Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About...

35
1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical Studies * Abstract Experimental restrictionists have challenged philosophers’ reliance on intuitions about thought experiment cases based on experimental findings. According to the expertise defense, only the intuitions of philosophical experts count—yet the bulk of experimental philosophy consists in studies with lay people. In this paper, we argue that direct (experimental) strategies for assessing the expertise defense are preferable to indirect (inductive) strategies. A direct argument in support of the expertise defense would have to show: first, that there is a significant difference between expert and lay intuitions; second, that expert intuitions are superior to lay intuitions; and third, that expert intuitions accord with the relevant philosophical consensus. At present, there is only little experimental evidence that bears on these issues. To advance the debate, we conducted two new experiments on intuitions about knowledge with experts and lay people. Our results suggest that the intuitions of epistemological experts are superior in some respects, but they also pose an unexpected challenge to the expertise defense. Most strikingly, we found that even epistemological experts tend to ascribe knowledge in fake-barn-style cases. This suggests that philosophy, as a discipline, might fail to adequately map the intuitions of its expert practitioners onto a disciplinary consensus. Keywords intuitions, thought experiments, knowledge, expertise defense, intuitive expertise, experimental philosophy, experimental restrictionism * The final publication is available at Springer via http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0627-1

Transcript of Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About...

Page 1: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

1

IntuitiveExpertiseandIntuitionsAboutKnowledge

JoachimHorvath&AlexWiegmann

December30,2015

ForthcominginPhilosophicalStudies*

Abstract Experimentalrestrictionistshavechallengedphilosophers’relianceon

intuitionsaboutthoughtexperimentcasesbasedonexperimentalfindings.Accordingto

theexpertisedefense,onlytheintuitionsofphilosophicalexpertscount—yetthebulkof

experimentalphilosophyconsistsinstudieswithlaypeople.Inthispaper,wearguethat

direct(experimental)strategiesforassessingtheexpertisedefensearepreferableto

indirect(inductive)strategies.Adirectargumentinsupportoftheexpertisedefense

wouldhavetoshow:first,thatthereisasignificantdifferencebetweenexpertandlay

intuitions;second,thatexpertintuitionsaresuperiortolayintuitions;andthird,that

expertintuitionsaccordwiththerelevantphilosophicalconsensus.Atpresent,thereis

onlylittleexperimentalevidencethatbearsontheseissues.Toadvancethedebate,we

conductedtwonewexperimentsonintuitionsaboutknowledgewithexpertsandlay

people.Ourresultssuggestthattheintuitionsofepistemologicalexpertsaresuperiorin

somerespects,buttheyalsoposeanunexpectedchallengetotheexpertisedefense.

Moststrikingly,wefoundthatevenepistemologicalexpertstendtoascribeknowledge

infake-barn-stylecases.Thissuggeststhatphilosophy,asadiscipline,mightfailto

adequatelymaptheintuitionsofitsexpertpractitionersontoadisciplinaryconsensus.

Keywords intuitions,thoughtexperiments,knowledge,expertisedefense,intuitive

expertise,experimentalphilosophy,experimentalrestrictionism

*ThefinalpublicationisavailableatSpringerviahttp://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11098-016-0627-1

Page 2: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

2

1 Introduction

Findingsfromexperimentalphilosophysuggestthatlaypeople’sintuitionsabout

philosophicalthoughtexperimentsvarywithanumberofseeminglyirrelevantfactors,

suchasculturalbackground(Machery,Mallon,Nichols,&Stich,2004),orderof

presentation(Liao,Wiegmann,Alexander,&Vong,2012;Swain,Alexander,&Weinberg,

2008;Wiegmann&Waldmann,2014),affectivecontent(Nichols&Knobe,2007),or

heritablepersonalitytraits(Cokely&Feltz,2009;Feltz&Cokely,2009).Basedonthese

findings,experimentalphilosophersofa‘restrictionist’benthavechallengedthe

trustworthinessofthoughtexperimentintuitions(Alexander,Mallon,&Weinberg,2009;

Alexander&Weinberg,2007;Feltz&Cokely,2012;Macheryetal.,2004;Weinberg,

2007;Weinberg,Nichols,&Stich,2001).Otherphilosophershaverespondedina

numberofwaystotheexperimentalrestrictionistchallenge(Bengson,2013;Cappelen,

2012;Deutsch,2009,2010;Grundmann,2010;Horvath,2010;Kauppinen,2007;

Ludwig,2007,2010;Nagel,2012;Sosa,2007,2009,2010)—somemorepromising,

somelesspromising(Alexander,2012;Alexander&Weinberg,2007;Deutsch,2015;

Horvath,2010;Mizrahi,2015;Nado,2014,2015b;Weinberg,Alexander,Gonnerman,&

Reuter,2012;Weinberg,Gonnerman,Buckner,&Alexander,2010).1

Theso-called‘expertisedefense’emergedasoneofthemostfruitfulandhotly

debatedreactionstotheexperimentalrestrictionists’challenge(seeNado,2014fora

recentsurvey).Proponentsoftheexpertisedefensehavevariouslyarguedthat

professionalphilosophersaretherelevantexpertswithrespecttotheintuitive

evaluationofthoughtexperiments,whocanthusbeexpectedtobelargelyresistantto

theinfluenceofirrelevantfactors(Devitt,2006,2011;Grundmann,2010;Hales,2006;

Hofmann,2010;Horvath,2010;Kipper,2010;Ludwig,2007;Turri,2013;Williamson,

1Weusetheterm‘intuition’fairlybroadlyinthispaper,i.e.,aspotentiallycoveringawiderangeofspontaneouscognitiveresponsestothoughtexperimentcases(see,e.g.,Pust,2012foranoverview).Thisbroaduseisopentotheobjectionthatonlyintuitionsofaspecifickindmatterforphilosophicalmethodologyandthuscountasgenuineintuitions(see,e.g.,Bengson,2013;Ludwig,2007).Wedonothavethespacetodiscussthisobjectioninmoredetailhere.However,wewouldliketonotethatweareskepticalaboutthemethodologicalsignificanceofthe‘genuineintuitionsobjection’,sinceitisnotclearwhetherevenprofessionalphilosopherstypicallyrespondtothoughtexperimentcaseswith“genuineintuitions”intheireverydaypractice(fordiscussion,see,e.g.,Alexander,2012,Chapter5;Alexander&Weinberg,2007;Horvath,2010;Weinberg&Alexander,2014).

Page 3: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

3

2005,2007,2011;Wright,2010).2Sincemostfindingsfromexperimentalphilosophy

concernonlylayintuitions,thesefindingscanaccordinglybeignoredasirrelevantto

philosophicalpractice,whichmainlyreliesontheintuitionsofwell-trainedprofessional

philosophers.3

Therearedirectandindirectstrategiesforassessingtheexpertisedefense

(Schulz,Cokely,&Feltz,2011,p.1724).TheseminalrestrictionistresponsebyWeinberg

etal.(2010)pursuesanindirectstrategy.Basedonasurveyofthepsychological

literatureonexpertise,Weinbergetal.arguethattheintuitiveabilitiesofprofessional

philosopherslacksomeofthefeaturesthatconstitutegenuineexpertiseinother

domains.Incontrast,proponentsofdirectstrategiesinvestigatetheintuitionsofthe

allegedphilosophicalexpertsmoredirectly,thatis,byperformingsuitableexperiments

withthoseexpertsubjects.

Inthispaper,wefirstargueinfavorofdirectstrategiesforassessingthe

expertisedefense,bothfordialecticalandsubstantivereasons(directandindirect

strategiesneednotbeinconflict,however,andcansometimesevenbemutually

reinforcing).

Toadvancethedebateaboutdirectstrategiesforassessingtheexpertisedefense,

wethenpresenttheresultsoftwonewexperimentsonexpertintuitionsabout

knowledge.Despitethefactthat“NormativityandEpistemicIntuitions”(Weinbergetal.,

2001)—arguablythe“foundingdocument”ofexperimentalphilosophy—reportsa

numberoffindingsaboutknowledge-relatedintuitions,therehasbeennoattemptsofar

toinvestigatetheknowledgeintuitionsofphilosophicalexpertsmoredirectly.4Thisisa

failurethatwewanttorectifyinthispaper.Ourexperimentswereguidedbythree

ideas:(1)tocompareexpertintuitionsaboutknowledgewithlayintuitions,(2)to

2Foraqualifiedempiricaldefenseofphilosophers’intuitiveexpertise,seeDeCruz(2015)onthebasisofdualprocesspsychology,andBuckwalter(2014)onthebasisofthepsychologyofexpertbiasesandlimitations.SeealsoNado(2015a)foraqualifiedendorsementofphilosophicalexpertisethatdoesnot,however,aimtorebuttheexperimentalrestrictionistchallenge.3Somephilosophershavearguedthatthefindingsofexperimentalphilosophyaremethodologicallyirrelevantbecauseintuitionsaboutthoughtexperimentcasesdonot,oncloserinspection,playanysignificantmethodologicalroleinphilosophicalpractice(Cappelen,2012,2014;Deutsch,2009,2010,2015).Inthiscase,theexpertisedefensemightbeobsoletesimplybecausetherewouldbenochallengefromexperimentalphilosophyinthefirstplace.Thecontroversyoverthisimportantissueisstillongoing,however,andanumberofphilosophershaveofferedforcefulrepliestovariousargumentsforthemethodologicalirrelevanceofintuitions(see,e.g.,Bengson,2014;Boghossian,2014;Brogaard,2014;Chalmers,2014;Ichikawa,2014;Nado,2015b;Weinberg,2014).Forthepurposesofthispaper,wewillthereforesimplyassumethatintuitionsaboutthoughtexperimentcases,broadlyunderstood,doplayasignificantmethodologicalroleinphilosophicalpractice.4OnereasonmightbethattheresultsofWeinberg,Nichols,andStichfailedtoreplicate(Macheryetal.,2015;Nagel,2012;Nagel,Mar,&SanJuan,2013;Nagel,SanJuan,&Mar,2013;Seyedsayamdost,2015).

Page 4: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

4

measuretheirqualityagainsttherelevantepistemologicalconsensus,and(3)tocheck

whethertheexperts’intuitionsareinlinewiththeconsensusoftheirowndiscipline.

Incontrasttomostotherstudiesonphilosophicalexpertintuitions,ourresults

offersomedegreeofsupportfortheexpertisedefense.Forexample,wefoundthatthe

knowledge-relatedintuitionsofepistemologicalexpertsdiffersystematicallyfromthose

oflaypeopleinanumberofcriticalcases,andthattheydifferinawaythatonewould

expectonthebasisoftherelevantliterature.Ontheotherhand,ourresultshavea

puzzlingaspectaswell,forourexpertsubjectstendedtoascribeknowledgeevenin

caseswhereepistemologicalorthodoxywoulddenyknowledge,suchasfake-barn-style

cases.Thus,ourfindingsalsoraisethetroublingnewquestionwhetherepistemologists

havebeencollectivelyunawareofwhattheirownintuitiveexpertisereallytellsthem

aboutcertainkeythoughtexperimentsaboutknowledge.

2 WaysofAssessingtheExpertiseDefense

2.1 IndirectandDirectStrategiesforAssessingtheExpertiseDefense

Letusfirstconsiderthemeritsofindirectanddirectstrategiesforsupportingor

challengingtheexpertisedefense.Asmentionedabove,theearlyrestrictionistresponse

byWeinbergetal.(2010)pursuesanindirectstrategy.Weinbergetal.extractcertain

findingsaboutgenuineexpertisefromtherelevantpsychologicalliteratureandthen

suggestanampliativeinferencefromthesefindingstotheallegedexpertintuitersin

philosophy.Oneoftheirkeypointsisthat,inawiderangeofdomains,thedevelopment

ofgenuineexpertiserequiresclear,timely,andreliablefeedbackduringtheprocessof

traininginalargenumberoftrainingsituations(seealsoClarke,2013).Weinbergetal.

thenarguethatthetrainingofprofessionalphilosophersintheintuitiveevaluationof

thoughtexperimentsfallsconsiderablyshortofsatisfyingtheserequirementsonthe

developmentofgenuineexpertise,andtheyconcludethatprofessionalphilosophers’

intuitionsaboutthoughtexperimentsareunlikelytoresultfromgenuineintuitive

expertise.Thecruxintheirinductiveargumentistheassumptionthatintuitiveexpertise

withrespecttothoughtexperimentsisrelevantlysimilartointuitiveexpertiseinother

domains,becauseotherwisefindingsaboutthelatterwouldnotbeprojectibletothe

Page 5: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

5

former.Buttherearereasonstobeskepticalaboutthisassumptionofprojectibility(see

alsoAndow,2015).

