Kapferer Stratherns New Comparative Anthropology

download Kapferer Stratherns New Comparative Anthropology

of 7

Transcript of Kapferer Stratherns New Comparative Anthropology

  • 7/30/2019 Kapferer Stratherns New Comparative Anthropology

    1/7

    StrathernS new Comparative

    anthropology

    Thoughts from Hagen and Zambia

    Bruce Kapferer

    Marilyn Strathern, recalling her Hagen ethnography, asks challenging questions

    about the character and potential o anthropological generalizations grounded in

    comparative ethnographic knowledge. In taking a new look at the issue o com-

    parison, Strathern aims to overcome all sorts o dualisms (or simple binarisms),

    distorting oppositions, and simple negative inversions (whereby what is dened

    as distinct is requently presented as the obverse o Euro-American realities).

    The biurcation o dierence that she stresses opens the potential o partial con-

    nections rather than absolute distinctions: dierences that separate can also be

    integral with other aspects that establish connections through similarity. Strath-

    ern emphasizes the multiplicity o perspectives (akin to Alred Schutzs multiple

    realities?) and reuses notions o coherent and discrete totalities or unities that

    characterized comparisons in the highly relativist anthropology o yore. Thisarticle o Stratherns, as also her recent work as a whole, pushes beyond the nega-

    tive dialectics o modernism versus postmodernism versus poststructuralism that

    have governed anthropological and sociological debate and discussion, though

    less extensively than in philosophy and the humanities. I note, however, a lean-

    ing in her orientation toward the current technologically infuenced discourse

    Common Knowledge 17:1

    DOI 10.1215/0961754X-2010-041

    2011 by Duke University Press

    104

    S y m po s i um : C om pa r a t i v e R e l a t i v i s m

  • 7/30/2019 Kapferer Stratherns New Comparative Anthropology

    2/7

    Kapfrr

    Rspos

    toS

    trathr

    10

    5o the posthuman. A major reerence o her article is to the neorealist positions

    o John Law, Annemarie Mol, and especially Bruno Latour (who similarly stress

    connectivities rather than separations), as well as to Eduardo Viveiros de Castros

    perspectivism. With regard to the last, she makes a distinction, on the one hand,

    between perspectivalism or perspectivism the multiple positions o human and

    nonhuman within a single open, networked, horizontal eld and, on the other

    hand, the multiplicity o perspectives that are potential within a specic onto-

    logical context and that are united through the commanding viewpoint o the

    anthropologist.

    Ontology (as Graham Harman has reminded us recently) is used in a great

    many dierent ways. One usage conceives o all human beings as united in the

    one ontology as a act o their common embodiment. The dierentiation within

    human being, or the dierences that are ethnographically demonstrated between

    human beings, are such within the one ontology, every dierence expressing adimension o an ontological universal. So Jadran Mimica, whose Iqwaye research

    Strathern cites, is able to show how the apparently unique Iqwaye approach to

    numbers evidences an embodied human imaginary with general ontological pos-

    sibilities, one that is likewise maniested in advanced mathematics. Another orm

    o ontology which, according to Strathern, is that o perspectivism in Eduardo

    Viveiros de Castros sense involves a more discrete embodied orientation that

    is cosmologically dened and enclosed. These dierent orms o ontology need

    not be mutually exclusive, which I think is Stratherns impression also (though she

    is ambiguous on this point), or she contests the idea that perpectivalism in the

    broad, primary sense makes comparison irrelevant and pointless. She claws her

    way back to the importance o comparativism (and to a more restricted concept

    o ontology) or the uses o anthropologists, in the ace o apparently radical new

    perspectivist and neorealist directions in anthropology that, or the most part, are

    casting questions o ontology aside. Strathern can be understood as combining

    the two notions o ontology to which I have reerred, the ormer underpinning

    connectivities that do not necessarily erase a more restricted sense that Stratherns

    approach to comparison would reveal. Unlike many anthropologists, Stratherndoes not necessarily equate ontology with culture, a confation that is a actor in

    the dualistic relativism (biurcation?) that dogs much anthropological compari-

    son and is still apparent in some who are trying to develop alternative approaches.

    Thus she suggests that the risks o a dualism are evident in Viveiros de Castros

    perspectivism (as applied to Amazonia), as well as in Simon Harrisons discussion

    o ethnic confict, which occupies much o Stratherns essay. In it, she takes an

    important step toward restoring comparison to a central place in the anthropo-

    logical project, while avoiding some o the pitalls. At this point, I would like to

    place Stratherns discussion in the context o other arguments relating to anthro-

    pologys comparative project and to more specic ethnographic concerns about

  • 7/30/2019 Kapferer Stratherns New Comparative Anthropology

    3/7

    COmmOn

    KnO

    w

    leDge

    10

    6

    1. Louis Dumont,Homo Hierarchicus: The Cas te System

    and Its Implications(Chicago: University o Chicago Press,

    1980);Essays on Individuali sm: Modern Ideology in Anthro-

    pological Perspective (Chicago: University o Chicago Press,

    1986); The German Ideology: From France to Germany and

    Back (Chicago: University o Chicago Press, 1994).

