainMichaud, Aby Warburg and the Image in Motion, trans. Sophie Hawkes (New York, 2004).

    69.   See Artists at Court: Image-Making and Identity1300–1550, ed. Campbell (Boston, 2004),

    esp. EvelynWelch, “Painting as Performancein the ItalianRenaissance Court,” pp. 19–32.70.  See Bruno Latour, We Have Never Been Modern, trans. CatherinePorter (Cambridge, Mass.

    1993).

    comes around to serve something—in this case, a notion of human free-

    dom. Within art history and criticism our view of paintings of the past is

    still conditioned by modernist expectations of painting as nonnarrative,

    subjectless (as in Gilbert’s wishful thinkingabout Renaissanceart).As I sug-gested earlier, Renaissance art has often been mobilized to establish a nar-

    rative of progressive vanquishing of content that tends toward a notion of 

    perfect freedom for the human subject. We might, however, make more

    headway with Renaissance art by considering objects and subjects as a web

    of multiple dependencies. This does not, however, mean stasis. The forms

    of objects were, in the Renaissance, regularly put intomotion—asWarburg,

    notably, emphasized.68 Images and iconographies circulated from panel

    painting to parade to manuscript, costume,and amulet.In theRenaissance,

    the objects we consider art played a variety of social and politicalfunctions,

    and those who might be designated professionally as painters or architects

    also painted furniture and banners for festive occasions, designed luxury 

    objects and tapestries, and made political statements—as Botticelli didwhen he was commissioned to paint the defeated Pazzi conspirators,

    hanged and humiliated, on the outer wall of the Palazzo Vecchio in 1478.

    Objects attained shape and significance by their participation in complex 

    scenes of social and cultural performance.69

    Much recent research in Renaissance art suggests we should think of ob-

     jects as more ambiguously approaching the status of the human—part of 

    a continuum that includes stories of animated statues, portraits that seem

    to lack nothing but breath, coins that serve as representatives of the sov-

    ereign, performancesin which humans are costumed as images, andobjects

    invested with subjective value through gifting, proximity,or memory. They 

    do not, in other words, fit a simple subject-object paradigm. Thus, if we see

    meaning latent in the web of social, political, and psychological relationsin

    which a work exists—as exchange or interchange, circulation, intersection,

    ambivalence—we might pry it from the assumptions of modern subject-

    object relations.70

    I have dealt with these issues at some lengthin order to establisha frame-

    work for understanding pictures. Beyond a simple oppositionbetween “ob-

     ject of aesthetic contemplation” and “medium for conveying iconographic

    This content downloaded from 62.204.192.85 on Sat, 6 Jun 2015 04:54:15 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

  • 8/9/2019 Love, Truth, Orthodoxy, Reticence; Or, What Edgar Wind Didn’t See in Botticelli’s Primavera-REBECCA ZORACH

    26/36

    214 Rebecca Zorach / Botticelli’s  Primavera

    71.  See forexample Lauro Martines, Power and Imagination: City-States in Renaissance Italy (New York,1979), p. 158. Forinstance,in one sign of covert exercise of power, Lorenzo monitoredvoting in the governingcouncil,while not explicitly interveningin it.

    72.   Work by Webster Smithdrew attention to the presencein an inventory of the Medici housein the ViaLarga (owned by Lorenzo di Pierfrancescoand his brotherGiovanni) of a painting with“nine figures,men and women” (Webster Smith, “On the Original Location of the Primavera,” Art Bulletin 57 [Mar. 1975]: 37). See also Shearman, “TheCollections of the Younger Branch of theMedici.” The painting hung above a lettuccio (“daybed”)in a room next to Lorenzodi

    Pierfrancesco’s bedroom.73.  See Bredekamp, Botticelli “Primavera”:Florenz als Garten der Venus (Frankfurt, 1988), esp.

    pp. 34–55. Dempsey reviews the competingproposals on the datingof the work in his “AHypothesisConcerning the Castello Nativity and a Scruple about the Date of Botticelli’s

    Primavera,” in Opere e giorni: Studi su mille anni di arte europea, ed. Klaus Bergdolt and GiorgioBonsanti (Venice, 2001), pp. 349–54. Proposals include the idea th