Hanbali Theology in the Oxford Handbook

download Hanbali Theology in the Oxford Handbook

of 13

Transcript of Hanbali Theology in the Oxford Handbook

  • 7/26/2019 Hanbali Theology in the Oxford Handbook

    1/13

    CHAPTER

    3 5

    HANBALI THEOLOGY

    JON HOOVER

    T H E

    modern study of Han.bali theology was initially plagued by the problem of viewing

    Hanbalism through the eyes of its Ash`arite opponents. I. Goldziher (d. 1921) and 0. B.

    Macdonald (d. 1943) labelled the Hanbalis 'reactionary' and bemoaned the harm that

    they had done to the cause of a conciliatory Ash`arite orthodoxy.1 he work of H. Laoust

    (d. 1983) and G. Makdisi (d. 2002) turned the tide of scholarship t ,

    ward closer exami-

    nation of Hanbali texts on their own terms and deeper understai ding of Hanbalism

    in its historical context. Makdisi in particular argued that Hanbali,in had a dispropor-

    tionate impact on the development of Islamic theology because it iv; the only Sunni

    school to maintain a consistently traditionalist theological voice. kn. Makdisi, the

    iaribalis were the 'spearhead' of a wider traditionalist movemen:.

    in,...dieval Islam

    :rgainst the rationalism of Mu`tazili and Ash`arite

    Kalam (Makdisi 1962-3; -)81). Aspects

    of Makdisi's narrative require modification, especially as some leading Hanbalis of the

    fifth/eleventh and sixth/twelfth centuries were more rationalist than earlier' thought, but

    the main thrust of his argument still stands. It may be added that Hanbali theology has

    also had a disproportionate impact on modern Islamic theology. "fhe WAhhabi move-

    ment in Arabia and contemporary Salatism have appropriated and spic.id. the iwology

    of the eighth/fourteenth-century scholar Ibn Taymiyya far beyon,' the conli9es of the

    modern Hanbali school of law. This chapter begins with the formation

    early devel-

    opment of Hanbalism in order to clarify Makdisi's claim, and it cor

    E .ty stirveyitlg

    key F,Ianbalt figures from Ahmad b. .Hankal in the third/ninth cen wry

    to lho `Abd

    Wahhab in the twelfth/eighteenth and giving extended attention to the unique theology

    of Ibn Taymiyya.

    I THE FORMATION OF HANBALISM

    The Hanbali law school originated in the 'Abbasid capital Baghtdici i, the late ninth

    and early tenth centuries

    CE as the most rigorous heir of the trade onalist movement

  • 7/26/2019 Hanbali Theology in the Oxford Handbook

    2/13

    626

    'JON HOOVER

    _

    " ., L o

    627

    that had emerged nearly two centuries carlier. The triditionaiists 1i:inured the collec-

    tion and study of

    ljadith,

    and they sought to ground Islamic Ectici Ind 1iri.ctice solely

    in the Quran and

    hadith

    reports from the Prophet Mulaamin.ii his Ciimpanions, and

    their Successors. Opposite the traditionalists were the more torninant proponents of

    ray

    (common sense' or 'rational discretion'). Advocates of ra r, iicd

    degree on

    Qur'an and tladith, but they also located religious authority in existing toslim prac-

    tice, general notions of upright conduct from the past, and the corr,iA red opinion of

    prominent scholars of the day. Traditionalists and proponents of ra 'y came into con-

    flict by the late second/eighth century, and, in response to traditionalist pressure, the

    advocates of

    ray

    began adjusting their jurisprudence toward traditionalist positions

    and grounding it in the precedents of an eponymous founder and

    hadith

    reports from

    the Prophet to a far greater extent. The Hanafi law school emerged through the course

    of the third/ninth and fourth/tenth centuries by vesting authority in a body of jurispru-

    dence ascribed to its eponym Abil Hanifa (d. 150/767) and in turn linking these rulings

    to Prophetic

    hadith.

    The notion that law should be based on

    hadith

    from the Prophet,

    but not

    hadith

    from the Prophet's Companions and Successors, was argued by al-Shafil

    (d. 204/820), the eponym of the Shafil law school, and he worked to interpret the Qur'an

    and

    the ljadith

    so that it correlated with received legal practice. Al-Shafil's position may

    be called 'semi-rationalist' because he made more room for reasoning by analogy

    (qiyas)

    than did the pure traditionalists. Be also favoured a ruling derived by analogy from a

    Prophetic

    hadith

    over a report from a Companion or Successor, and, in this, al-Shafi'l

    Was

    at odds with Abmad b. Hanbal (d. 241/855 ) (Melchert 1997; Fiallaq 2009: 36-71).

    Ahnnad was the most prominent traditionalist of the third/ninth century and the

    eponym of the Hanbali school. He gave priority to health from the Companions

    and Successors over analogy, and he also sought to prevent people from recording

    his opinions because, in his view, Islamic doctrine and law should be based in the

    revealed sources, not a later scholar like himself. Such a rigorist methodology proved

    untenable in the long run, and, in a shift away from pure traditionalism, Ab5 Bakr al-

    Khallal (d. 311/923) gathered Ahmad's views into a vast collection to form the textual

    foundation for the Hanbali school. A little later, Ab5 Qasim al-Khiraqi (d. 334/945-

    6) produced the first handbook of Hanbali jurisprudence, and Ibn H3

    (-. 4031

    1013) worked to reconcile conflicting views within these preceding Hanbali sourcus

    (Melchert

    1997;

    al-Sarhan 2011: 96-107). In the realm. of legal theory

    (ustil al-fiqh),

    Abn Ya`la (d. 458/1065) carried forward al-Shafi

    r

    i's project of correlating the law to

    the Qur'an and the

    Ijadith

    with unprecedented thoroughness and consistency.

    pressing the claim that the law corresponded to the literal

    (zahir)

    sense of revelation,

    he

    elided the historical and hermeneutical process by which the law came into exist-

    ence. The point was to rationalize the equation of revelation with prescribed belief

    and practice as inherently obvious (Vishanoff 2011). For most Hanbalis, affiliating

    with the school meant following the rulings attributed to Ahmad b. Hanbal loyally,

    much as Shafils followed the rulings of al-Shafil and Hanafis the rulings of Abu

    klanifa. However, being Hanbali could also mean engaging in creative jurisprudence

    (ijtihcid)

    according to Ahmad's traditionalist method without necessarily following

    t i

    i

    s

    rulings. This is the sense in which ibn 'fayrniyya considered iiinsell Hanbali. As

    a creative jurist

    (mujtahid),

    Ibn Taymiyya did not hesitate to cri:cize Ahmad's rul-

    ings, but he nonetheless claimed loyalty to the Hanbali school 1 'id Ali)inad's juristic

    inethod (al-Matroudi 2006).

    The classical Sun ni law schoo ls were comm itted first and foremo .i to the study of their

    ycspective jurisprudential systems, and by the fifth/eleventh ceim

    Sunni orthodoxy

    c...nsisted most fundamentally in belonging to a scho ol of law, Odic religi.iits groupings

    such as Sufis and Mu

    r

    tazili

    Kalam

    theologians had to take their plak es w Rhin this struc-

    ture in order to protect themselves from traditionalist persecution. The Mu`tazili theo-

    logians found refuge in both the Hanafi and Shafil schools, but, with time, Mu`tazilism

    died out among Sunnis and continued on only among Shns. Shah' ism appears to have

    been semi-rationalist in both jurisprudence and theological doctrine in the late third/

    ninth century before confining itself to jurisprudence in the course of the fourth/tenth.

    hafils of semi-rationalist persuasion in theology eventually took up Ash`arite

    Kalam.

    )the/

    Shafils were traditionalist in theology and took their theological lights from the

    limbalis. This is apparent in biographical dictionary entries describing such scholars as

    `Shafil in law, Hanbali in principles of religion'

    (shcifirtyyat al-fiqh, hanbaltyyat

    As M.akdisi observed, the El anbalis were the most consistently traditionalist in both law

    and theology. Traditionalists within the Shaffi and Ha.nati law schools also opposed

    Kalam.

    However, they did not voice their criticism as openly in order to safeguard the

    unity of their respective schools. As we will see, some Hanbali scholars drew on

    .Kalam

    and later the philosophy of Ibn Sina in their theologies, but, on the whole, the Hanbalis

    were the most vociferous in propagating traditionalist theological doctrines (Melchert

    1997; Mak disi 1962- 3; 1981).

    II EARLY HANBALi THEOLOGICAL

    DOCTRINE

    A number of texts used to depict the doctrinal views of Alamad b. Hanbal in past

    search are evidently not his. It has been shown recently that the six creeds attributed to

    11 1.11 in the biographical dictionary

    Tabaqat al-hanabila

    of Ibn Abi

    (d. 526/1133) (see

    Joust

    1 9 5 7

    for locations; three are translated into English in Watt 1994: 29 -40) go back

    to diverse traditionalist sources in the third/ninth and fourth/tenth ci.lituries rather than

    thmad himself. The creeds were apparently linked to him at a later date, probably to

    consolidate his position as the seminal authority for Hanbali doctrine. Another work,

    al-

    Radd

    -

    Jahmtyya

    wa-I-Zanadiqa

    ('Refutation of the Jahinis and the Irreligious'), may

    go back to Alamad in earlier forms. However, the final edition (trans. in Seale19,4:9,

    -

    u5) includes substantial rational argument against non-traditionalist doctrines, and it

    was probably written in the fifth/eleventh century to rally Ahmad to the side of Hanbalis

    coking to justify rational argument in theology (al-Sarhan

    20 11:

    29

    54).