    2. See also Marshall Sahlins, Culture and Practical Reason

    (Chicago: University o Chicago Press, 1976).

    ethnicity and urbanism. Her revitalization o anthropological comparison has

    some resonance with the work o Louis Dumont, although her general approach

    more explicitly acknowledges that o McKim Marriott, Dumonts major critic.1

    Dumont tried, as Strathern does, to steer a dicult course between the Scylla

    o relativism and the Charybdis o universalism a universalism that, albeit, is

    imbued with an ideological and normative individualism (o Euro-American post-

    Enlightenment provenance) that has been essentialized in much political philoso-

    phy, as well as in anthropological ethnography.2 In a similar spirit to the body o

    Stratherns work, which depends on Melanesian materials, Dumont attempted

    to develop conceptualizations, based on his ethnographic work in India, or a

    comparative anthropological methodology.

    Dumonts concept o hierarchy (and encompassment) and Stratherns

    approach to the partible person (related to Marriotts concept o the dividual)

    are comparative principles. Although initially grounded in their Indian and Mel-anesian ethnography, these concepts are, in dierent ways, then reconceptualized

    as abstract universals. The concepts are both concrete and general, distinguishing

    and connecting demonstrating irreducible ethnographic specicity and, simul-

    taneously, a unity through the dierence. Thus, in Dumonts analysis, diverse

    practices in India are, in their various concrete ways, expressive o hierarchy.

    On the surace, this situation diers rom that in Europe. However, the surace

    contrast or opposition that his comparative method reveals also discloses a deeper

    unity. Hierarchy is suppressed in accordance with egalitarian and individualist

    value but has continued to show its eects in racism and in notions o homoge-

    neous national communities and unity in identity (extreme instances being seg-

    regation in the United States, apartheid, and Nazi racist essentialism). Strathern

    conceives o Melanesian dividualism as a principle that permits interconnections

    precisely because the person or individual is not conceived as a coherent inte-

    grated entity prior to the relations that people come to orm with others. As

    Dumont argues about India, Strathern eectively argues that the individual as

    value does not exist in Melanesia, but rather exists as a partible being relationally

    constituted, and that this understanding has general orce or sociological under-standing beyond Melanesia.

    The comparativism o Dumont and Strathern are very dierent rom previ-

    ous attempts in anthropology, or they stress principles and processes that simul-

    taneously connect as they separate. They promise an anthropology that is able to

    demonstrate the continuities despite dierences among human beings (though

  • 7/30/2019 Kapferer Stratherns New Comparative Anthropology

    4/7

    Kapfrr

    Rspos

    toS

    trathr

    107Strathern seems more reticent than Dumont about the continuities) and to deal

    with the signicance o both. Anthropology is divested o the spoiling reputation

    whereby its comparative and ethnographic work is assigned a positive rather than

    negative role.

    Apart rom their similarities in purpose or spirit, the perspectives o

    Dumont and Strathern are distinct. Dumont is very much a ormalist in the tradi-

    tion o Durkheim and later Lvi-Strauss, although Dumont aims to escape what

    he considers to be their Eurocentrism. Dumont is a holist or whom the part can

    only be conceived through its relation with the whole. Strathern is wary, I think,

    o such holism placing parts and wholes into more dynamic relation, the parts

    being points or the emergence o new wholes or assemblages. In contrast with

    that o Strathern, Dumonts position might be seen as ar more static, although

    this is not necessarily the case.3 While Dumont can be described as a tradition-

    alist (i not an Orientalist, committed, as some critics claim, to homogeneousorders), Stratherns viewpoint is more open and contemporary. Nonetheless, it is

    useul to raise a ew questions that Dumont might have considered in relation to

    Stratherns approach, i only to expose some potential risks.

