FROESE -...

3
     C     O     M     P     U     T     A     T     I     O     N     A     L     S     Y     N     T     H     E     S     I     S     I     N     E     N     A     C     T     I     V     E     C     O     G     N     I     T     I     V     E     S     C     I     E     N     C     E 86  CONSTRUCTIVIST FOUNDATION . , N° David Vernon is a Professor of Informatics at the University of Skövde, Sweden. He works on cognitive systems and is particularly interested in modeling autonomy. Over the past 34 years, he has held positions at Westinghouse Electric, Trinity College Dublin, the European Commission, the National University of Ireland, Maynooth, Science Foundation Ireland, and Khalifa University, UAE. Tool-use Leads to Bodily Extension, but not Bodily Incorporation: The Limits of Mind-as-it-could-be? Tom Froese Universidad Nacional Autónoma de México t.froese/at/gmail.com > Upshot Sato and colleagues make use of an innovative method that com- bines robotics modeling and psycho- logical experimentation to investigate how tool use aects our living and lived embodiment. I situate their approach in a general shift from robotics to human- computer interface studies in enactive cognitive science, and speculate about the necessary conditions for the bodily incorporation of tools. Putting subjectivity back into the sensorimotor loop « 1 » Enactive cognitive science (ECS) is founded on the theory that life and mind are integrated within a process of sense- making (ompson 2007). Following its rst extensive presentation by Francisco Varela, Evan ompson and Eleanor Rosch (1991), the paradigm of enaction was oen loosely grouped with embodied, sensori- motor, and dynamical approaches to cog- nition, while its explicit phenomenological commitments were mostly ignored. And whereas these latter approaches rapidly led to the development of new styles of doing cognitive science and robotics (Wheeler 2005; Clark 2008; Kelso 1995), specically enactive research continues to face unique challenges today. For if we accept that cog- nition is a form of sense-making, and that sense-making is the generation and appre- ciation of meaning from a point of view, then ECS – in contrast to most science and engineering methods – has to place living and lived subjectivity at the center of all its endeavors (Froese 2011). « 2 » ere are therefore some unique methodological challenges for ECS. While embodied and dynamical approaches can be satised with AI and robotics to do a lot of their theoretical work (e.g., Pfeifer & Scheier 1999; Beer 2000), enactive AI is specically confronted by the profound problem of how to design a sense-maker  – something for which we still lack theo- retical and practical knowledge (Froese & Ziemke 2009). Given this impasse, it was to be expected that ECS would shi its meth- odological focus from constructing and analyzing articial agents to phenomeno- logical investigations of human experience (Froese 2007). However, there is still plenty of room for innovative use of technology. « 3 » One of the most resourceful de-  velopments in this direction is a hybrid methodology that retains the idea of con- structing new technical systems, but for the purpose of investigating how tool use – via its eects on our living embodiment – mod- ulates our lived experience (Froese, Suzuki, Ogai & Ikegami 2012). In analogy with arti- cial life’s objective to use technology to ex- plore life-as-it-could-be, we can refer to this eld as “articial embodiment” and dene its aim as mapping out the space of “mind- as-it-could-be.” « 4 » e authors of the present tar- get article, Yuki Sato, Hiroyuki Iizuka, and Takashi Ikegami, make a valuable contri- bution to this cross-disciplinary method by investigating the phenomenon of ex- tended embodiment – currently a hot topic (ompson & Stapleton 2009) – by bringing together insights from both robotics mod- eling and psychological experimentation. ey thereby join a new generation of enac- tive researchers who are just as interested in the dynamics of articial agents as they are in the sense-making of humans, oen relat- ing these two areas in a mutually inform- ing manner by making use of custom-built human-computer interfaces (e.g., Rohde 2010; Iizuka, Ando & Maeda 2009; Suzuki, Wakisaka & Fujii 2012; Suzuki, Garnkel, Critchley & Seth, in press). In the following, I situate the work by Sato et al. in this wider context. I begin by clarifying their method, and conclude by deriving a new working hypothesis from their results. Tool use as a method to investigate mind-as-it-could-be « 5 » While conducting a study of the experiential eects of using a sensorimo- tor substitution device (Froese, McGann, Bigge, Spiers & Seth 2012), I started work- ing out a basic methodological scheme for an enactive approach to consciousness re- search based on human-computer interfac- es (HCI). is scheme is nicely illustrated by the series of psychological experiments by Sato and colleagues (Figure 1). « 6 » We can see this scheme at work in the study by Sato et al. as follows. First, they completed the methodological cycle in the domain of articial life. ey synthesized an evolutionary robotics model, analyzed its emergent dynamics, and formulated a hypothesis, i.e., that tool-based extension of bodily sensitivity is correlated with the regularity of the user’s movements (§26). To test this hypothesis of lived bodily extension properly, they then conducted a psychologi- cal experiment on users’ experience. ey   synthesized a simplied real version of the single windmill tool to be used with a stick,   allowed the participants to become skilled users,   analyzed the resulting user experience – albeit measured indirectly via objective success, and   received a partial conrmation of their hypothesis. « 7 » ey then embarked on the meth- odological cycle again. ey   constructed a more accurate version of the double-windmill tool,   allowed participants to become su- ciently skilled,   assessed their experience, and   formulated a novel hypothesis. More specically, in contrast to their ini- tial assumption, they found that objective success at the task is not an appropriate in- direct measur e of the lived experience of bod- ily extension. Rather, strong and continuous coupling between user and tool seems to be more important to shiing their attention away from the tool (§37). is hypothesis