  • 7/26/2019 Hanbali Theology in the Oxford Handbook

    3/13

    628

    CVER

    Iv Iiin

    a.4s may

    still be It

    Prior to

    be

    :lil:1

    'E

    ,

    oiarfli of the

    led t

    pia

    kiftd:: ?: .

    /^r.^

    Uthniu

    liovs

    .

    evor, tipHti

    i ich then

    ;

    in ills: ...a:1y

    ..'iluf

    ,;. -irp;

    :::111.iries, but It:,

    eschide,

    ;:iMaiph

    radier than the fourth (al-Sarhan

    20i :

    ;-

    Ii

    :s also likely that Ahmad, like other traditionalists of his day, had no qualms about

    speaking of God in creaturely or corporeal terms, so long as there were Qur'an or

    iexts in support. He affirmed for example that the

    'God created Adam in

    his form (.514ra)' meant that God created Adam in God's form, which implied that God

    himself had a form or shape like that of Adam. To

    Kalarn

    theologians this constituted

    the grave error of assimilating God to creatures

    (tashbih,

    also called 'anthropomor-

    phism' in much scholarship). Taking their cue from 'There is nothing like [God], and.

    He is iil l-Hearing and all-Seeing' (Q 42;

    later Hanbalis such as al-Barbahari (d. 329/

    941) sought to avoid the charge of assimiliationism by denying any likeness between

    God's attributes and those of creatures while yet affirming that God indeed had the

    attributes mentioned in revelation. This 'noninterventionist' (Swartz 202) or `noncog-

    nitive' (Shihadeh 2006) approach refused to inquire into the modality

    (kayj) of God's

    attributesa position known as

    balkafa

    or

    kayf

    ('without how')or to inter-

    pret the meaning of the attributes in any way. 'ale texts should be passed over with-

    out comment (imrar). Some scholars have identified this kind of non-interventionism

    :n Alamad b. H anbal as well (e.g. Abrahamov .1995: 366 -7). . lowever, there is no evi-

    dence that Ahmad affirmed the

    balkafa

    doctrine explicitly (Williams

    2002;

    see also

    Melchert 2o11).

    Questions of

    tashbih

    and the status of

    Kalam

    theology were at the centre of the

    Inquisition

    (millria)

    initiated by the 'Abbasid caliph al-Ma'ninn in 218/833 and famously

    resisted by Ahmad

    It has been often said that al-Ma'rnrin imposed the created

    Qur'an on judges and leading religious scholars to support Mu`tazili

    &dam.

    However,

    the Nilu'tazilis were not the only or even the main beneficiaries of the Inquisition.

    doctrine of the created Qur'an was also known among followers of Alai, Hanifa

    going back to the master himself, and the Inquisition sought primarily to support the

    Hanafis, as well as other rationalist and semi-rationalist currents, against an increas-

    ingly assertive traditionalism. In the face of al-Ma'mun's Inquisition, Ahmad b. Hanbal

    would affirm only that the Qur'an was the word of God. No Queanic verse or

    l'aadTtli

    report stated explicitly that the Qur'an was created

    (makhlaq),

    and Alamad discounted

    on principle the Kalam

    reasoning supplied for the doctrine. Ahmad was subjected to

    imprisonment and flogging under al-Ma'intan's successor al-Nlu`tasim, but the later

    caliph al-Mutawakkil brought the Inquisition to a gradual halt from 233/847 to 237/852.

    In a letter to al-Mutawa.kkil, Ahmad did go a bit beyond the witness of the texts to affirm

    that the Qur'an was also 'uncreated

    (ghayr makhlaq),

    and he added that anyone who

    efosed to affirm this was an unbeliever. 'The failure of the Inquisition marked a major

    yi:sk

    ion

    .trid he c,iliphate'..; gamkt For ..

    .ner;ted froin I he Inquisition

    hero of the traditionalist ,.-

    :herr

    [4;H:.; 196o

    6; Madelting 1974; 897).

    ho aid . . . .as

    :

    .

    or his con:plc:L. sli.;intett..

    ,,t

    po :tis...ii

    ; (t' lived a quiet

    md he Ulle,

    ,

    icted

    (siliog autho:ities

    ilitie .i,;

    ring .snd

    14,iiih4lis were mii6: niore ,Lstiv

    71,1

    -r

    cons: i, ined

    powet

    !A

    eai2,11..j:::.;

    ;11t r ,

    riii

    .

    . . .C;AUCY

    ,

    't1

    ,,

    11:1. I

    I R :

    .oust

    famous figure in I lie first half of the ioirth/tenth v was

    lien/

    al-Barbahari, author of a comprehensive crec. al statement

    Sharh, al-

    ,,uitna

    (in ibn Abi Yala 1952: ii. 18-45). He was implicated in Han.bali attacks on Shafil

    Jurists and purveyors of vice and innovation

    (bid`a),

    and he often went into hiding to

    escape the authorities. Al- Barbahari may have been involved in riots that began in 317/

    919 over interpretation of the divine address to the Prophet Muhammad 'Perhaps your

    Lord will raise you up to a praiseworthy station' (Q 17: 79). Al-Barbahari understood this

    that God would seat Muhammad on the 'Throne beside Himself whereas semi-

    r ionalists of the timeincluding followers of the renowned Qur'an commentator al-

    Tabari (d. o/923)preferred to interpret this metaphorically as Muhammad's right

    to intcrcede for grave sinners (Melchert 2012). With the Bityid takeover of Baghdad in

    334/945, 1:1:inbali animosities turned against the Shils as well, and Hanbalis engaged

    in numerous attacks on Shi r

    is, Ka/cirn

    theologians, and others well into the seventh/

    thirteenth century. M. Cook attributes this Hanball social power to their great num-

    s and a weakened state. Additionally, with the rise of the Bilyids and then later the

    Sal juq amquest of Baghdad in 447/1055, the H, anbalis and the 'Abbasid caliphs found

    common cause in undermining those foreign rulers (Sabah 1981:

    101-20;

    Cook 2000:

    115-28).

    A key fourth/tenth-century author on H.anbali theological doctrine beyond al-

    Barbahari was Ibn Batta (d. 387/997). lbn Balla composed

    al-lbana al-kubra,

    a large col-

    lection of traditions on belief, the Qur'an, God's predetermination, and other doctrinal

    matters. He also wrote

    al-lbana al-ughra,

    a shorter creedal text that is also amply sup-

    plied with supporting traditions (ed. and trans. in Laoust 1958). A brief survey of this

    treatise will serve to summarize the key points of early Hanbali doctrine.

    I bn Balla begins

    al-lbana al-sughra

    with a long exhortation to adhere to the comrnu-

    nizy

    (jam4 'a)

    and the Sunna of the Prophet and to avoid division and innovation. Then,

    he mentions belief

    (itncin),

    which is affirming what God says, cor:imands, and prohibits

    and putting this into practice. Unlike the Murji'is for whom beiIef depends on confes-

    sion alone, belief can increase or decrease according to one's deet

    .

    s. 'It God wills' should

    be added when affirming that one is a believer, not out of doubt t.ver one's religious sta-

    tus as a believer, hut because the future is unknown, Ibn Batta affirms that the Qur'an is

    the Word of God, and he deems it uncreated no matter where it is found, even written

    on the chalkboards of children. Not one letter is created, and wh.ever deems otherwise

    is an unbeliever worthy of death. God's attributes mentioned in

    ,

    cycaled texts must be

    affirmed. Among other things, God is living, speaking, powerful, wiseind knowing. He

    LiO/cs Ste and death, and He speaks and laughs. Believers will also see Cod on the Day

  • 7/26/2019 Hanbali Theology in the Oxford Handbook

    4/13

    630 ION HOOVER

    of -at rrection. Ibn Batla does not mention

    balkafa with this list

    attributes, but he

    it later when affirming God's descent each night to the loweA heaven. This,

    s.

    .acmcd wi,

    hout .1:41(ii;g

    Low (.'01;1)

    tiitila). In opposition to

    .11'd

    1

    ,

    ,:tazi17. doctrine iliat lunuans

    their own at is.

    tta affirm,.

    i)();11:401)j and

    a c e - . . i i

    .

    dinig to thc

    le pes

    On

    to affirm numerous cli...rnetits of

    di

    ,

    : toinb, the weighing o ftlectls

    ales ai t he

    i t . . C S 4 1 1 ' 1 ' , 2 1 : !

    intercession for believers, and so on. The latter part of the treatise extols the virtues of

    the prophets and the Prophet Mubainmad's Companionsespecially Abu Bakr, `Umar,

    `Uthman, and 'Ali, in that order to oppose the Shils--and treats several matters of prac-

    tice. Overall,

    al-lbana al-sughra

    provides very little explanation or rational argument. It

    is largely a series of affirmations supported with Qur'anic verses and

    hadith

    reports.

    III HANBALi THEOLOGY FROM THE

    ELEVENTH CENTURY TO THE THIRTEENTH

    Research on Hanbali theology in the fifth/eleventh to seventh/thirteenth centu-

    ries remains spotty, but it is readily apparent that this period marks a new departure

    as some of the leading Hanbali scholars of the time adopted

    Kalam

    views and argu-

    mentation. The earlier Hanbali Abu 1-I-Jusayn al-Munadi (d. 335/947) had advocated

    metaphorical interpretation

    (ta 'wil)

    of God's attributes, and the lost

    Sharh ow al-din

    of Ibn Hamid may have been a Ka/am-style work (Swartz.

