Journal for the Study of Greek and Latin Philosophical Traditions · beyond the work of Nicole...

198

Transcript of Journal for the Study of Greek and Latin Philosophical Traditions · beyond the work of Nicole...

  • 1

    Journal for the Study of Greek and Latin Philosophical

    Traditions

    1st INTERNATIONAL ISSUE

    Institute of Philosophy

    Academy of Sciences

    of the Czech republic v.v.i.

    Praha 2010

  • 2

    Redakce časopisu Aithér Filosofický ústav AVČR

    Jilská 1 Praha 1 110 00

    www.aither.eu

    ISSN 1803-7860 (Online) ISSN 1803-7879 (Print)

  • 3

    Table of contents

    Foreword....................................................................................... 5

    1. Pavel Hobza............................................................................. 9

    Ethics or Epistemology? Parmenides' Verse B 8.34

    Reconsidered

    2. Chiara Chinello...................................................................... 41

    Oedipus, the Tragedy of Self Recognition

    3. Jakub Jirsa............................................................................. 69

    Value pluralism, Sophocles' Antigone and liberalism

    4. Alice Pechriggl .................................................................... 107

    Tragic ways of thinking the political. Some considerations

    beyond the work of Nicole Loraux

    5. Tomáš Hejduk....................................................................... 139

    Bernard Williams and Ancient Greek Tragedy

    6. Kryštof Boháček................................................................... 173

    Between Truth and Beauty

  • 4

  • 5

    Dear readers,

    Let me introduce the first international edition of our

    journal, Aither International Issue 2010.

    Aither is a journal devoted to European philosophical

    traditions, as they were constituted and formulated in their

    classic form of Greek and Latin writings. The journal is

    primarily designed for the study of philosophical texts in

    their original form from ancient Greece to the early Modern

    Times (Latin). As well as for analysis, commentary and

    interpretation of these texts, the magazine is open to the

    broadest studies of cultural backgrounds and contexts, that

    may in any way help to clarify or reinterpret Greek and

    Latin philosophical thought. Reviews are also welcome, as

    well as polemical articles and critical reflections on the

    topic. The publisher of the journal Aither is the

    Philosophical Institute of the Czech Academy of Sciences.

    Aither has been published bi-annually since 2009. The

    International Issue will be issued once every two years.

    Therefore, every fourth issue of Aither is international. The

    Aither International Issue publishes articles in English,

    German and French.

    For more information, see the section forauthors.

  • 6

    The first international issue is dedicated to the Attic tragedy

    and Greek archaic thought. Tragic authors are now

    generally regarded as the necessary basis for an alternative

    or classical philosophical theories of Plato and Aristotle. In

    any case, they represent to us contemporary common sense,

    on the basis of which it were possible to formulate such

    unique philosophical positions. Increasingly, however, the

    works of tragic thinkers are interpreted directly as philo-

    sophical texts, expressing an autonomous philosophical

    position. Articles in our number are showing that the tragic

    writers have great intellectual potential also for today's

    philosophical debate, and that they were prominent figures

    of ancient discussions. Furthermore, it appears that the topic

    of tragic thought or tragic philosophy affects a wider group

    of thinkers, than just tragic poets from Athens. Lastly, it

    turns out that the inclusion of tragic texts in philosophical

    literature requires some reflection on the concept of

    philosophy in general. Such a new reflection on the

    traditional reading of the text of the poem of Parmenides –

    the highly respected epistemologist of the tradition – offers

    the first paper, which in accordance with the main focus of

    number suggests an ethical reading of Parmenides.

    As a virtual magazine, we invite you on the first journey

    into the world of classic thought. We hope that you will

  • 7

    enjoy it and that our magazine will become for you a

    reliable and perhaps even a permanent and freely available

    guide for the future. Therefore, in awareness of the lack of

    such a specifically oriented electronic journal, we chose the

    name of the fifth element. Quintessence is unavailable for

    our physical world, but acts as its persistent framework

    which can be taken into account at all times and used to

    better understand the world and ourselves. We hope that

    some of the brilliance of Aither you will see in our

    magazine.

  • 8

  • 9

    Pavel Hobza

    Parmenides’ Verse B 8.34 and the Practical Meaning of

    One of the most famous notions associated with

    Parmenides is the relationship between thought and being.

    Although in philosophical tradition this notion has been

    understood as the notorious identity of thought and being,

    the precise form of the relationship in Parmenides is a

    matter of dispute, depending on syntactical construction of

    Greek lines that seem to express this relationship, i.e. the

    fragment B 3 () and

    the line B 8.34 :

    '

    However, the interpretation of B 3 is essentially ambiguous

    since could be taken either as a predicate or as a

    subject. Although in B 8.34 could be taken to be as

    problematic as in B 3, there is an important

    difference between both lines. Whereas line B 8.34 occurs

    within a clear context of the fragment B 8 that can – as we

    shall see – help to settle its interpretation, the fragment B 3,

  • 10

    not taking up the whole hexametric verse, appears alone; we

    are thus short of clues on which it would be possible to

    decide how to construe it. Because of the rather problematic

    nature of the fragment B 3i we should concentrate merely

    on line B 8.34.

    Now, although the precise form of the relationship

    between thought and being in B 8.34 is a matter of dispute,

    there seems to be no disagreement on its theoretical or

    epistemological character. However, it is the aim of this pa-

    per to undermine this general agreement on the theoretical-

    epistemological character of the line. Whereas, on the usual

    interpretation, (or ) is understood in theoretical

    terms as the act of, or the capacity for, , in interpreting

    the line we should rather proceed from the ordinary, rather

    practical meaning of as found, e.g., in the archaic lyric

    poetry, where it meant a character, attitude, or even moral

    self. On this interpretation, the line is to be understood in

    practical or even ethical rather than epistemological terms.

    Hence, its main message is practical-ethical and only

    secondarily it has theoretical-epistemological implications.

    i Sometimes it is even suspected that B 3 is not an authentic

    quotation from Parmenides. Cf. Gadamer 1996, p. 154: ‗Inzwischen hat

    mich Mansonner überzeugt, daß Fragment 3 überhaupt kein

    Parmenides-Zitat ist, sondern eine von Platon selbst stammende

    Formulierung, die (...) Clemens Parmenides zugeschrieben hat.‘

  • 11

    I. Syntactical Considerations about B 8.34

    As we have suggested, there is a problem of how

    exactly to construe the line B 8.34 ('

    ). In general, there

    are three main possibilities of how to construct it. They are

    based primarily on the understanding of which can

    function as predicate, subject, or attribute. The conjunction

    can be also rendered in three ways: ‗therefore‘,

    ‗that‘ and ‗because‘. First of all, let us list some possible

    constructions for each interpretational type:

    A. ( as predicate)

    1. Dasselbe aber ist Erkennen und das, woraufhin

    Erkenntnis ist.i (Heitsch)

    2. Penser et ce pourquoi la pensée est, sont la même chose.ii

    (Cordero)

    3. It is the same to think and the thought that [the object of

    thought] exists.iii

    (Tarán)

    B. ( as subject)

    i Heitsch 1974, p. 31.

    ii Cordero 1984, p. 39.

    iii Tarán 1965, p. 86.

  • 12

    1. Das Selbige aber ist zu erkennen, und zugleich der

    Grund, weshalb eine Erkenntnis seiend ist.i (Hölscher)

    2. The same is to think and (is) wherefore [or ‚that‗] is (the)

    thought [or ‚thinking‗].ii (Mourelatos)

    C. ( as attribute)

    Als Identisches kann es erkannt werden und weil die

    Erkenntnis Bestand hat.iii

    (Wiesner)

    As to the (grammatical) suitability of the renderings

    suggested, the type B (or C) is to be preferred on two

    grounds: 1) Unlike type A, the grammatical construction

    is used in its usual way: ‗it is (possible) to

    think‘. 2) To interpret as subject fits better the

    context of the fragment B 8 for in B 8.29 (only five lines

    above our line) unambiguously appears in the

    function of subject, being synonymous with . As

    Hölscher puts it: ‗Es ist unwahrscheinlich, daß Parmenides

    fünf Verse später, und wieder am Versanfang, dasselbe

    Wort in einem anderen, unprägnanten Sinn gebraucht.‘iv

    Or

    as Mourelatos puts it: ‗The presumption is that

    i Hölscher 1986, p. 25.

    ii Mourelatos 1970, p. 165

    iii Wiesner 1987, p. 176.

    iv Hölscher 1986, p. 97-98.