    Methodologically, she aligns hersel with increasingly dominant social sci-

    ence approaches, such as actor-network theory, as well as with the dividualist

    orientation o Marriott. Both in some ways accord with her Melanesian eth-

    nography, which indicates that the person is not a coherent integrated singular

    individual, but rather partible, a point o dierentiation that can be plugged into

    or unplugged rom a variety o relations that cross over what may appear as di-

    erences and separations and that a previous comparative anthropology may have

    held to be unbridgeably distinct. Actor-network theory, at least in the work o

    Latour (which bears some resemblance to Manuel DeLandas assemblage theory,

    which in turn has its kinship to Stratherns perspective), is set unabashedly within

    the contemporary Euro-American re-imagination or re-ontologization o the

    nature o existence as conceived in a world o digitalized technology, cyberspace,

    and virtuality.4 Dumont, I surmise, would see this development as blatantly

    individualist, rooted in the conceptualizations o recent history (and its utur-isms). Marriotts individualism, or example, is presented as a shit away rom the

    individual as value, a concept that, as Dumont explains, is at the root o Euro-

    American social scientic thinking and that is seen to be centrally involved in the

    ailure o comparative and generalist objectives. But I think that Dumont would

    3. See Bruce Kaperer, Louis Dumont and a Holist

    Ant hropology, in Theory and Practice in Anthropology:

    The Holist Approach, ed. Ton Otto and Nils Bubandt

    (New York: Blackwell, 2010), 21338, where I argue that

    Dumonts hierarchical conception posits a logic o dier-

    entiation in which hierarchy is a dynamic rame or the

    continual actualization o new potential.

    4. Bruno Latour,Reassembling the Social : An Introduc-

    tion to Actor-Network-Theory (Oxord: Oxord University

    Press, 2005); Manuel DeLanda,A New Philosophy of Society:

    Assemblage Theory and Social Complexity (London: Contin-

    uum, 2006).

  • 7/30/2019 Kapferer Stratherns New Comparative Anthropology

    5/7

    COmmOn

    KnO

    w

    leDge

    10

    8

    see Marriott (and, by extension, Stratherns notion o the partible person) as an

    expansion o the individual-as-value idea and as a orm o hyperinvidualism. Thus

    the individual is no longer a coherent entity (or a unitary sel) but is broken down

    into a composite set o dividuals, each o which eectively acts like an individual

    rom which a variety o dierent social assemblages can be generated.

    Whether or not this critique o Marriott is air, it does seem that Strathern

    sustains Western authority while appearing to destabilize it with her compara-

    tive Melanesian ethnography. Furthermore, her destabilization may not be as

    radical as it at rst appears, since she is discovering in Melanesia directions that

    were already present, i suppressed, in Western philosophical and social thought.5

    There could be a return to the comparative anthropology o old, despite the radi-

    cal appearance. The ault o early comparative anthropology was to discover the

    West in other systems, which, or all their apparent strangeness, ended up reveal-

    ing and conrming ideologically embedded dimensions (at least, in Dumontssense) o the world rom which the anthropologists mainly came. Dumont largely

    avoided this trap by insisting on a thorough critique o his own historical sit-

    uation, which he regarded as crucial or developing an authentic comparative

    understanding that had real generalizing potential. Strathern is also critical (in

    her present article, as in much other work), but in a more tentative and subdued

    way; and here a comparative binarism could be creeping in the back door. An

    example would be her suggestion that a cosmo-ontology o the Iqwaye sort, as

    described by Mimica, may be underpinning the relationalities o Hageners.

    As a demonstration o her argument, Strathern describes the complex,

    dierentiating, even ractalizing way in which Hageners carve up their reali-

    ties to establish the multiplicity o their relations. She claims no originality or

    her observations, which to me resonate with those o Max Gluckmans Rhodes-

    Livingstone Institute (RLI) researchers in what is now Zambia. Rather like the

    situation in Hagen as Strathern denes it, in Zambia migrants to town rom rural

    areas developed many novel, situationally relevant, and thereore constantly di-

    erentiating and shiting categories, in terms o which their social relations were

    dened and through which new social assemblages were created that crossedover thoroughly separate social and cultural orders, or what in other situations

    would have been regarded as such. The urban practices o Zambians, like those

    o Stratherns Hageners, involved a thorough consciousness o social and cultural

    dierence (they behaved like anthropological comparativists o the past), which

    they used to generate new social and cultural categories in terms o which people

    who would have been considered separate could orm new unities. Dierence

    was engaged to produce communality. In urban Zambia, relations, oten feeting,

    5. See Gilles Deleuze, Difference and Repetition, trans. Paul

    Patton (London: Continuum, 2004); The Fold: Leibniz and

    the Baroque, trans. Tom Conley (London: Athlone, 1993).

  • 7/30/2019 Kapferer Stratherns New Comparative Anthropology

    6/7

    Kapfrr

    Rspos

    toS

    trathr

    10

    9were constituted in and through the category, which expressed a virtual relation

    in terms o which actual relations were ormed. Such dynamics can be widely

    attested, especially in the current conditions o migration and urbanization and

    in the context o what some commentators are reerring to as contemporary cos-

    mopolitanism. Stratherns critical take is that such globalizing intermixture may

    mask persisting ontological dierences that (i I understand her argument) may

    underpin the new associations and relations ormed. Further, Strathern would

    disagree with the urban/rural division and separation that marked the RLI per-

    spective and or which these researchers were criticized by many anthropolo-

    gists at the time. ( J. Clyde Mitchell, the key urban anthropologist o the RLI

    group, eventually attempted to overcome the dichotomization with his network

    approach, which is distinct rom that currently being popularized by Latour.)

