John Gray Hayek on Liberty

199

description

John Gray Hayek on Liberty

Transcript of John Gray Hayek on Liberty

  • d d

  • HAYEKon

    LIBERTY

  • This page intentionally left blank.

  • HAYEKon

    LIBERTY

    Third Edition

    John Gray

    London and New York

  • First published 1984 by Basil Blackwell Ltd

    Second edition 1986

    Third edition published 1998by Routledge

    11 New Fetter Lane, London EC4P 4EE

    Simultaneously published in the USA and Canadaby Routledge

    29 West 35th Street, New York, NY 10001

    Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group

    This edition published in the Taylor & Francis e-Library, 2003.

    1984, 1986, 1998 John Gray

    The right of John Gray to be identified as the Author of this Workhas been asserted by him in accordance with the Copyright, Designs

    and Patents Act 1988

    All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted orreproduced or utilised in any form or by any electronic, mechanical,

    or other means, now known or hereafter invented, includingphotocopying and recording, or in any information storage or

    retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers.

    British Library Cataloguing in Publication DataA catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library

    Library of Congress Cataloguing in Publication DataGray, John, 1948

    Hayek on liberty/John Gray.3rd ed.p. cm.

    Includes bibliographical references and index.1. Hayek, Friedrich A.von. (Friedrich August), 1899Political

    and social views. 2. Liberty. 3. Liberalism. I. Title.HB101.H39G73 1998

    323.44dc21 9751498

    ISBN 0-203-00401-9 Master e-book ISBN

    ISBN 0-203-20944-3 (Adobe eReader Format)

    ISBN 0-415-17315-9 (Print Edition)

  • Contents

    Note to the Third Edition viii

    Preface to the First Edition and Acknowledgements ix

    1 HAYEKS SYSTEM OF IDEAS: ITS ORIGINS ANDSCOPE

    1

    The unity of Hayeks system of ideas and itsphilosophical character

    1

    Hayeks general philosophy: the Kantian heritage 4 Four influences on Hayeks sceptical Kantianism:

    Mach, Popper, Wittgenstein and Polanyi 8

    Hayeks relations with the Austrian School ofEconomics and his account of the methodology ofsocial science

    15 Hayek on knowledge and the mind: implications for

    social theory 20

    2 THE IDEA OF A SPONTANEOUS SOCIAL ORDER 26 Spontaneous order versus the constructivist fallacy 26 The central conception of spontaneous order and its

    applications to physical and social phenomena 30

    The application of spontaneous order in economic life:the catallaxy

    33

  • Cultural evolution and the natural selection oftraditions

    39

    3 THE LAW OF LIBERTY 54 The origins and nature of law 54 Individual liberty under the rule of law 59 The rule of law and the myth of social justice 69 The juridical framework of spontaneous social order 73

    4 ECONOMIC THEORY AND PUBLIC POLICY 76 Social science and public policy 76 Neoclassical equilibrium, the theory of capital and the

    character of the business cycle 80

    Hayek versus Keynes and Friedman on the role ofmoney in the real economy

    84

    Shackles critique of Hayek 88

    5 SOME CONTRASTS AND COMPARISONS 92 J.S.Mill 92 Herbert Spencer 100 Karl Popper 106

    6 ASSESSMENT AND CRITICISM 112 The unity of Hayeks system of ideas 112 The status and content of the idea of spontaneous

    order in society

    114 Hayeks constitution of liberty: some criticisms

    assessed

    120 Conservatism and radicalism in Hayeks social

    philosophy

    124 The Hayekian research programme and the prospects

    of social philosophy

    129 Hayeks thought and the future of political philosophy 135

    Postscript: Hayek and the dissolution of classicalliberalism

    141

    Biographical Note on Hayek 157

    vi HAYEK ON LIBERTY, THIRD EDITION

  • Bibliographical Note on Recent Studies of Hayek 159

    Notes 160

    Index 180

    CONTENTS vii

  • Note to the Third Edition

    In the Postscript to this new edition I have tried to assessHayeks thought by reference to historical events since the publi-cation of the books first edition in 1984 and by consideringhow well Hayeks thought copes with enduring problems of lib-eral political philosophy. The Postscript therefore reflectschanges both in my own thinking and in the world at large.

    John Gray

  • Preface to the First Edition andAcknowledgements

    Though Hayeks central place in twentieth-century economicthought is uncontested, his general philosophy has yet to receivethe sustained critical attention it merits. A major theme of thisstudy is that Hayeks work composes a system of ideas, fully asambitious as the systems of Mill and Marx, but far less vulnera-ble to criticism than theirs because it is grounded on a philosoph-ically defensible view of the scope and limits of human reason. Arelated claim made in this study is that we find in Hayek arestatement of classical liberalism in which it is purified of errorsspecifically, the errors of abstract individualism and uncriticalrationalismwhich inform the work of even the greatest of theclassical liberals and which Hayek has been able to correct byabsorbing some of the deepest insights of conservative philoso-phy. For these two reasons alone, Hayeks work should com-mand the critical interest of philosophers and social theorists aswell as political economists.

    More fundamentally, however, Hayeks work initiates aparadigm shift in social philosophy and launches a new researchprogramme in social theory. In ways I will specify in detail inthe body of this book, Hayek displaces the focus of social phi-losophy from the preoccupations which have led the analyticalschool into an impassepreoccupations with the conceptualanalysis of the main terms of political discourse and with theendless discussion of rival principles against a background of

  • moral scepticismto the areas of epistemology and philosophi-cal psychology. His intuition is that a way of assessing differentsocial systems more fruitful than the traditional method ofappraising their moral content is to be found in illuminating thedemands they make upon the powers of the mind and the usesthey are able to make of human knowledge. His conclusion isthat, once we have arrived at a realistic picture of the powersand limitations of the human mind, we see that many importantsocial doctrinesthose of socialism and interventionist liberal-ism, for example,make impossible demands upon our knowl-edge. Even the liberalism of John Stuart Mill, for all its harpingon the fallibility of our beliefs, embodies a navely rationalisticconception of the relations of the individual mind with its cul-tural inheritance of tradition. Hayek on liberty transcends therationalistic fallacies which disfigure Mills liberalism and givesus a defence of individual freedom without equal in modernthought. Hayeks work has every claim to occupy a distin-guished place in the mainstream of contemporary philosophy.

    This brief study has been assisted by a large number of peo-ple. Among those who have commented on the manuscript atvarious stages in its evolution, or with whom I have hadextended discussions on Hayekian themes, I would like to thankparticularly W.W.Hartley III (whose biography of Hayek will bea notable event in Hayek scholarship), Norman P.Barry, SamuelBrittan, James Buchanan, Tim Congdon, Walter Eltis, MiltonFriedman, Sir H.J.Habbakuk, Donald Hay, Nevil Johnson, IsraelKirzner, Irving Kristol, Robert Nozick, J.C.Nyiri, MichaelOakeshott, Dr D.A.Rees, Murray Rothbard, G.L.S.Shackle andJeremy Shearmur (whose important work on Hayek, shortly tobe published in a book, has contributed a valuable referencepoint for my own, especially where our interpretations have dif-fered widely). I wish to thank most warmly Professor Hayekhimself, for the unstinting generosity and unfailing patience withwhich he has dealt with my innumerable (and often ill-formulated) questions and criticisms, and to Professor Hayekssecretary, Mrs C.Gubitt, for her assistance in revising theBibliography.

    x HAYEK ON LIBERTY, THIRD EDITION

  • I acknowledge permission to publish the following extracts:The Liberalism of Karl Popper from Government and Opposi-tion, Vol. II, no. 3 (Summer 1976), pp. 33755 and Spencer onthe Ethics of Liberty and the limits of State Interference fromHistory of Political Thought, Vol. III, no. 3 (Winter 1982),pp. 46581.

    I am grateful to the Principal and Fellows of my College forgranting me two periods of sabbatical leave during which I wasable to bring the book nearer completion. I wish to express mygratitude for the assistance given me in the early stages of myresearch by a small Research Grant in the Humanities awardedby the British Academy. Also, I wish to acknowledge a debt ofgratitude to the Institute for Humane Studies in Menlo Park,California. Under the direction first of Kenneth S.Templeton Jr.and then Leonard P.Liggio, this excellent institution devoted toresearch and scholarship in the traditions of classical liberalismhas since 1977 supported my studies of Hayek in many ways.With the invaluable support of Liberty Fund of Indianapolis theInstitute enabled me to spend several summers in Menlo Park asa residential research scholar, pursuing my inquiries into Hayekin the context of colloquia on classical liberal thought operatedby Liberty Fund. This book owes its origin to a monograph onF.A.Hayek and the Rebirth of Classical Liberalism published bythe Institute in its excellent (but unhappily now defunct) journalLiterature of Liberty. Without the interest shown in my work byKen Templeton and Leonard Liggio, and the scholarly supportgiven me at the Institute by John Cody and Walter Grinder, Iam sure I would not have begun this book, still less finished it.

    Finally, I would like to thank Carole Charlton in Oxford andPat Ortega in Palo Alto for their work in deciphering my hand-written manuscript.

    John GrayJesus College, Oxford

    1984

    PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION AND ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS xi

  • This page intentionally left blank.