Forexample,paradigmaticcasesofintuitiveexpertiseinthepsychological

literature,suchasfiregroundcommanders(G.Klein,Calderwood,&Clinton-Cirocco,

1986)ornursesinneonatalintensivecareunits(Crandall&Getchell-Reiter,1993),are

primafaciequitedisanalogoustophilosophicalthoughtexperimenters.Whilethe

intuitivejudgmentsoftheformerareinthebusinessofmakingcausalpredictionsin

highlycomplex,uncertainsituations,intuitivejudgmentsaboutthoughtexperiments

typicallydonotconcerncausalrelationsoruncertainoutcomes.Rather,inatypical

philosophicalthoughtexperiment,allrelevantfeaturesoftheintendedscenarioare

eitherexplicitlystipulatedorotherwiseimplicitlyassumedbythethought

experimenter.Ifimportantfactsaboutthescenariostillremainopenorunclear,thenthe

thoughtexperimentinquestionissimplynotagoodone.Thus,thethought

experimenter’smainjobistoevaluateascenariothatalreadycontainsenough

informationtoforecloseanyuncertaintywithrespecttothetargetquestion,e.g.,

whetherSmithknowsthatsomeoneinhisofficeownsaFord(Lehrer,1965).Thisis

quitedisanalogoustotheinformationalsituationofafirefighterinaburningbuilding,

oraneonatalnursewhocaresforprematureinfants.

Whetheronesharesourreservationsaboutindirectstrategiesornot,theycan

hardlyprovidethemostcompellingwayofassessingtheexpertisedefense.Onereason

isthattherelevantinductiveargumentsarealmostalwaysepistemicallyriskierthana

moredirectinvestigationofprofessionalphilosophers’intuitiveexpertise.5Direct

strategiesarealsodialecticallymoreeffective,forinthefaceofindirectargumentsonly,

manyprofessionalphilosopherswillsurelycontinuetothinkthattheysimplymustbe

betterandlessbiasedintheirintuitiveevaluationsofthoughtexperimentsthanlay

people.Thisexpectationisactuallysupportedbypsychologicalresearchonthebias

blindspot,i.e.,bythefindingthatalmosteveryonetakesher-orhimselftobelessbiased

thanotherpeople(Armor,1998;Pronin,2007;Pronin,Gilovich,&Ross,2004)—a

tendencythatmanyexpertsexhibitintheirownareaofexpertiseaswell(Chi,1978;

Glenberg&Epstein,1987).Directstrategiesforassessingtheexpertisedefenseshould

thustakepriorityoverindirectstrategiesatthepresentstageofthedebate.

5Itshouldbenoted,however,that—duetothemediatingroleofoperationalization—eventhemostdirectpsychologicalinvestigationofphilosophicaljudgmentsandintuitionswillstillbeindirectincomparisonto,e.g.,theobservationofoverthumanbehaviororbodilymovements.Forthisreason,oneshouldthinkofthedistinctionbetweendirectandindirectstrategiesmoreasacontinuumthanasastrictdichotomy.

Page 6: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

6

2.2 TheTaskforDirectStrategies

Whatneedstobeshownbydirectstrategiesforsupportingtheexpertisedefense?

First,thereneedstobeasignificantdifferencebetweentherelevantintuitionsof

professionalphilosophersandlaypeople.Intheabsenceofsuchadifference,the

questionwhetherprofessionalphilosophershavebetterintuitionsthanlaypeoplewill

typicallybemoot.Ofcourse,wideintuitiveagreementbetweenallegedexpertsandlay

peopleisnotsufficienttoruleoutintuitiveexpertise,nordoessubstantialintuitive

disagreementbetweenexpertsandlaypeoplealreadyestablishintuitiveexpertise(both

expertsandlaypeoplemightarriveattheirintuitiveverdictsinepistemicallydubious

ways).Butontheassumptionthatphilosophicalexpertspossessgenuineintuitive

expertise,somesignificantdifferencebetweenexpertandlayintuitionsissurelythe

mostnaturalexpectation,anditsabsencewouldseemtoconstitutestrongprimafacie

evidenceagainsttheexpertisedefense.6

Onedirectstrategyforchallengingtheexpertisedefensewouldthereforebeto

showthatlaypeopleandprofessionalphilosophershavemoreorlessthesame

intuitionsinagivendomain.Extantstudiesthatrevealasignificantdifferencebetween

laypeopleandprofessionalphilosophersareSytsmaandMachery(2010)onintuitions

aboutphenomenalconsciousness,Schulz,Cokely,andFeltz(2011)onincompatibilist

intuitionsaboutfreewill,andMachery(2012)onexpertintuitionsaboutreference.7

Otherpertinentstudies(Hitchcock&Knobe,2009;Schwitzgebel&Cushman,2012,

2015;Tobia,Buckwalter,&Stich,2013;Tobia,Chapman,&Stich,2013;Vaesen,

Peterson,&VanBezooijen,2013)didnotreportanysignificantdifferencebetween

philosophersandlaypeople.Ourownexperimentalresultsindicatethatthereisindeed

asignificantdifferencebetweenprofessionalepistemologistsandlaypeopleconcerning

intuitionsaboutknowledge(seebelow).

Second,asignificantdifferencebetweenexpertsandlaypeoplebyitselfisnot

enoughtosupporttheexpertisedefense,ofcourse.Therelevantdifferencemustalso

involveasignificantimprovementofexpertintuitionsoverlayintuitions,forexample,by

6Thankstoananonymousreviewerforpromptingtheseclarifications.7Afterthispaperwasacceptedforpublication,welearnedaboutarecentstudybyJ.AdamCarter,MartinPeterson,andBartvanBezooijen(2015)thatinteraliasuggeststhatphilosophicalexpertsarelesswillingthanlaypeopletoself-ascribeknowledgeofsimpleanalytictruthsversusknowledgeofwidelyacceptedempiricaltruths(thankstoMartinPetersonforthepointer).

Page 7: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

7

revealingthatexpertintuitionsarelesssusceptibletotheinfluenceofsomeofthe

irrelevantfactorsthatexperimentalphilosophershaveidentified.Sofar,thereisonly

littleexperimentalevidencethatthismightbethecase.WhiletheresultsofSytsmaand

Machery(2010)areatleastconsistentwithexpertsuperiority,thefindingsofSchulz,

Cokely,andFeltz(2011)indicatethatphilosophers’compatibilistintuitionsaboutfree

willareequallyaffectedbytheinnatepersonalitytraitofextraversionasthoseoflay

people.AndMachery(2012)presentsevidencethatthereferentialintuitionsinvarious

subgroupsoflinguisticexpertspointinratherdifferentdirections.Turri(2013)offersat

leastsomeindirectsupportforanimprovementofintuitionsaboutknowledgethrough

expertise,sincehefoundthatlaypeople’sjudgmentsaboutGettiercasescanbebrought

inlinewiththeepistemologicalconsensusbyamoreperspicuouspresentationoftheir

structure.Ourownresultsalsosuggestthatvariousknowledge-relatedintuitionsof

professionalepistemologistsmightbebetterthanthoseoflaypeopleinsofarasthey

comesignificantlyclosertothetextbookconsensusoncasesoftherelevanttype(see

below).Aswewillsee,however,theymightstillnotcomecloseenough.

Third,adirectstrategyinsupportoftheexpertisedefensewouldideallyshow

thattheexpertintuitionsareinlinewiththetextbookconsensusontheintuitive

evaluationofthoughtexperimentsoftherelevanttype.Iftheintuitionsofprofessional

philosophersturnedouttobesignificantlydifferentfromtherelevantconsensusinthe

literature,thiswouldseemtobeaconsiderableembarrassment,becauseitwould

indicatethatphilosophy,asadiscipline,mightbedeludedaboutwhattheintuitionsof

itsexpertpractitionersactuallysay.Forexample,eveniftheintuitionsofprofessional

epistemologiststurnedouttobefreeofallknownbiases,butalsocameoutinfavorof

ascribingknowledgeinGettiersituations,thiswouldstillbeatroublingresultfor

epistemologyasadiscipline.Forsucharesultwouldsuggestthatthedisciplineof

epistemologyisdysfunctionalinsofarasitfailstomaptheintuitionsofitsexpert

practitionersontoadisciplinaryconsensusintherightkindofway.Ourownresults

indicatethatsomethinglikethismightinfactbethecase(seebelow).

Inconclusion,itmustbeconcededthatthepresentlyavailableexperimental

evidencedoesnotsubstantiatedirectstrategiesforsupportingtheexpertisedefense.

Andwhileourownexperiments—tobereportedbelow—offersomesupportforthe

superiorityofexpertintuitionsaboutknowledge,theyalsosuggestthatsomeofthese

intuitionsdeviatefromthetextbookconsensusinunexpectedandtroublesomeways.

Page 8: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

8

3 Experiments

3.1 Experiment1

3.1.1 RationaleandMaterial

Afirstideabehindourexperimentissimplytocomparetheintuitionsofexpert

epistemologistsandlaypeopleconcerninganumberofsystematicallyimportanttypes

ofthoughtexperimentsaboutknowledge.

Asecondideaistomeasurethequalityoflaypeople’sandexpertepistemologists’

intuitionsagainsthowclosetheycometotherelevanttextbookconsensusonthought

experimentsofthesamekind.Wethereforeapproachtheissueofintuitiveexpertise

fromaslightlydifferentanglethanusual.Thestandardprocedurewouldbetocheck

whetherprofessionalphilosophersarelesssusceptibletosomephilosophically

irrelevantfactorthatwasfoundtoinfluencelaypeople’sintuitions(see,e.g.,

Schwitzgebel&Cushman,2012,2015).Incontrast,weaimforapositiveevaluationof

thequalityofexpertintuitionsaboutknowledgefromtheviewpointofthepresent

epistemologicalconsensus.Experimentsthat“only”testforthesusceptibilityofexpert

intuitionstophilosophicallyirrelevantfactorscan“atbest”establishapurelynegative

result,i.e.,thatprofessionalphilosophersarenotsusceptibletotheinfluenceofsuch

factors.Ourexperimentsthusbearontheexpertisedefenseinwaysthatdifferfrom

experimentsthatfollowthestandardprocedureand,asaconsequence,leadto

interestinglydifferentresults,aswewillarguebelow.8

Itmightbeobjectedthatregardingthetextbookconsensusasanadequate

standardforevaluatingintuitionsaboutknowledgebegsthequestioninfavorof

intuitionsthatsupportthetextbookconsensus.Inthiscase,however,wefacethe

unusuallydifficulttaskofassessingthequalityofintuitionsaboutknowledgeinthe

absenceofsomeindependentstandard.Moreover,theinsistencethatwehaveto

bracketeventhosecaseswherewedofindarobustepistemologicalconsensusis

arguablyanundulyskepticalmaneuver(Sosa,2007;Williamson,2004,2011).Forthese

reasons,theassumptionthatthetextbookconsensusprovidesatleastadefeasibleor

8Thankstoananonymousreviewerforencouragingustomakeourproceduremoreexplicit.

Page 9: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

9

primafaciestandardforassessingthequalityofintuitionsaboutknowledgedoesnot

seemespeciallyproblematicorquestionbegging.

