In Search of the Good Society: The Work of Daniel Callahan || Escaping from Legalism: Is It...

2
Hastings Center Report, November-December 1996 Escaping from Legalism: Is It Possible? T he law is America’s greatest strength, but sometimes also its greatest curse, when it gets in the vicinity of ethics. No myth is so hardy as the notion that “you can’t legislate morality,” which of course we do all the time. But that myth has been well noted. Less appreciated, however, is the conceit that when the law decides to stand aside from moraljudgment and to leave matters to personal choice, it has not made a moral judgment. Our country properly rejected pro-choice arguments in favor of racial segregation, recognizing the tacit public moral approval they gave to segregation. Yet it seems we still try to per- suade ourselves that there is no such oflicial moral approbation in leaving matters of sex, or end4life choices, including physician-assisted suicide, up to individuals. The irony here is that, in a country so devoted to the law, so quick to legislate on everything in sight, a failure to legdate-or a removal of an old prohibition from the b o o k a n n o t fail to send a moral message. It was once said of some European countries that if the law remained silent on some- thing, it was probably morally forbidden. It is just the opposite here: if the law remains silent, that means an act is probably morally acceptable. It is hardly any wonder, for example, that in the cam- paign against smoking the only way to demonstrate moral seriousness is legally to ban it, anywhere and everywhere that is politicallyfeasible. For public pur- poses, true ethical weight rests on the majesty of the law. None of this would matter so much if- I hy pothesize-the greatest obstacle to outright and se- rious public moral debate in thii country were not the hovering presence of the law. It is as if the public is presented with a stark choice: if you really believe something is morally important, take it to court or pass a law about i t But if you believe the courts should stay out of it, or that there should not be a law, then shut up and leave the matter to private choice. And when we say “private choice” in this country, we characteristically mean one thing: that we ought not to pass moral judgment on each other’s choices, much less issue public moral con- demnations of the practices of different groups, a It is this dilemma, I suspect, that has made it so hard to have any serious debate about the moral patent offense against pluralism. uses of freedom, the difference between responsible and irresponsible moral choices. I have met few se- rious feminists who would deny in private that there can, and are, some wrong and irresponsible abor- tion decisions. I have met practically none, however, who are willing to admit that publicly, or to sanction my moral discourse at all for fear of providing am- munition to those who would like to see Roe v. Wade overturned. As much as I deplore elevating expedi- ency over principle, I have to admit it’s a smart tac- tic. The danger in our country of opening moral discussion about private matters is that someone or other is likely to have the idea that “there ought to be a law.” Meanwhile, unfortunately, because we do let the law legislate considerable morality, or use moral ar- guments to overcome existing bans, a great deal of the work of ethics ends up being done in court- rooms and enshrined in legal decisions. The Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals has recently seen fit to judge what counts as human dignity, as ethical an issue as there can be. I was surprised to learn that, should my life end in the dependent, weak, and messy condition of a baby, I will have lost my dignity. I looked at a newborn baby recently-unable to talk, stinking of feces, not a thought in her head, utterly dependent-and just failed altogether to note the absence of dignity. It is hard, in fact, to thiink of a more superficial moral theory of human dignity than the one voiced in the Ninth Circuit’s decision. Yet by virtue of its pronouncement in a court decision that theory is likely to have far greater public weight than anythmg put forward by the field of ethics. The papers report important court decisions in great detail, our judg- ments get media sound bites. (I assume, for the sake of argument, that ethics as a field can do better, though it has never been immune from moral tone deafness.) Legalism may, then, be defined as the translation of moral problems into legal problems; the inhibi- tion of moral debate for fear that it will be so trans- lated; and the elevation of the moral judgments of courts as the moral standards of the land. Are the courts and lawyers to blame for this state of affairs? I would be happy to blame them-many of my best friends are not judges or lawyers-but I suspect that there has come to be some enormous moral vac- uum in this country, which for lack of better insti- 34

Transcript of In Search of the Good Society: The Work of Daniel Callahan || Escaping from Legalism: Is It...

Hastings Center Report, November-December 1996

Escaping from Legalism: Is It Possible?