  • 13

    refers back to the subject under discussion in B 8 as a whole

    – , ―what-is‖; it must therefore function as subject in B

    8.34, not as predicate.‘i

    However, type B is not immune to objections since

    its grammatical construction is not quite plausible. On this

    interpretation, the line consists of two clauses which are

    dependent on:

    ‗' (subject)

    (first predicate)

    (second predicate).‘ii

    The main problem of this construction is not that it requires

    supplying from the preceding clause before

    but that the meaning of supplied differs from

    the original one. The first means ‗it is (possible) to‘

    whereas the second one has to be understood in the sense ‗it

    is the reason‘.iii

    Taking into account both the problems and the

    advantages of types A and B, Wiesner suggests a new

    i Mourelatos 1970, p. 165.

    ii Mourelatos 1970, p. 166.

    iii Wiesner 1987, p. 174: ‗Sie macht ja ein Zeugma insofern

    erforderlich, als vor dem Infinitiv zunächst als ―es ist

    (möglich) zu ..., kann‖ erscheint, dann aber vor dem -Satz als

    ―ist der Grund, ‖ zum anschließenden ―weshalb‖ oder ―wherefore‖

    überleiten soll.‘

  • 14

    interpretation of the line listed as type C. But his

    interpretation is also susceptible to objections; for the

    present, it suffices only to mention that it is superfluous and

    (grammatically and factually) rather forced to construe

    as attribute (see our considerations further below).

    To reiterate, apart from the differences within each

    particular interpretational type (depending largely on the

    understanding of , there are three main

    possibilities of how to interpret our line which are based on

    . As to the grammatical construction, each type is

    somewhat problematic. Hence the interpreters are seeking

    to account for each type by virtue of factual reasons. I even

    suspect that in construing the line, Wiesner was primarily

    led by the alluring factual (i.e. ontological) considerations:

    For to construe as attribute and as

    ‗because‘ entails two reasons why being (what-is) can be

    thought: 1) Being can be thought only as identical, i.e.

    because it is identical. 2) Being can be thought because

    there is thought. According to Wiesner, this reason is

    supported by the fact ‗daß Erkennen nur mit dem Seienden

    anzutreffen ist (B 8,35-36), d.h. einem realen, sachhaltigen

    Objekt.‘i Yet, most scholars see in the line different factual

    or ontological implications. The advocates of the type A

    interpret it as stating the identity of being and thought

    i Wiesner 1987, p. 176.

  • 15

    whereas the advocates of the type B interpret it as follows:

    ‗The two clauses are complementary. The first guarantees

    the presence or the availability of a certain object. But it

    posits no obligation for mind to seek it. The second posits

    the obligation, but gives no guarantee of the object‘s

    availability.‘i

    Now, we seem to be moving in a circle since the

    grammatical reasons are conditioned by the factual ones and

    vice versa. How could we get out of this vicious circle? To

    be sure, there is no perfect and indisputable solution of how

    to understand our line since it is the destiny of all

    interpretation to be captive in a circle – may we call it

    vicious or hermeneutical. Nevertheless, despite (or rather

    because of) the problems pertaining to the line B 8.34, we

    should try to develop a new approach of how to interpret it.

    Let us start by tentatively considering the best

    grammatical construction. is best to be construed as

    subject (see the reasons mentioned in favor of the type B).

    However, unlike in the type B, we should avoid the

    supplying of before, which seems too forced

    and controversial. As to the rendering of which is

    most problematic, von Fritz‘s remark is worth quoting: ―It

    is true, as Fränkel points out, that in the overwhelming

    i Mourelatos 1970, p. 168. Cf. also Hölscher 1968, p. 99: ‗es ist

    das Denk-Mögliche und als solches der Grund für die Wahrheit des

    Denkens.‘

  • 16

    majority of the cases in which the word occurs in

    Homer, it means either ‗because‘ or ‗that‘ (...). But, in spite

    of this, it can hardly be denied that essentially and

    originally is (‗on account of which‘). (...)

    [I]ts origin from is so apparent that it is always

    possible to revert to the original meaning. In Parmenides the

    word occurs only once outside the passage

    discussed, but in this case it certainly means ‗because of

    which‘ or ‗therefore‘ (...).‖i In fact, for the meaning of

    in our line, it is decisive how it is used ‗in the only

    occurrence outside the passage discussed‘, i.e. two lines

    above (in B 8.32), where – as von Fritz and the majority of

    the interpreters concede – it has to be rendered as

    ‗therefore‘. Moreover, if we take into account that

    Parmenides‘ poem belongs to oral culture and as such was

    designed for listening to rather than reading, one may be

    even prone to think that Parmenides used in B

    8.32 (i.e. in a context where its meaning is unproblematic)

    only in order to make its meaning clear, thus giving his

    audience a clue of how to understand it two lines below.

    Our considerations about the best grammatical

    construction would, then, result in the following

    preliminary rendering:

    i von Fritz 1945, p. 237-238.

  • 17

    PR (Preliminary Rendering)

    What is in itself the same (i.e. ) is to think and

    that is why there is thought.

    The objection to this rendering is evident: it may be

    grammatically most appropriate but factually it is very

    problematic for it seems to be tautological. To say ‗Since it

    is possible to think (being), there is thought‘ is trivial and as

    such – we can suspect – it has nothing to do with the

    elaborate and sophisticated argument of the fragment B 8.

    Yet, before we reject this rendering on the grounds of its

    triviality, we should consider whether it is not only the

    translation into modern languages that is trivial and tauto-

    logical. Since the alleged tautology of the line is based on

    the conception of thought, we should first inquire into the

    meaning of and its cognates.

    II. The Meaning of

    Since our understanding of and draws

    largely upon Kurt von Fritz‘ brilliant study, let us start our

    inquiry into this topic by summarizing and rethinking some

    of his approaches and conclusions. His main contribution,

    let us preliminarily remember, consists in proving that

    whereas our concept of thought involves discursive activity

  • 18

    as its constitutive element, the Greek word being

    closely related to the sense of visioni is based on a passive

    and receptive relation to the world.

    Unlike the verbal form, the meaning of its

    nominal cognate underwent extensive changes which

    sometimes led even to the contradictory uses of this noun.

    Whereas the original meaning of was ‗to realize or to

    understand a situation‘,ii in Homer developed as

    follows: ‗Since the same situation may have a different

    ―meaning‖ to persons of different character and circum-

    stances of life, the notion develops that different persons or

    nations have different . As these different meanings of

    a situation evoke different reactions to it, and since these

    reactions are more or less typical of certain persons,

    sometimes implies the notion of a specific ―attitude‖.‘iii

    In

    opposition to many different another meaning of

    gained ground: a notion of ‗the which penetrates

    beyond the surface appearance [and] discovers the real truth

    about the matter. There can, then, be no different in

    this situation, as the in this case is obviously just

    one.‘iv

    In Hesiod further semantic shifts took place: ‗The

    i Cf. von Fritz 1945, p. 223: ‗But in the stage of the semantic

    development represented by the Homeric poems, the concept of is

    more closely related to the sense of vision.‘

    ii von Fritz 1945, p. 223.

    iii von Fritz 1945, p. 223.

    iv von Fritz 1945, p. 224.

  • 19

    notion that different persons may have different has

    been further developed in two opposite directions. On the

    one hand, the same person may have a different at

    different times. On the other hand, now can designate

    not only a more or less permanent attitude, as in Homer, but

    also a fixed moral character, so that the word is now often

    connected with adjectives expressing moral praise or

    blame.‘i

    Having analyzed Homer and Hesiod with respect of

    , von Fritz claims that ‗[w]ith the rise of philosophical

    speculation in the narrower sense, common language and

    philosophical terminology gradually begin to develop on

    different lines.‘ii Nonetheless, that is I suggest the most

    problematic move of von Fritz‘s analysis. For it is far from

    evident to assume – as he does – a philosophical tradition or

    line of thought based merely on such scanty evidence as

    provided by Xenophanes, Heraclitus and Parmenides. We

    cannot be even sure whether these thinkers were acquainted

    with one another, let alone assume a continuous line of their

    interdepending thoughts. So von Fritz appears to squeeze

    these thinkers into narrow limits of an assumed philo-

    sophical tradition that he takes to be determined by the

    i von Fritz 1945, p. 225.

    ii von Fritz 1945, p. 226-227.

  • 20

    tendency of to be rare and exceptional among people.i

    Although this notion of seems to obtain for

    Xenophanes and Heraclitus in whom only few occurrences

    of survived, it is not suitable for Parmenides. For in

    his poem there is at least one occurrence of that is

    unambiguously attributed to all men.ii

    So if we want to understand how was used in

    Parmenides, we should not close him up in a presumed or

    prefabricated line of thought but, instead, situate him in a

    wider contemporary language context (represented to us by

    the surviving contemporary texts). Let us then shortly

    survey the use of in the post-Homeric tradition as

    found primarily in the archaic lyric poetry, which – on von

    Fritz‘s account – represents the second (non-philosophical)

    i Cf. von Fritz 1945, p. 230: ‗In any case, the notion that is

    something exceptional which only few people possess becomes very

    prevalent in the generation after Xenophanes, especially with

    Heraclitus, though it can already be found in the poems of Semonides of

    Amorgos. It is obvious that this implies a change in the character of the

    insight which is supposed to be the result of genuine.‘

    ii It is the notorious expression in B 6.6. This

    is not rare and exceptional among men but rather widespread and

    even ubiquitous. It is further significant that von Fritz takes this

    expression to be mysterious and unintelligible: Cf. von Fritz 1945, p.