  • 1Hayeks system of ideas: itsorigins and scope

    THE UNITY OF HAYEKS SYSTEM OF IDEAS AND ITSPHILOSOPHICAL CHARACTER

    As part of the reawakening of public and scholarly interest inthe intellectual tradition of classical liberalism, Hayeks writingsin a range of academic disciplines have been recalled from aperiod of neglect during which it seemed to many that they hadbeen consigned to oblivion. It is not an exaggeration to say thatthe re-emergence of classical liberalism and the rediscovery ofHayeks writings are complementary aspects of a single currentof opinion. For, while Hayeks writings address and illuminatesome of the most formidable issues of the age, and answer tomany comtemporary anxieties, they do so within the frame ofthought constructed by the great classical liberals. Hayeks workis in the tradition of classical liberalism, not simply because hisconcerns are in many areas those of Locke and Burke, AdamSmith and Kant, but also because, like the theorists of liberal-isms Golden Age in the eighteenth century, Hayek seeks to raiseup a system of ideas, a structure of principles with the aid ofwhich we can understand social and political life and subject itto reasoned criticism. No-one who knows Hayeks work candoubt that his attempt to restate liberal principles in a formappropriate to the circumstances and temper of the twentieth

    1

  • century has yielded a body of insights wholly comparable in pro-fundity and power with those of his forebears in the classicalliberal tradition. In Hayeks work, the chief values of classicalliberalismthe dignity of the human individual and the moralprimacy of his freedom, the virtues of free markets and the neces-sity for limited government under the rule of laware defendedwithin an intellectual framework of uncompromising modernity.There can be no doubt that Hayeks reformulation of classicalliberalism succeeds in building on the intellectual foundationsinherited from the liberal period a body of thought as powerfulas any that can be found within the classical liberal writers andfar more resistant to criticism than was classical liberalism itself.

    Even Hayeks most convinced critics would hesitate to denythese achievements of his work. At the same time, even amonghis friends and disciples, the sense of Hayeks work as compos-ing a system of ideas is often missing. The reasons for thiswidespread failure to grasp the systematic character of Hayeksthought may seem obvious. His writings cross several major dis-ciplinestheoretical economics, jurisprudence, philosophy, psy-chology and intellectual history among themand they spanover half a century. Again, though there has been some interestin recent years among philosophers and cultural historians in themilieu of thought of the last decades of Hapsburg Vienna, mosteconomists and social theorists remain deeply ignorant of thatmilieu, and accordingly can have little understanding of the con-text of thought in which Hayeks outlook was nurtured. It seemsto me, though, that the general failure of comprehension inregard to the character of Hayeks work as a system of ideas hasother sources, distinct from the two I have just mentioned andhaving to do rather with the inherent structure of Hayeks out-look itself.

    The chief aim of this study is to exhibit Hayeks contributionsto the various disciplines of inquiry in which he has worked asconstituting a system in virtue of their being informed and gov-erned throughout by a distinctive philosophical outlook. EvenHayeks achievements in economic theory can be shown on theinterpretation I advance to trade upon and put to work genuine

    2 HAYEK ON LIBERTY, THIRD EDITION

  • and powerful insights in philosophy which Hayek achieved veryearly in his intellectual career. My interpretation has the novelaspect that it treats Hayek as a philosopher sans phrase, whosecontributions to the social sciences (like those of J.S.Mill)express a natural application of his philosophical outlook. Thecomparison with Mill is here a close one, despite their manydeep differences, in that in Hayeks case as in Mills, his contri-butions to economics were preceded by an effort to establish anew position in the theory of knowledge in the most generalsense. This has been concealed in Hayeks case because his pro-found and neglected study in epistemology and philosophicalpsychology, The Sensory Order, was published only in 1952,after Hayeks principal contributions to economics, whereasMills System of Logic (1843) is a temporal as well as a method-ological forerunner of his Principles of Political Economy(1848). Though it was published only in the fifties, The SensoryOrder was first sketched as a student paper by Hayek in 1920,and its argument was substantially complete by the early twen-ties. A careful investigation of its argument is indispensable toany adequate understanding of Hayeks work, not only becauseit remains his most extended explicit statement in general philos-ophy, but also because it reveals most clearly the intellectualinfluences at work in Hayeks writings. Most crucially, however,the view of knowledge it defends can be shown to be presup-posed by many of the positions Hayek has adopted in economictheory and in social philosophy. The elusiveness and subtlety ofHayeks writings, on which many commentators have remarked,is in great part explained by their general failure to perceive therelevance of his work in the philosophies of knowledge andmind to the stands he has taken up in economic and social the-ory. This failure is regrettable and surprising: regrettable, in thatit has reinforced the neglect which Hayeks work has suffered incontemporary intellectual life, and surprising in that his writingsin the social sciences are studded with references to his moreexplicitly philosophical works, and, above all, to The SensoryOrder.

    Hayeks philosophical outlook is an extremely distinctive ver-

    HAYEKS SYSTEM OF IDEAS: ITS ORIGINS AND SCOPE 3

  • sion of post-Kantian critical philosophy in which a number ofmore contemporary influencesthe philosophies of Mach, Pop-per, Wittgenstein and Polanyi, most notablyhave been synthe-sized into a coherent system. It would be a mistake, at the sametime, to see Hayeks thought as essentially eclectic, a weavingtogether over decades of strands of reflection garnered fromother writers, since all the evidence suggests that his conceptionof the mind and of the limits to our knowledge has been withhim from the start, acquiring refinement and expansion in thecourse of his intellectual development but remaining unaltered inits most fundamental respects. The structure of his conception,and its persistence throughout the many influences under whichhe has temporarily come, has misled many of Hayeks inter-preters into periodizing his intellectual career into distinct phasesa Misesian phase, perhaps, in which he supposedly embracedthe philosophical outlook of his colleague in economics, L.vonMises, followed by a Popperian one which emerged from hismeeting and friendship with Sir Karl Popperbut it is easy toshow that such interpretations are wide of the mark. Hayeksthought retains the character of a coherent system rather than aneclectic construction, even if in the end it harbours conflictswhich demand a revision of some of its elements.

    HAYEKS GENERAL PHILOSOPHY: THE KANTIANHERITAGE

    The entirety of Hayeks workand, above all, his work in epis-temology, psychology, ethics, and the theory of lawis informedby a distinctively Kantian approach. In its most fundamentalaspect, Hayeks thought is Kantian in its denial of our capacityto know things as they are or the world as it is. It is in hisdenial that we can know things as they are, and in his insistencethat the order we find in our experiences, including even oursensory experiences, is the product of the creative activity of ourminds rather than a reality given to us by the world, thatHayeks Kantianism consists. It follows from this sceptical Kan-

    4 HAYEK ON LIBERTY, THIRD EDITION

  • tian standpoint that the task of philosophy cannot be that ofuncovering the necessary characters of things. The keynote ofcritical philosophy, after all, is the impossibility of our attainingany external or transcendental standpoint on human thoughtfrom which we could develop a conception of the world that iswholly uncontaminated by human experiences or interests. Wefind in Kants own writingsabove all the Critique of Pure Rea-son (1781)a case against the possibility of speculative meta-physics which Hayek himself has always taken to be devastatingand conclusive. It is a fundamental conviction of Hayeks, andone that he has in common with all those who stand in the tradi-tion of post-Kantian critical philosophy, that we cannot so stepout of our human point of view as to attain a presuppositionlessperspective on the world as a whole and as it is in itself. Thetraditional aspiration of western philosophyto develop a specu-lative metaphysics in terms of which human thought may be jus-tified and reformedmust accordingly be abandoned. The taskof philosophy, for Hayek as for Kant, is not the construction ofany metaphysical system, but the investigation of the limits ofreason. It is a reflexive rather than a constructive inquiry, sinceall criticismin ethics as much as in sciencemust in the end beimmanent criticism. In philosophy as in life, Hayek avers, wemust take much for granted, or else we will never get started.

    Hayeks uncompromisingly sceptical Kantianism is stronglyevidenced in The Sensory Order. There Hayek disavows any con-cern as to how things really are in the world, affirming that a question like what is X? has meaning only within a givenorder, andwithin this limit it must always refer to the relationof one particular event to other events belonging to the sameorder.1 Above all, the distinction between appearance and real-ity, which Hayek sees as best avoided in scientific discourse,2 isnot to be identified with the distinction between the mental orsensory order and the physical or material order. The aim of sci-entific investigation is not, then, for Hayek, the discovery behindthe veil of appearance of the natures or essences of things inthemselves, for, with Kant and against Aristotelian essentialism,he stigmatizes the notion of essence or absolute reality as useless

    HAYEKS SYSTEM OF IDEAS: ITS ORIGINS AND SCOPE 5

  • or harmful in science and in philosophy. The aim of science canonly be the development of a system of categories or principles,in the end organized wholly deductively, which is adequate tothe experience it seeks to order.3

    Hayek is a Kantian, then, in disavowing in science or in phi-losophy any Aristotelian method of seeking the essences ornatures of things. We cannot know how things are in the world,but only how our mind itself organizes the jumble of its experi-ences. He is Kantian, again, in repudiating the belief, common toempiricists and positivists such as David Hume and Ernst Mach,that there is available to us a ground of elementary sensoryimpressions, untainted by conceptual thought, which can serveas the foundation for the house of human knowledge. Againstthis empiricist dogma, Hayek is emphatic that everything in thesensory order is abstract, conceptual and theory-laden in charac-ter: It will be the central thesis of the theory to be outlined thatit is not merely a part but the whole of sensory qualities whichisan interpretation based on the experience of the individualor the race. The conception of an original pure core of sensationwhich is merely modified by experience is an entirely unneces-sary fiction.4 Again, he tells us that the elimination of the hypo-thetical pure or primary core of sensation, supposed not tobe due to earlier experience, but either to involve some directcommunication of properties of the external objects, or to consti-tute irreducible mental atoms or elements, disposes of variousphilosophical puzzles which arise from the lack of meaning ofthese hypotheses.5 The map or model we form of the world, inHayeks view, is in no important respect grounded in a basis ofsheer sense-data, themselves supposed to be incorrigible. Rather,the picture we form of the world emerges straight from ourinteraction with the world, and it is always abstract in selectingsome among the infinite aspects which the world contains, mostof which we are bound to pass by as without interest to us.