    2002:

    61, 94). But it is from

    Ibn Harnid's student Abu Yala Ibn al-Parra' (d. 458/1066), the most prominent Hanbali

    of his time, that we have our first extant Hanbali

    Kalam

    manual,

    al-Mu`tamad uszal

    al-din,

    a summary of a larger lost work by the same title. Typical of

    Kalam manuals,

    al-Mu`tamad

    first outlines the foundations of knowledge and explains that the initial

    human obligation is reasoning

    (nazar)

    to knowledge of God. The book then outlines

    the basics of

    Kellam

    atomism, proves the existence of God from the origination of the

    world, arid treats, among other things, God's attributes, God's creation of the world and

    human acts, prophecy, eschatology, belief, and the Imamate. Abu Yala adopts Ash'arile

    positions on a number of issues in

    al-Mu tamad.

    For example, he bases the obligation

    to nazar on revelation as do the Ash'arites, not reason as held by the MuTazilis, and he

    employs the Ash`arite notion of acquisition

    (kasb)

    to give humans responsibility for the

    acts that God creates in them (Gimaret

    1977:161-5).

    Abu Y)la also wrote two other theo-

    logical works that are extant:

    Ibtal

    i-akhbar al-sifat

    and

    Kitcib al-Irnan,

    The

    Kitab al-Iman,

    also known as

    Masa 51 al-iman,

    is a detailed treatment of belief and the

    status of believers and bad sinners.

    (bpi al-ta'wilat

    is a lengthy work on the interpreta-

    tion of God's corporeal qualities.

    Abu Ya`la's approach to God's corporeal qualifications seeks to mediate between

    Kalam

    rationalism and Hanbali traditionalism. In

    al-Nfu'iamad,

    he joins the

    Kolan:

    theologians in arguing that God cannot have a body ("ism). I

    hu/

    ,x&

    corporeal qualifications such as eyes, hands, face, and

    mean that

    body ,

    ,

    art:;. Yet, .Abil Yala also rejt..cts metaphorical interpihmi ion ("a 'le

    F T ) i , 1

    tjUaiiii: iOntiind

    he in aintain.s that i hey are simply attributi .

    some

    (fihat.:1

    Jud .4herm; added (zii 'itl) to God's essence (Abti

    - ; - () ) . al:;;)

    i

    n AO

    -fa .teilat.

    For example, he affirms that

    I

    -Ik

    and ula

    lie seen, as stated in the kifailith. ins

    per:,

    -

    ::thir),

    Abu Yala explains, but without interpreting it furtlicr ic imply

    opens

    Iiia mouth or that He has body parts such as molars or an uvula, and without interpret-

    ing it metaphorically to mean God's grace and generosity. God's laughing is an attribute

    (sifa),

    but its meaning

    (ma`na)

    is not understood (Holtzman 2010: 186-7). Despite Abu

    Yalia's attempt to avoid corporealism

    (tajsim)

    on the one hand and

    ta'wil

    on the other, he

    and his teacher Ibn Haruki later came under sharp attack from fellow Hanbali scholar

    Ibn al-Jawzi for crass literalism and corporealism.

    Aba YaTa's foremost student was Ibn 'Aqil. (d. 513/1119), a precocious reader of

    Kalam

    alongside his Hanbali legal studies. With the death of his patron in

    460/1067-8, Ibn 'Aqil suffered under the intrigues of rival Hanbali jurist Sharif

    TaTar (d. 470/1077) and was eventually forced to retract his Mu'tazili writings in 1072,

    as well as his sympathies for the Sufi martyr al-Hallaj (d. 309/922). G. Makdisi ties Ibn

    'Aqil's retraction to the 'Abbasid Caliph al-Qadir's (d. 422/1031) earlier promulgation of

    a traditionalist Hanbali creed as official doctrine of the caliphate and interprets it as the

    culmination of traditionalist ascendancy in Baghdad: [The retraction] represents the

    triumph of the Traditionalist movement supported by the caliph lie, against Rationalist

    MuTazilism, on the decline, and a militant Rationalist Ash'arism, on the ascendant'

    thanks to support from the Saljuqs (Makdisi 1997: 14; also Mikdisi 1963). As Makdisi

    indicates, the traditionalist battle with

    Kalam

    was not done, ant Ash`arism continued

    to rival Hanbalism for centuries to come. Ibn 'Aqil's major work ill theology

    al-Irshadfi

    arid al-din

    is not extant. Otherwise, i t appears that Ibn `A.q11 , post- retraction, was mod-

    erately rationalist within a traditional Hanbali doctrinal .fratrework and advocated a

    limited use of ta 'wil (Makdisi1997),

    Mention of Ib.n 'Aqil's interest in al-I

    -

    Jallaj raises the question of Hanbali-Sufi rela-

    tions, especially as Hanbalis have often been seen to be opponents of Sufism. This

    reputation derives from the later Hanbali polemic of Ibn al--Jawzi and Ibn Taymiyya

    against innovated practices and doctrines linked to Sufism, although not against

    its ideal of a spiritual path to God. Han.balis and Sufis share common origins in tra-

    ditionalist currents of renunciant piety, and, like other traditionalists, early Sufis stud-

    ied

    1 1

    adith

    and rejected Kalam.

    As the legal schools formed from the late third/ninth

    century onward, Sufis affiliated largely with semi-rationalist schools such as the Shafil

    ,Ind the Maliki. However, Sufi relations with the traditionalist IJanbalis, were generally

    good. Traditionalist Sufi writers such as Abil Nu'aym al-Isfahani (d. 430/1038) included

    klarnad b. Hanbal among the pious saints

    (aw/iyal

    of past generations, and some

    itotable Sufis were Hanbalis including 1bn 'Ata' (d. 309/921-2 or 31.1/923-4), who was

    for defending al-Hallaj, 'Abd Allah al-Ansari (d. 481/1o/t9

    ind the eponym of

  • 7/26/2019 Hanbali Theology in the Oxford Handbook

    5/13

    632 JON HOOVER

    the

    Sufi or. k.hd

    ,,,

    1 al-

    '

    al are borli

    , i i . .iii:jeance for Y

    ' halt

    Al Ati-zi'iri bati led

    As1J'arit .

    il , e0logans 1:1 ...horas-tii, Ind out o:

    A

    m,: hi

    s io

    al

    les a ti.i1J aild well cr,,J,ani,

    , ( 1 . . , : ' . 1 W ; 1 1 : . : 1 1 E o f tr a -

    fli1:0 1,11

    . !

    rine ii

    trios

    J. 1 -

    I,

    '

    Tii, most

    ,

    ;ophisticat-il Jorih.Jli

    .1.1i:r

    (d.

    527/1[12), author of

    al-laah ji

    ,

    inanual similar in length and stritclure to Abil

    Mu'tamad,

    and it reats God's

    corpt weal qualifications in much the same way, To take God's eyes, for exailiple, Ibn al-

    Zaghtini denies that God's eye consists of a fleshly eyeballGod's eye is not an origi-

    nated body. Yet, he also disallows interpreting God's eye metaphorically along

    Kalatii

    lines as God's 'protection'. Rather, God's eye is an attribute to be taken literally without

    assimi.lationism or modality (tbn al-Zaghimi 2003: 291-4). With his, tbn al-Zaghimi

    sought to find his way between corporealism and

    ta'wil,

    but it failed to please his fore-

    most student Ibn al-Jaw.zi.

    Ibn al-Jawzi W. 597/1201) was the leading Hanbali scholar and preacher of h.is day. He

    initially opposed the Ash`arites and Mu tazilis, partly because they were aligned with the

    Saljuq sultans, but, as Saljuq power waned and the 'Abbasid caliphate revived, he took

    a more relaxed attitude toward

    Kalam

    and eventually drew on Kalcim argumentation

    to produce his fullest theological work,

    Kitab

    Akhbdr

    al-sijat,

    in the late 1.18os or early

    1190s. This book contains a stinging condemnation of assimilationism and corporealisto

    within the Hanbali school, and it probably

    contributed to his banishment to Wasit

    590/1194 (Swartz 2002:

    33

    45).

    Ibn

    al,

    wrote a similar but shorter work called

    the

    Daf shubah al-tashbih

    (trans. 'Ali 2oo6), oh) known as

    al-Baz

    achl,,,b.

    The targets of ibn al-Jaw/1'3

    Akithar

    re three of the mos prominent

    Hanbalis of the preceding two oracles-1bn Hamid, Abu Ya

    lla, and Ibn

    whom he accuses of interpretirg (1od's corporeal qualifications literally and disallow-

    ing metaphorical interpretation. In a strongly rationalist tone, Ibn al-Jawzi explains that

    reason apart from revelation knows God's existence, God's unity, God's necessary attrib-

    utes, the originated quality of the world, and prophecy. Reason also knows that God is

    not a body; otherwise He would be subject to temporality. Thus God cannot be said tu

    have corporeal attributes in any literal sense.

    Then, in

    Kitab Akhbar

    bn al-Jawzi sets forth two approaches to God's corpo-

    real qualifications: non-interventionism for the masses and metaphorical interpretation

    (ta'wil) for the scholars. The error of the

    Kalam theologians is to subject the public to

    their dialectic because it only sows doubt and spreads heresy, Rather, God has spoken

    to the masses in language that they can undiTstand and readily accept, and, in public.