    237: ‗But a very real difficulty, which has never been solved and

    perhaps does not admit a perfect solution, is created by the fact that in

    some instances Parmenides seems to assert that and are

    always and necessarily connected with and and therefore with

    the truth, which seems to imply that the cannot err.‘ For the

    alternative interpretation of see the third and fourth

    sections of our paper.

  • 21

    line of the semantic development of he is not

    interested in. This survey reveals two main semantic trends

    of : 1) The is sometimes attributed to gods,

    thereby appearing to retreat out of range of ordinary

    people.i To attribute the to gods does not however

    necessarily involve denying it completely to ordinary men.

    It is only more difficult for them to possess it. It is this use

    of that the von Fritz analysis finds in Xenophanes and

    Heraclitus. Yet, this meaning of is quite rare in our

    extant texts. 2) As a number of occurrences of in our

    extent texts suggests, meant above all a character or

    even a kind of moral self. So the original Homeric notion of

    as a character or attitude was not only preserved and

    strengthened but also morally deepened and developed

    towards a kind of men‘s moral fundament or self. The

    frequent connection of with a moral attribute testifies

    to this sweeping trend.ii

    i Cf. Semonides: ' ' (fr. 1.3, Diehl);

    Solon: ' (fr. 17,

    Diehl); Theognis: (v.

    142).

    ii In Solon occurs eight times. Only once it is ascribed to

    God (cf. preceding note), the other occurrences testifies to the meaning

    ‗character or attitude‘. Moreover, since it is used five times with a moral

    attribute, it is possible to conclude that in Solon this (practical) meaning

    of is emphasized by its connection with the moral domain; cf.

    (fr. 3.7, Diehl); (fr. 4.7); (fr.

    5.10); (fr. 8.6); (fr. 23.15). For a similar

    account see Theognis; cf. (v. 74, cf. v. 88);

  • 22

    By the way, either semantic use of seems to

    have quite different a relationship to the original verbal

    form . For whereas in the former use might (as a

    kind of divine insight or plan) be related to the act of,i

    the in the latter use seems to be lacking all relations

    with the verbal form, meaning just a moral character.

    III. in Parmenides

    Let us now look at how is used in Parmenides.

    Preliminarily, it could be submitted that whereas was

    – as the majority of its occurrences in the contemporary

    texts suggests – usually used in moral-practical terms

    (meaning a character or even moral self), Parmenides seems

    to have used it quite differently. Since Parmenides‘ poem is

    usually understood as an ontological exposition, it is sus-

    (v. 89); v. 109); (v.

    196); (v. 223) etc.

    i This use of could be rendered either way (i.e. as an

    insight or a plan/intention) corresponding to the original Homeric

    meaning of as ‗realizing or understanding a situation‘, cf. von

    Fritz 1945, p. 223-224: ‗A dangerous situation, or a situation which

    otherwise deeply affects the individual realizing it, often immediately

    calls forth or suggest a plan to escape from, or to deal with, the

    situation. The visualization of this plan, which, so to speak, extends the

    development of the situation into the future, is then also considered a

    function of the, so that the terms and can acquire the

    meaning of ―plan‖ or ―planning‖.‘

  • 23

    pected that the meaning of is theoretical rather than

    moral-practical. For as the expressions like

    (‗Observe through your mind‘, B 4.1) or

    , ‗hold

    back your mind from this way of inquiry‘, B 7.2) suggest,

    Parmenides seems to conceive of the meaning of in

    theoretical terms. So there seems to be a considerable

    difference in how was used in usual colloquial

    language, on the one hand, and in Parmenides, on the other

    hand. That deserves not only our attention, but also an

    explanation.

    First of all, it is a question why we are so easily

    prone to understand in Parmenides in theoretical rather

    than practical terms. For although in the expressions

    mentioned above seems to have theoretical meaning, it is

    not difficult to imagine another constructions (e.g. ‗Observe

    by virtue of your character‘, ‗Hold back your character from

    this way of inquiry‘). There are I suggest at least two rea-

    sons for its theoretical construction: 1) The usual onto-

    logical or theoretical understanding of Parmenides‘ poem

    seems to play an important role in it. For if one expects to

    find in the poem an ontological exposition, they are also

    prone to understand as a basis of, or a capacity for,

    this ontological or theoretical activity. 2) Probably a more

    important reason for its theoretical construction involves

    our assumption or even prejudice to construe by

  • 24

    means of its connection to . As to , it is actually

    to be construed in theoretical terms since it is an activity of

    seeing, contemplating, or thinking. Moreover, in

    Parmenides it seems even to be explicitly connected with

    (cf. ‗without ... you won‘t find B 8.35-36).

    Since is supposed to be an ontological (i.e. highly

    theoretical) concept, the connection of to seems

    to only stress the original theoretical meaning of .

    Now, since there is an etymological or linguistic

    connection between and , we are prone to

    assume that – similarly to our words ‗to think‘ and

    ‗thought‘ – there must be also a functional or semantic con-

    nection between both Greek words. As we have however

    suggested at the end of second section of our paper, the

    functional or semantic connection between and

    is largely at odds with the contemporary usual and most

    frequent meaning of . For if was then construed in

    moral-practical terms as a character, it seems to have been

    discharged of most of its connections to . So although

    we can find it evident to functionally or semantically

    connect to (in particular because of the con-

    nection of our own words ‗to think‘ and ‗thought‘), in the

    contemporary language it did not seem to hold. In any case,

    in assuming the functional or semantic connection between

    and , we could be inclined to render as an

    act of, or a capacity for, , thereby understanding it in

  • 25

    theoretical terms. To reiterate, if means a character or

    a moral self, it is rather difficult to see how it could bear

    upon the verbal form, the meaning of which is the activity

    of seeing or contemplating.

    If the theoretical meaning of largely depends

    on its functional or semantic connection to , we can

    ask whether this connection is explicitly to be found in the

    poem or whether it is only vaguely implied on the analogy

    of our words ‗to think‘ and ‗thought‘. There is at least one

    place in the poem where both words seem to occur in a very

    close connection. This connection seems to be somehow

    established in the line B 8.34; but since it is this line we are

    dealing with and since we have not so far arrived at its

    interpretation, we had now better pass it over. Another

    place where the connection appears to be established im-

    mediately follows lines B 8.35-36 that (by means of the

    particle ) give reason for the line B 8.34: ‗For ()

    without being () on which it (i.e. ) once revealed

    dependsi you won‘t find contemplation ().‘ (B 8.35-

    i I construe the clause in keeping

    with Mourelatos‘ interpretation: ‗The key to the phrase is, I believe, not

    in the participle (from a rare verb, the semantics of

    which are unavoidably obscure) but in the phrases. The

    usual translation assumes that has vaguely locative or instrumental

    force. It has been overlooked that the together with can have

    an idiomatic sense ―to depend on, to rely upon, to be under the authority

    of‖.‘ (Mourelatos 1970, p. 171) The subject of the clause is

    supplied from the preceding line, being just the attribute.

  • 26

    36) As these lines suggest, and (or )i are

    linked by virtue of ii

    since both and are

    thought to be closely related to .iii

    Although the theoretical implications of in

    Parmenides‘ poem seems to be very strong and con-

    spicuous, there still remain two questions to ask: 1) Do

    i Although is sometimes distinguished from by the

    reference to the grammatical fact that the nouns with the ending

    designate the result of an action (cf. Stenzel 1989, p. 221), in

    Parmenides and mean the same (cf. von Fritz 1945, p. 241,

    n. 95). See also uses of in Xenophanes and Theognis: In

    fragment B 23 Xenophanes says that God is totally different from

    mortal beings in shape () and . The contrast with God‘s

    outer shape makes it clear that means his inner nature or

    character, and not (only) his thought. In three of all four occurrences (v.