    Hayeks Kantianism, so prominent in his theory of knowledge,is no less pronounced in his jurisprudence and in his politicalphilosophy. It is neglect of the influence on his social theory ofKants account of the law that has misled some of Hayeks inter-

    6 HAYEK ON LIBERTY, THIRD EDITION

  • preters into construing him as a theorist of rights in the traditionof John Locke (a tradition whose most distinguished contempo-rary spokesman is found in Robert Nozick). In fact Hayeksview of law and justice is altogether Kantian in that it relin-quishes any reference to natural lawwhich forms the necessarymatrix for any account of natural rightsand treats moralrights, not as themselves framing absolute constraints of justiceon the content of law, but rather as implications of the nature oflaw itself when certain fundamental features of the human cir-cumstance are taken into account. As I shall try to make clear ina later chapter, Hayeks theory of justice is not rights-based, butprocedural: we discover the demands of justice by applying tothe permanent conditions of human life a Kantian test of univer-salizability. This is to say that, if a rule or maxim is to be accept-able as just, its application must be endorsed by rational agentsacross all relevantly similar cases. Hayeks view of justice is littleunderstood, in part because it has often been assumed that thecontrast between a patterned account of justice such as that ofJohn Rawls (himself a theorist in a Kantian tradition) and theentitlement-based theory of Robert Nozick in which moral rightsfigure as fundamental constraints on all other values, is a con-trast which exhausts all plausible accounts. Hayeks view of jus-tice would in fact have been better understood, if we had fol-lowed his own explicit guidance, and seen it as a synthesis ofKants requirement of universalizability in practical reasoningwith David Humes account of the content and basis of the rulesof justice. One of the most intriguing features of Hayeks politi-cal philosophy is its attempt to mark out a tertium quid betweenthe views of justice of Hume and Kant. His theory of knowledgemay similarly be interpreted as aiming at a reconciliation of theapparently opposed insights of Popper and Wittgenstein. In allof his writings, however, the distinctively Kantian flavour is evi-dent in his strategy of working with postulates or regulativeideas, epistemological and normative, which are as metaphysi-cally neutral, and as uncommitted to specific conceptions of thegood life, as he can reasonably make them. It is this minimalist

    HAYEKS SYSTEM OF IDEAS: ITS ORIGINS AND SCOPE 7

  • or even formalist strategy of argument that most pervasivelyexpresses Hayeks Kantian heritage.

    FOUR INFLUENCES ON HAYEKS SCEPTICALKANTIANISM: MACH, POPPER, WITTGENSTEIN AND

    POLANYI

    Hayeks theory of knowledge is Kantian, we have seen, in affirm-ing that the order we find in the world is given to it by the orga-nizing structure of our own mind and in claiming that even sen-sory experiences are suffused with the ordering concepts of thehuman mind. His view of the mind, then, is Kantian in that itaccords a very great measure of creative power to the mind,which is neither a receptacle for the passive absorption of fugi-tive sensations, nor yet a mirror in which the worlds necessitiesare reflected.

    There are a number of influences on Hayek, however, whichgive his Kantianism a profoundly distinctive and original aspect.The first of these influences is the work of Ernst Mach (18361916), the positivist philosopher whose ideas dominated muchof Austro-German intellectual life in the decades of Hayeksyouth. Hayeks debts to Mach are not so much in the theory ofknowledge, as in the attitude both take to certain traditionalmetaphysical questions. I have observed already that Hayek dis-sented radically from the Humean and Machian belief thathuman knowledge could be reconstructed on the basis of elemen-tary sensory impressions, and throughout his writings Hayek hasalways repudiated as incoherent or unworkable the reductionistprojects of phenomenalism in the theory of perception andbehaviourism in the philosophy of mind. In these areas of philos-ophy, then, Hayeks work has been strongly antipathetic to dis-tinctively positivistic ambitions for a unified science. At the sametime, while never endorsing the dogma of the Vienna Circle thatmetaphysical utterances are literally nonsensical, Hayek hasoften voiced the view that many traditional metaphysical ques-tions express phantom-problems.

    8 HAYEK ON LIBERTY, THIRD EDITION

  • In both The Sensory Order and later in The Constitution ofLiberty, Hayek affirms that the age-old controversy about thefreedom of will embodies such a phantom-problem.6 Hayekscompatibilist standpoint in respect of freedom of the willhisbelief that the causal determination of human actions is fullycompatible with ascribing responsibility to human agents forwhat they dois analogous with his stance on the mindbodyquestion. In both controversies Hayek is concerned to deny anyultimate dualism in metaphysics or ontology, while at the sametime insisting that a dualism in our practical thought and in sci-entific method is unavoidable for us. Thus he says of the rela-tions of the mental and physical domains that While our theoryleads us to deny any ultimate dualism of the forces governingthe realms of the mind and that of the physical world respec-tively, it forces us at the same time to recognize that for practi-cal purposes we shall always have to adopt a dualistic view.7

    And Hayek concludes his study of the foundations of theoreticalpsychology in The Sensory Order with the claim that to usmind must remain forever a realm of its own, which we canknow only through directly experiencing it, but which we shallnever be able to fully explain or to reduce to something else.8

    Hayeks thought has a Machian positivist aspect, then, not inthe theories of mind or perception, but in its attitude to tradi-tional metaphysical questions, which is dissolutionist and defla-tionary. There is yet another link with positivism. Notwithstand-ing Hayeks opposition to any sort of reductionism, whether sen-sationalist or physicalist, he seems to be a monist in ontology,averring that mind is thus the order prevailing in a particularpart of the physical universethat part of it which is ourselves.9

    Hayek may seem here to be qualifying or withdrawing from thatstance of metaphysical neutrality which in Machian spirit hecommends, but this appearance may be delusive. There is muchto suggest that, when Hayek denies any ultimate dualism in thenature of things, he is not lapsing into an idiom of essences ornatural kinds, but simply observingmuch in the fashion of theAmerican pragmatist philosopher, W.V.Quinethat nothing inour experience compels us to adopt ideas of mental or physical

    HAYEKS SYSTEM OF IDEAS: ITS ORIGINS AND SCOPE 9

  • substance.10 Though Hayek has not to my knowledge ever pro-nounced explicitly on the question, the whole tenor of histhought inclines to a Quinean pragmatist view of ontologicalcommitments. In his sceptical and pragmatist attitude to ultimatequestions in metaphysics and ontology, Hayek lines up withmany positivists rather than with Kantian critical philosophythough positivists themselves sometimes claim, with some justifi-cation, to be treading a Kantian path.

    A second influence on Hayeks general philosophy which givesit a distinctive temper is the thought of his friend, Karl Popper(b. 1902). I mean here, not Poppers hypotheticodeductiveaccount of scientific method, which there is evidence that Hayekheld prior to his meeting with Popper,11 nor yet Poppers pro-posal (which Hayek was soon to accept) that falsifiability ratherthan verifiability should be adopted as a criterion of demarca-tion between the scientific and the non-scientific. Again, Hayekhas under Poppers influence come to make an important distinc-tion between types of rationalism,12 such that critical rational-ism is commended and constructivistic rationalism condemned,but this is not what I have in mind. I refer rather to certain strik-ing affinities between Hayeks view of the growth of knowledgeand that adumbrated in Poppers later writings on evolutionaryepistemology. As early as the manuscript which later becameThe Sensory Order (published in 1952, but composed in thetwenties), Hayek made it clear that the principles of classifica-tion embodied in the nervous system were not for him fixeddata; experience constantly forced reclassification on us. In hislater writings, Hayek is explicit that the human mind is itself anevolutionary product and that its structure is therefore variableand not constant. The structural principles or fundamental cate-gories which our minds contain ought not, then, to be inter-preted in Cartesian fashion as universal and necessary axioms,reflecting the natural necessities of the world, but rather as con-stituting evolutionary adaptations of the human organism to theworld that it inhabits.

    The striking similarity between Poppers later views, and thoseexpounded by Hayek in The Sensory Order, is shown by Pop-

    10 HAYEK ON LIBERTY, THIRD EDITION

  • pers own application of the evolutionist standpoint in epistemol-ogy to the theory of perception:

    if we start from a critical commonsensc realismthen we shall takeman as one of the animals, and human knowledge as essentially almostas fallible as animal knowledge. We shall suppose the animal senses tohave evolved from primitive beginnings; and we shall look therefore onour own senses, essentially, as part of a decoding mechanisma mecha-nism which decodes, more or less successfully, the encoded informationabout the world which manages to reach us by sensory means.13

    J.W.N.Watkins comment on this view is as apposite in therespect of Hayek as it is of Popper:

    Kant saw very clearly that the empiricist account of sense experiencecreates and cannot solve the problem of how the manifold and very var-ious data which reach a mans mind from his various senses get unifiedinto a coherent experience.