    However, Stratherns resolution o the conceptual divide seems to replace

    a horizontal distinction with a vertical one. That is, the ontological dimensionso relations in migrants villages persist into urban space as the occluded base

    o relations in town. Playing on Gluckmans extremist position (which opposed

    town situations to rural tribal situations), Strathern conceives o the Hageners as

    simultaneously tribesmen, their tribal ontological roots, as it were, still deeply

    relevant, i suppressed, or the relations that they are orming in town.

    The RLI point is, o course, more complicated than I have so ar repre-

    sented it. Mitchell, or example, did not conceive o Zambian urban lie as an

    integrated totality.6 As he saw it, lie fowed through a diversity o events and

    situations, in which relations were being constantly recreated. These relations

    were in accordance with the maniold perspectives o participants whose motivat-

    ing conditions, rather than ontological undamentals (ideological constructions

    being preerable in this case), were predominantly those o the political economy

    o the colonial and postcolonial order (in both urban and rural spaces).

    Here I would suggest (still in the context o the RLI situationist perspec-

    tive) that Stratherns argument intimates a dimension o social/societal integra-

    tion more than she might otherwise preer. The event-centered and situational

    approach that the RLI researchers experimented with (in explicit reaction againstnotions o the inherent unity o society) is more fuid and oriented toward poten-

    tial (that is, toward the production o something entirely original). This is so

    despite their privileging o structure and their antagonism toward individualist

    psychologism, which is always a risk, though not a necessity, o an orientation that

    stresses ontology o the restricted and even cultural kind that Strathern sees as

    relevant to the Hageners.

    6. J. Clyde Mitchell, Social Networks and Urban Situations:

    Analyses of Personal Relationships in Central African Towns

    (Manchester, U.K.: Manchester University Press, 1969);

    The Kalela Dance: Aspects of Social Relationships among

    Urban Africans in Northern Rhodesia (Manchester, U.K.:

    Manchester University Press, 1956).

  • 7/30/2019 Kapferer Stratherns New Comparative Anthropology

    7/7

    COmmOn

    KnO

    w

    leDge

    110

    The RLI point or Zambia, as distinct rom Stratherns observations

    about Hagen, would be that rural ontologies would be suspended or radically

    transormed or created entirely anew in urban zones, while in rural areas, i not

    suspended, they would increasingly be suppressed and, in eect, changed. Fur-

    thermore, the similarities and dierences, the ractionalizing dynamics o com-

    parison and association engaged in by Hageners in urbanizing contexts, as well

    as the power o certain anthropological and sociological concepts, are thoroughly

    connected to wider political orces that might systematically push aside the rel-

    evance o local ontologies.

    Stratherns kind o questioning goes to the heart o what makes anthropol-

    ogy important. But her approach continues to maniest the diculties o the

    biurcated orientation integral to anthropological comparison, which attempts

    to discover generalities or universals through the examination o what appears

    on the surace to be ethnographically based dierence. Strathern exempliesthe potential contribution o an anthropology that discovers a common human-

    ity through the study o dierence, a program that can eectively explode the

    apparent separations o dierence through the very study o dierence. Strathern

    shows how anthropological ethnography can decenter dominant (which usually

    means metropolitan) theory, but doing so is rendered problematic when the con-

    ceptual apparatuses o description and their assumptions are thoroughly those

    o some dominant theory. This obstacle is likely to be an enduring one or any

    sort o anthropology, but some o the dangers or risks may be reduced through a

    critique (which is not necessarily a rejection) o the conceptualizations engaged

    (including those that anthropologists might derive rom their particular eth-

    nographic experience). I have reerred to Dumont, who may appear outdated

    to many o us today. He attempted a rigorous investigation o his own realities

    simultaneously with his exploration o people who on the surace appeared to live

    outside them. His comparative methodology was developed as a kind o internal

    experimental method or the testing o both particular and general conceptual

    and theoretical assertions. Vital to this method is a concern to develop a thorough

    and continuing critique o the historical grounds o ones own understanding, onethat is sensitive to the very descriptive concepts through which both dierences

    and similarities are determined. Stratherns work is in line with such a project

    but, in my view, insuciently recognizes some o the ideological or ontological

    underpinnings that may be shaping aspects o her exciting and always illuminat-

    ing venture.