T he law is America’s greatest strength, but sometimes also its greatest curse, when it gets in the vicinity of ethics. No myth is so hardy as the notion that “you can’t legislate morality,” which of course we do

all the time. But that myth has been well noted. Less appreciated, however, is the conceit that when the law decides to stand aside from moral judgment and to leave matters to personal choice, it has not made a moral judgment. Our country properly rejected pro-choice arguments in favor of racial segregation, recognizing the tacit public moral approval they gave to segregation. Yet it seems we still try to per- suade ourselves that there is no such oflicial moral approbation in leaving matters of sex, or end4life choices, including physician-assisted suicide, up to individuals.

The irony here is that, in a country so devoted to the law, so quick to legislate on everything in sight, a failure to legdate-or a removal of an old prohibition from the b o o k a n n o t fail to send a moral message. It was once said of some European countries that if the law remained silent on some- thing, it was probably morally forbidden. It is just the opposite here: if the law remains silent, that means an act is probably morally acceptable. It is hardly any wonder, for example, that in the cam- paign against smoking the only way to demonstrate moral seriousness is legally to ban it, anywhere and everywhere that is politically feasible. For public pur- poses, true ethical weight rests on the majesty of the law.

None of this would matter so much if- I hy pothesize-the greatest obstacle to outright and se- rious public moral debate in thii country were not the hovering presence of the law. It is as if the public is presented with a stark choice: if you really believe something is morally important, take it to court or pass a law about i t But if you believe the courts should stay out of it, or that there should not be a law, then shut up and leave the matter to private choice. And when we say “private choice” in this country, we characteristically mean one thing: that we ought not to pass moral judgment on each other’s choices, much less issue public moral con- demnations of the practices of different groups, a

It is this dilemma, I suspect, that has made it so hard to have any serious debate about the moral

’ patent offense against pluralism.

uses of freedom, the difference between responsible and irresponsible moral choices. I have met few se- rious feminists who would deny in private that there can, and are, some wrong and irresponsible abor- tion decisions. I have met practically none, however, who are willing to admit that publicly, or to sanction m y moral discourse at all for fear of providing am- munition to those who would like to see Roe v. Wade overturned. As much as I deplore elevating expedi- ency over principle, I have to admit it’s a smart tac- tic. The danger in our country of opening moral discussion about private matters is that someone or other is likely to have the idea that “there ought to be a law.”

Meanwhile, unfortunately, because we do let the law legislate considerable morality, or use moral ar- guments to overcome existing bans, a great deal of the work of ethics ends up being done in court- rooms and enshrined in legal decisions. The Ninth Circuit Court of Appeals has recently seen fit to judge what counts as human dignity, as ethical an issue as there can be. I was surprised to learn that, should my life end in the dependent, weak, and messy condition of a baby, I will have lost my dignity. I looked at a newborn baby recently-unable to talk, stinking of feces, not a thought in her head, utterly dependent-and just failed altogether to note the absence of dignity.

It is hard, in fact, to thiink of a more superficial moral theory of human dignity than the one voiced in the Ninth Circuit’s decision. Yet by virtue of its pronouncement in a court decision that theory is likely to have far greater public weight than anythmg put forward by the field of ethics. The papers report important court decisions in great detail, our judg- ments get media sound bites. (I assume, for the sake of argument, that ethics as a field can do better, though it has never been immune from moral tone deafness.)

Legalism may, then, be defined as the translation of moral problems into legal problems; the inhibi- tion of moral debate for fear that it will be so trans- lated; and the elevation of the moral judgments of courts as the moral standards of the land. Are the courts and lawyers to blame for this state of affairs? I would be happy to blame them-many of my best friends are not judges or lawyers-but I suspect that there has come to be some enormous moral vac- uum in this country, which for lack of better insti-

34

Hastings Center Report, November-December 1996

tutional candidates has been left to the law to fa. The churches are either too sectarian or too morally bland, the universities too caught up in profession- alism or culture wars, the journals of opinion tiresomely focussed on the religious right (the left) or assaulting politically correct liberals (the right), and political life reduced during this campaign year to nasty negative attacks on anything and everyone.