    Kants solution consisted, essentially, in leaving the old quasi-mechanistic account of sense-organs intact, and endowing the mindwith a powerful set of organizing categoriesfree, universal and neces-sarywhich unify and structure what would otherwise be a madjumble.

    Poppers evolutionist view modifies Kants view at both ends: interpre-tative principles lose their fixed and necessary character, and senseorgans lose their merely causal and mechanistic character.14

    Hayeks account of sense perception anticipates Poppers laterviews in a most striking fashion, because, in both, sensation isconceived as a decoding mechanism, which transmits to us in ahighly abstract fashion information about our external environ-ment. Again, both Hayek and Popper share the sceptical Kantianview that the order we find in the world is given to it by the cre-ative activity of our own minds: as Hayek himself puts it uncom-promisingly in The Sensory Order, The fact that the worldwhich we know seems wholly an orderly world may thus bemerely a result of the method by which we perceive it.15 In hismost recent, and as yet unpublished writings, Hayek has

    HAYEKS SYSTEM OF IDEAS: ITS ORIGINS AND SCOPE 11

  • acknowledged important affinities between Poppers postulate ofa third world of abstract or virtual entities or intelligibles andhis own conception of tradition as the bearer of knowledge andvalues.16

    Later in this study, I will try to illuminate some important con-trasts between Hayek and Popper in both theory of knowledgeand social philosophy. Specifically, I shall argue that, some ofHayeks own statements notwithstanding, he has never acceptedwithout massive qualifications Poppers insistence that the falsifi-cationist methodology is appropriate in all the sciences, naturalas well as social. For Hayek, the search for simple universal lawsis in the social studies vain or even harmful, and there are goodreasons (rooted in their different subject-matters) to supportsomething like a dualism in methods as between natural andsocial sciences. In social philosophy, Hayeks outlook has anentirely different spirit and orientation from that of Popper. Thedistinction between facts and decisions, which Popper elevatesto the status of a fundamental tenet of liberalism, Hayek is com-mitted to repudiate as a shadow cast by the misconceiveddichotomy of nature and convention we inherit from the GreekSophists. More generally, there are many deep contrasts betweenHayeks view of a free society as one in which distinctive tradi-tions engage in peaceful competition under the rule of law andPoppers conception of the free society as embodying opennessto criticism in the ways elaborated by J.S.Mill in On Liberty.One of the greater achievements of Hayeks social theory is, Ishall submit, its successful synthesis of insights of conservativephilosophy which are fatal to the visions of Mill and Popperwith the classical liberal concerns which animated Kant andHume.

    A third influence on Hayeks thought which gives his view ofknowledge and the mind a very distinctive character is that ofhis relative, Ludwig Wittgenstein (18891951).17 This influenceruns deep, and is seen not only in the style and presentation ofThe Sensory Order, which parallels in an obvious way that ofWittgensteins Tractatus, but in many areas of Hayeks system ofideas. It is shown, for example, in Hayeks recurrent interest in

    12 HAYEK ON LIBERTY, THIRD EDITION

  • the way in which the language in which we speak shapes ourthoughts and forms our picture of the world. In fact, Hayeksinterest in language, and in a critique of language, predatesWittgensteins work, inasmuch as he had an early preoccupationwith the work of Fritz Mauthner, the now almost forgottenphilosopher of radical nominalism whom Wittgenstein mentions(somewhat dismissively) in Tractatus.18 There are, however,many evidences that Wittgensteins work reinforced Hayeks con-viction that the study of language is a necessary precondition ofthe study of human thought, and an indispensable prophylacticto the principal disorders of the intellect. Examples which maybe adduced are Hayeks studies of the confusion of language inpolitical thought and, most obviously, perhaps, of his emphasison the role of social rules in the transmission of practicalknowledge.

    It is on this last point that one of the most distinctive featuresof Hayeks Kantianism, its pragmatist aspect, is clearest.19 Ofcourse there is a recognition in Kant himself that knowledgerequires judgement, a special faculty, the Urteilskraft, which can-not be given any complete or adequate specification in proposi-tional terms, and whose exercise is necessary for the applicationof any rule. In the sense that we must exercise this faculty ofjudgement even before we can apply a rule, it is action which isat the root of our very knowledge itself. Hayeks concern is notwith this ultimate dependency of rule-following upon judgementwhich the later Wittgenstein, perhaps following Kant, empha-sizesbut rather with the way that knowledge of all sorts, butespecially social knowledge, is embodied in rules. Our perceptualprocesses, indeed all our processes of thought, are governed byrules with we do not normally articulate, which in some casesare necessarily beyond articulation by us, but which we relyupon for the efficacy of all our action in the world. Indeed, it isnot too much to say that, for Hayek (notwithstanding his stresson the abstract or conceptual character of our sensory knowl-edge) all our knowledge is at the bottom practical or tacitknowledge: it consists, not in propositions or theories, but inskills and dispositions to act in a rule-governed fashion. There is

    HAYEKS SYSTEM OF IDEAS: ITS ORIGINS AND SCOPE 13

  • here an interesting parallel with Poppers view, which sees evenour sense organs as being themselves embodied theories.20

    There is much in Hayeks writings to suggest that he takeswhat Gilbert Ryle calls knowing how,21 what Michael Polanyicalls tacit knowing,22 what Michael Oakeshott23 calls traditionalknowledge, to be the wellspring of all our knowledge. It is inthis sensein holding the stuff of knowledge to be at bottompracticalthat Hayek may be said to subscribe to a thesis of theprimacy of practice in the constitution of human knowledge. Itis not indeed that Hayek disparages the enterprise of theory-building, but he sees the theoretical reconstruction of our practi-cal knowledge as necessarily incomplete in its achievements. Inthe next section of this chapter I will discuss Hayeks view thattheoretical knowledge is always and only knowledge of abstractorders or patterns and often (in the social sciences, for example)only knowledge of a principle in terms of which such patternsmay be understood. Here I wish to identify another limitation oftheoretical knowledge in Hayeks view: theory is for him onlythe visible tip of the vast submerged fund of tacit knowledge,much of which is entirely beyond our powers of articulation.Neglect of this dependency of our necessarily abstract theorieson a vast range of inarticulate background knowledge has ledsocial science astray in many fields.

    The third source of influence on Hayeks sceptical Kantianism,which I have ascribed primarily to the work of his relativeWittgenstein, plainly comprehends other influences as well.Hayek cites Ryle in support of his observation that knowhow consists in the capacity to act according to rules which wemay be able to discover but which we need not be able to statein order to obey them, and glosses the point with reference toMichael Polanyi.24 Here the insight is that all articulated orpropositional knowledge arises out of tacit or practical knowl-edge, the knowledge of how to do things, which must be takenas fundamental. In Polanyis work, there is here, in fact, thefourth and final major influence on Hayek, which in conjunctionwith the other three further modifies his Kantianism and makesof it something that Kant himself could not have recognized.

    14 HAYEK ON LIBERTY, THIRD EDITION

  • The Polanyian element which enters into Hayeks work from atleast the fifties consists, first of all, in the refinement of his viewof knowledge as au fond practical and in his exploitation ofPolanyis insight that, since much of the knowledge we use isinarticulate, we always know more than we can ever say. In TheConstitution of Liberty and elsewhere, this insight gives a whollynew twist to the argument for liberty from human ignorance. Itis not just the fact that our knowledge is extremely limited thatsupports a regime of liberty in which experiments in living maybe tried. Rather, a regime of liberty permits knowledge to beused which we never knew (and could never have known) wehad: any centralized regime which relied only on our explicitknowledge would necessarily exploit only a small part of thestock of knowledgethat small part which is expressible instatements or propositions. Only a regime of liberty can fully usethat greater part of our knowledge which is not so statable. Oneimplication of this insight of Polanyis for social theory, recogni-tion of which by Hayek draws his social theory away from Pop-pers, is that rational criticism of social life is bound to come toa stop when it reaches the tacit dimension of our practices. Thisis a point to which I shall recur when in a later chapter I con-trast Poppers philosophy with Hayeks in a more extended andsystematic way.

    HAYEKS RELATIONS WITH THE AUSTRIAN SCHOOLOF ECONOMICS AND HIS ACCOUNT OF THE

    METHODOLOGY OF SOCIAL SCIENCE

    Hayeks debts to the Austrian School of Economics founded byMenger (18401921) and carried on by Hayeks teacher, F.vonWieser (18511926) and his colleague, L.von Mises (18811973), are so many and so obvious that they tend to concealthose elements of his thought which are original and which inmany cases cannot be accommodated within the orthodoxy ofthe Austrian School. In its most general contentions, however,Hayek has followed and developed the Austrian School. He has

    HAYEKS SYSTEM OF IDEAS: ITS ORIGINS AND SCOPE 15

  • deepened and refined the Austrian subjective theory of valuethe theory that value is conferred on resources by the subjectivepreferences of agents and cannot be explained as an inherentproperty of any asset or resource. It was this profound insightwhich spelt the end of that tradition of classical economic the-ory, encompassing Ricardo, J.S.Mill and Marx, in which valuewas analysed in objective terms as deriving from the labour con-tent of the asset or resource under consideration. This subjec-tivism regarding value in economic theory, strongly emphasizedin all of von Misess writings, is always defended by Hayek. Hegoes much further in the direction of subjectivism, however, bynoting that the data of the social studies are themselves subjec-tive phenomena. Such social objects as money, capital and toolscan never be given an analysis in objective or physicalist terms,since they are actually constituted by human beliefs and notions.These social objects are in no sense privatetheir existence isalways bound up with that of forms of life among communitiesof human beingsbut their dependency on human beliefs andconceptions means that any understanding of them in mechanis-tic fashion is bound to be abortive.