    God's corporeal qualifications such as His hands and eyes should be read in the texts and

    passed over as they are without comment (am:4r). Taking aim at Alla Ya`la,

    Jawzf

    declares that nothing further should be said about what kind of attributes these qualifi

    cations might be fri.g. essential (dhati)

    or additional (za'id)

    to the essence) or about their

    literal meaning. However, among the scholars, Ibn al-jawzi explains, God's corporeal

    clualifications should he i-einierp,-,ocd inetaphorically

    .k

    ^.'

    ri.as(

    .n, that is, to deny that

    h,a; a body. The bulk if

    .;i0t i s 1 1 1 , . . 1

    -

    1

    ond reinterprinion orJ

    and I

    tex is po ,

    -ems.1pu

    elitimr that

    ta 'w1; i.s only for be schola,

    - -; ,

    e

    iy

    Ibn al 1^,,

    ,-J.Ji i.lispla):; cot

    ism la hi:. book, and ins objective

    . , _P Lt ati i l of t il c

    ! , C 1 , 1:01 it1

    i.yes

    scholars. tbn al-Jawzi claims ijie highly regarded .'d:Iroad b. 1,-1Jal:

    /cil for the

    ontionism that he advocates for the masses, and he rejects layr T

    .

    1

    'i,ihall attenipii. at

    literality as deviant corporealisrn (Swartz

    2002: 46-64,

    27-138).

    lbn al-Jawzi's polemic did not escape Hanbali criticism, Abu i-ijadl al-Ahhi (d. 634/

    1236) wrote a diatribe that may have helped get the senior Haaliali scholar exiled to

    Wasit. Al-Althi takes Ibn al-Jawzi to task for his elitist advocacy

    'w.

    /

    and calls him to

    repentance. There is, however, no evidence that Ibn al-Jawzi ever recanted (Swartz

    2002:

    282-97).

    Later on, sometime after 6o3/12.06, the Syrian Hanbali jurist .1bn Q.uclama (d.

    620/1223) wrote his

    Tahrtrn al-nazar ji kutub ahl al-kalarn

    in which he discusses the

    retraction of Ibn `Aqil at length. No mention is made here of Ibn al-Jawzi, but it seems

    likely that Ibn Quelama had him and his admirers in mind (Swartz 2002: 42,62),

    Ibn Qudarna's Tahrirn al-nazar

    provides a lengthy refutation

    t

    nd 11 repeat-

    edly sets out the traditionalist

    H

    anbali position on God's attrilaa tes. ..iting the aut hor-

    ny of Ahmad b. Hanbal, Ibn Qudama explains that corporeal pici ions of God in the

    Qur'an and the

    Hadith

    must be accepted as true without saying anything more or less.

    God is described as He has described Himself, and the texts are passed over as they

    are without comment (imrar)

    and without inquiring into modality (./..,.irj) or meaning

    (ma `na

    ). Ib.n Qudama also claims that whatever God's attribute

    .;

    miglit mean is of no

    practical import, and believing in them in ignorance is the correct path. If one wants to

    inquire into something, Ibn Qudama argues, one should inquire into jurisprudence, not

    the attributes of God (Makdisi 1962).

    Hanbalism weakened in Baghdad after Ibn al-Jawzi, and the Mongol destruction of

    the city in 1258 dealt the

    H

    anbalis a further setback. Damascus took over as the intellec-

    tual centre of Hanbalism with Ibn Qudama being one of its great early figures. Damascus

    was'dominated by S.hafi'is, and

    H

    anbalis could not exercise the same so(

    ial and political

    power that they had enjoyed in Baghdad. Nonetheless, the Damas,:enc anbalis thrived

    and eventually produced the most creative theologian in the Hari

    mil tradition and one

    of the greatest minds in medieval Islam: Ibn Taymiyya.

    IV IBN TAYMIYYA

    11 ,

    n Taymiyya (d. 728/1.328) is at times portrayed as anti-rationolisi due to

    polemic

    against the main claimants to reason in his day: Ash`arite and Mil ta,li

    th.a6-

    -

    igy,

    Aristotelian logic, and the Aristotelian-Neoplatonist

    jalsiiiir

    ho . '11na.

    iwever,

  • 7/26/2019 Hanbali Theology in the Oxford Handbook

    6/13

    W 3 4

    JON HOOVER

    (

    635

    it has keen .:),ide clear that rbni Tay)nivya did

    not reic,

    r reason as

    hut argued for its

    :

    ,

    ),

    i,,

    ...co:r.i....oparcat that his

    % A ! 3 S 1 1

    , 1.

    of 1).101.1/.11

    .

    d piJet:

    It was

    . cad voo kal in .t intid

    ;le rcot ,:nstrual ot God

    piAatly i:na!

    ve and

    Ira

    nil In

    ( lo,)vcr

    :4: :to tr)a 1g ott both

    f:lisaftr and giv

    ;:tinc0 old

    01.1(:11),

    ';';; Oka,

    :). y ) it); rt;iiiiccd

    co, o o itt)prei_c.detticd in iltc

    school

    ar). not found et

    ,where in

    (el Omani zoio; Hoover zo..., Ozervarli

    201o).

    The theological world in which Ibn Taymiyya worked was permeated with philos-

    ophized Ash`arite

    .Kalcim,

    especially that of Fa.khr al-Din al-Rad (d. 606/1209). Ibn

    Taymiyya read al-Razi with his students, and he wrote extensively against al-Razi's

    ideas. His major works

    Dayan talbis al-jahrniyya

    and Dar' ta

    amid al-rag/ w^-/-nag/

    both respond directly to al-Razi's thought. The former work refutes al-Razi's book

    Asas

    al-tacidis

    on the metaphorical interpretation of God's corporeal attributes. The latter

    work

    Dar' ta`cirud

    confutes the 'Rule of Metaphorical Interpretation'

    *Man al-ta'wd)

    espoused by al-Ghazali and al-Razi, which gives reason precedence over the literal

    meaning of revelation when the two contradict. Although Mu`tazili

    Kalam

    had died out

    in Sunni Islam by the eighth/fburteenth century, it lived on in Imami Shil theology, and

    ibn Taymiyya's large refutation of Shfism

    Minhaj al-sunna al-nabawiyya

    directly rebuts

    Mu'tazili notions of divine justice.

    In addition to the tomes just mentioned, ibn Taymiyya wrote several other large

    works, including major refutations of Christianity and Aristotelian logic, and important

    treatises on S ufism, political theory, and prophecy. W hile a few of Ibn Ta ymiyya's works

    may be dated with precision, many cannot, and change or development in his thinking

    is often difficult to establish. However, his thought is remarkably consistent and coher-

    ent, and it is thus with some confidence that we may speak of a characteristic Taymiyyan

    theology that retained its essential contours throughout the course of his scholarly life.

    Except where indicated otherwise, the following overview of Ibn Taymiyya's theology is

    based on my own writings (Hoover zoo4; 2007; zoioa; see also Laoust 1939; Bell 1979).

    As Ibn Taymiyya saw it, the fundamental problem of his time was that God was no

    longer worshipped and spoken of correctly. A great many Muslims had strayed from

    true theological doctrine and proper religious practice and fallen into the errors of

    philosophers and

    Ka/um

    theologians, as well as Shils, Sufis, Christians, and others.

    The solution was to return Islam to its sources, the Qur'an, the

    8adith,

    and the doc-

    trine and practice of the Salaf, the first two or three generations following the Prophet

    Mubammad, before the religion was corrupted by error and sectarian division. In Ibn

    Taymiyya's view, the accumulated judgements and the consensus of later scholars were

    subject to error, and they had to be measured against the doctrine of the Salaf.

    At the core of Ibn Taymiyya's polemic against

    .Kalam

    and f alsafa

    is the subordina-

    tion of metaphysics to ethics and the theoretical to the practical.

    Kalam

    and falsafi

    reverse the order. Both disciplines reason from the nature of reality to thc existence of

    God. God's unity, and God's attributes and eventually to prophecy and the practical

    ,: i i ,h,gations that follow on from that. For ibn Taym iyya, th apf)::

    o

    rLice wor-

    :)ip

    a

    God at the fore Tal:ing his cue from the rioter of

    hons

    'ton

    w v c -

    .

    ,-,

    rship; You alone we

    1 1 K

    ':or help' (Q 1: 5), Ibn Tayrniyytt

    :hat

    k

    of worship. praist , And love is prior :) (Iotrs exclitstv:: creation of tIte wot

    ;:id provision of htlp fi

    H is servants. (,: t

    k the sole

    :he

    tor

    L . ) ) ) ,,ro ya this

    inetapItyslcal

    fi .Ifows on from :it ,:

    ft):::idational

    iod's ore-eminent worthiness ')1 of)ciiience and pro:Ne. to tr,..:os

    P:

    woryhip God alone because of who Cod is in Himself and ;iot simply because /(x

    alone creates and sustains. Here is how Ibn Taymiyya distinguishes

    Kahim

    from his own

    method, which he takes to be that of the Qur'an;

    The distinction between the Quednic and the

    kalam

    theological methods is that God

    commands worship of Him, a worship which is the perfection of the soul, i ts pros-

    perity, and its ultimate goa l. He did not limit it to mere affirmation of H im, as is the

    purpose of the kalam

    method. The Q ur'an relates knowledge of H im and service to

    Him. It thus combines the two human faculties of knowledge and practice; or sensa-

    tion and motion; or perceptive v olition and operation; or verb:El and practical. As

    God says, 'W orship your Lord: Worship necessarily entails knowledge of H im, hav-

    ing penitence and humility before Him, and need of H im. This is the goal. T he

    ktficirn

    method secures only the benefit of affirmatio.n and admission"(

    xists:nce.

    (Quoted in Ozervarli zoio: 89)

    ti:inTaymiyya also s peaks of the priority of worship and ethics over met aphysics in theo-

    :rigical terms that later became widespread among Wa.hhabis and modern Salafis. He

    istinguishes two rawhids, or two ways of confessing God's unity. Ibn faymiyya's first

    hriv/ifd is that of God's divinity

    (ulribiyya). Al-tawhid al-ulahiyya

    signifies God's sole

    .