Evenifoneshouldrejecttheideathatthetextbookconsensuscanbeusedasan

adequatestandardofcorrectnessforintuitionsaboutknowledge,onecanstill

acknowledgeathirdideabehindourexperiment,namely,totestwhethertheintuitions

ofexpertepistemologistsareinlinewiththerelevanttextbookconsensusoftheirown

discipline.

Inordertotrulyengagetheexpertiseofourepistemologicalexperts,we

confrontedthemwithunfamiliarvariationsofthoughtexperimentsthatalreadyfigure

intheepistemologicalliterature,althoughlessprominentlythan,e.g.,Gettier’soriginal

cases(1963)orthefake-barncase(Goldman,1976).Usingsuchwell-knowncasesmight

havetheunwantedeffectthatepistemologistsmerelyrecalltheirearlierintuitive

verdictsfrommemory,orthattheysimplyreproducethetextbookconsensus(seealso

Rini,2015,sec.5.1).Ofcourse,someonewhoknowstheepistemologicalliteraturereally

wellwillprobablybeabletoidentifythecasesthatinspiredourvignettes.Butusingnew

variationsoffamiliarcasesshouldatleastraisethechancethatevenprofessional

epistemologiststrulyengagetheirintuitiveabilities.

Letusnowintroducethevignettesthatweusedinourfirstexperiment.Ineach

case,wewillfirstreproducethevignettesinexactlytheformthatweusedinthe

experiment,alongsidewiththetargetquestionthattheparticipantswereaskedto

answer.Afterthat,wedescribethepointofthevignetteinamoreabstractway,and

thencitethecasesonwhichitwasmodeled,aswellastheconsensusontheevaluation

ofcasesofthiskindaccordingtotheepistemologicalliterature.

Asecurityguardmonitorsanumberofvideoscreensthatshowwhatisgoingoninan

officebuildingacrossthestreet.Atmidnight,theguardcheckshervideoscreensand

sees,onfivedifferentscreensthatshowfivedifferentoffices,thatpeoplearestill

workingintheiroffices.Shethinkstoherself:“Thereisstillsomeoneinthebuilding.”

Fourofthefivescreensareinfactworkingproperly.Butduetosomeunusual

malfunction,oneofthefivescreensactuallyshowsavideotapefromthenightbefore,

andtodaythisparticularofficeisalreadyempty.

Howmuchdoyoudisagreeoragreewiththefollowingclaim:

Theguardknowsthatthereisstillsomeoneinthebuilding.

Page 10: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

10

Monitorisacasewherethesubjecthasmultiplepiecesofevidenceforthetarget

proposition,eachofwhichwouldbesufficientforknowledge.Inaddition,thesubject

alsohasonefaultypieceofevidenceforthetargetproposition,inthiscase:theone

malfunctioningvideoscreen.Intheepistemologicalliterature,casesofthiskindare

regardedasclearcasesofknowledgethatrefutetheearlyno-false-assumptionsolution

(Clark,1963)toGettier’s(1963)originalcounterexamplestothestandardanalysisof

knowledgeasjustifiedtruebelief(cf.Lehrer,1965).Suchcasesthengaverisetotheno-

essential-false-assumptionsolution(see,e.g.,Harman,1973;Lehrer,1974;Lycan,2006).

InMonitor,forexample,thesecurityguard’sjustificationdoesnotessentiallydependon

themalfunctioningvideoscreen,sincesheequallyreliesonthefourscreensthat

functionproperly.

ACEOhasownedafamouspaintingforalongtime.Justthismorning,sheshowedittoa

colleagueinherofficewhereshecanwatchthepaintingeveryday.Intheevening,the

CEOreturnshomefromworkandisabouttocheckheremail.Whatshewillfindthereis

anurgentnotebyhersecretarythatsaysthatherpaintingwasstolenshortlyaftershe

hadleftheroffice.Infact,theCEO’scolleaguemerelywantedtoplayatrickonher,and

soitwasactuallyhimwhousedthesecretary’semailaccounttosendherthisnote.The

paintingitselfisstillontheCEO’sofficewall,justasitalwayswas.

Howmuchdoyoudisagreeoragreewiththefollowingclaim:

AtthetimewhentheCEOreturnshome,butbeforesheactuallychecksheremail,she

knowsthatthepaintingisstillonherofficewall.

Paintingisacasewhereevidencethatthesubjectdoesnot(yet)possess—here,an

unreademail—threatenstounderminethesubject’sjustificationforbelievingthetarget

propositionthatthepaintingisstillonherofficewall.GilbertHarman,whointroduced

casesofthiskindintotheepistemologicalliterature,regardedthemasintuitivecasesof

non-knowledge(Harman,1968,p.172,1973,pp.144–145).Paintingismodeledafter

thecaseofDonaldandtheunopenedletter(Harman,1973,p.143),whichisless

discussedtodaythanthemorefamiliarassassinationcase(Harman,1968,p.172,1973,

pp.143–144).Itisfairtosay,however,thatmanyepistemologistsdidnotfollow

Harman’sintuitiveassessmentofsuchcases,atleastnotwithoutqualifications(see,e.g.,

P.Klein,1981;Lycan,1977;Pritchard,2005).Accordingly,thepresentconsensusisthat

casesofthiskindareintuitivelyunclear(Shope,2002,p.32).

Page 11: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

11

Thedirectorofasculpturemuseumissoimpressedwithrecentimprovementsof

hologramimagesthatshedecidestoperformasecrettestonthevisitorsofhermuseum.

Tothisend,sheordershologramimagesthatevenartexpertscannotvisuallydistinguish

fromtherealsculpturesinhermuseum,andshereplacesallbutoneofthesculpturesby

theirhologramimage.Asthedirectorhadexpected,noonerealizesanydifference

betweenthehologramimagesandtherealsculptures.Oneday,theworld’sgreatest

Rodinexpertisvisitinghermuseum.Theexpertisstandinginfrontofafamousmarble

sculpturebyRodin,whichistheonlyrealsculpturethatispresentlyondisplayinthe

museum,andshethinkstoherself:“I’mfacingoneofRodin’sfamousmarblesculptures

now.”

Howmuchdoyoudisagreeoragreewiththefollowingclaim:

TheRodinexpertknowsthatthesculptureinfrontofherisoneofRodin’sfamous

marblesculptures.

InSculpture,thesubjecthasatruebeliefaboutamarblesculptureonthebasisofvisual

perception.However,themarblesculptureissurroundedbyvisuallyindistinguishable

hologramimagesofsculpturesinthesamemuseum.Inasense,then,itisamatterof

luckthatthesubjecthasacquiredatruebeliefinthissituation,forshecouldhaveeasily

lookedatanothersculptureandtherebyacquiredafalsebelief.Thiscaseispartly

inspiredbyLehrerandPaxson’s(1969,pp.234–235)caseofMr.Promoter,whichthey

presentasacounterexampletoUnger’s(1968)earlyanti-luckanalysisofknowledge,

andmainlybyCarlGinet’sfamousfake-barncase(Goldman,1976,pp.772–773),which

Goldmanusesasacounterexampletohisearliercausalanalysisof(perceptual)

knowledge(Goldman,1967).Thefake-barncasewasoriginallypresentedasaclearnon-

instanceofknowledge,andthisintuitiveverdictiswidelyacceptedinthe

epistemologicalliterature(see,e.g.,EngelJr.,2015;Hetherington,2015;Ichikawa&

Steup,2014;Shope,2004;Steup,2014),withonlyveryfewexceptions(see,e.g.,Gendler

&Hawthorne,2005;Heathcote,2006;Hetherington,1999;Lycan,1977,2006).9

Alittlegirllikestoplayagamewithflippingacoin.Shesometimesgetsa“special

feeling”thatthenextflipwillcomeoutheads.Whenshegetsthis“specialfeeling”,sheis

9Steup,forexample,explicitlynotesthatthereis“…broadagreementamongepistemologiststhatHenry’sbelief[inthefake-barncase]doesnotqualifyasknowledge”(Steup,2014,sec.1.2).

Page 12: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

12

rightabouthalfthetime,andwrongabouthalfthetime.Justbeforethenextflip,the

littlegirlgetsthat“specialfeeling”,andthefeelingleadshertobelievethatthecoinwill

landheads.Sheflipsthecoin,anditdoeslandheads.

Howmuchdoyoudisagreeoragreewiththefollowingclaim:

Thelittlegirlknewthatthecoinwasgoingtolandheads.

Thisclearcaseofanon-instanceofknowledge,ClearNon-Knowledge1,wasalready

usedseveraltimesinexperimentalstudies(see,e.g.,Nichols,Stich,&Weinberg,2003;

Swainetal.,2008;Weinbergetal.,2001).Ineachcase,thevastmajorityofthetestedlay

subjectsclassifieditasacaseofnon-knowledge.Asignificantdifferencebetweenexpert

intuitionsandlayintuitionsconcerningthiscasewouldthusbestrongevidenceforthe

superiority(orinferiority)ofexpertintuitions.

Beforeleavingthehouse,awomanwantstocheckwhetherthelightinherbathroomis

off.Sheopensthebathroomdoor,anditiscompletelydarkinside.Shethinkstoherself:

“Alright,thelightinmybathroomisoff.”

Howmuchdoyoudisagreeoragreewiththefollowingclaim:

Thewomanknowsthatthelightinherbathroomisoff.

Thisnewlydevisedcase,ClearKnowledge1,isintendedasaclear,everydaycaseof

knowledgeonthebasisofvisualperception.AsinthecaseofClearNon-Knowledge1,a

significantdifferencebetweenexpertandlayintuitionsaboutthiscasewouldbestrong

evidenceforthesuperiority(orinferiority)ofexpertintuitions.

3.1.2 Subjects

Overall,thedataof224subjectswereincludedinourmainanalysis.82wereidentified

asexpertsubjects(meanagewas38years;82%male)and142aslaysubjects(mean

agewas39years;37%male).

Theexpertsubjectswererecruitedviaacallforparticipationonanelectronic

mailinglistforphilosophers(PHILOS-L)andontheExperimentalPhilosophyblog

(http://philosophycommons.typepad.com/xphi/)thatcontainedalinkthatdirected

subjectstotheexperiment.Inordertobeincludedasexpertsubjects,participantshad

toindicatethat,firstly,theyhaveaPhDinphilosophyand,secondly,epistemologyisone

Page 13: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

13

oftheirareasofspecializationorcompetence.Furthermore,weexcludedthedataof

subjectswhodidnotcompletethesurveyorcompleteditinlessthanoneminute.Outof

initially421people,82metthesecriteria,whichwerenotannouncedinthecallfor

participationorduringthesurvey.Tomotivatepeopletotakepartinourstudywe

announcedthatabookaboutexperimentalphilosophywouldberaffledamongall

participants.Toenterthisoptionalraffle,subjectswereaskedtoprovidetheiremail

addressattheendofthesurvey.

LaysubjectswererecruitedviaadatabaselocatedintheUK.Theywereinvited

viaanemailthatcontainedalinkthatdirectedsubjectstotheexperiment.Eachsubject

received£0.50.Weincludedthedataofsubjectswhoindicatedthattheyhavenoprior

experiencewithphilosophyandthattheyarenativespeakersofEnglish.Moreover,we

excludedthedataofsubjectswhodidnotcompletethesurveyorcompleteditinless

thanoneminute.Outofinitially284people,142metthesecriteria,whichwereagain

notannouncedinthecallforparticipationorduringthesurvey.