    435, 1083, and 1149) Theognis uses synonymously with

    (meaning character). Only in v. 985 it seems to be used in the meaning

    ‗as swift as thought‘, but even this use of is more appropriately

    to be understood in terms of the swiftness of spirit that can immediately

    see even the most distant places and times (cf. von Fritz 1945, p. 224:

    ‗In this connection seems to designate the imagination by which

    we can visualize situations and objects which are remote in space and

    time.‘), and not in terms of the swiftness of thought as a particular act of

    thinking.

    ii See e.g. von Fritz 1945, p. 237: ‗Parmenides seems to assert

    (my italics) that and are always and necessarily connected

    with and ‘. Cf. also Wiesner‘s statement quoted in part above

    where the connection between and is also just supposed

    without being accounted for: ‗Der zweite Grund ―weil die Erkenntnis

    Bestand hat‖ wird dadurch gestützt, daß Erkennen nur mit dem

    Seienden anzutreffen ist (B 8,35-36), d.h. einem realen, sachhaltigen

    Objekt.‘ (Wiesner 1987, p. 176).

    iii Cf. 1) the relationship between and (‗without

    you will not find‘) and 2) the dependence of (or ) as

    the subject of the clause on .

  • 27

    really all occurrences of in the poem unambiguously

    testify to theoretical meaning? 2) Even if there is a unique.

    all uses of in Parmenides are completely lacking all

    practical implications had in the contemporary

    colloquial usage?

    As to the first question, we can answer it in the

    negative. For there is at least one occurrence of in the

    poem that unambiguously testifies to the colloquial

    practical meaning of as a character. It is the occu-

    rrence of in the line B 6.6. But before embarking on its

    interpretation, we should remember the context in which it

    occurs. As the survey of the contemporary, primarily lyric

    texts suggest, the main part of the fragment B 6 works up

    the traditional views about men and their relation to gods,

    which can be taken to be a kind of archaic anthropology.i

    Given its almost stereotypical use in the lyrics, the archaic

    anthropology could be considered to be a standard lyric

    motive. As the fragment B 6 taking up the traditional lyric

    vocabulary of the archaic anthropology states, in

    comparison with the omnipotent and omniscient gods, men

    appear to be not-knowing (cf. , B 6.4),

    helpless (cf. , B 6.5), straying (cf. , B

    6.5), deaf and blind (cf. , B 6.7) etc.

    i Cf. Mansfeld 1964, p. 1-41.

  • 28

    Now, it is significant that within Parmenides‘

    exposition of the archaic anthropology the word

    occurs, being attributed to ordinary men who are helpless,

    not-knowing, deaf and blind. Its relationship to ordinary

    men is further stressed by the attribute (‗straying‘,

    B 6.6) by which it is accompanied. In other words, (as

    a ) is here explicitly understood as straying,

    i.e. erroneous, labile, or changing. Now, if we take into

    account our preliminary survey of the uses of in the

    poem that largely accord with its usual theoretical

    understanding, the use of in B 6.6 seems to be quite

    unique, even anomalous. For – as we have seen – the usual

    meaning of in the poem seems to be construed by

    means of its connection to being, the appears to

    exclude any kind of error or lability; indeed it is hardly

    conceivable that what is essentially connected with the

    unchanging steady being could be labile. So, on this

    interpretation, the very notion of a straying or labile

    has to be dismissed as a unique or even anomalous use of

    in Parmenides.i

    i Cf. von Fritz 1945, p. 237: ‗But a very real difficulty, which

    has never been solved and perhaps does not admit a perfect solution, is

    created by the fact that in some instances Parmenides seems to assert

    that and are always and necessarily connected with

    and and therefore with the truth, which seems to imply that the

    cannot err.‘

  • 29

    Now, as to our first question, we can submit that

    there is indeed one occurrence of in the poem that

    unambiguously testifies to its colloquial practical meaning

    (to be rendered as a character). For if, within the exposition

    of the archaic anthropology, is attributed to ordinary,

    i.e. helpless and not-knowing men, it is first to be expected

    that it has practical rather than theoretical meaning. This

    colloquial practical meaning further explains why the

    can be straying, i.e. labile or erroneous. For it allows us not

    to construe by means of its apparently essential

    connection to being so that its straying or labile nature

    would no longer be suspicious or even problematic.

    Let us now turn to our second question, i.e. whether

    other occurrences of in the poem could also have

    some practical implications. To reiterate, our preliminary

    survey, that is in accord with the usual interpretation of

    suggested that in the poem should be construed

    in theoretical terms. Nevertheless, if there is one

    unambiguous practical use of in the poem (as it is in B

    6.6), then excluding all practical implications from other

    occurrences of would involve assuming two quite

    distinct and incompatible uses of in the poem.

    Although one usually tends to understand in this way,

    it would be nevertheless more plausible to assume that there

    is only one conception of in the poem. If so,

    should have both theoretical and practical meaning. In other

  • 30

    words, each occurrence of should be understood as

    having both theoretical and practical implications.

    Moreover, if we considered the occurrence of

    in the fragment B 6 to be unique or even anomalous, not

    only its very occurrence would be strange and incidental

    but, consequently, the whole exposition of the archaic

    anthropology in fragment B 6 would become rather

    superfluous and futile. However, given the central role of

    fragment B 6 for Parmenides‘ (ontological) argumenti, we

    have to take everything in the fragment to essentially

    contribute to Parmenides‘ argument or his narrative

    strategy.ii

    i The first two lines are usually considered to essentially

    contribute to an assumed ontological argument of the poem: Parmenides

    first relates being to and (given the difficult syntax of the

    first sentence, the precise form of the relationship is however a matter

    of dispute among the interpreters) and second makes a vital contention

    that whereas there is being, nothing is not (cf. B 6.1-2). Sometimes the

    fragment B 6 or rather its first two lines are taken to constitute a part of

    a continuous ontological argument containing the fragments B 2, B 3,

    and B 6.

    ii As we have suggested in the previous note, only the first two

    lines of B 6 are usually considered to relevantly contribute to

    Parmenides‘ intrinsic (ontological) argument, and the rest of the

    fragment where there is the exposition of the archaic anthropology is

    taken to be a mere poetical or metaphorical pendant to the intrinsic

    (ontological) argument.

  • 31

    IV. Interpretation of B 8.34

    After these general considerations about in

    Parmenides‘ poem, let us return to the line B 8.34. In the

    first section of our paper we have considered its most

    plausible syntactical construction and arrived at the

    following preliminary rendering (PR): ‗What is in itself the

    same (i.e. ) is to think and that is why there is thought.‘

    Yet, despite its syntactical plausibility, its (philosophical)

    meaning appeared problematic. For, on this rendering, the

    line amounts to saying ‗Since it is possible to think (being),

    there is thought‘. So the line seems to be trivial or even

    tautological. Yet, having clarified the meaning of and

    in particular that of (or ), we can now translate

    its rendering as follows:

    B 8.34

    What is in itself the same (i.e. ) is to contemplate

    and that is why the mind/character () is true.

    The line involves two statements: 1) being () is

    to contemplate () and 2) the contemplation of being

    makes mind/character true; as to the truthfulness of mind, I

  • 32

    take to be used in the veridical meaning.i The usual

    interpretation assumes that the intimate connection

    between and (seemingly supported, e.g., by the B

    8.35-36 ‗Without being () (...) you won‘t find

    contemplation ().‘) the truthfulness of mind would be

    indeed trivial, for it is first assumed that there is a semantic

    or functional similarity between and or

    ( so is thus understood as an act of, or a capacity for,

    ), so that – because of its connection to – is

    secondly supposed to be always true and steady. But if, on

    the contrary, the very nature of is labile and erroneous

    (and as the expression in B 6.6 clearly

    suggests it is), then the line puts forward a very nontrivial

    and even revolutionary idea, i.e. that the truthfulness of

    mind/character is possible only by means of the

    contemplation of being. In other words, in order for the line

    to be nontrivial, it has to presuppose the colloquial practical

    meaning of .

    i If we take the lability and erroneousness of the (as it is

    corroborated by the expression ) seriously, we have to

    construe in the veridical meaning. For if we interpreted it, e.g., in

    the existential meaning, the line would read as follows: The very

    existence of the is conditioned by the act of the contemplation of

    being; so if someone is not able to contemplate being, they do not have

    the , which entails its nonexistence. Yet since in B 6 is

    unambiguously attributed to ordinary, i.e. helpless and not-knowing,

    men, who confuse being and nonbeing (cf. B 6.8-9), the contemplation

    of being cannot itself guarantee the existence of the , as it is usually

    supposed.

  • 33

    Therefore the line has to be interpreted on two

    levels:

    1) The line makes sense only on the assumption that

    the is by itself labile and erroneous. This meaning of

    is not only clearly stated in B 6 but – as we found out

    in the second section of our paper – it was its ordinary

    colloquial meaning. Now, as we have suggested and as we

    would see more clearly in connection with the second level

    of interpretation, it might have been Parmenides‘ intention

    to get over this exclusively practical meaning of

    towards a more philosophically promising and relevant one.