    ,orthiness to be a god, that is, God's sole right to be an object of worship

    (Ybada). Al-

    :awhid al - uhThlyya

    is exclusive worship of God that refuses to give devotion and love to

    1nything or anyone else. Then flowing out from this is the second

    tawhid,

    the

    tawhid

    of

    lordship

    (rubUbiyya).

    God's lordship refers to His creative 'ower, and

    al-tawhid

    (d-rubUbiyya

    means confessing that God is the only source of .1teL aeings. For Ibn

    ,

    -

    'aymiyya

    al-tawhid al-ulithiyya

    is logically prior to

    al-tawhid -1-rububiyya:

    God in

    limself in His pre-eminent worthiness of love and worship comes first.

    Ibn Taym iyya's practical turn effectively transforms theology into an aspect of M uslim

    jurisprudence. He rejects the commonplace medieval distinction between the princi-

    ples

    (ustii)

    of religion and the branches

    (furin,

    in which the principles treat theologi-

    cal doctrines like God's existence and attributes from a theoretical perspective and the

    branches discuss religious obligations such as prayer and fasting from a practica), legal

    vantage point. Rather, for Ibn Taymiyya, the principles treat those matters of greatest

    importance in both theological doctrine and religious practice, and the branches deal

    with lesser matters of detail. Moreover, theological beliefs and r.ligious Trochees are

    both practical matters concerned with correct worship of God, iind theology is prirnar-

    ily about getting the language of praise and worship right, not establishing the existence

    of God.

  • 7/26/2019 Hanbali Theology in the Oxford Handbook

    7/13

    636

    , va .6 hoick

    i:e for riiason and its

    .:3[,:v:Ity ,

    I;

    and IL view

    raason , 10 i.i

    y opt:Ini511

    ,

    . I .e

    .:/m, .

    rrc)

    e

    hat .:virii

    it mit as it

    re.tks

    . 1 1 1

    ';,j-b. La

    ::10t.

    that it !

    hat

    nendit

    l

    ove et

    ,'i Sp, lug; in i' .: : istoteiati terms,

    l ,:

    iiyya

    frames the natur,d constitution as an innate potency toward the religion of

    t Lim at birth that is actualized as the human being develops; the role ot prophecy and

    revelation is then to perfect the natural constitutfit; and help it overcome corruption.

    For Ibn Tayrniyya, reason and the natural constitution on the one hand and revelation

    on the other do not contradict. They both come from the same source, and they provide

    much the same information and argument. Rational minds and natural constitutions

    can know the existence of God and the proper human end apart from roelation, but

    when they encounter revelation they immediately recognize it as true and congruent

    with what they already know. .t .bn Taymiyya observes that

    Ka/am

    theologians and phi-

    losophers confine revelation to information that cannot be attained by reason, and he

    ...ounters that revelation includes not merely information but also rational argument.

    1-1f.velation contains the correct proofs of reaso n, and reason recognizes the truth of rev-

    elation. In making the claim that revelation and reason agree, fbn Taymiyya is trying to

    take the rational high ground away fromfiilsafa and

    Kalam,

    which he believes are based

    on faulty foundations and lead to misguided conclusions.

    case in point is the

    Kalam

    proof for God's existence. 'The

    Ka lam

    proof in simplified

    form assumes that the world is made up of indivisible atoms and the accidents that sub-

    sist in them. Accidents are temporally originating (hadith), andthis is keyanything

    in which something temporally originating subsiststhe atommust also be tempo

    rally originating. Seeing that all atoms are temporally originating, and in view of the

    Kalam

    conviction that an infinite regress of temporally originating events is impossible,

    the world as a whole must have been originated in time. Having proved that the world

    had a beginning, the

    Ka/4m

    argument concludes that it required a Maker who was not

    originated but eternal.

    fbn Taymiyya often dismisses this proof and its talk of atoms and accidents as unnes -

    essarily complex. Yet, apart from a bit of complexity, it can be difficult to see why he

    would find it so problematic. However, the proof is based on two postulates that are

    incompatible with Ibn Taymiyya's theological vision: the impossibility of an infinite

    :egress and the notion that something in which temporally originating events subsist

    is itself tinnporally originating. As will become apparent, Ibn Taymiyya has no objec-

    tion to an infinite regress. His iiwn view of God as perpetually creative from eternity

    entails an infinite regress of created things. Additionally, his temporally dynamic view

    of

    t

    iod implies that originating events subsist in God's very essence. Ibn Tayrni) ya can-

    not accept the

    Kalam

    postulate that originating events render their host

    substrate tem-

    porally originating because he himself posits temporality in the essence of God. In his

    ve

    pOt1: tti S

    Ind

    ead to

    ,

    0 : 1 1

    :us

    own

    leCortlW ith both revelatio

    n :

    nil r,:ason,

    '

    ii,lis attributes and

    which lie a isciis,e,

    f it(

    i

    , d God's attribu:ii:s),

    n ic: t1,61. or :Ion-, .?t

    nttiviNtn, but

    ;; f.

    ma

    i ..,:cr 6n. lint TAy

    rtityya's

    i.eqn

    :he i:

    anies and :ntri6u:es

    ft .

    ravoa.

    without, on

    use hand, inquiring into t heir 'nodality

    c.,sinulating

    fraslittili) or likening

    tamtial)

    them to the attributes and names of creiullyzs, or, on the

    other hand, stripping them away

    tartf/)

    from God with metaphorical interpretation.

    iad is affirmed as all-Hearing, all-Seeing, but there is nevertheless nothing like Him (Q

    az:

    'This applies equally to all qualifications given in the Qur'an. and the

    Ijadith,

    from

    iod's 'willing' to God's 'laughter' and God's `sitting' on the Throne. Ibn Taymiyya rejects

    h:a Kahim practice of reinterpretation (ta 'w11 ) and dismisses the distinct ion between the

    7,ihir)

    and the metaphorical

    majaz)

    upon which it is bas:,:d, "ro tJ

    c ine of ibn

    t'ilyntiyya's examples, Ash`arite

    Kalam

    theologians reinterpret t ind's

    metaphori-

    : ally as God's 'will' on the grounds that speaking of God's love literally would assimi-

    late Him to creaturely qualities; God cannot be ascribed with crtiatu rely passions like

    lave. Ibn Taymiyya retorts that this reinterpretation in fact involves both likening and

    tripping

    away. First , the

    Kalcim

    theologians imagine the love ascribed to God to be like

    iuman love in a literal sense and thereby conclude that 'love

    In ry

    be ascribed to

    tTh id. Then, to free God of the untoward passions of human love, :hey

    strip God

    of His

    ' :i.: by

    calling

    it instead `will: The only reaso nable course, acco rding

    to liin

    Taymiyya, is

    ::1:iffirin all of God's names and attributes equally and without modality. The only simi-

    arity between the names and attributes of God and the names :ind

    ributes of crea-

    tures are the very names.

    The non-interventionism of a If anbali like Ibn Qudama stopped at

    point and for-

    : iade full ier inquiry into the nieimings of God's attributes because they were of no prac-

    ical consequence. God's names and attributes must be passed of er without inquiring

    i

    , ito their meaning

    imrar).

    Ibn Taymiyya, on the contrary, believes that the meanings

    matter, and this propels him on to a wide-ranging project of theological hermeneu-

    :ic:i. He discards the

    Kalam

    device of Will/ and places in its stead a project of linguistic

    ' ,,i;tiiry

    (*sir)

    that seeks to interpret God's attributes and names

    in

    ways that he deems

    nraiseworthy. While humans may know nothing about God's names and attributes

    'xcept the names, these names still evoke meaning in the human mind, and this mean-

    ing impacts human response to God for good or ill, depending on the character of the

    portrayal. For Ibn Taym iyya it is thus imperative to give sense to G od's names and attrib-

    ,tes that will evoke love and praise for God and ward off scepticism and disdain. This is

    (lie aim of Ibn Taymiyya's whole theological endeavour, and his foremost difficulty with

    cival theological visions is that they fail to give G od sufficient praise.

    An instructive example

    of how this works is Ihn. Taymiyya's contrast of . ill's own notion

    t God's justice

    (WI)

    with that of the Ash.'arites and the Mn'tazilis. In

    i he

    .

    voluntarisin

    fthe Ash`arites, God's justice consists in whatever God wills, with :out i:onsideration of

  • 7/26/2019 Hanbali Theology in the Oxford Handbook

    8/13

    638 JON HOOVER

    cause or wise purpose, God is just to punish hurrhios for the b-

    thaa He creates in

    them, and he would even

    lo pu

    wu6c. ,. 1 1 F ' ,.ymiyya rejects

    a

    as c,';): icio

    ,

    ts and uipa,o i-tily ,a.

    .

    trt, argue

    oi fact be uujest iod p.:11sti bad

    tilt

    ;1

    ,,au.aa

    . i

    nki

    C..1; ;

    )1M); ,1t:

    rnardfor

    :iced:, and pimisitinent

    ha

    d

    Taymiyya

    ta:/iii

    tirv,

    ;ot.a.:t1:d

    .

    : ins, ice

    .1 plurality of creators

    universe--both G. id .uid humansand because it makes

    God look .1;)olish. God ill . his foreknowledge knows that humans will commit evil deeds

    with the creative pow er that He gives them, and yet H e stupidly gives it to them anyway.

    'this, Ibn

    . faymiy-

    ya remarks, is like one person giving another a sword to fight unbeliev-

    ers when he already knows that the other person will use it to kill a prophet. In sum,

    Ibn Taymiyya castigates both the Mu`tazilis and the Ash`arites for depicting God in an

    unworthy manner. While God cannot be subjected to human moral standards because

    He is wholly unlike creatures, He must nonetheless be spoken of with the highest praise.