Transcript of FROESE -...

  • CO

    MP

    UTA

    TIO

    NAL

    SYN

    THES

    IS I

    N E

    NAC

    TIVE

    CO

    GN

    ITIV

    E SC

    IEN

    CE

    86

    ConStRuCtIVISt FoundatIons vol. 9, n1

    David Vernon is a Professor of Informatics at

    the University of Skvde, Sweden. He works on

    cognitive systems and is particularly interested

    in modeling autonomy. Over the past 34 years, he

    has held positions at Westinghouse Electric, Trinity

    College Dublin, the European Commission, the

    National University of Ireland, Maynooth, Science

    Foundation Ireland, and Khalifa University, UAE.

    Tool-use Leads to Bodily

    Extension, but not Bodily

    Incorporation: The Limits

    of Mind-as-it-could-be?

    Tom FroeseUniversidad Nacional Autnoma de Mxico t.froese/at/gmail.com> Upshot Sato and colleagues make use of an innovative method that com-bines robotics modeling and psycho-logical experimentation to investigate how tool use afects our living and lived embodiment. I situate their approach in a general shift from robotics to human-computer interface studies in enactive cognitive science, and speculate about the necessary conditions for the bodily incorporation of tools.

    Putting subjectivity back into the sensorimotor loop 1 Enactive cognitive science (ECS)