    Hayeks extension of Austrian subjectivism about value to thewhole realm of social objects in no way represents a deviationfrom the positions of his mentors, Menger and von Mises. Hisearliest extensive statement on the methodology of social science,The Counter-Revolution of Science: Studies on the Abuse of Rea-son (1952) bears in many aspects the imprint of the AustrianSchools doctrines, particularly in its firm assertion that themethods of social science are crucially different from those ofthe natural sciences. In one fundamental area, however, Hayekalways differed from the Austrian School, especially as that wasembodied in the person of von Mises. It was indefatigably main-tained by von Mises that economic laws were deductions from afew axioms about human action. Indeed, according to vonMises, all of economic science can be derived from a proper spec-ification of the nature of human action. Economic laws are thusapodictic truths, no less certain than the axioms which yieldthem as theorems, and the role of empirical evidence is sec-

    16 HAYEK ON LIBERTY, THIRD EDITION

  • ondary to identifying these necessary implications of humanaction in economic theory.

    Hayek never accepted this apodicticdeductive or (as vonMises called it) praxeological conception of economic theory.His seminal paper of 1937, Economics and Knowledge, marksan attempt to convert von Mises to a more empirical conceptionof the role of theory in economics rather than any change ofview on Hayeks part. In this paper Hayek seeks to distinguishthose elements of economic theory which are indeed a priori,inasmuch as they deal with the pure logic of choice as it appliesto single agents, from the greater part of economics which isempirical in that it aims to account for coordinating tendencieswhich bring about to varying degrees integration between theactivities of many people. Hayeks distinction generates problemsin his economic theory, especially problems about the nature ofequilibrium and the possibilities of large-scale endogenous disco-ordination which I shall canvass in a later chapter, but its impor-tance here is simply to underline that Hayek always regarded thegreater part of economic doctrine as testable and corrigible andhaving no apodictic status.

    What is noteworthy about Hayeks account of the methods ofthe social sciences is the continuity of its development. Specifi-callycontrary to T.W.Hutchison, who periodizes Hayekswork into an Austrian praxeological and a post-Austrian Poppe-rian period, and also contrary to Norman P. Barry, who seesboth trends running right through Hayeks writingsHayeknever accepted the Misesian conception of a praxeological sci-ence of human action which would take as its point of departurea few axioms about the distinctive features of purposefulbehaviour over time. True, in the Introduction to CollectivistEconomic Planning and elsewhere in his early writings, Hayekhad (as Hutchison notes) insisted that economics yields generallaws, that is, inherent necessities determined by the permanentnature of the constituent elements.25 As Hutchinson himselfacknowledges in passing, however, such laws or necessities func-tion in Hayeks writings as postulates (rather than as axioms),and they continue to do so even in his later writings, in which

    HAYEKS SYSTEM OF IDEAS: ITS ORIGINS AND SCOPE 17

  • (as I have already noted) a suspicion of the nomothetic paradigmof social science is expressed. It is clear from the context of thequotations cited by Hutchison that, in speaking of the generallaws or inherent necessities of social and economic life, Hayekmeant to controvert the excessive voluntarism of historicism,which insinuates that social life contains no unalterable necessi-ties of any sort, rather than to embrace the view that there canbe an a priori science of society or human action. To this extentBarry is right in his observation that there is a basic continuityin Hayeks writings on methodology.26 Certainly, there seemslittle substance in a periodization of Hayeks methodologicalwritings by reference to the supposedly Popperian paper of 1937on Economics and Knowledge.

    At the same time, there seems little warrant for Barrys claimthat throughout his work Hayek tries to combine two ratherdifferent philosophies of social science; the Austrian praxeologi-cal school with its subjectivism and rejection of testability infavour of axiomatic reasoning, and the hypothetico-deductiveapproach of contemporary science with its emphasis on falsifia-bility and empirical content.27 There is no evidence, so far as Iknow, that Hayek ever endorsed the Misesian conception of anaxiomatic or a priori science of human action grounded in apod-ictic certainties. Again, as we have seen, Hayeks view that thesocial sciences are throughout deductive in form antedates Pop-pers influence and is evidenced in the Introduction to Collec-tivist Economic Planning.

    Hayeks real debts to Popper are, I think, different from thoseattributed to him by Hutchison and Barry. It is not that Hayekunder Poppers influence abandoned an apodicticdeductivemethod that was endorsed (in different versions, Kantian andAristotelian) by von Mises and Menger, but rather that he cameto adopt Poppers proposal that falsifiability be treated as demar-cation criterion of science from non-science.28 Again, Hayek fol-lows Popper in qualifying his earlier Austrian conviction thatthere is a radical dualism of method as between natural andsocial science: this conviction, he tells us, depended on an erro-neous conception of method in the natural sciences: as a result

    18 HAYEK ON LIBERTY, THIRD EDITION

  • of what Popper has taught him, Hayek says, the differencesbetween the two groups of disciplines has thereby been greatlynarrowed.29 Hayeks debts to Popper are, then, in his seeingthat it is the falsifiability of an hypothesis rather than its verifia-bility which makes it testable and empirical, and, secondly, inhis acknowledging a unity of method in all the sciences, naturaland social, where this method is seen clearly to behypothetico-deductive.

    Even in these Popperian influences, it is to be noted, there aredifferences of emphasis from Popper himself. Hayek anticipatesLakatos in perceiving that the theoretical sciences may contain ahard core of hypotheses, well-confirmed and valuable in pro-moting understanding of the phenomena under investigation,which are highly resistant to testing and refutation.30 And Hayekexplicitly states that in some fields Poppers ideas of maximumempirical content and falsifiability may be inappropriate:

    It is undoubtedly a drawback to have to work with theories which canbe refuted only by statements of a high degree of complexity, becauseanything below that degree of complexity is on that ground alone per-mitted by our theory. Yet it is still possible that in some fields the moregeneric theories are the more useful ones Where only the most gen-eral patterns can be observed in a considerable number of instances, theendeavour to become more scientific by further narrowing down ourformulae may well be a waste of effort31

    In general, then, it seems fair to hold that Hayek acknowledgesthat the proper method in social and economic studies, as else-where, is the hypothetico-deductive method of conjectures andrefutations as set out by Popper. On the other hand, he contin-ues to recognize that in respect of complex phenomena such asare found in the social studies, testability may be a somewhathigh-level and protracted process, and the ideal of high empiricalcontent captured in a nomothetic framework a demanding andsometimes unattainable idea.

    Hayeks account of the methods of the social sciences,whereas it always stressed the subjective character of the data

    HAYEKS SYSTEM OF IDEAS: ITS ORIGINS AND SCOPE 19

  • of the social studies (social objects themselves), conceived thetask of social theory as that of identifying the principles govern-ing the formation of patterns in social life rather than of work-ing out the implications of any definition of human action.Again, Hayek shares with Popper the view that the methods ofthe social sciences are properly always hypothetico-deductiveand conjectural, but he identifies limitations on this method inthe social sciences which there is no clear evidence that Popperhimself has perceived or accepted.

    HAYEK ON KNOWLEDGE AND THE MIND:IMPLICATIONS FOR SOCIAL THEORY

    I began by noting the striking Kantian attributes of Hayeks epis-temology and philosophy of mindaspects which Hayek himselfdoes not stress, perhaps because he conceives the formative influ-ence of Kantian philosophy on his thought to be self-evident. Ashe puts it himself in a footnote to his discussion in a recent vol-ume of the government of conscious intellectual life by supercon-scious abstract rules: I did not mentionthe obvious relation ofall this to Kants conception of the categories that govern ourthinkingwhich I took rather for granted.32

    Hayeks Kantianism is seen, first in his repudiation of theempiricist view that knowledge may be constructed from a basisof raw sensory data and, second, in his uncompromising asser-tion of the view that the order we find in the world is a productof the creative activity of the human mind (rather than a recogni-tion of natural necessity). His Kantian view is distinctive in thatit anticipates Popper in affirming that the mental frameworks bywhich we categorize the world are neither universal nor invari-ant, but alterable in an evolutionary fashion; his Kantian viewalso follows Wittgenstein in grasping the role of social rules inthe transmission of practical knowledge. There are, at the sametime, some entirely original features of Hayeks view of themind, which it would be hard for either Kant or Wittgenstein toaccept, but which constitute one of Hayeks most intriguing con-

    20 HAYEK ON LIBERTY, THIRD EDITION

  • tributions to philosophical speculation. Hayek suggests that, notonly human social life, but the life of the mind itself is governedby rules, some of which cannot be specified at all. Note thatHayek does not contend merely that we cannot in fact specify allthe rules which govern both social and intellectual life: he arguesthat there must of necessity be an insuperable limit beyondwhich we are unable to specify the rules by which our lives aregoverned. As he puts it:

    So far our argument has rested solely on the uncontestable assumptionthat we are not in fact able to specify all the rules which govern ourperceptions and actions. We still have to consider the question whetherit is conceivable that we should ever be in a position discursively todescribe all (or at least any one we like) of these rules, or whether men-tal activity must always be guided by some rules which we are in princi-ple not able to specify.