    For Ibn T aymiyya, this means that God's justice consists in `putting things in their places'

    in accord with His wise purpose

    (hikma),

    and, in one o f his late texts, he affirms with Ibn

    Sina and al-Ghazali that God has created the best possible world.

    Ibn Taymiyya also sets forth a mechanism for deriving God's names and attributes

    rationally. W hile he disallows use o f the juristic analogy

    (qiyas) and the categorical syllo-

    gism in theology because they bring God and creatures into direct comparison, he does

    permit their use in an afirtiori argument

    (qiyas af-aw/a).

    In accord with the Queanic

    assertion that God is ascribed with the 'highest similitude'

    (al-mathal

    a ) (Q 16: 6o ) ,

    Ibn Taym iyya claims that God is all the worthier (awla) of perfections found in creatures

    than are the creatures themselves because He is their cause and source. Thus, using a

    fortiori

    reasoning, God is all the worthier of being ascribed with perfections found in

    creatures such as power, l ife, sight, and speech. Similarly, G od is all the wo rthier of being

    disassociated from anything considered imperfect in creatures, and the pinnacle of per-

    fection in God is for His attributes to be unlike those of creatures entirely. Ibn Taymiyya

    sums it up thus: [God] is qualified by every attribute of perfection such that no one

    bears any likeness to Him in it ' (quoted in H oov er 2007: 65). On this basis Ibn Taym iyya

    ascribes to God a wide range of attributes that he deems perfections in humans includ-

    ing laughter, joy, and mo vement. T hese attributes are of co urse attested in revealed texts,

    but Ibn Taymiyya maintains that they are apparent from reason as well. Moreover, God

    must be ascribed with such attributes of perfection. Otherwise, He will be regarded as

    imperfect and unworthy of worship.

    Ibn Tayrniyya's view of what constitutes God's essential perfectionperpetual, tem-

    poral, and purposeful activitysets him apart from practically the entire preceding

    Islamic tradition. Elements of his formulation are found in Karrami theology, Fakhr

    al-Din al-Razi, and the philosopher Aba 1-Barak8t al-Baghdadi (d. 56o/1165), but tbn

    'Fayniiyya surpasses all of these in developing a consistently dynamic understanding of

    God. According to Ibn Taymiyya, God has been acting, creating, and speaking by His

    will and power for wise purposes from eternity (min al-azal).

    God's acts subsist in His

    very essence, and

    in tc mporal succession. He -..r.:tvs

    ;

    be quai

    l -

    y )

    acts subs:sting in Him on.e after another' (t:10'

    ,

    '

    'd

    Y;). ihn

    a rarely uscs lie term iemporaily

    qualify ;od's acts, 'T.-eteri io:; to t r . '

    i ,

    ISIC.td of God's

    , ! .

    language Joser to tic

    does i;:dicat(.

    ,

    ..lnporality, and he takes it upon

    t'; elute the

    'Its

    `-itbmstiag i it (

    In maintaining that Cod bas been creating from eternity, Ib ri Tay

    I V

    ;;

    Alt a

    middle position between

    thefaisafa

    of Ibn Sind on the one hand ..nd

    on the other.

    Ibn Taymiyya agrees with

    the Jalsafa

    tradition that God's perfection entails eternal pro-

    ductivity. To posit a starting point in God's creative action, as does

    Kaiam,

    implies that

    God was imperfect prior to beginning to create and subject to change when He switched

    from not creating to creating. Moreover, an efficient cause or preponderator

    (murallih)

    was needed to tip the balance in favour of G od beginning His creative :L.' ivity, Resisting

    this argument, Ash`arite

    Kalam

    held that it was in the very nature 4 (;l cfs eternal will

    to preponderate or cause creation to begin at a certain point; no additional cause need

    be posited. tbn Tayrniyya rejects this. Nothing can arise without a prior cause. Ibn Sina

    concluded from these considerations that God's eternal productivity entailed the ema-

    nation of an eternal world. Ibn Taymiyya affirms similarly that God's perpetual creativ-

    ity entails that there have always been created things of one sort or another, However,

    he has no patience for Ibn Sina's emanation scheme and its hierarchy of eternal celestial

    spheres. In agreement now with the

    Ka/am

    tradition, he denies that any created thing

    can be eternal. Rather, created things by definition come into -..xistence in time after

    they were not. To make sense of his position, Ibn Taymiyya (list itici

    ,

    ishes between the

    genus

    (jins)

    of created things on the one hand and individual

    tlings on the other.

    The genus is eternalthere have always been created things of nie sort or another

    but each individual created thing originates in time. Additionally, God does not create

    new things out of nothing but out of prior created things, and this present world that

    God created in six days (Q

    7) was preceded by and created out of prior worlds. Ibn

    Taym iyya's view of creation is remarkably close to that of the phi le sop i Ibn Rushd, but

    it is not clear whether there was direct influence.

    Regarding God's speech, .lbn Taymiyya rejects the Ash`arite ooct ri 1

    -

    f of the eternal

    Qur'an, but he does not follow the Mu`tazilis in calling the Qur'in

    ei

    timed. Instead, he

    holds that God has been speaking from eternity by His will and po

    ,

    ver arid that God's acts

    of speaking subsist in God's essence.

    As with created things, the

    of God's speak-

    ing is eternal while His individual speech acts are not. However, it is not said that God's

    speech acts are created. This is because they subsist in God's essen

    ,

    .c, not outside of God.

    Thus, God's individual speech acts are neither created nor eternal, and, likewise, God's

    speech in the Qur'an is 'uncreated'

    (ghayr makhlaq)

    but not etei pal. ..%3 IS

    apparent, the

    erm 'uncreated' does not mean timeless eternity for Ibn Taymiyya. ilather, it distill-

    ishes God's acts from created things in the world. On the verbal eve , lbn Td:,- .11 iiyy i

    l i

    s

    ful to the traditional Hanbali doctrine of the Qur'an's uncrealednessind he .1;tints

    :hat his position is that of Ahmad b. blanbal. But his introduction

    tcmiloi al seiii:enee

  • 7/26/2019 Hanbali Theology in the Oxford Handbook

    9/13

    ...tethtit

    ..;tfocc.; t

    .

    ya

    r 'tt

    11'.

    1,11Q:.,1

    640

    JON HOOVER

    into the s

    :6-tc Ai God

    :na

    nr ,,

    F

    1r,l

    c...

    - 11 ( in a debai

    vitt

    ..s..sn a cite,

    ttcs.iiit

    .d ,tok

    e

    :~^. e

    1 ,

    1d

    i';

    -4ithotat illy

    itf ity

    a Ti' the to,ot

    - i k f t t :

    Asinari

    inch as al Rai and Sayi al-Din al ,A

    (ii. n11/1233) dtny :hat ( lod creates

    for iiirposes or causes in :ler to render Ge, 's 66iti

    if the world i cely i vatuitous.

    In this Ash`arite voluntarism, God has no tic

    ,al olike wiirld, and the i.voi lel is st rictly the

    product of God's sheer will. Ibn Taymiyya does not interpret Ciid's independence or

    iaitticiency apart from the world in this voluntarist sense. Instead, he explains that God's

    suilkiency consists in needing no help in creating the world, and he follows Ibn Sind in

    giving priority to God's self-intellection and selt-love and making that the ground for

    the rest of existence. We see this for example in Ibn 'Eaymiyya's statement: 'What God

    loves of worship of Him and obedience to Him follows from love for Himself, and love

    of that is the cause of [His] love for His believing servants. His love for believers follows

    from love for Himself' (quoted in Hoover 2007: 99). Here, God's self-love is the ground

    for all other love. God does not need human love, and, likewise, God does not need the

    creation. Nevertheless, human love and the whole of creation follow necessarily from

    God's love ion Himself and from His perfection.

    The nec..i-oity with which God's acts flow from God's perfection would appear to obvi-

    ate

    rpality -

    of God's choice. Ibn Taymiyya responds, however, that it is possible for

    * u

    p cedetermined to occur through God's will and power. God's will and power

    arc

    means by which the concomitants of God's perfection are brought into existence.

    1bn irayiniyya writes, 'It is not impossible that something, which is necessary of occur-

    rence because the decree that it must inevitably be has preceded it, occur by... His power

    and His will, even if it is among the necessary concomitants of His essence like His life

    and His knowledge' (adapted from Hoover zoioa: 66).

    A similar question arises at the level of human acts. If God predetermines and creates

    all human acts, how are humans to be held accountable for their deeds? Following in

    the steps of Fakhr al-Din al-Razi, Ibn Taymiyya affirms that the human act is real and

    that humans undertake their acts by means of their own will and power. Nonetheless,

    it is God who creates the human will and power, and it is by means of these that He

    necessitates human acts. Nothing occurs independently of God's will and creation. lbn

    -

    l'ayiniyya denies any contradiction in this formulation, and when pressed on the point,

    he sometimes switches from the perspective of God's creation to the human perspec -

    live of responsibility to evade the inference that humans cannot be held accountable

    for deeds that God creates. Faced with a similar paradox between God's ccfnmand to

    do good deeds and God's creation of bad deeds, Ibn Taymiryia appeals to :..;od's wise

    purpose

    :he creation of all things and suggests ways of rri itigatinr, the difficulty. He

    than a khig

    -rind his

    timt

    .

    Yt2t.

    tha.: Icing mit

    .

    ;',It dko refrain from

    i

    ort:cri Ind L'4. hit subt

  • 7/26/2019 Hanbali Theology in the Oxford Handbook

    10/13

    101

    642

    V O N I";

    sola.fi

    A 1:1;101.11.

    iC CCM-

    (TY::

    healing

    alinicots

    c . ' 0 r : + 1 1 1 .