    Still, in interpreting the line we have to proceed from the

    ordinary practical meaning. For it was this meaning which

    Parmenides had at his disposal when he composed his poem

    and from which he had to proceed by conceiving of in

    a new way. Moreover, if we take account of his audience,

    that was at that time constituted by listeners rather than

    readers, it is hardly conceivable that Parmenides would

    have utterly ignored its expectations and possibilities of

    understanding and used one of his key philosophical terms

    in a rather solipsistic manner. Indeed, it is hardly

    conceivable that he (or any other author) would have run

    the risk of being totally misunderstood by his audience.i

    i Of course, it could be at once objected that Parmenides was a

    philosopher who ignored the contemporary audience and

    uncompromisingly elaborated his visions and arguments. Although

  • 34

    However, against the background of the ordinary

    practical meaning of , the line not only becomes

    intelligible, but also receives a new important dimension.

    For whereas the line has so far been usually understood in

    (theoretical) terms of epistemology (i.e. as somehow

    relating or to ), its practical and even ethical

    dimension now becomes evident. On this practical or

    ethical interpretation, the first part of the line (‗What is in

    itself the same is to contemplate‘) is to be understood as an

    appeal to contemplating being, whereas the second one

    (‗that is why the mind/character is true‘) states what one can

    expect as the fulfillment of the appeal, i.e. truthfulness and

    steadiness of one‘s own character. Hence, by contemplating

    being, our mind/character becomes true and steady; in other

    words, by contemplating being, we can hope to overcome

    the lability and erroneousness of our character or even our

    human nature.

    2) As to the first level of interpretation, it largely re-

    presents the way of how contemporary audiences would

    have proceeded by interpreting the line. Yet, as we have

    suggested, it might have been Parmenides‘ intention to

    philosophers could be seen that way, in the case of Parmenides that kind

    of philosophic arrogance is out of place. As we have suggested, his

    audience was listeners rather than readers. Unlike the readers, who –

    because of their repeated reading – have the time and possibility to

    rethink their usual notions, the listeners have to immediately grasp the

    meaning of what they are listening to.

  • 35

    achieve the essential link between and and,

    consequently, construe in theoretical terms. It is the

    lines B 8.34-36 that seem to testify to this effort: ‗What is in

    itself the same (i.e. ) is to contemplate and that is why

    the mind/character () is true. For () without being

    () on which it depends (i.e. ), once revealed you

    won‘t find contemplation ().‘ The theoretical

    construction of or the functional connection between

    and seems to be established by virtue of ; for

    both and are here thought to be closely related

    to .i

    It is, however, significant that the connection of

    and to (and thereby the theoretical

    construction of ) is not argued for but rather

    rhetorically or poetically invoked. One can be of course

    inclined to refuse this interpretation as not philosophically

    relevant, for philosophy is supposed to proceed by ar-

    guments and justifications. Still, before doing so, we should

    realize that, on the usual interpretation, the connection of

    and to is also very vague, being merely

    assumed, i.e. not only not argued for, but not explained

    either. So, in comparison with the usual interpretation that

    is based on a mere assumption, our interpretation provides

    i Cf. 1) the relationship between and (‗without

    you won‘t find‘) and 2) the dependence of (or ) as the

    subject of clause on .

  • 36

    an explanation. If we take into account that we are dealing

    with a poem, it is not so surprising that there are non-

    argumentative narrative strategies and procedures there. At

    any rate, it is also significant that in philosophical tradition

    this interpretation, that is only secondary, has become not

    only prevalent, but the only possible.

    V. Conclusion

    Unlike the usual approach that construes the line B

    8.34 in terms of epistemology, we should proceed from the

    ordinary practical meaning of as a character. In our

    interpretation, the line is then to be understood both as an

    ethical appeal and as Parmenides‘ effort to redefine or

    extend the colloquial practical meaning of towards a

    more theoretical or epistemological one. If we, on the other

    hand, discarded the relevance of the ordinary practical

    meaning of for the interpretation of the poem, we

    would not only run the risk of misconstruing it but we

    would not be able to correctly appreciate Parmenides‘

    innovative genius and his contribution to philosophy; in

    other words, we would miss how he established the fun-

    ctional connection between and or how he

    conceived in theoretical terms.

  • 37

    In our interpretation of line B 8.34, there further

    seems to be an important (practical or ethical) alternative

    between two sorts of human attitude or character () in

    Parmenides‘ poem: the one , we can call philosophical,

    is characterized by its truthfulness and steadiness (being

    dependent on ), whereas the other, peculiar to ordinary

    men as characterized by the archaic anthropology, is

    straying, erroneous and labile. This interpretation may have

    some consequences for the understanding of the poem as a

    whole. For whereas it is usually seen as a kind of theoretical

    treatise on ontology or epistemology, it now turns out to

    have important practical implications. In fact, it is what one

    would expect from the very fact that it is a poem composed

    in Homeric hexameters and using the Homeric and the old

    lyric vocabulary and phraseology (e.g., the motive of

    archaic anthropology).

  • 38

    Bibliography:

    Cordero, N.-L., 1984, Les deux chemins de Parménide,

    Paris.

    Fritz, K. von, 1945, ―Nous, Noein, and Their Derivatives in

    Pre-Socratic Philosophy (excluding Anaxagoras): Part I.

    From the Beginnings to Parmenides‖, in: Classical

    Philology, p. 223-242.

    Gadamer, H.-G., 1996, Der Anfang der Philosophie,

    Stuttgart.

    Heitsch, E., 1974, Parmenides. Die Anfänge der Ontologie,

    Logik und Naturwissenschaft, München.

    Hölscher, U., 1968, Anfängliches Fragen, Göttingen.

    Hölscher, U., 1986, Parmenides. Vom Wesen des Seienden,

    Frankfurt a.M.

    Mansfeld, J., 1964, Die Offenbarung des Parmenides und

    die Menschliche Welt, Assen.

    Mourelatos, A. P. D., 1970, The Route of Parmenides, New

    Haven, London.

    Stenzel, J., 1989, ―Zur Entwicklung des Geistesbegriffes in

    der griechischen Philosophie‖, in: H.-G. Gadamer, (ed.),

    Um die Begriffswelt der Vorsokratiker, Darmstadt, p. 214-

    245.

  • 39

    Tarán, L., 1965, Parmenides. A Text with Translation,

    Commentary, and Critical Essays, Princeton, New Persey.

    Wiesner, J., 1987, ―Überlegungen zu Parmenides B 8,34‖,

    in: P. Aubenque (ed.), Études sur Parménide II. Paris.

  • 40

  • 41

    Chiara Chinello

    Oedipus, the Tragedy of Self Recognition

    My intent in this article is to show how, according to

    Ricoeur, the tragedy of Oedipus can be read as a tragedy of

    self recognition. In order to do that, we need to view

    Oedipus‘ story as a whole. This means that we should read

    Oedipus Rex in light of Oedipus at Colonus. This will help

    us to understand that two identities will be reached at the

    end of the story, the identity of a man, Oedipus, and the

    identity of a state institution, Athens. So this tale has

    political value, as well.

    We can read this story as a whole. As it is symbolic,

    it needs two opposite developments to be understood; a

    retrospective quest, which goes towards its origins and

    towards the birth of tragedy in general, to reconstruct its

    past and an anticipating quest, which permits a new

    meaning to emerge. To follow these developments in the

    story of Oedipus, we must use two different perspectives:

    the archaeological interpretation, which goes back to the

    past and reaches the unconscious by overcoming the border

    of repressed instincts, and the teleological construction,

    which offers the opportunity to solve the conflict of the

    interpretations of the self by walking the path of truth. This

  • 42

    implies that we should follow two different magistri

    through this path: Freud and Hegel. We are going to start

    with Freud.

    The Freudian interpretation of tragedy

    According to Freud (1900), tragedy has its own source in

    the same primitive heritage on which we draw liberally.

    ‗His destiny (that of Oedipus) moves us only because it

    might have been ours […].‘ And then he adds: ‗King

    Oedipus […] merely shows us the fulfilment of our own

    childhood wishes.‘i This tragedy consists of a process of

    revealing ‗that Oedipus himself is the murderer of Laius,

    but further, that he is the son of the murdered man and of

    Jocasta.‗ii The pleasure we feel seeing his misadventures

    derives from two processes: the identification with Oedipus,

    which the spectator experiences, and the distance that he

    knows divides him from the character on stage. To

    understand why we see ourselves in Oedipus as if we were

    looking at ourselves in a mirror, we need to investigate this

    primitive heritage and to find the reason for the pleasure we

    feel by means of the enjoyment that takes place.

    In his essay: Psychopatische Personen auf der

    i 261.

    ii 262.