    If it should turn out that it is basically impossible to state or commu-nicate all the rules which govern our actions, including our communica-tions and explicit statements, this would imply an inherent limitation ofour possible explicit knowledge and, in particular, the impossibility ofever fully explaining a mind of the complexity of our own.

    Hayek goes on to observe of the inability of the human mindreflexively to grasp the most basic rules which govern its opera-tions that this would follow from what I understand to beGeorg Cantors theorem in the theory of sets according to whichin any system of classification there are always more classes thanthings to be classified, which presumably implies that no systemof classes can contain itself. Again, he remarks that it wouldthus appear that Gdels theorem is but a special case of a moregeneral principle applying to all conscious and particularly allrational processes, namely the principle that among their deter-minants there must always be some rules which cannot be statedor even be conscious. Hayek concludes this development ofthemes first explored in his Sensory Order with the fascinatingsuggestion that conscious thought must be presumed to be gov-erned by Yules which cannot in turn be consciousby a supra-conscious mechanismor, as Hayek prefers sometimes to call

    HAYEKS SYSTEM OF IDEAS: ITS ORIGINS AND SCOPE 21

  • it, a meta-conscious mechanismwhich operates on the con-tents of consciousness but which cannot itself be conscious.33

    Hayeks argument here seems to be that there is in both actionand perception a hierarchy of rules, with the most fundamentalrules at any time being meta-conscious rules beyond our capaci-ties of identification and articulation. Thus the rules of actionand perception by which both intellectual and social life are gov-erned are stratified or ranked in a hierarchy, with the most basicrules (which shape the categories of our understanding) alwayseluding conscious articulation. It is not that there is a set of suchmeta-conscious rules, coexistent with the human mind, such thatwe must suppose ourselves to be governed by invariant princi-ples which we can never state and whose content must remainforever unknown to us. Rather, all the rules by which social andintellectual life is governed are conceived by Hayek to be prod-ucts of a process of evolutionary selection and modification. Aswe acquire new, consciously articulate rules of action and percep-tion, we will come to be governed by new meta-conscious rules,which may in turn generate further meta-conscious rules as theythemselves are articulated or perhaps simply altered out ofrecognition.

    I will return to this most fascinating idea of a meta-consciousrule in the next chapter, when I shall consider its place inHayeks conception of a spontaneous social order. Here I wishto bring out how this idea shows Hayeks differences with Kantand Wittgenstein. For all his discussion of the anti-nomies of thehuman understanding, I do not think Kant could have acceptedso drastic a limitation on the possibilities of human self-understanding as that suggested by Hayeks claim that intellec-tual life is always governed by inarticulable laws or principles. Inthis respect, Hayeks rationalism is even more self-critical thanKants. Again, Wittgensteins general conception of the mindwould forbid any such notion of rule-following as that presup-posed in Hayeks conception. For Wittgenstein, rule-followingseems always to involve intentional knowledge, and, at least inthe PhilosophicalInvestigations, Wittgenstein is concerned tostress the freedom of judgement we possess in applying even the

    22 HAYEK ON LIBERTY, THIRD EDITION

  • most basic rules, such as those of arithmetic. Hayeks conceptionis here far removed from Wittgensteins, and has closest affinitieswith the evolutionary epistemology developed by Popper and hisdisciples.

    How do these considerations bear on Hayeks view of society?Hayek himself is emphatic that these insights in the theories ofmind and knowledge have the largest consequences for socialtheory. The inaccessability to reflexive inquiry of the rules thatgovern conscious thought entails the bankruptcy of the Cartesianrationalist project and implies that the human mind can neverfully understand itself, still less can it ever be governed by anyprocess of conscious thought. The considerations adduced ear-lier, then, establish the autonomy of the mind, without everendorsing any mentalistic thesis of minds independence of thematerial order. Where Hayek deviates from Descartess concep-tion of mind, however, is not primarily in his denying ontologi-cal independence to mind, but in his demonstration that com-plete intellectual self-understanding is an impossibility.

    Hayeks conception of mind is a view, then, whose implica-tions for social theory are even more radical than are those ofHayeks Kantianism. It is the chief burden of the latter, let usrecall, that no external or transcendental standpoint on humanthought is achievable, in terms of which it may be supported orreformed. In social theory, this Kantian perspective implies theimpossibility of any Archimedian point from which a synopticview can be gained of society as a whole and in terms of whichsocial life may be understood and, it may be, redesigned. AsHayek puts it trenchantly: Particular aspects of a culture can becritically examined only within the context of that culture. Wecan never reduce a system of rules or all values as a whole to apurposive construction, but must always stop with our criticismof something that has no better grounds for existence than thatit is the accepted basis of the particular tradition.34 This is auseful statement, since it brings out the Kantian implication forsocial theory: that all criticism of social life must be immanentcriticism, just as in all philosophy, inquiry can only be reflexiveand never transcendental.

    HAYEKS SYSTEM OF IDEAS: ITS ORIGINS AND SCOPE 23

  • Hayek goes beyond Kantianism, however, in his recognitionthat, just as in the theory of mind we must break off when wecome to the region of unknowable ultimate rules, so in socialtheory we come to a stop with the basic constitutive traditionsof social life. These latter, like Wittgensteins forms of life, can-not be the objects of further criticism, since they are at the termi-nus of criticism and justification: they are simply given to us,and must be accepted by us. But this is not to say that these tra-ditions are unchanging, nor that we cannot understand how it isthat they do change.

    In social theory, Hayeks devastating critique of Cartesianrationalism entails that, whatever else it might be, social ordercannot be the product of a directing intelligence. It is not justthat too many concrete details of social life would always escapesuch an intelligence, which could never, therefore, know enough.Nor (though we are nearer the nub of the matter here) is it thatsociety is not a static object of knowledge which could surviveunchanged the investigations of such an intelligence. No, theimpossibility of total social planning does not rest for Hayek onsuch Popperian considerations,35 or, at any rate, not primarilyon them.

    Such an impossibility of central social planning rests, firstly,on the primordially practical character of most of the knowledgeon which social life depends. Such knowledge cannot be concen-trated in a single brain, natural or mechanical, not because it isvery complicated, but rather because it is embodied in habitsand dispositions and governs our conduct via rules which areoften inarticulate. But, secondly, the impossibilty of total socialplanning arises from the fact that, since we are all of us gov-erned by rules of which we have no knowledge, even the direct-ing intelligence itself would be subject to such government. It isnave and almost incoherent to suppose that a society could liftitself up by its bootstraps and reconstruct itself, in part at leastbecause the idea that any individual mindor any collectivity ofselected mindscould do that, is no less absurd. The order wefind in social life cannot, for these reasons, be the product of

    24 HAYEK ON LIBERTY, THIRD EDITION

  • any rational design, and it can never become so. Social order isand must always be a spontaneous formation.

    HAYEKS SYSTEM OF IDEAS: ITS ORIGINS AND SCOPE 25

  • 2The idea of a spontaneous socialorder

    SPONTANEOUS ORDER VERSUS THECONSTRUCTIVIST FALLACY

    If the order we discover in society is in no important respect theproduct of a directing intelligence, and if the human mind itselfis a product of cultural evolution, then it follows that socialorder cannot be the product of anything resembling consciouscontrol or rational design. As Hayek puts it:

    The errors of constructivist rationalism are closely connected withCartesian dualism, that is, with the conception of an independentlyexisting mind substance which stands outside the cosmos of nature andwhich enabled man, endowed with such a mind from the beginning, todesign the institutions of society and culture among which he livesThe conception of an already fully developed mind designing the institu-tions which made life possible is contrary to all we know about the evo-lution of man.1

    The master error of Cartesian rationalism2 lies in its anthropo-morphic transposition of mentalist categories to social processes.But a Cartesian rationalist view of mind cannot explain even theorder of mind itself. Hayek himself makes this point when heremarks on the difference between an order which is brought

    26

  • about by the direction of a central organ such as the brain, andthe formation of an order determined by the regularity of theactions towards each other of the elements of a structure. Hegoes on:

    Michael Polanyi has usefully described this distinction as that between amonocentric and a polycentric order. The first point which it is in thisconnection important to note is that the brain of an organism whichacts as the directing centre for the organism is in turn a polycentricorder, that is, that its actions are determined by the relation and mutualadjustment to each other of the elements of which it consists.3

    Hayek states his conception of social theory, and of the centralimportance in it of undesigned or spontaneous orders, program-matically and with unsurpassable lucidity:

    It is evident that this interplay of the rules of conduct and of the indi-viduals with the actions of other individuals and the external circum-stances in producing an overall order may be a highly complex affair.The whole task of social theory consists in little else but an effort toreconstruct the overall orders which are thus formed It will also beclear that such a distinct theory of social structures can provide only anexplanation of certain general and highly abstract features of the differ-ent types of structures Of theories of this type economic theory, thetheory of the market order of free human societies, is so far the onlyone which has been developed over a long period4

    Because it is undesigned and not the product of conscious reflec-tion, the spontaneous order that emerges of itself in social lifecan cope with the radical ignorance we all share of the countlessfacts of knowledge on which society depends. That is to say, tobegin with, that a spontaneous social order can utilize frag-mented knowledge, knowledge dispersed among millions of peo-ple, in a way a holistically planned order (if such there could be)cannot. This structure of human activities as Hayek puts itconsistently adapts itself, and functions through adapting itself,to millions of facts which in their entirety are not known toeverybody. The significance of this process is most obvious and

    THE IDEA OF A SPONTANEOUS SOCIAL ORDER 27

  • was at first stressed in the economic field.5 It is to say, also,that a spontaneous social order can use the practical knowledgepreserved in mens habits and dispositions and that societyalways depends on such practical knowledge and cannot dowithout it.