3.1.3 DesignandProcedure

TheexperimentwasconductedontheInternet.Uponclickingonalinkwhichsubjects

receivedviaemailorontheblogpost,theywereredirectedtoawebsitecontainingthe

experiment.Subjectsfirstreadgeneralinstructions.Thesefamiliarizedthemwiththe6-

pointLikertscalerangingfrom1(‘stronglydisagree’)to6(‘stronglyagree’),askedthem

toreadthesubsequentdescriptionsofscenarioscarefully,andappealedtothemtotake

thetaskseriously.Afterthat,thethreecasesMonitor,Painting,andSculpturewere

presentedinarandomizedorder.TheClearNon-Knowledge1caseandtheClear

Knowledge1casewerealwayspresentedonfourthandfifthposition,respectively.We

presentedtherelativelyclearcasesafterthelessclearcasesinordertoavoidcontrast

effectsasfoundinotherstudies(cf.Swainetal.,2008).Onthefinalpage,weaskeda

numberofdemographicquestionsandassessedtheparticipants’levelofphilosophical

educationandexpertise.

3.1.4 Results

TheresultsofourfirstexperimentaresummarizedinFigure1.AmixedANOVA

(betweensubjects:laysubjectsvs.expertsubjects;withinsubject:thefivecases)

showedaverysignificantinteractionofsubjectsandcases,indicatingthattheresponse

patternoflaysubjectsandexpertsubjectsdifferedstronglyoverthefivecases,F(4,

Page 14: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

14

888)=20.58,p<.001,η2=.08.Theaveragetimespenttocompletethesurveydidnotdiffersignificantlybetweenlaypeople(322seconds)andexperts(353seconds),F(1,

220)=.77287,p=.38.10

Figure1.Meanratingsforthefivecasesdividedinlayandexpertjudgments.Thescaleranged

from1(‘stronglydisagree’withtheclaimthattheagentknewtherelevantproposition)to6

(‘stronglyagree’).Errorbarsrepresent95%confidenceintervals.

Amorefine-grainedanalysisrevealedthatforthreeofthefivecasesthejudgmentsoflaysubjectsandexpertsubjectsdifferedsignificantly,withtheexperts’judgmentsbeingclosertotheevaluationofcorrespondingcasesintheepistemologicalliterature.ForMonitor,laysubjects(M=4.72,SD=1.51)andexpertsubjects(M=5.10,

SD=1.11)bothtendedtoagreewiththeclaimthattheguardknowsthatthereisstill

someoneinthebuilding.Thelevelofagreementforthiscase,whichcorrespondsto

casesthatareregardedasacasesofknowledgeintheepistemologicalliterature,was

significantlyhigherforexpertsubjects,F(1,222)=3.93,p<.05,η2=.02.11ForSculpture,

laysubjects’(M=4.79,SD=1.20)agreedsignificantlystrongerwiththeclaimthatthe

RodinexpertknowsthatthesculptureinfrontofherisoneofRodin’sfamousmarble

10Twosubjects(oneexpertsubject,onelaysubject)wereexcludedfromthisanalysisbecausetheyspentover10,000secondslongerthanallothersubjects.11Wecalculatedallcomparisonsassumingequalandunequalvariances.Sincetheresultsdifferedonlymarginally(itwasneverthecasethatacertaindifferencewassignificantusingoneassumptionbutnotsignificantwhentheotherassumptionwasused)wechosetoreportourfindingsinthemostcommonform,i.e.,withoutadjustingthedegreesoffreedom.

1,0

2,0

3,0

4,0

5,0

6,0

Leve

l of A

gree

men

t

Lay Subjects

Expert Subjects

Page 15: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

15

sculpturesthanexpertsubjects(M=3.77,SD=1.67),F(1,222)=28.06,p<.001,η2=.11.12Althoughexpertsweremoreskepticalthanlaysubjectsabouttheclaimthatthis

caseconstitutesacaseofknowledge,theywerealsomoreinclinedtoagreewiththis

claimthanonewouldexpectfromtheconsensusintheepistemologicalliterature(see

Figure2forthedistributionofexpertjudgmentsforSculpture).13ForClearNon-

Knowledge1,expertsubjects(M=1.41,SD=0.74)disagreedsignificantlystrongerthan

laysubjects(M=2.64,SD=1.44)withtheclaimthatthelittlegirlknewthatthecoin

wasgoingtolandheads,F(1,222)=51.55,p<.001,η2=.19.14Afurtherinterestingdifferencebetweenlaysubjectsandexpertsubjectsisthatlaysubjects’evaluationsfor

thefirstthreecases(Monitor,Painting,andSculpture)didnotdiffersignificantly,F(2,

282)=2.00,p=.14,whiletheevaluationsofexpertsubjectsdifferedstrongly,F(2,

162)=27.32,p<.001,η2=.25andinlinewiththerelevantconsensusintheepistemologicalliterature.ForthePaintingcaseandClearKnowledge1,nosignificant

differencebetweenlaysubjectsandexpertsubjectswasfound(p=.52andp=.09,

respectively).

12SinceSculptureismodeledafterfake-barncases(seeabove),ourfindingthatlaypeopletendtoascribeknowledgeinthiscasebasicallyconfirmsakeyresultofthepioneeringstudyonfake-barncasesbyColaçoetal.(2014).13Afterthispaperwasacceptedforpublication,welearnedaboutanunpublishedstudybyJ.AdamCarter,DuncanPritchard,andJoshuaSheperd(ms)thatinteraliacomparesexpertandlayintuitionsconcerningfake-barn-stylecases,andthatmostlyconfirmsourownfindings.Forexample,Carter,Pritchard,andSheperdalsofoundthat,onaverage,laypeopleandexpertsdoascribeknowledgeinsuchcases,eventhoughexpertsarelessinclinedtoascribeknowledgethanlaypeople(thankstoJoshuaShepherdforthepointer).14Sincetheratingsof3and4werelabeledwith‘mildlydisagree’and‘mildlyagree’,respectively,onemightinterpretratingsof3orbelowascasesofdisagreementandratingsof4oraboveascasesofagreement.Applyingthisclassification,only3.8%oftheexpertsubjectsagreedwiththeclaimthatthelittlegirlknewtheoutcomeofthecoinflip,while33.8%ofthelaysubjectsagreedwiththisclaim.

Page 16: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

16

Figure2.DistributionofexpertratingsforSculpture.

Moreover,theresultpatternofexpertswhoindicatedthatepistemologyisoneof

theirareasofspecializationversusexpertswhomerelyindicatedthatepistemologyis

oneoftheirareasofcompetencedidnotdiffersignificantly,F(4,320)=1.67,p=.16(for

theinteractionoflevelofcompetence*cases).Inordertoseewhetherthereisa

significantdifferencebetweenourexpertsubjectsandthosesubjectswho“merely”hold

aPhDinphilosophy,yetwithouthavingepistemologyasoneoftheirareasof

specializationorcompetence,wecomparedtheratingsofthelatter(N=74,not

includedinpreviousanalyses)withtheratingsofourexpertssubjects.Theresponse

patternofthesetwogroupsdifferedsignificantly,F(4,468)=4.51,p=.001,η2=.04(fortheinteractionofepistemologicalexpertise*cases).15Atthelevelofindividualcases,

however,thedifferencebetweenexpertsubjects(M=3.77,SD=1.67)and“mere”

philosophyPhDs(M=4.54,SD=1.32)wasonlyclearlysignificantforSculpture,F(1,

117)=15.20,p=.01,η2=.05,anditwentinthedirectionthatonewouldexpectonthebasisoftheepistemologicalliterature.Thisdifferencebetweenexpertepistemologists

and“mere”philosophyPhDslendssomesupporttothedomain-specificityofintuitive

expertiseinepistemology,whichisawell-establishedfeatureofexpertisemore

generally(cf.Ericsson&Lehmann,1996;Gobet&Simon,1996;Vicente&Wang,1998).

15ThankstoShen-yiLiaoandHannesRuschforpressingthispointonindependentoccasions.

0

5

10

15

20

25

Num

ber

of r

espo

nses

Level of (dis)agreement

Expertra)ngsforScuplture

Page 17: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

17

3.2 Experiment2

3.2.1 RationaleandMaterial

Themainideabehindoursecondexperimentwastoreplicateandcorroboratetwo

strikingresultsofourfirstexperiment.

Ontheonehand,thiswasthefindingthateventheepistemologicalexperts

classifiedSculptureasacaseofknowledge(incontrasttohowcasesofthiskindare

commonlyassessedintheepistemologicalliterature).Tothisend,werepeated

Sculptureinthesecondexperimentandaddedtwonewcases,ExamandDollar,that

shouldalsoberegardedasnon-instancesofknowledgeaccordingtotheepistemological

literature(seebelow).

Ontheotherhand,wetriedtoexplainthesignificantdifferencebetween

epistemologicalexpertsandlaypeopleintheirintuitiveevaluationofClearNon-

Knowledge1.Wespeculatedthatthissurprisingdifferencemightresultfromthefact

thattheagentseestheresult,i.e.,thattheagentcomestoknowthatshewasrightabout

theoutcomeofhercoinflip(labeledas“successbias”inthefollowing—seebelow).

Therefore,wereplacedClearNon-Knowledge1byananalogouscase,ClearNon-

Knowledge2,whichonlydiffersinsofarastheagentdoesnotcometoknowthather

predictionabouttheoutcomeofthecoinflipwascorrect.

Letusnowintroduceandexplaintheadditionalvignettesthatweusedinour

secondexperiment,followingthesameschemaasabove(cf.section3.1.1).

Aprofessorofmedicinelearnsthatoneinabillionstudentsdiewhiletakingtheirfinal

exam.Inaboutfiveminutes,theprofessorissettosubstituteforasickcolleaguein

conductingafinalexamofastudentthatshehadnevermetbefore.Theprofessorthinks

toherself:“Thestudentwillsurviveherfinalexam.”Andinfact,thestudentdoessurvive

herfinalexam.

Howmuchdoyoudisagreeoragreewiththefollowingclaim:

Beforetheexambegan,theprofessorknewthatthestudentwouldsurviveherfinal

exam.

Page 18: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

18

InExam,aprofessoracquiresabeliefaboutthesurvivalofastudentonthesolebasisof

overwhelmingstatisticalevidence.Thiscaseismodeledafteralotterycase,whereone

acquiresthebeliefthatone’slotteryticketwilllosemerelyonthebasisofknowingthe

extremelyhighoddsforwinningthelottery(Harman,1968,p.166,1973,p.118).Such

casesaretypicallytreatedasclearnon-instancesofknowledgeintheepistemological

literature(see,e.g.,DeRose,1996;Hawthorne,2004;Pritchard,2005;Williamson,

2000).16

Awaiterwasrecentlyhiredbyarestaurantinaremotepartofthecountrywhere,

unbeknownsttoeveryone,mostofthecirculatingdollarbillsarefake.Therestaurant

managerowesthewaitertendollarsforanextrahourthatheworked.Shetakesaten

dollarbillfromthecashregisterandhandsitovertothewaiter,andthisleadsthewaiter

tobelievethattherestaurantmanagerhasjustgivenhimtendollars.Infact,this

particulartendollarbillhappenstobeoneofthefewgenuinedollarbillsinthearea.17

Howmuchdoyoudisagreeoragreewiththefollowingclaim:

Thewaiterknowsthattherestaurantmanagerhasgivenhimtendollars.

Dollarisavariationonthefake-barncasethatisusedlessfrequentlythantheoriginal

fake-barncase(seeabove).Justlikethefake-barncase,itistreatedasaclearnon-

instanceofknowledgeintheepistemologicalliterature(see,e.g.,Littlejohn,2012,p.

193;Sutton,2005,p.360).