  • 43

    Bühne, Psychopathic Characters on the Stage, Freud says

    that the purpose of drama consists of:

    opening up sources of pleasure or enjoyment in our

    emotional life, just as, in the case of intellectual

    activity, joking or fun open up similar sources, many

    of which that [intellectual] activity had made

    inaccessible.i

    These sources are normally closed, having been

    madeunreachable for our consciousness. But they have not

    been erased. They are still there in our unconscious and,

    sometimes, they find a way to reveal themselves. This is

    possible thanks to the play, intended in both its meanings as

    a piece acted on stage and as a child‘s game.

    Freud explains that the performance has the same

    function for adults as the play has for children. To be more

    exact, we could say that they obtain an opposite effect:

    while playing, children act as if they were adults, and they

    are able to imagine their future; whilst seeing a drama,

    adults relive that childhood feeling of being able to do

    anything, and they are able to recall their past. In both

    cases, what emerges is will power, a desire to reshape the

    world and their destiny in their own image. Briefly, we

    i Freud, S. (1905 or 1906). 305.

  • 44

    could say that spectators enjoy the drama because in this

    way their narcissism is gratified. By identifying themselves

    with the characters on stage, they become heroes. The

    ‗pleasure principle‘ here overcomes the ‗reality principle‘.

    Moreover, drama allows some dangerous feelings to

    emerge from our subconscious, without our being

    compromised by them. Their catastrophic consequences are

    suffered by someone else, and after all it is all an illusion,

    which lets us watch what happens without any danger. So

    this character identification is neither definitive nor

    permanent; it is instead revocablei: when the ludus

    scaenicus finishes, spectators put themselves back in their

    own shoes again and restart their ‗normal‘ life. Drama gives

    ‗an enjoyable shape even to forebodings of misfortune.‗ii

    Pleasure derives from the awareness of the aesthetic

    distance which separates the audience from the violence

    performed. It is an experience of suffering which can be

    lived without dying, thanks to character identification.

    Though tragedy shows all the aspects of suffering, it

    involves a principle of compensation as well and the

    possibility of pleasure. This is its greatest ἀποπία.

    This is also true of Oedipus. In a letter to his friend Fliess,

    dated October 15th

    , 1897, Freud writes that Oedipus

    i Cf. Lavagetto, M. (1985). Freud, Literature and Other. 359.

    Torino: Einaudi. [In Italian].

    ii Freud, S. (1905 or 1906). 306.

  • 45

    represents the fulfilment of a desire, which comes from our

    own childhood. There is a difference between us and him,

    as well. We are happier than he is, because we have

    separated our sexual impulses from our mother and we have

    forgotten our envy towards our father. The horror we feel

    towards his story is caused by the primal repression of our

    desires. The poet obliges us to face our inner selves, where

    they still survive.

    The desire is not attainable in itself: its only access

    consists of semantics: the symbolism is the mathematics of

    instinct. By means of symbols, desire and impulses are

    articulated and acquire meaning which must be subjected to

    constant interpretation. Only in this way do we not lose the

    vital and changing afflatus of the longing for existence of

    which they are expressions. As lava tends to solidify upon

    contact with air, so does sentiment, which runs the risk of

    being fossilized when emerging at the level of discourse;

    the symbol is the only institution capable of preserving its

    fluidity.

    Pleasure in drama is related as well to the sacrifice

    which men were obliged to make by the need to enter

    society. They had to accept the reality principle and

    sacrifice part of their narcissism. This process caused those

    discontents of civilization which gave name to one of

  • 46

    Freud‘s most famous textsi. There is also something more.

    Tragedies and their representations give vent to that primary

    drive which, according to Freud, is as fundamental as Eros:

    the death drive, Todestrieb or Thanatos. Tragedy offers an

    advantage to society: this drive can be satisfied by means of

    performance so that it does not need to be actualized.

    Furthermore, the origins of drama should not be

    forgotten: its birth belongs in a religious context. In the

    beginning, dramatisations were performed during religious

    ceremonies, and their origin probably can be traced back to

    sacrificial rites.

    In Psychopathic Characters on the Stage Freud says

    that a hero is someone who rebels against God and the

    presence of suffering in the world, ‗and pleasure is derived,

    as it seems, from the affliction of a weaker being in the face

    of divine might.‘ii So the origins of drama can be found in a

    rebellion against God and society and in fact, according to

    Freud, there are three kinds of drama: religious drama,

    social drama and drama of character, which differ only in

    the domain of action.iii

    In Totem and Taboo, Freud says that

    this rebellion against the Father-God led to a sense of guilt.

    This tragic guilt is borrowed by the hero, who must suffer

    and take the guilt out on himself ‗in order to relieve the

    i Cf. Freud, S. (1930). 59-145.

    ii Freud, S. (1905 or 1906). 89.

    iii Cf. Freud, S. (1905 or 1906). 90-91.

  • 47

    Chorus from theirs.‗i He is that Father-God and his death

    has to be reproduced on stage. This scene is hypocritical,

    because in reality the members of the Chorus were those

    who had committed the crime, who had rebelled against

    authority; now they commiserate with the hero whom at the

    same time they had condemned to suffer.

    Κάθαπζιρ is not only an aesthetic phenomenon, it

    also has religious and anthropological genesis, because it is

    the expiation of a sin which was truly committed.

    According to Freud, the sin being the father‘s killing and

    the consequent violation of the incest prohibition. The

    tragedy of Oedipus shows the origins of religion and

    society. However, this tragedy also shows something more

    interesting: it contains evidence of something else and its

    way of proceeding is similar to that of psychoanalysis. The

    spectators‘ reaction to it derives from acknowledging

    themselves in Oedipus. They see that beyond God and fate,

    their subconscious is hidden. They discover their identity by

    watching this tragedy.

    i Freud, S. (1913). 156.

  • 48

    Ricoeur’s mimesis 3 and its capability to rebuild

    the world

    Following Freud‘s analysis of the tragedy of Oedipus to

    this point, we have explored the origins of drama and the

    cause of the pleasure it generates. We have discovered that

    in drama we find again our past as individuals and species;

    we have recognized a part of our own story in Oedipus‘

    story. Ricoeur goes further and interprets the story of

    Oedipus as a tragedy of self-consciousness, as the

    explication of the Delphic motto ‗γνῶθι ζεαςηόν‟, ‗know

    thyself‘. Tragedy helps us to recognize our true identity and

    to elaborate upon it. It is a symptom as well as a treatment.

    Every tragedy teaches us who we are and which

    consequences our actions will have. It teaches how to be

    happy. ‗Every tragedy stages the relationship between

    action and happiness or unhappiness, through virtue and

    vices.‗i The pleasure we feel is the pleasure of learning and

    the pleasure of recognition. This pleasure which derives

    from fear and pity and which is what Aristotle called

    κάθαπζιρ, leads to the level which Ricoeur calls mimesis 3ii.

    He draws on the Aristotelian idea of narration as an

    imitation of actions, mimesis, to explain how narration can

    give a new meaning to the world in which we inhabit. To do

    i Cf. Ricoeur, P (1984). Interview.

    ii Cf. Ricoeur, P. (1984). 50.

  • 49

    so he uses Gadamers‘ Hermeneutic Circle, which he

    transforms into another circle, the Circle of Mimesis.

    According to Ricoeur, we can distinguish three kinds of

    mimesis:

    Mimesis 1, the field of ππᾶξιρ, always already

    prefigured and pre-interpreted. At this level ethics is

    not yet a rule, but it is an intuition of the models of

    actions which constitute what Hegel calls

    Sittlichkeit, the ethical substance of society. It

    creates a normative dimension which becomes

    paradigmatic to confront and value actions. Ricoeur

    (1984) says that there are no stories which do not

    arouse approval or disapproval when confronted

    with a hierarchy of values, whose poles are

    goodness and wickedness.

    Mimesis 2, the level in which actions are configured

    in a story; they receive an order, a new and deeper

    sense. ‗C‘est dans la mesure où l‘action en tant que

    telle a une dimension éthique, que le récit, qui en est

    la mimèsis, a lui aussi une dimension éthique.‘i

    Mimesis 3, where the story in the form of a text can

    re-enter the world to be inhabited by readers and to

    re-shape the world of actions. ‗What is

    communicated, in the final analysis, is, beyond the

    i Ricoeur, P. (1996). 656.

  • 50

    sense of a work, the world it projects and that

    constitutes its horizon.‘i

    At this stage, tragedy is able to enter the world of human

    actions again, and to change it. ‗The thought experiments

    we conduct in the great laboratory of the imaginary are also

    explorations in the realm of good and evil.‘ii Once

    have discovered themselves in Oedipus, they cannot avoid

    rethinking their own life too. This aspect is not owned only

    by tragedies; instead it is characteristic to every text. The

    text offers its readers the possibility of finding themselves

    within it. It helps them to see themselves as the starting

    points of a series of actions. ‗Discourse in action and in use

    refers backwards and forwards, to a speaker and a world'iii

    .