    Examples abound in Hayeks writings of spontaneous ordersapart from the market order. The thesis of spontaneous order isstated at its broadest when Hayek says of Bernard Mandeville(16701733) that for the first time [he] developed all the classi-cal paradigmata of the spontaneous growth of orderly socialstructures: of law and morals, of language, the market andmoney, and also the growth of technological knowledge.6 Notethat whereas Hayek acknowledges that spontaneous orderemerges in natural processesit may be observed, he tells us,not only in the population biology of animal species, but in theformation of crystals and even galaxies7it is the role of sponta-neous order in human society that Hayek is most concerned tostress. For applying what Hayek illuminatingly terms the twinideas of evolution and of the spontaneous formation of anorder8 to the study of human society enables us to transcend theview, inherited from Greek, and, above all, from Sophist philos-ophy, that all social phenomena can be comprehended withinthe crude dichotomy of the natural (physis) and the conventional(nomos). Hayek wishes to focus attention on the third domainof social phenomena and objects, neither instinctual in originnor yet the result of conscious contrivance or purposive construc-tion, the domain of evolved and self-regulating structures in soci-ety via the natural selection of rules of action and perceptionthat is systematically neglected in much current sociology(though not, it may be noted, in the writings of HerbertSpencer,9 one of sociologys founding fathers). It is because hethinks that the sociobiologists view social order as being a mix-ture of instinctive behaviour and conscious control, and soneglect the cultural selection of systems and rules, that Hayekhas subjected this recent strain of speculation to a sharp criti-cism.10 It may be noted, finally, that Hayeks repudiation of theSophistic nature-convention dichotomy sets him in some opposi-

    28 HAYEK ON LIBERTY, THIRD EDITION

  • tion to Popper with his talk of the critical dualism of facts anddecisions and brings him close to the Wittgensteinian philoso-pher, Peter Winch, for whom the distinction is essentially mis-conceived.11 At the same time, Hayeks constant insistence onthe competitive selection of rival rules and practices gives hisconception of social life a naturalistic and evolutionary dimen-sion which is alien to Wittgensteinian thought.

    Constructivism is the error that the order we discoverinnature, in our minds and in societyhas been put there by somedesigning mind. Hayeks conception of spontaneous order, incontesting the constructivist view, embodies an insight whichgoes very much against the grain of the dominant Platonist andChristian traditions in Western culture. For these traditions,order is imposed upon the world or injected into it by the exer-cise of reason or is found there as the reflection of a suprasensi-ble domain of Ideas. The task of reason may be the apprehen-sion of the eternal Forms of which all things that we can knowin this world are but shadowy copies, or else the office of reasonmay be conceived as that of identifying a set of clear ideaswhose mutual relations constitute an unchanging order. ForHayek, this cannot be the role of reason: the mind is as much aspontaneous order as is the human body or the human brain,and our ideas are merely the visible exfoliation of spontaneousforces. For Hayek, then, as against Plato and Descartes, theorder of our ideas is supervenient upon the spontaneous order ofthe mind, which it can never reconstruct entirely or hope to sup-plant. Our conscious selves can never be governors of our men-tal lives, for they are at every moment utterly dependent uponthe unseen (and, in large measure, uncomprehended) workingsof spontaneous order in the cosmos of nature and society. Inneglecting the dependency of reason itself on spontaneous orderin the life of the mind, the constructivist error inverts the truerelations of tacit with explicit knowledge and accords reason aprescriptive role it is wholly unfitted to perform in mind orsociety.

    THE IDEA OF A SPONTANEOUS SOCIAL ORDER 29

  • THE CENTRAL CONCEPTION OF SPONTANEOUSORDER AND ITS APPLICATIONS TO PHYSICAL AND

    SOCIAL PHENOMENA

    The most explicit and systematic development of the insight thatorder in society is a spontaneous formation is given by the eco-nomic theory of market exchanges, where the thesis that unham-pered markets display a tendency to equilibrium is its most obvi-ous application. (In a world of constantly changing beliefs andpreferences, of course, equilibrium is never achieved, but is to beviewed as a constantly changing asymptote. This should warn usagainst construing spontaneous order as a static condition ratherthan a process displaying certain orderly features). At the sametime, Hayek has made clear that the spontaneous-order concep-tion has application to physical systemsto crystals, galaxies,and perhaps even, somewhat paradoxically, to certain artificialdevices12and it has many exemplifications in human social lifeapart from those in the economic realm. We find the sponta-neous formation of self-regulating structures in the growth oflanguage, the development of law and in the emergence of moralnorms. (We find in David Hume, for example, a brilliant exposi-tion of the spontaneous emergence of moral conventions, whichis explicitly directed against Hobbess constructivist rational-ism).13 In all these domains, the key idea of the spontaneousorder thesis is that self-organizing and self-replicating structuresarise without design or even the possibility of design, such thatknowledge of some of the elements of these structures allows theformation of correct expectations about the structure of thewhole.

    Whereas I do not aim here to assess Hayeks conception inany definitive fashion, a number of questions are worth raisingat this point. Hayek has asserted that the emergence and persis-tence of spontaneous orders is to be accounted for by somethingakin to the generalization of Darwinian evolution as it is under-stood in the context of the development of species. Selective evo-lution is the source of all order, he tells us, not only of the orderwe find in living things and which we recognize in the classifica-

    30 HAYEK ON LIBERTY, THIRD EDITION

  • tion of species. At the same time, Hayek never maintains thatthe mechanism of Darwinian evolutionnatural selection ofgenetic accidents via their reproductive fitnessmust be repli-cated exactly in all areas where selective evolution generatesspontaneous order. In the case of the capitalist market economy,there is a real analogy with Darwinian selection in that theprofit-and-loss system provides a mechanism for the eliminationof unfit enterprises. It is less clear what it is that accounts forthe emergence and persistence of orderly structures in languageand law. Again, though we may indeed sensibly speak of evolu-tion at the molecular and galactic levels, there will be nothinganalogous with the mechanism of Darwinian evolution at theselevels, since there appears there to be no possibility of self-replication. An evolutionary account may be given of the emer-gence of self-organizing systems, which invokes mechanisms ofselection other than that specified in the Darwinian theory. Onequestion that arises, then, is just what these other mechanismsmay be in the areas where the Darwinian one does not apply.

    In the context of social and cultural evolution, Hayek has inrecent years accorded increasing prominence to the Darwinianmechanism itself. Social institutions and structuressuch as reli-gions and modes of productioncome to prevail insofar as theyenhance the reproductive fitness of the groups which practisethem. Religions which emphasize the importance of private orseveral property and which support the institution of the familywill enhance the life prospects of their practitioners by creatingconditions of high productivity in which there will be relativelymore numerous infant survivals. Modes of production whichallow and encourage the identification of malinvestments andwhich provide incentives for their liquidation will spread, if onlybecause they permit larger populations to be sustained than domodes of production without these features making for produc-tivity. As Hayek sees it in his latest writings,14 social or culturalevolution is directly continuous with evolution at the classicalDarwinian level and embodies the same fundamental principle ofnatural selection. Hayeks conception differs from that of nine-teenth century Social Darwinism, however, whether in its Spence-

    THE IDEA OF A SPONTANEOUS SOCIAL ORDER 31

  • rianLamarckian form or in that expounded by W.G.Sumner,inasmuch as the natural selection it speaks about is not of indi-viduals, but of groups or populations, and it occurs via theimpact of the practices and institutions, the rules of action andperception, of groups on the life chances of their members.

    A further question now suggests itselfa question as to themeans of identifying the rules of which Hayek speaks. He isexplicit that he refers always both to rules of action and to rulesof perception.15 To take the example he mentions and whichPolanyi often uses, both sorts of rule would be involved in theprocess of recognizing someones face and greeting him. Perhaps,for Hayek, the differences between the two sorts of rule are lessthan radical, but in respect of rules of action the problem is thatobserved regularities of behaviour are usually compatible with arange of imputed rules. If the imputation of such rules is toexplain the order of a group, we need some method of selectionamong the range of possible rules which might equally wellaccount for the same regularities in individual behaviour. Thisproblem may be easier with rules of perception in that tech-niques are available for isolating Gestalten, but it is still a realproblem in these cases too.