16ThereisadisanalogybetweenExamandstandardlotterycasesthatmightberelevanttotheirknowledge-relatedassessment,however.Foronthenaturalassumptionthatthestudentisinnormalphysicalcondition,theremightbenoclosepossibleworldwherethisparticularstudentdiesduringherfinalexam.Andinthatcase,theprofessor’sbeliefthatthestudentwillsurviveherfinalexamcouldnoteasilyhavebeenfalse,i.e.,theprofessor’sbeliefissafe.Forthisreason,onemightcountcaseslikeExamasbonafidecasesofknowledge—unlikestandardlotterycases,whereweassumethateverylotteryticketwinsinsomeclosepossibleworld(see,e.g.,Pritchard,2005).Amoresystematicinvestigationof(expert)intuitionsaboutlottery-stylecaseswouldthushavetocomparecaseslikeExamwithcasesthataremorecloselyanalogoustostandardlotterycases(thankstoJensKipperforpressingthispoint).17Afterthispaperwasacceptedforpublication,AaronMeskinpointedouttousthatthephrase‘dollarbills’—withoutthequalifier‘ten’—isnaturallytakentorefertoonedollarbillsonly.Sotakenliterally,ourvignettewouldtriggerareadingaccordingtowhichonlytheonedollarbills—butnotthetendollarbills—arefakeinthescenariodescribed,andthiswouldweakentheanalogywiththeoriginalfake-barncase.However,noneofthepeoplewhotookthestudy,orwhosawthevignetteinconferencepresentations—andnoteventhenativespeakersamongourproof-readers—seemtohavenoticedthemistake(or,morecautiously,noneofthemfelttheneedtopointitouttous).Moreover,ourresultsforDollararealmostidenticaltootherresultsforfake-barnstylecases(seeaboveandbelow).Therefore,itseemsreasonabletoassumethattheparticipantsinourexperimentsimplyaccommodatedthemistakeinlinewiththeintendedreadingofthecasedescription,whichisclearlysuggestedbythefinalsentenceofourvignette—asentencethatmakeslittlesenseontheassumptionthatonlytheonedollarbillsinthescenarioarefake.Inallfairness,however,itwouldbeusefultohaveafollow-upstudythatconfirmstheinsignificanceofourmistakenphrasing(thankstoJoshuaAlexanderandAaronMeskinfordiscussion).

Page 19: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

19

Alittlegirllikestoplayagamewithflippingacoin.Shesometimesgetsa“special

feeling”thatthenextflipwillcomeoutheads.Whenshegetsthis“specialfeeling”,sheis

rightabouthalfthetime,andwrongabouthalfthetime.Justbeforethenextflip,the

littlegirlgetsthis“specialfeeling”,andthefeelingleadshertobelievethatthecoinwill

landheads.Sheflipsthecoin,anditdoeslandheads.Butshehasinadvertentlyflipped

thecoinoutofthewindow,andthereforeshecannot—andwillnot—seetheresult.

Howmuchdoyoudisagreeoragreewiththefollowingclaim:

Thelittlegirlknewthatthecoinwasgoingtolandheads.

ThemainpointofClearNon-Knowledge2wastotestastrikingresultconcerninglay

people’sintuitionsaboutClearNon-Knowledge1fromourfirstexperiment,namely,that

asignificantnumberoflaysubjects(33,8%)didinfactascribeknowledgeinthiscase.

Ourmainhypothesisforexplainingthisfindingwasthatlaypeoplemightbesusceptible

tosomethinglikea“successbias”,i.e.,thattheymightbeinfluencedbythefactthat,

afterflippingthecoin,thelittlegirllearnsthather“specialfeeling”abouttheoutcomeof

thecoinflipturnedouttobecorrect(see,e.g.,Baron&Hershey,1988).Arelated

phenomenonthatmightexplainwhyathirdofalllaysubjectsascribedknowledgetothe

littlegirliscalled“protagonistprojection”anddescribespeople’stendencytoproject

themselvesintothepointofviewoftheprotagonist(see,e.g.,Holton,1997;Nagel,San

Juan,&Mar,2013).Totestthesehypotheses,wereplacedtheclearcaseofnon-

knowledgefromexperiment1withacasewheretheagentdoesnotand,infact,cannot

seetheresult.

3.2.2 Subjects

Overall,thedataof227subjectswereincludedinouranalysis.50wereidentifiedas

expertsubjects(meanagewas33years;76%weremale)and177aslaysubjects(mean

agewas46years;53%weremale).

Therecruitingandclassificationprocedureforexpertsubjectswasthesameasin

experiment1,withthefollowingexceptions.Inordertogainenoughexpertsubjects,we

includednotonlyparticipantswhoindicatedthattheyhaveaPhDinphilosophy,but

alsothoseparticipantswhoindicatedthattheyhaveanMAinphilosophy(inadditionto

havingepistemologyasoneoftheirareasofspecializationorcompetence).Subjects

Page 20: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

20

whoindicatedthattheyhadparticipatedinourfirstexperimentwereexcluded.Outof

initially186people,50metthesecriteria.

Apartfromthefactthatweonlyinvitedsubjectswhodidnotparticipateinour

firstexperiment,therecruitingandclassificationprocedureforlaysubjectswasthe

sameasinexperiment1.Outofinitially293people,177mettherelevantcriteria.

3.2.3 DesignandProcedure

Thedesignandprocedurewasthesameasinexperiment1,i.e.,participantssawthefirst

threecases(Exam,Sculpture,andDollar)inarandomizedorderwhilethecasesClear

Non-Knowledge2(seeabove)andClearKnowledge1(sameasinexperiment1)were

alwayspresentedinfourthandfifthposition,respectively.

3.2.4 Results

TheresultsofoursecondexperimentaresummarizedinFigure3.AmixedANOVA

(betweensubjects:laysubjectsvs.expertsubjects;withinsubject:thefivecases)

showedaverysignificantinteractionofsubjectsandcases,indicatingagainthatthe

responsepatternoflaysubjectsandexpertsubjectsdifferedstronglyoverthefivecases,

F(4,900)=13.80,p<.001,η2=.06.Therewasasignificantdifferenceintheaveragetimespenttocompletethesurveybetweenlaypeople(267seconds)andexperts(370

seconds),F(1,224)=7.54,p>.01,η2=.03.18

18Oneexpertsubjectwasexcludedfromthisanalysisbecausesheorhespentover1,000secondslonger(2,554seconds)thanallothersubjects.

1,0

2,0

3,0

4,0

5,0

6,0

Leve

l of A

gree

men

t

Lay Subjects

Expert Subjects

Page 21: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

21

Figure3.Meanratingsforthefivecasesdividedinlayandexpertjudgments.Thescaleranged

from1(‘stronglydisagree’withtheclaimthattheagentknewtherelevantproposition)to6

(‘stronglyagree’).Errorbarsrepresent95%confidenceintervals.

Amorefine-grainedanalysisrevealedthat,asinexperiment1,thejudgmentsoflaysubjectsandexpertsubjectsdifferedsignificantlyforthreeofthefivecases,withtheexperts’judgmentsbeingclosertotheevaluationofcorrespondingcasesintheepistemologicalliterature.IncaseofDollar,laysubjects(M=5.10,SD=1.31)andexpert

subjects(M=3.84,SD=1.73)bothtendedtoagreewiththeclaimthatthewaiterknows

thattherestaurantmanagerhasgivenhimtendollars.Thelevelofagreementforthis

case,whichcorrespondstocasesthatareregardedascasesofnon-knowledgeinthe

epistemologicalliterature,wassignificantlylowerforexpertsubjects,F(1,225)=28.97,

p<.001,η2=.11.Interestingly,andincontrasttothetextbookconsensus,themajorityofexpertsubjects(60%,cf.footnote9)evaluatedDollarasacaseofknowledge.For

Sculpture,weobtainedthesameresultpatternasinourfirstexperiment.Laysubjects’

(M=4.94,SD=1.35)agreedsignificantlystrongerwiththeclaimthattheRodinexpert

knowsthatthesculptureinfrontofherisoneofRodin’sfamousmarblesculpturesthan

expertsubjects(M=3.72,SD=1.86),F(1,225)=26.83,p<.001,η2=.11.Again,expertsubjectsweremoreinclinedtoagree(56%)withthisclaimthanonewouldexpectfrom

theconsensusintheepistemologicalliterature,whichisanalmostexactreplicationof

thesurprisingresultfromourfirstexperiment.ForClearNon-Knowledge2,theresult

patternwassimilartotheoneobtainedforthecorrespondingcaseinourfirst

experiment.Expertsubjects(M=1.40,SD=0.67)disagreedsignificantlystrongerthan

laysubjects(M=2.94,SD=1.63)withtheclaimthatthelittlegirlknewthatthecoin

wasgoingtolandheads,F(1,225)=42.52,p<.001,η2=.16.Again,asurprisinglyhighnumberoflaysubjects(40%)agreedwiththisclaim.Theresultspeaksagainstour

hypothesisthatthehighnumberofagreeinglaysubjectsinourfirstexperimentwasdue

tothefactthattheprotagonistofthecasecomestoknowtheoutcomeofhercoinflip.

Wediscussthissurprisingfindingbelow(seeDiscussion).

ForthecasesExamandClearKnowledge1,therewasnosignificantdifference

betweenlaysubjectsandexpertsubjects(p=.73andp=.19,respectively).Interestingly

andagainintensionwiththetextbookconsensus,themajorityofexpertsubjects(68%)

consideredExamasacaseofknowledge.

Page 22: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

22

Moreover,theresultpatternofthoseexpertswhoindicatedthattheyhaveaPhD

versusthoseexpertswhoindicatedthattheirhighestdegreeinphilosophywasanMA

didnotdiffersignificantly,F(4,192)=1.00,p=.40(fortheinteractionofdegree*

cases).Inaddition,wecomparedourexpertsubjectswiththosesubjectswhoholdat

leastanMAinphilosophybutindicatedthattheyhavenocompetenceinepistemology

(N=32,notincludedinpreviousanalyses).Theresponsepatternofthesetwogroups

differedsignificantly,F(4,320)=3.18,p=.01,η2=.04(fortheinteractionofepistemologicalexpertise*cases).Atthelevelofindividualcases,however,the

differencebetweenthesetwogroupsdidnotturnouttobesignificant.

4 Discussion

Whatistheupshotofourexperimentswithrespecttothethreemotivatingideas

explainedabove,i.e.,(1)tocompareexpertwithlayintuitions,(2)tomeasuretheir

qualityagainsttherelevanttextbookconsensus,and(3)tocheckwhetherexpert

intuitionsareinlinewiththetextbookconsensus?

First,thereisindeedasignificantexpert-laydifferenceinthemajorityofthe

testedcases.ThisconcernsthecasesMonitor,Sculpture,andClearNon-Knowledge1in

experiment1,andthecasesDollar,Sculpture,andClearNon-Knowledge2inexperiment

2.Incontrast,wefoundnosignificantexpert-laydifferenceforPainting(experiment1),

Exam(experiment2),andbothinstancesofClearKnowledge1.Inthelattercase,expert-

layagreementmaynotcomeasabigsurprise,butexpert-layagreementonthemore

probingcasesPaintingandExamsuggeststhatthereisnostraightforwardgeneral

patternofexpert-layagreementordisagreement.Overall,however,theexpert-lay

differencesthatwefoundareprimafacieencouragingforproponentsoftheexpertise

defense.

Second,whenthequalityofexpertandlayintuitionsismeasuredagainstthe

relevanttextbookconsensus,theresultsareagainprimafaciefavorableforthe

expertisedefense.Inallcaseswherewefoundasignificantexpert-laydifferencethe

meanexpertratingswereclosertotherelevantconsensusintheepistemological

literature.IncaseofSculpture,forexample,onewouldexpectthatthemeanexpert

ratingissignificantlyclosertothe‘disagree’-endofthescalethanthatoflaypeople,

giventhatSculptureisinspiredbyfake-barncases,whicharewidelyconsideredascases

Page 23: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

23

ofnon-knowledgeintheepistemologicalliterature(seeabove).Andindeed,thatiswhat

wefoundinbothofourexperiments.