    Texts are written discourses which address themselves to a

    cogito so that he could reshape his world. For this reason

    they always contain an ethical connotation, which can be

    enlightened by a science of interpretation: the hermeneutics.

    The ethical aspect of hermeneutics is that it offers the

    possibility to build a world which can be inhabited.

    Between narration and life there is a gap emphasized by

    symbols and metaphors. This gap prevents us from an

    immediate apprehension of reality and helps us to discover

    new meanings within it, thanks to the emergence of

    i Ricoeur, P. (1984). 77.

    ii Ricoeur, P. (1992). 164.

    iii Ricoeur, P. (1976). 22.

  • 51

    meaning to which symbols and metaphors give hospitality.

    Otherwise we would have a perfect coincidence between

    reality and our apprehension of it and due to this univocity,

    no ethics would be possible.

    Comme un texte, l‘action humaine est une œuvre

    ouverte, dont la signification est «en suspens». C‘est

    parce qu‘elle «ouvre» de nouvelles références et en

    reçoit une pertinence nouvelle que les actes humains

    sont aussi en attente d‘interprétation nouvelles

    décidant de leur signification.i

    This assumption is possible because here Ricoeur

    entwines Aristotle‘s conception of mimesis with the

    Kantian conception of the aesthetic, which has a unifying

    function given by the faculty of judgement. At the level of

    the tragedy, mimesis 2 according to Ricoeur‘s

    classification, the Kantian reflective judgement is at work in

    order to give a new succession to the events which take

    place but, by doing so, a new meaning is given to the story

    as a whole and to those events as single happenings. They

    assume a sense in relation to a subject who has to take

    charge of those new implications and of those new

    meanings. This is an ethical task. ‗Le récit, jamais

    i Ricoeur, P. (1986). 220.

  • 52

    éthiquement neutre, est le premier laboratoire du jugement

    moral.‘i

    Hegel and the way of teleology

    To understand how this is possible and to interpret

    the drama of Oedipus properly, we need the help of another

    magister: Hegel. We said that the tragedy of Oedipus is

    symbolic, and its true meaning can be found only in light of

    what comes next. Oedipus rex can be read as the ‗tragedy of

    truth,‗ii if examined in the light of the subsequent Oedipus

    Colonus. The Oedipus trilogy is really a tragedy of self

    recognition, according to Ricoeur: Oedipus‘ guilt is his

    ὕβπιρ, his claim to be in possession of truth. This ὕβπιρ of

    truth is also owned by the spectators. The ὕβπιρ of truth

    must be purified in order to obtain the real knowledge of

    self. This can be reached only by means of poetic replica,

    the only figure which is capable of keeping together the

    ἀποπίαι, which constitute human identity and which cannot

    be solved by choosing only one of the alternatives: Oneself

    as another is the secret of human identity. This identity can

    only be told by constructing a plot and that is what Oedipus

    does: while he discovers the truth about his identity, he tells

    i Ricoeur, P. (1990). 197.

    ii Ricoeur, P. (1974). 112.

  • 53

    the story of himself and he becomes an adult. Hence this is

    also what the spectators do while watching Oedipus‘ story.

    The blind Tiresias is the real representative of truth, and for

    this reason Oedipus persecutes him. The conflict played out

    by this tragedy is the conflict between the human pretension

    of owning the totality of truth and the accepted blindness of

    the seer. Oedipus will end his days blind: he decides to

    blind himself, because when he could see, he was not able

    to see the real truth. By putting out his eyes, he lets his

    inner and intellectual eye see the real light of truth. This

    meaning of Oedipus Rex can be understood only in the light

    of Oedipus at Colonus. The archaeological hermeneutics of

    Freud is no longer sufficient, as it explores the symbolism

    of this story to retrace the past of mankind. Here, we need a

    new hermeneutics, the teleological hermeneutics, which

    interprets one figure in the light of the next one. This means

    that we should read the first tragedy considering the end of

    the story, which is told in the second tragedy.

    Thus there are indeed two types of hermeneutics. One

    is oriented towards the resurgence of archaic symbols

    and the other towards the emergence of new symbols

    and ascending figures, all absorbed into the final

  • 54

    stage, which, as in the Phenomenology of Spirit, is no

    longer a figure but as knowledge.i

    Oedipus is not the voluntary author of his first

    actions. He suffers his destiny. However, the end of his

    story shows that there is still something that he can do: he

    can carry upon his shoulders that unwilling guilt, by

    acknowledging himself as the starting point of his actions.

    He is able to acknowledge his responsibility in this

    initiative. The initiative is the external proof that we can

    start something new, that a new series of events can begin.

    So Ricoeur can say: „la promesse (…) est l‘éthique de

    l‘initiative.‗ii The initiative is ‗an intervention of the agent

    action into the course of the world, an intervention that

    effectively causes changes in the world.‗iii

    The recognition, ἀναγνώπιζιρ, is defined by

    Aristotle as a transition from ignorance to knowledge;

    Aristotle himself sees the best example of it in the tragedy

    of Oedipusiv

    . Having arrived at Colon, Oedipus can de-

    termine which crime he has really committed, he can

    evaluate his acts. He now comprehends his innocence. ‗I am

    charged with a crime, stranger;‗ says Oedipus, ‗yes, I am so

    i Ricoeur, P. (1974). 114.

    ii Ricoeur, P. (1986). 301.

    iii Ricoeur, P. (1992). 109.

    iv Aristotle, Poetics, 1452 a 33.

  • 55

    charged in spite of myself; let the gods know, I wanted

    nothing of this (421-422).‗i No one else but Oedipus has

    killed his father and married his mother, and he feels regret,

    but he can also feel relief because of his ignorance and

    innocence. According to Ricoeur, the tragedy of Oedipus is

    the best example of a Bildungsroman: by following his

    story, we can understand what the Freudian motto: Wo es

    war, soll ich werden means.

    This tragedy can also be read in the light of the

    latest book by Ricoeur: The Course of Recognition.

    Following the indications given by Ricoeur in this book, we

    can say that Oedipus completes a course of recognition. At

    the end of Oedipus Rex, Oedipus reaches the first level of

    recognition; he discovers his natural ties, that is, he finally

    knows who his real parents are and to which family he

    belongs. Those natural ties which were denied to him are

    now restored. Oedipus at Colonus, furthermore, shows

    Oedipus being accepted in a social and political context,

    entering this way the second and third level of recognition.

    According to Ricoeur, recognition can be classified as a

    relation of reciprocity, understood in the Kantian Critique

    of Pure Reason‘s sense: ‗All substances, in so far as they

    can be perceived to coexist in space, are in thoroughgoing

    reciprocity.‘ The principle of reciprocal action can be

    i Cf. Ricoeur, P. (2005). 78.

  • 56

    called, this way, a principle of community.i To complete the

    the self recognition, the institutional recognition appears as

    essential and necessary.

    Oedipus, a political tragedy

    My personal opinion is that this reading of Oedipus,

    when put into perspective, gives us something more, which

    we should investigate further. From my point of view, it is

    not only Oedipus‘ identity which is discovered at the end of

    the story. This tragedy also has political value. However, let

    us take it one step at a time and see how the story ends.

    Finally, Oedipus‘ suffering comes to an end. His condition

    as a persecuted being and a reject from society finds a

    conclusion. He eventually finds peace and is at last received

    into a political community. His isolation ends. This can

    happen because finally Oedipus understands. What happens

    here is that Oedipus is now conscious of not being king. His

    kingdom has led to only pity and suffering, being based on

    ignorance of his true identity and arrogance of being master

    of his destiny. His desire for totality has been put in doubt

    and mortally wounded. His damned progeny is condemned

    to perish and end without successors. Thebes is destined to

    be torn apart by civil war. The desire for dominion and

    i Ricoeur, P. (2005), 153.

  • 57

    complete possession, which distinguishes Oedipus‘ race,

    will be humiliated and defeated. Here the real nature of man

    and of political dimension emerges.

    Man is essentially desire, but this desire has the

    character of a subversive and potentially dangerous Trieb, a

    drive full of aggression: ‗Men are not gentle creatures, who

    want to be loved, and who at the most can defend them-

    selves if they are attacked; they are, on the contrary,

    creatures among whose instinctual endowments are to be

    reckoned a powerful share of aggressiveness‘ said Freud,

    and further: ‗Homo homini lupus [man is wolf to man].

    Who in the face of all his experience of life and of history

    will have the courage to dispute this assertion?‘i

    Civilization has been built in accordance with

    utilitarian purposes: to guarantee the survival of humanity.