    Again, although I have stated it in simple, unitary fashion, theidea of a spontaneous order in society has at least three distinctaspects or elements. First, there is the thesis that social institu-tions arise as a result of human action but not from humandesign. Let us, following Robert Nozick and others16 call thisthe invisible-hand thesis about social institutions. Intimations ofthis thesis are found in Mandeville and Hume, but a systematicversion of it in respect of the institution of money is given byCarl Menger, founder of the Austrian School of Economics.17

    Secondly, there is the thesis of the primacy of tacit or practicalknowledge, which asserts that our knowledge of the world, andespecially of the social world, is embodied first of all in practicesand skills, and only secondarily in theories, and which speculatesthat at least part of this practical knowledge is always inarticula-ble. Thirdly, there is the thesis of the natural selection of compet-itive traditions. Here traditions are understood to refer to

    32 HAYEK ON LIBERTY, THIRD EDITION

  • whole complexes of practices and rules of action and perceptionand the claim is that there is a continuous evolutionary filteringof these traditions. This last thesislet us call it the thesis ofcultural evolution by the natural selection of traditionscompletes the complex idea of spontaneous social order as it isexpounded by Hayek.

    THE APPLICATION OF SPONTANEOUS ORDER INECONOMIC LIFE: THE CATALLAXY

    The central claim of Hayeks philosophy, as we have expoundedit so far, is that knowledge is, at its base, at once practical andabstract. It is abstract inasmuch as even sensory perception givesus a model of our environment which is highly selective andpicks out only certain classes of events, and it is practical inas-much as most knowledge is irretrievably stored or embodied inrules of action and perception. These rules, in turn, are inHayeks conception the subject of continuing natural selection incultural competition. The mechanism of this selection, bestdescribed in Hayeks fascinating Notes on the Evolution of Sys-tems of Rules of Conduct,18 is in the emulation by others ofrules which secure successful behaviour. It is by a mimetic conta-gion that rules conferring successwhere success means, in thelast resort, the growth of human numbers19come to supplantthose rules which are maladapted to the environment. Finally,the convergence of many rule-following creatures on a single sys-tem of rules creates those social objectslanguage, money, mar-kets, the lawwhich are the paradigms of spontaneous socialorder.

    It is a general implication of this conception that, since socialorder is not a purposive construction, it will not in general serveany specific purpose. Social order facilitates the achievement ofhuman purposes: taken in itself, it must be seen as having nopurpose. Just as human actions acquire their meaning by occur-ring in a framework that can itself have no meaning,20 so socialorder will allow for the achievement of human purposes only to

    THE IDEA OF A SPONTANEOUS SOCIAL ORDER 33

  • the extent that it is itself purposeless. Nowhere has this generalimplication of Hayeks conception been so neglected as in eco-nomic life. In the history and theory of science, to be sure,where the idea of spontaneous order was (as Hayek acknowl-edges)21 put to work by Michael Polanyi, false conceptions werespawned by the erroneous notion that scientific progress couldbe planned, whereas, on the contrary, any limitation of scientificinquiry to the contents of explicit or theoretical knowledgewould inevitably stifle further progress.22 In economics, how-ever, the canard that order is the result of conscious control hadmore fateful consequences. It supported the illusion that thewhole realm of human exchange was to be understood after thefashion of a household or an hierarchical organization, with lim-ited and commensurable purposes ranked in order of agreedimportance.

    This confusion of a genuine hierarchical economysuch asthat of an army, a school or a business corporationwith thewhole realm of social exchange, the catallaxy, informs manyaspects of welfare economics and motivates its interventionistprojects via the fiction of a total social product. This confusionbetween catallaxy and economy is, at bottom, the result of aninability to acknowledge that the order which is the product ofconscious directionthe order of a management hierarchy in abusiness corporation, for exampleitself always depends upon alarger spontaneous order. The demand that the domain ofhuman exchange taken as a whole should be subject to purpo-sive planning is, therefore, the demand that social life be recon-structed in the character of a factory, an army, or a business cor-porationin the character, in other words, of an authoritarianorganization. Apart from the fateful consequences for individualliberty that implementing such a demand inexorably entails, itsprings in great measure from an inability or unwillingness tograsp how in the market process itself there is a constant ten-dency to self-regulation by spontaneous order. When it isunhampered, the process of exchange between competitive firmsitself yields a coordination of mens activities more intricate and

    34 HAYEK ON LIBERTY, THIRD EDITION

  • balanced than any that could be enforced (or even conceived) bya central planner.

    The relevance of these considerations to Hayeks contributionsto the question of the allocation of resources in a socialist eco-nomic order is central, but often neglected. It is, of course,widely recognized23 that one of Hayeks principal contributionsin economic theory is the refinement of the thesis of his col-league, Ludwig von Mises, that the attempt to supplant marketrelations by public planning cannot avoid yielding calculationalchaos. Hayeks account of the mechanism whereby this occurshas, however, some entirely distinctive and original features. ForHayek is at great pains to point out that the dispersed knowl-edge which brings about a tendency to equilibrium in economiclife and so facilitates an integration of different plans of life, isprecisely not theoretical or technical knowledge, but practicalknowledge of concrete situationsknowledge of people, of localconditions, and of special circumstances. As Hayek puts it: Theskipper who earns his living from using otherwise empty or half-filled journeys of tramp-steamers, or the estate agent whosewhole knowledge is almost exclusively one of temporary oppor-tunities, or the arbitrageur who gains from local differences ofcommodity pricesare all performing eminently useful functionsbased on special knowledge of circumstances of the fleetingmoment not known to others. Hayek goes on to comment: It isa curious fact that this sort of knowledge should today beregarded with a kind of contempt and that anyone who by suchknowledge gains an advantage over somebody better equippedwith theoretical or technical knowledge is thought to have actedalmost disreputably.24 The problem of the division of knowl-edge, which Hayek describes as the really central problem ofeconomics as a social science,25 is therefore not just a problemof specific data, articulable in explicit terms, being dispersed inmillions of heads: it is the far more fundamental problem of thepractical knowledge on which economic life depends beingembodied in skills and habits, which change as society changesand which are rarely expressible in theoretical or technical terms.

    One way of putting Hayeks point, a way we owe to Israel

    THE IDEA OF A SPONTANEOUS SOCIAL ORDER 35

  • Kirzner rather than to Hayek himself but which is wholly com-patible with all that Hayek has said on these questions, is toremark as follows: if mens economic activities really do show atendency to coordinate with one another, this is due in largepart to the activity of entrepreneurship. The neglect of theentrepreneur in much standard economic theorizing, the inabilityto grasp his functions in the market process, may be accountedfor in part by reference to Hayeks description above of the sortof knowledge used by the entrepreneur. As Kirzner puts it, Ulti-mately, then, the kind of knowledge required for entrepreneur-ship is knowing where to look for knowledge rather thanknowledge of substantive market information.26 It is hard toavoid the impression that the entrepreneurial knowledge ofwhich Kirzner speaks here is precisely that practical or disposi-tional knowledge which Hayek describes. Kirzners accountbrings out a feature of entrepreneurship, crucially relevant tospontaneous order in the economic realm, which Hayek recog-nizes but has not developed systematically. This is that theentrepreneurial insight or perception on which the tendency toequilibrium depends, because it cannot be planned or broughtabout at will, but is always a matter of serendipity and flair, isitself a spontaneous phenomenon. Different institutional frame-works may encourage it in differing degrees, but it is in itsnature as much beyond our powers of conscious control as arethe meta-conscious rules of Hayeks theory of mind. I do notmean to suggest that entrepreneurial perception is rule-governedthough its affinities with Gestalt-perception would repayresearchbut only to stress its uncontroll-ability by consciousthought. One major flaw in all proposals for economic planningis that they are bound to attempt to transform entrepreneurialperception of opportunities into mechanical procedures forresource-utilization and to incur vast losses of efficiency in soattempting.

    It is the neglect of how all economic life depends on this prac-tical knowledge which allowed the brilliant but, in this respect,fatally misguided Joseph Schumpeter (18831950) to put awhole generation of economists on the wrong track, when he

    36 HAYEK ON LIBERTY, THIRD EDITION

  • stated in his Capitalism, Socialism and Democracy (1942) thatthe problem of calculation under socialism was essentiallysolved.27 It is the neglect of the same truth that Hayekexpounded which explains the inevitable failure in Soviet-styleeconomies of attempts to simulate market processes in computermodeling. All such efforts are bound to fail, if only because thepractical knowledge of which Hayek speaks cannot be pro-grammed into a mechanical device. They are bound to fail, also,because they neglect the knowledge-gathering rle of market pric-ing. Here we must recall that, according to Hayek, knowledge isdispersed throughout society and, further, it is embodied inhabits and dispositions of countless men and women. Theknowledge yielded by market pricing is knowledge which allmen can use, but which none of them would possess in theabsence of the market process; in a sense, the knowledge embod-ied or expressed in the market price is systemic or holisticknowledge, knowledge unknown and unknowable to any of theelements of the market system, but given to them all by the oper-ation of the system itself. No sort of market simulation orshadow pricing can rival the operation of the market order itselfin producing this knowledge, because only the actual operationof the market itself can draw on the fund of practical knowledgewhich market participants exploit in their activities. The knowl-edge exhibited in market prices is not only the practical knowl-edge possessed by millions of dispersed market actors; it is alsoknowledge possessed by none of them as individuals, even tac-itly. It is thus systemic or holistic knowledge, knowledge gener-ated by the market process itself and belonging (as does all tradi-tional knowledge) to the entire society rather than to any of itsseparate members. It is this systemic knowledge which isdestroyed or wasted when attempts are made to correct or planmarket processes.

    Three further points may be worth noting in respect ofHayeks refinements of the Misesian calculation debate. First,when Hayek speaks of economic calculation under socialism as apractical impossibility, he is not identifying specific obstacles inthe way