Oncloserinspection,however,thedistributionpatternofexpertresponsesover

theratingscaleraisescertaindoubtsabouttheirintuitiveexpertise,inparticularwith

respecttothefake-barn-stylecasesSculptureandDollar.19Inbothcases,wefoundthe

samestrikingpatternofexpertresponses.First,theslightmajorityofexpertratingsfall

intothe‘agree’-halfofthescale.Second,thetwomiddleoptions(‘mildlydisagree’and

‘mildlydisagree’)werenotthefavoriteoptions,indicatingthatmostofourexpert

participantswereprettyconfidentintheirjudgments(seeFigure2foratypical

distributionpatternofexpertjudgmentsaboutthesecases).Thefactthatmostofour

expertparticipantstendedtoclassifythesecasesasinstancesofknowledgeraises

questionsofitsown,whichwillbediscussedbelow.Butevenapartfromthissurprising

finding,thefactthattheexperts’intuitionsaredividedinthewaydescribeddoesnot

reallycountinfavoroftheirintuitiveexpertise,atleastwhenweconsiderthemasa

group.Thus,whenonetakesdistributionpatternsintoaccount,theinitialimpression

thatourexperimentsfavortheexpertisedefensealreadybeginstofade.

Afurtherstrikingresultwasthehighlysignificantexpert-laydifferenceincaseof

ClearNon-Knowledge1,whichwasusedasacontrolcaseinearlierstudies,withthe

explicitpurposeofweedingoutparticipantswhodidnotunderstandtheprobes

correctly(see,e.g.,Swainetal.,2008).Thedegreeofexpert-laydifferencesforthiscase,

bothinmeanratingsandabsolutenumbers,isaboutthestrongestevidenceforthe

superiorityofexpertintuitionsthatonecangetfromourexperiments.Giventhatthe

caseofsomeonewhocorrectlyguessestheoutcomeofarandomcoinflipissuchaclear

non-instanceofknowledge,thehighnumberoflaypeoplewhotendtoascribe

knowledgeinthiscasecallsforanexplanation.

Thefirsthypothesisthatwetestedinexperiment2wasthepresenceofa“success

bias”inlaypeople,i.e.,thetendencytoascribeknowledgetosomeonewholearns,on

independentgrounds,thathertargetbeliefistrue—irrespectiveofhowproblematically

herbeliefwasinitiallyacquired.Inordertosuppressthistendency,weaddedthe

followingsentencetoourfollow-upvignetteClearNon-Knowledge2:‘Butshehas

inadvertentlyflippedthecoinoutofthewindow,andthereforeshecannot—andwill

not—seetheresult.’Sincewefoundthesameexpertlay-differenceasinexperiment1,

19ThankstoShen-yiLiaoandHannesRuschforpressingtheimportanceofdistributionpatterns.

Page 24: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

24

ourhypothesisofa“successbias”inlaypeoplewasclearlydisconfirmed.Thesame

holdsforthehypothesisof“protagonistprojection”inlaypeople,i.e.,thetendencyto

projectoneselfintothepointofviewoftheprotagonist,becauseinClearNon-Knowledge

2theoutcomeofthecoinflipisnotaccessiblefromthepointofviewofthelittlegirl.

Thesecondhypothesis,whichwetestedinanadditionalfollow-upexperiment

withlayparticipants,turnsonasubtledifferencebetweenourversionofthecoinflip

caseandthestandardformulationthatwasusedinearlierstudies.InourvignettesClear

Non-Knowledge1and2,wereferredtotheprotagonistofthecaseas‘alittlegirl’,while

inearlierstudiestheprotagonistwassimplycalled‘Dave’,andonemightspeculatethat

laypeoplearemorewillingtoascribeknowledgetolittlechildrenthantonormalhuman

adults.20Totestthishypothesis,weconfrontedlaypeoplewithsixversionsofthecoin

flipcase,wheretheonlydifferencewasthat—inthefiveadditionalcases—thephrase‘a

littlegirl’wasreplacedwith‘alittleboy’,‘awoman’,‘aman’,‘anoldwoman’,and‘anold

man’,respectively(pronounswereadjustedaccordingly).Wefoundnosignificant

differenceinlayresponsestothosecases,butwecouldagainreplicatethehighlevelof

layagreementforthisclearnon-instanceofknowledge.21

AthirdhypothesistradesonAlvinGoldman’sclaimthattheEnglishword‘know’

isambiguousbetweenaweakandastrongreading(Goldman,1999,2001).Accordingto

Goldman,‘know’intheweaksenseismoreorlesssynonymouswith‘truebelief’,while

‘know’inthestrongsensealsoentailsjustificationorotherepistemicproperties(see

alsoHawthorne,2002).InlightofGoldman’sclaimaboutthemeaningof‘know’,one

mighthypothesizethatasignificantnumberoflaypeopleinterpretoccurrencesof

‘know’inthecoinflipcaseintheweaksenseof‘truebelief’,giventhattheywerenotin

anywaypromptedtofocusonthestrongsenseof‘know’.Epistemologicalexperts,on

theotherhand,aretrainedtointerpret‘know’inthestrongsenseinthecontextof

philosophicalthoughtexperimentsaboutknowledge,andsotheyshouldnotbeinclined

totheweakreadingof‘know’insuchcontexts.Ourfindingsarehighlyconsistentwith

thishypothesis.Moreover,ifoneconsidersthedistributionoflayresponsesinallofour

20ThankstoJonathanWeinbergforthesuggestion.21Thelayparticipantsforthisadditionalexperimentwereselectedinthesamewayasinourtwomainexperiments(seeabove).178laysubjectswereincludedinouranalysis.Themaindifferenceinthedesignoftheexperimentwasthateachparticipantonlyrespondedtoonerandomlyselectedversionofthesixversionsofthecoinflipcase,whichhelpedtopreventordereffects(thankstoShen-yiLiaoforsuggestingthatouroriginalfindingsmightinvolveordereffects).Themeanratingsforthesixcasesdidnotdiffersignificantly,F(5,172)=.41,p=.84,withmeansvaryingbetween2.45and2.92(overall=2.74)andpercentagesofagreementbetween24%and46%(overall=36%).Sotheadditionalexperimentclearlydisconfirmsoursecondhypothesis.

Page 25: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

25

experimentswithcoinflipcases,onefindsthatthereisapeakatthe‘stronglydisagree’-

endofthescale,andanotherpeakaround‘mildlyagree’.Itseemsnaturaltoassumethat

theparticipantsintheformerpeakread‘know’inthestrongsense,whileparticipantsin

thesecondpeakread‘know’intheweaksense,althoughwithsomehesitation(maybe

becausethecoinflipcaseissuchaclearnon-instanceof‘know’inthestrongsense).

Nevertheless,confirmingtheambiguityhypothesiswouldrequireadditional

experimentsthattargettheideaofanambiguitybetweenaweakandastrongsenseof

‘know’moredirectly.Inthemeantime,itseemsadvisabletosuspendtheuseofcoinflip

casesascontrolcasesinexperimentswithlaypeople.

Irrespectiveofwhatthebestexplanationforthestrikingratesoflayagreement

forClearNon-Knowledge1and2andotherversionsofthecoinflipcasemightbe,it

shouldbepointedoutthatallconsideredhypothesesfavorexpertoverlayjudgments

withrespecttosuchcases.

Third,areexpertintuitionsinlinewiththeconsensusintheepistemological

literature?Inexperiment1,meanexpertratingswereinlinewiththerelevantconsensus

forMonitor,andforClearNon-Knowledge1andClearKnowledge1(theresultsforthose

clearcaseswerealsoreplicatedinexperiment2).Withrespecttotheremainingcases,

Painting,Sculpture,Exam,andDollar,ourtwoexperimentssuggest,however,thatthe

intuitionsofexpertepistemologistsarenotinlinewiththeconsensusintheliterature.

EvenifweputPaintingaside,whichtheliteraturewouldclassifyasanunclearcase,we

stillgetthestrikingresultthatthreecasesthattheepistemologicalliteraturewould

regardasnon-instancesofknowledgeareneverthelessclassifiedasknowledgebyour

experts.Whatmightexplainthisstrikingmismatchbetweentheintuitionsofindividual

expertepistemologistsandthecorrespondingdisciplinaryconsensus?

Afirstandsomewhatfriendlysuggestionwouldbethatonlytheintuitionsof

epistemological“super-experts”reallycount,whomightroughlybeunderstoodasthose

philosopherswhopublishpapersonknowledgeinphilosophicaltop-journals—anditis

arguablythose“super-experts”whoshapetherelevantdisciplinaryconsensus.22This

hypothesisistentativelydisconfirmedbythefactthatwefoundnosignificantdifference

betweenvariousgroupsof“first-rate”vs.“second-rate”experts(e.g.,epistemologyas

areaofspecializationvs.areaofcompetence,orPhDvs.MAinphilosophy—seeabove).

So,unlessthedevelopmentofintuitiveexpertiseishighlydiscontinuous,thehypothesis

22ThankstoEddyNahmiasforthissuggestion(inacommentonourpost“ExpertIntuitionsAboutKnowledge”ontheExperimentalPhilosophyblog;cf.Horvath&Wiegmann(2013)).

Page 26: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

26

ofintuitive“super-expertise”inepistemologyisrenderedprimafacieimplausiblebyour

results.Yeteveniftrue,thisrelativelyfriendlyhypothesiswouldstillrequirefar-

reachingmodificationsofouractualphilosophicalpractice,becauseitsuggeststhat

everyoneshoulddefertoareallysmallgroupof“eliteintuiters”whenitcomesto

intuitionsaboutthoughtexperimentsonknowledge.

Asecondandlessfriendlysuggestionmightbethatcontemporaryepistemology

fallssquarelywithinthe“puzzle-solving”paradigmofphilosophy,likemostanalytic

philosophyingeneral,accordingtosomeauthors(cf.Rorty,2007).Andofcourse,the

moredifficulttherelevantpuzzlesare,themoreinterestingtheactivityofpuzzle-

solvingbecomes.Therefore,onemighthypothesizethatepistemologistsareoverly

liberalinacceptingfake-barn-styleorlotterycasesasnon-instancesofknowledge—

despitetheirintuitivetendencytothecontrary—becausethismakesthepuzzleof

analyzingknowledgealotharderandthusalotmoreinterestingtosolve.Itgoes

withoutsayingthatthishypothesis,ifcorrect,wouldsignificantlyunderminethecurrent

practiceofprofessionalepistemology.

Athirdandevenlessfriendlysuggestionmightbethatthedisciplinaryconsensus

inepistemologywithrespectto,e.g.,fake-barnorlotterycasesissimplytheresultof

somekindofsocialconformity.Maybecertainepistemological“opinionleaders”,suchas

AlvinGoldmanincaseoffake-barncases,initiallyclassifytherelevantcasesasnon-

instancesofknowledge.Thebulkofepistemologiststhensimplyfollowtheintuitive

evaluationsofsuchauthorities,forexample,inordertobetakenseriouslyin

professionaldiscussions,ortogettheirpaperspublishedinleadingjournals(cf.Turri,

forthcoming;Weinberg,2007,p.337).

Ourresultsdonotactuallytelluswhichofthesehypotheses,ifany,providesthe

bestexplanationforthemismatchbetweenexpertintuitionsandthedisciplinary

consensusthatwefoundinexperiments1and2.However,noneoftheseexplanations

wouldprovideavindicationforouractualdisciplinarypractice,forbothexplanations

appealtoirrelevantfactorsintheexperimentalrestrictionistsense,thatis,tofactors

thatareirrelevanttothetruthoftherelevantfirst-orderclaimsaboutknowledge.Our

experimentsthereforerevealasurprisingproblemwithexpertintuitionsabout

knowledgethatisdifficulttoexplainwithoutunsettlingtheexpertisedefense.Despite

thefactthatourexperimentsprovidesomeevidencethatfavorstheexpertisedefense,

theyalsogiverisetoachallengingnewproblem—andultimatelyraisemorequestions

thantheyanswer.