    It has conveyed the burden of sublimation of impulses and

    narcissism upon itself to uphold this guarantee. It offers

    comfort and protection and rewards the sacrifice of the

    impulse of aggression towards others made by the indi-

    vidual by means of art, science, and religion; the

    constructions of culture. According to Freud, civilization is

    an order suspended over evil: the potential violence of indi-

    vidualistic and amoral libido is suspended and sublimated,

    but it is not overcome.

    i Freud, S. (1930), 63.

  • 58

    Society consists of only the discovery that the greatest

    strength of an individual could be overcome by the union of

    the weaker people:

    Violence could be broken by union, and the power of

    those who were united now represented law in

    contrast to the violence of the single individual. Thus

    we see that right is the might of a community. It is

    still violence, ready to be directed against any

    individual who resists it; it works by the same

    methods and follows the same purposes. The only real

    difference lies in the fact that what prevails is no

    longer the violence of an individual but that of a

    community.i

    Even the evangelical precept: love thy neighbour as thyself,

    hides a perversion: that person whom I love by loving my

    neighbour is myself. Therefore, altruism is a narcissistic and

    selfish sentiment, a critique already applied to Christianity

    by Nietzsche.

    Can this really be the only key to understanding the

    social phenomenon? According to Ricoeur, no, it cannot,

    and to demonstrate this he uses the concept developed by

    the young Hegel in Jena, that of man as desire for others‘

    i Freud, S. (1932). 204-205.

  • 59

    desire, which is expressed in the political and social sphere

    by the need for respect, the basis of the process of

    recognition, thus, becoming: ‗the desire to live well with

    and for others in just institutions.‘i The same Ricoeurian

    attempt to integrate the archaeology of the subject by Freud

    with the Hegelian teleology of self-consciousness can be

    read as an effort to rediscover the presence of the other even

    in the roots of man's desire to be, which constitutes identity.

    But the political dream of a state where it would be

    possible to live in peace and in accordance with law and

    justice is neither death nor destined to be defeated even in

    the tragedy of Oedipus. Oedipus has a heritage to deliver: a

    dream of a new political dimension which is begun by

    Theseus. Theseus offers the gift of hospitality to Oedipus

    and requires nothing in return. Thebes is destined to

    succumb because of its fratricidal hate. Athens will offer a

    new political dimension of justice. When legal systems are

    developed in human communities, there is the need to dis-

    tinguish between different degrees of culpability, in order to

    give just punishment, proportionate to the crime committed.

    Athens can be proud of its Aeropagus and of its justice.

    i Ricoeur, P. (1994). 180.

  • 60

    A new identity, which must be found through the

    ἀπορία.

    This is why in this case it is not only Oedipus who

    finds his identity: it is also Athens. The identity of a

    community is based on a temporal continuity projected

    towards the future. We can make a parallel between the

    identity of the individual and the identity of a society. Both

    are founded on what we can call persistence of the self,

    which assures the permanence of sameness both in

    individuals and in societies and makes their stories continue

    in the present tense. Both can be defined as a ‗narrative‘, as

    they can be described as the story of a self who understands

    himself by composing the events of his life in a narrative

    structure. Athens discovers its identity by watching the

    discovery of his true identity made by Oedipus. While

    following Oedipus‘ story, Athens reaches a better

    understanding of itself.

    All this can be obtained only by means of enlarged

    metaphors, which the tragedy is, since symbols, metaphors

    and dramas give hospitality to that explosive event of

    meaning called ἀποπία. The ἀποπία, far from being an

    obstacle that makes it difficult to carry on philosophical

    reflection, when not preventing completely its development

    and forcing it to halt in front of its difficulties, instead,

    according to Ricoeur, represents the heart of philosophical

  • 61

    discovery, the centre button of the activity of thought,

    which allows philosophy to maintain its dynamic structure

    and productivity. The ἀποπία is a real and genuine choice of

    methodology, deliberately and constantly preserved as

    stimulus to think and rejection of the possibility of lingering

    in what can be considered as a final solution.

    Tragedy provokes thought, since it invites thought

    to hold the contradictions which it proposes. The possibility

    of multiple possible interpretations of tragedies, sometimes

    in conflict with one another and equally valid, must be

    preserved as a constant supply of new beginnings for

    philosophy. Philosophy is called to re-think critically the

    contents of tragedy. Tragedy offers its contradiction to a

    cogito, whose judgement is called into question. ‗A partir

    de la donation, la position‘, Ricoeur (1959). The cogito be-

    comes guarantor of the truth of the interpretation given to

    the tragedy and the responsibility to look for it belongs to

    cogito. The cogito is called to be responsible and to become

    a theoretical structure of certitude. This cogito is no longer

    the Cartesian cogito, already put into question by those

    whom Ricoeur calls the masters of suspicion: Marx,

    Nietzsche, and Freud. They have definitively discovered

    and destroyed its pretension to be a real and self sufficient

    foundation for knowledge. With their disruptive analysis,

    ἀποπία appears as insuperable. However, we must not be

    scared of it; on the contrary, we must stay within this

  • 62

    contradiction. Only this way can we discover the real

    human nature, which is rooted in desire. This root can be

    reached only by metaphors and drama.

    Here we find a new conception of identity, accord-

    ing to Ricoeur at last: it derives from a new model of

    cogito, which he defines as brisé. Brisé means broken, in

    fact it is just by being broken that it is able to meet the

    other. This cogito brisé is able to remember but also to

    forget, after the Freudian work of mourning. ‗The past is in-

    destructible, but we cannot be destroyed by it,‘i said

    Ricoeur in an interview. It is not about erasing, it is about

    restoring. This new cogito is reconciliation. Its identity is

    not a starting point but a goal attainable by composing the

    incoherencies of memory. The ego of the ego cogito

    requires an interpretation. As the word being, with which

    Hegel's Science of Logic begins, this ego is as true as it is

    abstract and empty. It requires filling: Erfüllung. Through

    the appropriation of meaning within the symbol, we are

    called to regain possession of our essence, which is our

    effort to exist and our desire for being. We are distracted by

    that situation of divertissement in which we are situated

    from the very beginning of our being in the world. This

    Erfüllung is given by actual experience, the works in which

    our essence appears, as Hegel said. Becoming ourselves

    i Mele, F. (2001). 78.

  • 63

    implies an ethical task, it is not an acquisition previously

    possessed. All that we have said can be told for Oedipus,

    who discovers his real being along his path.

    Narrative helps this work using μίμηζιρ, in the

    Aristotelian sense of μίμηζιρ ππάξεωρi, whose object is

    action and which consists of construction. It organizes the

    events into a system and permits the creation of a new

    identity: the narrative identity, subjected to a constant

    interpretation. Ricoeur speaks about mimesis 3: this is the

    power which a text possesses to change the world. The

    power owned by tragedy is that it can be told. Telling a

    story helps the possibility to find a sense in what happens

    and to disclose new possibilities. A new concept of imagi-

    nation, the Kantian productive imagination, comes into

    relevance here. It involves a fictional dimension, as an

    opening to what is possible, and it opens the doors to the

    expression of desire, to its representationii.

    The narration of a tale and its construction in

    intrigue help reason to find a way of interpretation through

    the conflicts which actions always take with themselves.

    Oedipus‘ tragedy can be put into a number of stories: ‗qui

    offrent à l'expérience morale à la fois la singularité et

    l'exemplarité de leur configuration.‗iii

    The pleasure Oedipus

    i Aristotle, Poetics, 50 b 3.

    ii Cf. Ricoeur, P. (2002). 66.

    iii Ricoeur, P. (1999).

  • 64

    offers is a pleasure of self knowledge and of a new

    beginning. No more tyrannies: Athens is the land of

    Εὐμενίδερ, and of democracy. Theseus is its king, but he

    helps Oedipus, promising him refuge and a grave. Oedipus

    will compensate for this unconditional offer by assuring

    prosperity to Athens. The gods have decided that his body

    will be sacred and will assure perpetual protection to the

    city which is ready to receive him. He finally disappears,

    letting his destiny and the place of his burial be known only

    to Theseus, the only man who can understand the pain of

    wandering, since he was a foreigner and a refugee too.

    Conclusion

    Following Ricoeur and his interpretation of

    Oedipus‘ tragedy through Freud and Hegel, we have inter-

    preted Oedipus as a tragedy of recognition. This recognition

    is that of Oedipus, who finds himself by knowing his story

    and by being hosted by Theseus, and that of Athens, which

    finds its political identity: that of a fair and welcoming state

    entity. These identities can be reached only by means of the

    narration of their story: they are narrative identities which

    carry upon their shoulders the responsibility for the con-

    struction of a new world .

  • 65

    Aristotle considers the ‗as if‘ of metaphor an instrument

    by which language can find another order in the world,

    because the ‗reference of metaphorical utterance brings

    being as actuality and a