That leaves the law. It is relatively free of scandal, still generally respected, national and relatively uni- form in its scope, and ready to take on ethics if that is what gets served up to it for the making of deci- sions. It may be the best institution we have, but it is a poor substitute for moral consensus and public debate on ethics. w

Alexander Morgan Capron

Morality and the State, caw and Legalism

aniel Callahan’s essay returns to famil- iar themes, both hi own and those D with even older roots: the extraordi-

nary role of law in American life, and the resulting curse of legalism. As always, he has with great econ- omy raised a host of issues. Yet, however acute his observations and cogent his claims, the example that lies at the heart of his argument does not in my view support the generalization he draws from it, which leads me to less dire conclusions about the law’s relationship to bioethics. His first point echoes one made more than 160

years ago by Alexis de Tocqueville, who famously observed that “Scarcely any political question arises in the United States that is not resolved, sooner or later, into a judicial question. Hence all parties are obliged to borrow, in their daily controversies, the ideas, and even the language, peculiar to judicial proceedings.”’ It is worth remembering, however, that Tocqueville did not decry this resuls indeed, he saw the civil jury as a unifying and even civilizing force in the raw, new Republic.

As a counterweight to the centrality of law, Cal- lahan notes the myth that “you can’t legislate m- rality,” which he believes has pronounced negative consequence. To confirm that it is a myth-whether the word “legislate” is taken literally or used more broadly to mean any form of lawmaking by the state-one need look no further than modernday Iran or, closer to home, puritan New England. To some extent, all societies attempt to direct behavior into approved channels by criminalizing certain con- duct. In so doing, the law is not merely enforcing

morality but .einficjng it, and society’s success on the first score is heavily dependent on the second, that is, on whether a broad consensus is achieved on the underlying moral view. When wide agree- ment exists, the law is at once less visible and more powerful. Less visible because in the Peaceable King- dom, the lamb can safely lie down with the lion: there is less occasion to enforce laws that reflect b e liefs deeply ingrained in virtually the entire popula- tion. But also more powerful, both because when it acts for the moral consensus the law has strong allies (such as church, school, and family) in its role as teacher and because the existence of the broad con- sensus makes credible the implicit threat to employ the state’s authority by legislating against unaccept- able behavior and enforcing the legislation. Agam, in Tocqude’s words, “Laws are always unstable un- less they are founded upon the custom of a nation: customs are the only durable and resisting power in a people.”

But the real issue here is normative, not descrip tive: Is it right to legislate morality? Callahan argues that when we answer that question in the negative, we implicitly declare the conduct in question to be acceptable, to be beyond the scope of interference or even critical commentary. It seems to me that he has collapsed two separate ideas here and over- looked important features of liberal societies and especially of the one framed by our Constitution.

Take Grimold u Connecticut, the 1965 decision in which the Supreme Court overturned a state statute banning the use of contraceptives? In Callahan’s view the Court thereby encouraged or at least en- dorsed the use of contraceptives; taking it one step further, Justice Douglas was attacking a vestige of Puritan morality that used the fear of pregnancy to cool the ardor of unmarried couples contemplating sexual intercourse. Now, there is no question that the elimination over the following decade of a wide range of laws governing reproduction-which of course extended to unmarried persons as well as married couple+played a role in what was dubbed the “sexual revolution.” But the change in mores preceded the striking down of contraception and abortion statutes. Indeed, so little respected were some of the laws that the s t o r y is told of Justice Douglas (who had once taught at Yale Law School) asking counsel for the Planned Parenthood League of Connecticut, after the formal arguments had fm- ished in Grimo4 whether it was stil l possible to buy condoms under the counter at the drug store across the street from the Yale campus.

Thus, it would seem fairer to say that the law got out of the way of morality on this question. The moral issue-rather than having been decreed for unmarried couples by the Supreme Court-coinci- dentally was being resolved in favor of a more re- laxed view toward their engaging in sexual activity as well as toward married couples controlling the timing and size of their families. The development of “the pill” and related pharmacologic means of

35