Page 27: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

27

5 Conclusion

Inthispaper,wefirstdistinguisheddirectandindirectstrategiesforassessingtheclaim

thatprofessionalphilosophersareintuitiveexpertsforevaluatingphilosophicalthought

experimentcases.Aproblemforindirectstrategiesisthattheparadigmsofempirical

researchonintuitiveexpertiseareveryunlikethought-experimentingphilosophers,

becausetheformer,unlikethelatter,primarilyengageincausalpredictions.Incontrast,

directstrategiesthatarebasedonexperimentaldataaboutphilosophers’intuitionsare

epistemicallylessriskyanddialecticallymoreeffective.Inordertoadvancethedebate

aboutdirectargumentsforassessingtheexpertisedefense,weconductedtwonew

experimentswithexpertepistemologistsandlaypeople.

Inthefirstexperiment,wetestedanumberofunfamiliarthoughtexperiment

casesaboutknowledgewithexpertepistemologistsandlaypeople.Inthemajorityof

thetestedcases,theexperts’intuitionswereindeedsignificantlydifferentfromthoseof

laypeople,andthedifferencewasalwaysinthedirectionthatonewouldexpectonthe

basisoftherelevanttextbookconsensus.However,concerningthefake-barn-style

vignetteSculpturewefoundtwothingsthatchallengetheintuitiveexpertiseofour

epistemologicalexperts:first,onaverage,theytendedtoascribeknowledgeinthiscase,

andsecond,theiroverallresponsepatternexhibitstwoopposingpeaks.Wealsofounda

strikingdifferencebetweenexpertandlayintuitionsconcerningthecoinflipcaseClear

Non-Knowledge1.Asignificantnumberoflaypeople—unliketheexperts—tendedto

ascribeknowledgeinthiscase.

Thepointofoursecondexperimentwastotestandcorroboratethemore

surprisingresultsofourfirstexperiment.Tothisend,wetestedtwofurthernon-

instancesofknowledge:Dollar,anotherfake-barn-stylecase,andExam,acasethatis

inspiredbylotterycases.Onaverage,theepistemologicalexpertsagainascribed

knowledgeinthesecases,andagainwiththesamepolarizeddistributionpattern.

Toexplainthehighrateoflayknowledgeascriptionsinthecoinflipcase,wealso

testedthehypothesisofa“successbias”inlaypeople,whichwasnotconfirmedbyour

secondexperiment.Inanadditionalexperimentwithlaypeople,wetestedthefurther

hypothesisthatlaypeoplemightbemorewillingtoascribeknowledgetolittlechildren

thantoadults,whichwasdisconfirmedaswell.Thehighrateoflayapprovalincoinflip

Page 28: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

28

casesthereforeremainspuzzling.Themostpromisingexplanationmightbeintermsof

anambiguitybetweenaweakandastrongsenseof‘know’.

Ourmosttroublingresultfromtheviewpointoftheexpertisedefenseisthe

strikingmismatchbetweentheintuitionsofourexpertsubjectsandtherelevant

consensusintheepistemologicalliterature.Thisfindingsuggeststhattheremightbe

somethingwrongwithphilosophyasadiscipline,giventhatitapparentlyfailstomap

theintuitionsofitsexpertpractitionersontoadisciplinaryconsensusintherightkindof

way.Friendlyexplanationsofthismismatcharehardtocomeby,andsoour

experimentsindicateaproblemthathasnotbeenacknowledgedsofar—andthat

challengestheexpertisedefenseinunexpectedandtroublesomeways.

Acknowledgments WewouldliketothankJoshuaAlexander,JamesAndow,SteveClark,JensKipper,

Shen-yiLiao,AaronMeskin,JonasNagel,EddyNahmias,JenniferNado,MartinPeterson,HannesRusch,

JoshuaSheperd,JonathanWeinberg,andthreeanonymousreviewersforveryhelpfulcommentsand

discussions.ThanksalsotoouraudiencesatthelectureseriesGedankenexperimente—Kannmanausdem

LehnstuhldieWelterforschen?atUniversitätZürichinMay2014,theX-PhiWorkshopViennaat

UniversitätWieninJune2014,theconferenceMöglichkeitenundGrenzenderExperimentellenPhilosophie

atPhilippsUniversitätMarburginJune2014,andtheconferenceInvestigatingtheNatureandour

UnderstandingofCausality,Morality,Language,Mind,andAesthetics—theinauguralmeetingofthe

ExperimentalPhilosophyGroupGermany—atRuhr-UniversitätBochuminNovember2015.

References

Alexander,J.(2012).ExperimentalPhilosophy:AnIntroduction.Cambridge:PolityPress.

Alexander,J.,Mallon,R.,&Weinberg,J.(2009).AccentuatetheNegative.Reviewof

PhilosophyandPsychology,1(2),297–314.

Alexander,J.,&Weinberg,J.(2007).AnalyticEpistemologyandExperimental

Philosophy.PhilosophyCompass,2,56–80.

Andow,J.(2015).ExpectingMoralPhilosopherstobeReliable.Dialectica,69(2),205–

220.

Armor,D.A.(1998).TheIllusionofObjectivity:ABiasinthePerceptionofFreedomfrom

Bias.UCLA,LosAngeles.

Baron,J.,&Hershey,J.C.(1988).OutcomeBiasinDecisionEvaluation.Journalof

PersonalityandSocialPsychology,54(4),569–579.

Page 29: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

29

Bengson,J.(2013).ExperimentalAttacksonIntuitionsandAnswers.Philosophyand

PhenomenologicalResearch,86(3),495–532.

Bengson,J.(2014).HowPhilosophersUseIntuitionand“intuition.”PhilosophicalStudies,

171(3),555–576.

Boghossian,P.(2014).PhilosophyWithoutIntuitions?AReplytoCappelen.Analytic

Philosophy,55(4),368–381.

Brogaard,B.(2014).IntuitionsasIntellectualSeemings.AnalyticPhilosophy,55(4),382–

393.

Buckwalter,W.(2014).IntuitionFail:PhilosophicalActivityandtheLimitsofExpertise.

PhilosophyandPhenomenologicalResearch,n/a–n/a.

http://doi.org/10.1111/phpr.12147

Cappelen,H.(2012).PhilosophyWithoutIntuitions.Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress.

Cappelen,H.(2014).X-PhiWithoutIntuitions?InA.R.Booth&D.P.Rowbottom(Eds.),

Intuitions(pp.269–286).Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress.

Carter,J.A.,Peterson,M.,&Bezooijen,B.van.(2015).NotKnowingaCatisaCat:

AnalyticityandKnowledgeAscriptions.ReviewofPhilosophyandPsychology,1–

18.http://doi.org/10.1007/s13164-015-0279-7

Carter,J.A.,Pritchard,D.,&Sheperd,J.(ms).Knowledge-How,Understanding-Whyand

EpistemicLuck:AnExperimentalStudy.

Chalmers,D.(2014).IntuitionsinPhilosophy:AMinimalDefense.PhilosophicalStudies,

171(3),535–544.

Chi,M.(1978).KnowledgeStructuresandMemoryDevelopment.InR.Siegler(Ed.),

Children’sThinking:WhatDevelops?(pp.73–96).Hillsdale,NJ,England:Lawrence

ErlbaumAssociates,Inc.

Clarke,S.(2013).IntuitionsasEvidence,PhilosophicalExpertiseandtheDevelopmental

Challenge.PhilosophicalPapers,42(2),175–207.

Clark,M.(1963).KnowledgeandGrounds:ACommentonMr.Gettier’sPaper.Analysis,

24(2),46–48.

Cokely,E.,&Feltz,A.(2009).AdaptiveVariationinJudgmentandPhilosophical

Intuition.ConsciousnessandCognition,18(1),356–358.

Colaço,D.,Buckwalter,W.,Stich,S.,&Machery,E.(2014).EpistemicIntuitionsinFake-

BarnThoughtExperiments.Episteme,11(02),199–212.

Crandall,B.,&Getchell-Reiter,K.(1993).CriticalDecisionMethod:ATechniquefor

ElicitingConcreteAssessmentIndicatorsfromtheIntuitionofNICUNurses.

Page 30: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

30

AdvancesinNursingScience,16(1),42–51.

DeCruz,H.(2015).WherePhilosophicalIntuitionsComeFrom.AustralasianJournalof

Philosophy,93(2),233–249.

DeRose,K.(1996).Knowledge,AssertionandLotteries.AustralasianJournalof

Philosophy,74(4),568–580.

Deutsch,M.(2009).ExperimentalPhilosophyandtheTheoryofReference.Mind&

Language,24(4),445–466.

Deutsch,M.(2010).Intuitions,Counter-Examples,andExperimentalPhilosophy.Review

ofPhilosophyandPsychology,1(3),447–460.

Deutsch,M.(2015).TheMythoftheIntuitive:ExperimentalPhilosophyandPhilosophical

Method.Cambridge,Mass.:MITPress.

Devitt,M.(2006).IgnoranceofLanguage.Oxford:ClarendonPress.

Devitt,M.(2011).ExperimentalSemantics.PhilosophyandPhenomenologicalResearch,

82(2),418–435.

EngelJr.,M.(2015).EpistemicLuck.InJ.Fieser&B.Dowden(Eds.),Internet

EncyclopediaofPhilosophy.Retrievedfromhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/epi-luck/

Ericsson,K.A.,&Lehmann,A.C.(1996).ExpertandExceptionalPerformance:Evidence

ofMaximalAdaptationtoTaskConstraints.AnnualReviewofPsychology,47(1),

273–305.

Feltz,A.,&Cokely,E.(2009).DoJudgmentsAboutFreedomandResponsibilityDepend

onWhoYouAre?PersonalityDifferencesinIntuitionsAboutCompatibilismand

Incompatibilism.ConsciousnessandCognition,18(1),342–350.

Feltz,A.,&Cokely,E.(2012).ThePhilosophicalPersonalityArgument.Philosophical

Studies,161(2),227–246.

Gendler,T.S.,&Hawthorne,J.(2005).TheRealGuidetoFakeBarns:ACatalogueofGifts

forYourEpistemicEnemies.PhilosophicalStudies,124(3),331–352.

Gettier,E.(1963).IsJustifiedTrueBeliefKnowledge?Analysis,23(6),121–123.

Glenberg,A.M.,&Epstein,W.(1987).InexpertCalibrationofComprehension.Memory&

Cognition,15(1),84–93.

Gobet,F.,&Simon,H.A.(1996).RecallofRapidlyPresentedRandomChessPositionsIsa

FunctionofSkill.PsychonomicBulletin&Review,3(2),159–163.

Goldman,A.(1967).ACausalTheoryofKnowing.TheJournalofPhilosophy,64(12),357–

372.

Goldman,A.(1976).DiscriminationandPerceptualKnowledge.TheJournalof

Page 31: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

31

Philosophy,73(20),771–791.

Goldman,A.(1999).KnowledgeinaSocialWorld.Oxford:ClarendonPress.

Goldman,A.(2001).SocialRoutestoBeliefandKnowledge.TheMonist,84(3),346–367.

Grundmann,T.(2010).SomeHopeforIntuitions.AReplytoWeinberg.Philosophical

Psychology,23(4),481–509.

Hales,S.(2006).RelativismandtheFoundationsofPhilosophy.Cambridge,Mass.:MIT

Press.

Harman,G.(1968).Knowledge,Inference,andExplanation.AmericanPhilosophical

Quarterly,5(3),164–173.

Harman,G.(1973).Thought.Princeton,N.J.:PrincetonUniversityPress.

Hawthorne,J.(2002).DeeplyContingentAPrioriKnowledge.Philosophyand

PhenomenologicalResearch,65(2),247–269.

Hawthorne,J.(2004).KnowledgeandLotteries.Oxford:ClarendonPress.

Heathcote,A.(2006).TruthmakingandtheGettierProblem.InS.Hetherington(Ed.),

AspectsofKnowing:EpistemologicalEssays(pp.152–167).Amsterdam:Elsevier.

Hetherington,S.(1999).KnowingFailably.TheJournalofPhilosophy,96(11),565–587.