    1

    Ind :Imlay of

    u^ or tileologic.1 -sues

    if. ,1 ;ve intel ice-

    *);:ta.:.les to ,:t.it1Ci.1

    1:.

    ng

    ,k i10011

    ,

    111111:31t 1r

    C

    C

    1

    , ;11 ill:: Asia

    C111,1 j1alge (10''.11:11.SCUS

    ea71

    ,

    explains, among other things, God's wi.a. purposes in tbe creation of lie diverse phe-

    nomena of this world (Holtzman 2009: /09-10, 216-17; Boni and I lollztnan 2010: 25-6).

    TwO of ffin al-Qay

    yim's later books, written after 1345, are among the fullest treatments

    of their respective theological topics in the Islamic tradition. Shifcil al-`ald

    fleshes out

    the contours of Ibn Taymiyya's theodicy at great length. The first half elaborates God's

    determination and creation of all things, and it explains that, while God creates human

    acts, humans are the agents of their acts and therefore responsible for their deeds. The

    second half of the book argues that God creates all things for wise purposes in a causal

    sense. Evils are in fact good in view of God's wise purposes in creating them, and pure

    evil does not exist. Ibn al-Qayyim then outlines, in detail far exceeding anything found

    in Ilan Tayrniyya, the wise purposes that God has in creating everything from poisons to

    disobedience, and even Iblis (Perho 2001; Hoover 2010b).

    The second work, Ibn. al-Qayyim's

    al-,Sawariq al-mursala,

    is a massive refutation of

    the presuppositions underlying

    Kaldm

    metaphorical reinterpretation. Only the first

    half of the work is extant, and resort must be made to the abridgement

    Mukhtasar al-

    sawa`iq al-mursala

    of Shams al-Din b. al-Mawsili (d. 774/1372) to gain a sense of the

    whole. Writing along Taymiyya.n lines, Ibn al-Qayyim denies that reason and revelation

    ever contradict in the interpretation of God's attributes. I le attacks the

    Kalam

    notion

    of metaphor

    (majaz)

    at great length and defends the reliability of traditions providing

    information about God's attributes (Qaclhi 2010).

    IHanbali theology in the centuries following Ibn Qayyim al-Jawziyya has not been

    studied carefully (for surveys, see Laoust 1939: 493-540; Laoust 196o-2004), but it

    appears that Ibn Taymiyya's thought was not highly influential within the school, at

    least not until the Taymiyyan-inspired revivalism of the nineteenth century in Iraq,

    Syria, and Egypt. Even in his own day, Ibn Taymiyya's circle of students was small (Bori

    2010), and Lianbalis have never embraced his theology as school doctrine. However,

    Ibn Taytniyya's ideas did find their best-known pre-modern advocate in Ibn 'Abd al-

    Wahhab (d. 1206/1792), a Hanball scholar in central Arabia.

    'Taking his cue from Ibn 'Paymiyya, Ibn 'Abd al-Wahhab drew a distinction between

    taw*/ al-ruhubiyya,

    the affirmation that God is the sole creator of the world, and

    tawhid al-ulithlyya

    or

    tawhid alitbada,

    the exclusive devotion of worship and service

    ''..d according to the divine law. Ibn 'Abd al-Wahhab likewise gave priority to the

    ethical/legal tawhid al- ulithiyya

    over the mere confession of God as Creator in

    taw,i)id

    al-rububiyya, and he narrowed the scope of

    tawhid al-tillthiyya to exclude a wide

    range of popular practices such as saint veneration, tomb visitation, and magic. lbo

    Niad

    was .:darr.a;u

    pi :

    ictices had to be

    (:iti:

    ) Ind k:radi

    ,

    :at?1, ,uld lie

    ,.Iligneci

    with the ce-ziral

    lbian em;

    .

    ,)

    h*

    1

    ctiLJgical i-zion into practi,

    throtio'n :619.

    :fl ry. T}

    :4

    -

    , 1:di ...t:110, the modern :tate

    the

    os been Ills rLm icnt 41 in spreadino

    %:',)1117;i1) far beyond. :is lior,Tars, especially in lie

    ,

    u:s 1999).

    BIBLIOGRAPHY

    _

    'Abd al-Qadir al-Jilani (1995).

    Sufficient Provision for Seekers of the Pith

    Al-Chunya

    Taffy al-Haqq).

    Trans. M. Holland. 5 vols. Houston: Al-

    P,:b1 Mg.

    `Abd al-)adir al-Jilani (1999).

    Al-Ghunya

    uriq al-haqq.

    Ed, 1::11:1 r-js ai-Harastani. 2

    vols. Beirut: Dar

    Abrahamov, B. (1995). "The bi-la kayfa Doctrine and its Foundations in Islamic licology.

    Arabica 42:365-79.

    Abu va

    .

    la Ibn al-Farm` (1974).

    Kitab al- mu`tarnad ji usal al-din.

    Ed. Wadi Z. Haddad.

    Beirut: Dar el-machreq.

    Abit Ya'1,1 1bn al- Farra (1989-9oa).

    11)4 al-ta'wilat li-akhbar al-sitat.

    Ed. Abii 'Abd Allah

    Muhammad b. Hamad al-Hammild al-Najdi. Kuwait: Maktabat Dar al- 'Juan'. al-Dhahabi.

    Abil tali Ibn al-Farra' (1989-9ob).

    Masall al-iman.

    Ed. Saud

    'Alit' aljAziz Khalaf.

    Riyadh: Dar al

    2

    asima.

    Ahmad

    Hanbal (attrib.) (1973).

    Al-Radd

    a-l-jo;a

    airo: al-Matba'a

    al-salafiyya wa-maktabatuha.

    'Ali, 'Abdullah bin Fl amid (trans.) (2006).

    Abd al-.Rahrnan Ibn atlawzi: The Attributes of God.

    Bristol, UK: Amal Press.

    d-A.nsari al-liarawi, 'Abd Allah (1998).

    DilaMM

    al-kalam wa-ahlih, I 1.

    abir 'Abd Allah

    b. Muhammad b. 'Uthinan al-Ansari. 5 vols. Medina: Maktabal al4;:iuraba' al-Athariyya.

    I, J. N. (1979).

    Love Theory in Later ,Hanbalite Islam.

    Albany, NY: :31.' N Prcss.

    C. (201o). 'Ibn `Taymiyya wa-jama'tuhu: Authority, ColAL.t IA Consensus in Ibis

    Ta.ymiyya's Circle In Y. Rapoport and S. Ahmed (eds.),

    Ibn

    nd His Times,

    Karachi: Oxford University Press, 23-52.

    iori, C., and L. Holtzman (2010), 'A Scholar in the Shadow ;

    Jod 1.-loltzman (eds.),

    A Scholar in the Shadow: Essays in the Legal and Theological Mc

    /

    /

    ^

    V' .1`'*' al-

    Cawziyyah. Oriente Moderno

    monograph series, 90/1: 13-44.

    :ook, M. (2000).

    Commanding Right and Forbidding Wron

    ,-

    oagia

    (...:,imbrisige: Cambridge University Press.

    -

    .Aber, H. (1994). 'The Quran as a "Shibboleth" of Varying Conecrtl, .-,:15,

    ,

    Jr0-:,,

    ,

    A ath

    Century Hanbalite-Ash'arite Discussion and its Theological

    in :II,' Protocol

    ibn

    Qudama

    Israel Oriental Studies

    14: 249-95.

    Gimarct,

    (1977).'Theories de l'acte humain dans l'ecolebanbalite.

    o{ B. (2009).

    Shan.,i: Thcory, Practice, Tr s

    tions.

    .:iiiversity

    Press.

  • 7/26/2019 Hanbali Theology in the Oxford Handbook

    11/13

    P

    ;;::0

    ? .'vya

    10

    a.

    stina. stajtf,..i

    J

    11

    644

    ION HOOVER

    Theodicy

    pr:snisin.

    ;.3-...r.. 1.

    1. ,

    ..% .tr, by His Will cud

    yis ; ncology ot a Personal

    ,iid it)1.

    uCie Voluntary Attributes:

    In Y. Rapoport al S. Ahmed (eds.), Ibn

    ;: ,

    I i i J a a ;

    1,HICS. Karachi: Oxford University Press,

    55-77.

    1.))'

    God's Wise Purposes in Creating flails: Ihn Qayynn al-Gawziyyah's

    ,f

    E:ames and Ali rj LCIT.11: ' ' ' . In C. Burl and L. Ho l tzman (eds. ) ,

    A Scholar in the

    I

    .:.s.rys in the Legal and

    hought ofthu

    s ;

    at4 rowziyyah. Oriente

    [no fionograph series, 90/1:113 14,

    Abu 1.-Husayn MuhammaJ..1 (1952).

    Tabaqat

    :d. Muhammad klamid

    Cairo: Ma tba

    jat al-sunna al-mulaammadiyya.

    k a

    tia I .p;8). il

    ProfOssio.::

    oi

    crIbn Batta [al-l/inc if ju.;11,,il.

    Ed. and trans. FL Laoust.

    ),onascus: Institut irau iS ii Damas.

    lbr, (1990.

    Dap/H&c/1a: -Ws/thin bi-akdff al

    ,,,

    l

    af. Amman: Dar

    al Lia;:i al: Nlawawi.

    'hi

    (2.,:o1). A Mc:Ili -

    I.:it Cr,

    tique of Anthroponlorphiou

    sk.h

    r t

    , 7 ( 1

    A i.t

    .,1:cal

    Edition of ,ne AJ -abic Text with Translat i

    ,

    o.

    Swxrtz.

    Jim - iawd L006).