Hetherington,S.(2015).GettierProblems.InJ.Fieser&B.Dowden(Eds.),Internet

EncyclopediaofPhilosophy.Retrievedfromhttp://www.iep.utm.edu/gettier/

Hitchcock,C.,&Knobe,J.(2009).CauseandNorm.JournalofPhilosophy,106,587–612.

Hofmann,F.(2010).Intuitions,Concepts,andImagination.PhilosophicalPsychology,

23(4),529–546.

Holton,R.(1997).SomeTellingExamples:AReplytoTsohatzidis.JournalofPragmatics,

28(5),625–628.

Horvath,J.(2010).How(Not)toReacttoExperimentalPhilosophy.Philosophical

Psychology,23(4),447–480.

Horvath,J.,&Wiegmann,A.(2013).ExpertIntuitionsAboutKnowledge.Retrievedfrom

http://philosophycommons.typepad.com/xphi/2013/08/expert-intuitions-

about-knowledge.html

Ichikawa,J.J.(2014).WhoNeedsIntuitions?TwoExperimentalistCritiques.InA.R.

Booth&D.P.Rowbottom(Eds.),Intuitions(pp.232–255).Oxford:Oxford

UniversityPress.

Ichikawa,J.J.,&Steup,M.(2014).TheAnalysisofKnowledge.InE.N.Zalta(Ed.),The

StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy(Spring2014).Retrievedfrom

http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/knowledge-analysis/

Page 32: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

32

Kauppinen,A.(2007).TheRiseandFallofExperimentalPhilosophy.Philosophical

Explorations,10(2),95–118.

Kipper,J.(2010).PhilosophersandGrammarians.PhilosophicalPsychology,23(4),511–

527.

Klein,G.,Calderwood,R.,&Clinton-Cirocco,A.(1986).RapidDecisionMakingontheFire

Ground.ProceedingsoftheHumanFactorsandErgonomicsSocietyAnnual

Meeting,30(6),576–580.

Klein,P.(1981).Certainty:ARefutationofScepticism.Minneapolis:Universityof

MinnesotaPress.

Lehrer,K.(1965).Knowledge,Truth,andEvidence.Analysis,25(5),168–75.

Lehrer,K.(1974).Knowledge.Oxford:ClarendonPress.

Lehrer,K.,&Paxson,T.(1969).Knowledge:UndefeatedJustifiedTrueBelief.Journalof

Philosophy,66(8),225–237.

Liao,S.M.,Wiegmann,A.,Alexander,J.,&Vong,G.(2012).PuttingtheTrolleyinOrder:

ExperimentalPhilosophyandtheLoopCase.PhilosophicalPsychology,25(5),

661–671.

Littlejohn,C.(2012).JustificationandtheTruth-Connection.Cambridge:Cambridge

UniversityPress.

Ludwig,K.(2007).TheEpistemologyofThoughtExperiments:FirstPersonversusThird

PersonApproaches.MidwestStudiesInPhilosophy,31(1),128–159.

Ludwig,K.(2010).IntuitionsandRelativity.PhilosophicalPsychology,23(4),427–445.

Lycan,W.(1977).EvidenceOneDoesNotPossess.AustralasianJournalofPhilosophy,

55(2),114–126.

Lycan,W.(2006).OntheGettierProblemproblem.InS.Hetherington(Ed.),

EpistemologyFutures(pp.148–168).Oxford:ClarendonPress.

Machery,E.(2012).ExpertiseandIntuitionsAboutReference.Theoria,27(1),37–54.

Machery,E.,Mallon,R.,Nichols,S.,&Stich,S.(2004).Semantics,Cross-CulturalStyle.

Cognition,92,1–12.

Machery,E.,Stich,S.,Rose,D.,Chatterjee,A.,Karasawa,K.,Struchiner,N.,Sirker,S.,Usui,

N.,&Hashimoto,T.(2015).GettierAcrossCultures.Noûs,n/a–n/a.

http://doi.org/10.1111/nous.12110

Mizrahi,M.(2015).ThreeArgumentsAgainsttheExpertiseDefense.Metaphilosophy,

46(1),52–64.

Nado,J.(2014).PhilosophicalExpertise.PhilosophyCompass,9(9),631–641.

Page 33: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

33

Nado,J.(2015a).PhilosophicalExpertiseandScientificExpertise.Philosophical

Psychology,28(7),1026–1044.

Nado,J.(2015b).TheIntuitionDeniers.PhilosophicalStudies,1–20.

http://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-015-0519-9

Nagel,J.(2012).IntuitionsandExperiments:ADefenseoftheCaseMethodin

Epistemology.PhilosophyandPhenomenologicalResearch,85(3),495–527.

Nagel,J.,Mar,R.,&SanJuan,V.(2013).AuthenticGettiercases:AreplytoStarmansand

Friedman.Cognition,129(3),666–669.

Nagel,J.,SanJuan,V.,&Mar,R.A.(2013).LayDenialofKnowledgeforJustifiedTrue

Beliefs.Cognition,129(3),652–661.

Nichols,S.,&Knobe,J.(2007).MoralResponsibilityandDeterminism:TheCognitive

ScienceofFolkIntuitions.Noûs,41(4),663–685.

Nichols,S.,Stich,S.,&Weinberg,J.(2003).Metaskepticism:MeditationsinEthno-

Epistemology.InS.Luper(Ed.),TheSkeptics(pp.227–247).Aldershot:Ashgate.

Pritchard,D.(2005).EpistemicLuck.Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress.

Pronin,E.(2007).PerceptionandMisperceptionofBiasinHumanJudgment.Trendsin

CognitiveSciences,11(1),37–43.

Pronin,E.,Gilovich,T.,&Ross,L.(2004).ObjectivityintheEyeoftheBeholder:

DivergentPerceptionsofBiasinSelfVersusOthers.PsychologicalReview,111(3),

781–799.

Pust,J.(2012).Intuition.InE.N.Zalta(Ed.),TheStanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy

(Winter2012).Retrievedfrom

http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/intuition/

Rini,R.A.(2015).HowNottoTestforPhilosophicalExpertise.Synthese,192(2),431–

452.

Rorty,R.(2007).AnalyticandTransformativePhilosophy.AnalysisandExistence,5.

Schulz,E.,Cokely,E.,&Feltz,A.(2011).PersistentBiasinExpertJudgmentsAboutFree

WillandMoralResponsibility:ATestoftheExpertiseDefense.Consciousnessand

Cognition,20(4),1722–1731.

Schwitzgebel,E.,&Cushman,F.(2012).ExpertiseinMoralReasoning?OrderEffectson

MoralJudgmentinProfessionalPhilosophersandNon-Philosophers.Mind&

Language,27(2),135–153.

Schwitzgebel,E.,&Cushman,F.(2015).Philosophers’BiasedJudgmentsPersistDespite

Training,ExpertiseandReflection.Cognition,141,127–137.

Page 34: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

34

Seyedsayamdost,H.(2015).OnNormativityandEpistemicIntuitions:Failureof

Replication.Episteme,12(01),95–116.

Shope,R.(2002).ConditionsandAnalysesofKnowledge.InP.Moser(Ed.),TheOxford

HandbookofEpistemology(pp.25–71).Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress.

Shope,R.(2004).TheAnalysisofKnowing.InI.Niiniluoto,M.Sintonen,&J.Wolenski

(Eds.),HandbookofEpistemology(pp.283–329).Dordrecht:KluwerAcademic

Publishers.

Sosa,E.(2007).ExperimentalPhilosophyandPhilosophicalIntuition.Philosophical

Studies,132(1),99–107.

Sosa,E.(2009).ADefenseoftheUseofIntuitionsinPhilosophy.InM.Bishop&D.

Murphy(Eds.),StichandhisCritics(pp.101–112).Oxford:Blackwell.

Sosa,E.(2010).IntuitionsandMeaningDivergence.PhilosophicalPsychology,23(4),

419–426.

Steup,M.(2014).Epistemology.InE.N.Zalta(Ed.),TheStanfordEncyclopediaof

Philosophy(Spring2014).Retrievedfrom

http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/epistemology/

Sutton,J.(2005).StickToWhatYouKnow.Noûs,39(3),359–396.

Swain,S.,Alexander,J.,&Weinberg,J.(2008).TheInstabilityofPhilosophicalIntuitions:

RunningHotandColdonTruetemp.PhilosophyandPhenomenologicalResearch,

76(1),138–155.

Sytsma,J.,&Machery,E.(2010).TwoConceptionsofSubjectiveExperience.

PhilosophicalStudies,151(2),299–327.

Tobia,K.,Buckwalter,W.,&Stich,S.(2013).MoralIntuitions:ArePhilosophersExperts?

PhilosophicalPsychology,26(5),629–638.

Tobia,K.,Chapman,G.,&Stich,S.(2013).CleanlinessisNexttoMorality,Evenfor

Philosophers.JournalofConsciousnessStudies,20(11-12),195–204.

Turri,J.(forthcoming).KnowledgeJudgmentsin“Gettier”Cases.InJ.Sytsma&W.

Buckwalter(Eds.),ACompaniontoExperimentalPhilosophy.Malden,MA:

Blackwell.

Turri,J.(2013).AConspicuousArt:PuttingGettiertotheTest.Philosophers’Imprint,

13(10),1–16.

Unger,P.(1968).AnAnalysisofFactualKnowledge.TheJournalofPhilosophy,65(6),

157–170.

Vaesen,K.,Peterson,M.,&VanBezooijen,B.(2013).TheReliabilityofArmchair

Page 35: Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge · 1 Intuitive Expertise and Intuitions About Knowledge Joachim Horvath & Alex Wiegmann December 30, 2015 Forthcoming in Philosophical

35

Intuitions.Metaphilosophy,44(5),559–578.

Vicente,K.J.,&Wang,J.H.(1998).Anecologicaltheoryofexpertiseeffectsinmemory

recall.PsychologicalReview,105(1),33–57.

Weinberg,J.(2007).HowtoChallengeIntuitionsEmpiricallyWithoutRisking

Skepticism.MidwestStudiesInPhilosophy,31(1),318–343.

Weinberg,J.(2014).CappelenBetweenRockandaHardPlace.PhilosophicalStudies,

171(3),545–553.

Weinberg,J.,&Alexander,J.(2014).TheChallengeofStickingwithIntuitionsthrough

ThickandThin.InA.R.Booth&D.P.Rowbottom(Eds.),Intuitions(pp.187–212).

OxfordUniversityPress.

Weinberg,J.,Alexander,J.,Gonnerman,C.,&Reuter,S.(2012).ExperimentalPhilosophy:

RestrictionismandReflection.TheMonist,95(2),201–222.

Weinberg,J.,Gonnerman,C.,Buckner,C.,&Alexander,J.(2010).ArePhilosophersExpert

Intuiters?PhilosophicalPsychology,23(3),331–355.

Weinberg,J.,Nichols,S.,&Stich,S.(2001).NormativityandEpistemicIntuitions.

PhilosophicalTopics,29(1/2),429–460.

Wiegmann,A.,&Waldmann,M.R.(2014).TransferEffectsBetweenMoralDilemmas:A

CausalModelTheory.Cognition,131(1),28–43.

Williamson,T.(2000).KnowledgeandItsLimits.Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress.

Williamson,T.(2004).Philosophical“Intuitions”andScepticismaboutJudgement.

Dialectica,58(1),109–153.

Williamson,T.(2005).ArmchairPhilosophy,MetaphysicalModalityandCounterfactual

Thinking.ProceedingsoftheAristotelianSociety,105(1),1–23.

Williamson,T.(2007).ThePhilosophyofPhilosophy.Malden,Mass.:Blackwell.

Williamson,T.(2011).PhilosophicalExpertiseandtheBurdenofProof.Metaphilosophy,

42(3),215–229.

Wright,J.C.(2010).OnIntuitionalStability:TheClear,theStrong,andtheParadigmatic.

Cognition,115(3),491–503.