    The Ai; ributes

    ,

    Tod (Dar Shubah Al-Tasidalt

    Al)(1 ,

    itlah

    bin 1:larnid Ali. It isi.01, UK: Amal Press.

    lbn Qa:y jtn al-Jawziyya (1987-8).

    Kitab al-sawa`iti al- Innrsala

    a 1-mu

    Ed. 'Ali b..Muharnmad

    Allah. 4 vols. RE,

    !lir Ii Asima.

    Ibn Qayyim. al-Eawzayya (2004).

    Mukhtasar al saw.i i ii oeursata

    i

    mu`attila.

    Abridgement Muhammad b.

    Al-li,isau b. 'Abd al-Rahman al-

    `Alawi. Riyadh: Maktabat adwa

    j

    atsalaf.

    Ibn Qayyim al-Jawziyya (2007).

    Al-Kajiyya al-shajiyya ji 1-inti

    .

    ar

    l-najiyya.

    Ed.

    Muhammad b. Abd al-Rahman al

    2

    Arifi eta ,

    4

    vols. Mecca: Dar A/am

    al-Jawziyya (2008).

    Shifa'

    nasa al-qader'wa-l-qaciar wa-l-hikma wa-I-

    1,11d Ed. Ahmad b. Salila b. Al al-Sam

    d

    ani and All b. Muhammad h. `Abd Allah al-dAjlan.

    3

    101s. Ilir

    adh: .Dar

    Ibn :,jayyitn al-Jawziyya (2010-11). mifikaij

    dar al-sdada.

    Ed, Abd al-.Ralatnan b. Hasan

    b. Utid. 3 outs. Mecca: Dar 'Adam al-fawald.

    lb a 0110,Ain :962).

    Ibn.Qudarnds Censure of Speculative Theology

    riltlarfrn al-ruazarl. Ed. and

    tams. 1. Makdisi. London: Lii,r.ac.

    "111

    iyya (1979-83).

    Dar

    a al-naql.

    Ed. Muhammad P. had Udlifli. ii vols.

    Riyadh: lamfat

    NI ulaaminad b. Sa`fid al- slInicv; a.

    ::iyijyya (1986).

    Minha) ai.sunna al-nabawiyya I. lu,;.l 1,aialti al

    lQarlarlyva. Id

    1

    ,

    ..:3;w1n3

    ashad Salim. 9 vols. Riyadh: Jami`at itl-Imain Muhammad b. Su'fiti

    ff:irr.:11:

    J fr

    .

    jte t

    1.

    )57). 'Les Premieres P

    ,

    :dcssions de thi

    , irbalitc-d

    3:

    aoust, 11, (1958).

    La Profession de foi

    atta.

    Da1113.A:US:.Instilut

    de Damas,

    irtust, it.

    (i96o-

    zoo4).`Hantibilal

    In

    .Encyclopaedia of Islam.

    New edo

    462.

    .. adel:mg, W. (1974). 'The Origins of the Controversy Concerning ill.: Cia:at,...al

    of he

    Koran:

    j' arral (ed.),

    Orient:lint hispanica.

    Leidina: Brill,

    504-25 [!1r':r. i W.

    Madelung,

    . - :./lo ,

    4s and Sects in Al..diTal Is/un, Ton.

    on... Viriorum

    (;. (1962).

    Ibn Qudarnds l

    iour of Speculative Theology. 1 01, 1,,,n

    ;

    k11;si, G. (1962-3). Ash'ari and the Ash`arites in Islamic Religious listtirv:

    Islamica

    1 .

    .7: 37-80

    and 18: 19-39 [Repr. in 0. Makdisi,

    Religion, Law and I

    1,H

    Thire, UK: Variorum, 199i, Part IJ.

    1`.1:1ixdis i , G. (1 963) .

    /1:n

    11 iil

    et ta resurgence de l'Islam traditionalist:

    ).:mascus:

    Ins:Mut Francais de Damas.

    G. (1973). "The Sunni Revival: In D. S. Richards (..8.1.)',: ,

    11s Cord: I

    .

    assirer,155-68.

    (

    979). The Hanbali School and Siifistn:

    flo1,170 :le 11

    o;

    .

    poiola de

    (it,

    ::,i/Istas

    15: 115-26 [Repr. in C. Makdisi,

    Rhgioo, Law

    W fi

    I ilop:hire, UK: Variorum, 1991, Part V].

    0.11)8').

    isnon: In M. 1.. Swart.:

    I:.1.1Ntudics

    ford

    t,iiersity Press, 216-64.

    997). Ibn 'Agit:

    nd Cairarc in 1

    ,

    . - ; . s i c a l

    i \Jai oudi, A, H. (2006).

    The 1..litilba/rSchool.ij

    Lite

    anil

    Ad; her , C. (1997).

    The Formation of the Stow;

    N

    3'.

    'U if In,

    I

    . . .Kt. ): B rill..

    H. bet t, C. (2006). Ahmad

    Ibn 1Ianbal.

    Oxford:

    14.:ih rt, C. (2011). "`Cod

    rested Adam in His image- .

    I- i--24.

    :` icnsTl: C. (2012), 41 Ijafbaharf.

    Encyclopaedia of

    11. Ldit

    s1 bv

    i tenis Matringe. John Nawas, Everett Rowson, Brill Online, 2013. I

    , ersil

    is August 2013 .littp://referenceworks.brillonline.com/entries/c-

    yclor:i,01.1 -.if slam-3/

    al-barbahari-001\1_22944>

    M idiot, J.

    R.(1994).

    Ibn Tayrniyya: I ...tire a

    ;:e

    l'Universite Catholique de List:vain.

    hot, Y. I.

    Mamnik lieolop,jan's ( joninh ithiry on Ay;

    d.Uif, Itililv)ya:

    .3

    Translation of a Pact oi

    dr 1 of

    lbn Tayrn,) v,:.

    jraroduction,

    ).:;:t

    and :):4

    ,pendices:kn.:71,1,f

    :::::(11cs 14: 149-203 (Pitri'

    I 3, 309-63

    I: J.

    ls.

    10

    ,1: H.LIC,'..f.,

    4

    .

  • 7/26/2019 Hanbali Theology in the Oxford Handbook

    12/13

    `Th,Taytniyya's

    , , v ,

    1:'11.1CS

    he

    ie.apo:

    ,

    ort

    and S. Allmed

    K anh i 1i;

    1

    .

    11H

    Criiic1srn

    , I 1(i3

    Thnes.

    .;iiv

    Pr r8 i

    `;9).I I .

    .

    o

    ViON,on Predestination:

    C irisi

    . q i

    cl

    utions 12

    :

    61-.70.

    (196o-zoo4). "orahhisibiyya: In

    Ettcyclopuerna

    .,

    L1 1 . New edn., xi. 39-45.

    es, E. (n9). 'The Walihd5iyya and Sufism in the Eighteekith Century: In F. de Jong and B.

    Radtke (eds.),

    Islamic Mysticism Contested: Thirteen Centuries of Controversies and Polemics.

    Leiden: Brill, 145-61.

    Qadhi, Y. (2010).

    -

    The Unleashed Thunderbolts" of Ibn Qayyim al-Ciawziyyah: An

    Introductory Essay: In C. Bori and L. Holtzman (eds.),

    A Scholar in the Shadow: Essays in the

    Legal and Theological Thought of Ibn Qayyim al-Cawziyyah. Oriente Moderno monograph

    series, 90/i: 135-49.

    Sabari, S. (1981). Mouvements populaires

    a Bagdad a repoque 'abbaside, ixe-xie siecies.

    Maisonneuve.

    al-Sarhan, S. S. (2011). 'Early Muslim Traditionalism: A Critical Study of the Works and

    Political Theology of Ahmad Ibn Hanbal: Doctoral dissertation, University of Exeter.

    Seale, M. S. (1964).

    Muslim 'Theology: A Study of Origms with Reference to the Church Fathers.

    London: Luzac.

    Shihadeh, A. (2006). "three Apologetic Stances in

    Theological Cognitivism,

    Noncognitivism, and a Proof of Prophecy from Scriptural Contradiction'.

    Journal of

    Qur'anic Studies

    8:1-23.

    Swartz, M. (2002).

    A Medieval Critique of Anthropomorphism: Ibn al-,rawzi: kit ab .Akhbar

    as-Sifat. A

    Critical El/lion of the Arabic Text with Tran.lation, Intp.;duction and Notes.

    Leiden: Brill.

    Tiff', Najm al-Din (2002). Al-Isharat

    ra l-mabaljith al-usidiyya.

    Ed. Abu

    `Asim

    Hasan b, 'Abbas b. Qutb. 3 vols. Cairo: al-Fa:ray al-haditha.

    Tan, Najm al-Din (2005).

    Dar' al-qawl al-qablh

    a al-taqbfit, Ed. Ayman Shihada.

    Riyadh: Markaz

    F:aysal.

    Vshanoff, D. R. (2011). The Formation

    o f Islamic Hermeneutics: How Sunni Legal Theorists

    Imagined a Revealed Law.

    New Haven: American Oriental Society.

    Wa tt , W. M .

    (1 9 9 4) .

    Islamic Creeds,

    Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Williams, W. (2002). 'Aspects of the Creed of Imam Ahmad Ibn Hanbal: A Study of

    Anthropomorphism in Early Islamic Discourse:

    International Journal of Middle East Studies

    34: 441-63.

  • 7/26/2019 Hanbali Theology in the Oxford Handbook

    13/13

    THE OXFORD HAND KOOK OF

    ISL M IC

    THEOLOGY

    Edtedby

    SABINE SCHMIDTKE

    2_ ?

    OXFORD

    UNIVERSITY PRESS