    is founded on the theory that life and mind

    are integrated within a process of sense-

    making (hompson 2007). Following its

    irst extensive presentation by Francisco

    Varela, Evan hompson and Eleanor Rosch

    (1991), the paradigm of enaction was oten

    loosely grouped with embodied, sensori-

    motor, and dynamical approaches to cog-

    nition, while its explicit phenomenological

    commitments were mostly ignored. and

    whereas these latter approaches rapidly led

    to the development of new styles of doing

    cognitive science and robotics (Wheeler

    2005; Clark 2008; Kelso 1995), speciically

    enactive research continues to face unique

    challenges today. For if we accept that cog-

    nition is a form of sense-making, and that

    sense-making is the generation and appre-

    ciation of meaning from a point of view,

    then ECS in contrast to most science and

    engineering methods has to place living

    and lived subjectivity at the center of all its

    endeavors (Froese 2011). 2 here are therefore some unique

    methodological challenges for ECS. While

    embodied and dynamical approaches can

    be satisied with aI and robotics to do a

    lot of their theoretical work (e.g., Pfeifer

    & Scheier 1999; Beer 2000), enactive aI

    is speciically confronted by the profound

    problem of how to design a sense-maker

    something for which we still lack theo-

    retical and practical knowledge (Froese &

    Ziemke 2009). Given this impasse, it was to

    be expected that ECS would shit its meth-

    odological focus from constructing and

    analyzing artiicial agents to phenomeno-

    logical investigations of human experience

    (Froese 2007). However, there is still plenty

    of room for innovative use of technology. 3 one of the most resourceful de-

    velopments in this direction is a hybrid

    methodology that retains the idea of con-

    structing new technical systems, but for the

    purpose of investigating how tool use via

    its efects on our living embodiment mod-

    ulates our lived experience (Froese, Suzuki,

    ogai & Ikegami 2012). In analogy with arti-

    icial lifes objective to use technology to ex-

    plore life-as-it-could-be, we can refer to this

    ield as artiicial embodiment and deine

    its aim as mapping out the space of mind-

    as-it-could-be. 4 he authors of the present tar-

    get article, Yuki Sato, Hiroyuki Iizuka, and

    takashi Ikegami, make a valuable contri-

    bution to this cross-disciplinary method

    by investigating the phenomenon of ex-

    tended embodiment currently a hot topic

    (hompson & Stapleton 2009) by bringing

    together insights from both robotics mod-

    eling and psychological experimentation.

    hey thereby join a new generation of enac-

    tive researchers who are just as interested in

    the dynamics of artiicial agents as they are

    in the sense-making of humans, oten relat-

    ing these two areas in a mutually inform-

    ing manner by making use of custom-built

    human-computer interfaces (e.g., Rohde

    2010; Iizuka, ando & Maeda 2009; Suzuki,

    Wakisaka & Fujii 2012; Suzuki, Garinkel,

    Critchley & Seth, in press). In the following,

    I situate the work by Sato et al. in this wider

    context. I begin by clarifying their method,

    and conclude by deriving a new working

    hypothesis from their results.

    Tool use as a method to investigate mind-as-it-could-be 5 While conducting a study of the

    experiential efects of using a sensorimo-

    tor substitution device (Froese, McGann,

    Bigge, Spiers & Seth 2012), I started work-

    ing out a basic methodological scheme for

    an enactive approach to consciousness re-

    search based on human-computer interfac-

    es (HCI). his scheme is nicely illustrated

    by the series of psychological experiments

    by Sato and colleagues (Figure1). 6 We can see this scheme at work in

    the study by Sato et al. as follows. First, they

    completed the methodological cycle in the

    domain of artiicial life. hey synthesized

    an evolutionary robotics model, analyzed

    its emergent dynamics, and formulated a

    hypothesis, i.e., that tool-based extension

    of bodily sensitivity is correlated with the

    regularity of the users movements (26). to

    test this hypothesis of lived bodily extension

    properly, they then conducted a psychologi-

    cal experiment on users experience. hey

    synthesized a simpliied real version of the single windmill tool to be used with

    a stick,

    allowed the participants to become skilled users,

    analyzed the resulting user experience albeit measured indirectly via objective

    success, and

    received a partial conirmation of their hypothesis. 7 hey then embarked on the meth-

    odological cycle again. hey

    constructed a more accurate version of the double-windmill tool,

    allowed participants to become sui-ciently skilled,

    assessed their experience, and formulated a novel hypothesis.

    More speciically, in contrast to their ini-

    tial assumption, they found that objective

    success at the task is not an appropriate in-

    direct measure of the lived experience of bod-

    ily extension. Rather, strong and continuous

    coupling between user and tool seems to be

    more important to shiting their attention

    away from the tool (37). his hypothesis

  • 87

    The Limits of Mind-as-it-could-be? Tom Froese

    Enactive Cognitive Science

    http://www.univie.ac.at/constructivism/journal/9/1/073.sato

    could not have been derived solely from

    the modeling study or just in terms of par-

    ticipants objective performance, thereby

    conirming the necessity of including irst-

    person phenomenological analysis in the

    enactive approach and in the science of con-

    sciousness more generally.1

    From bodily extension to bodily incorporation 8 Based on their new hypothesis,

    i.e., that the strength of coupling is expected

    to correlate with the strength of feeling bod-

    ily extension, Sato et al. propose to conduct

    future experiments in which the strength of

    coupling between user and tool is the pa-

    rameter to be manipulated (46). While it

    would be useful to conirm this expectation,

    I propose a more radical research agenda.

    9 When discussing how people ex-

    perience hand-held tools we must take care

    to distinguish several possibilities. as Sato

    et al. acknowledge (5), the user could be

    either focused on the tool as such, in which

    case they feel the tool in contact with their

    body, or they could be focused on the task,

    such that they perceive via the tool and

    tactile sensitivity is extended to where the

    tool makes contact with the objects being

    manipulated. Indeed, it is probably the po-

    tential for extended action, rather than con-

    stant physical contact per se, that constitutes

    the feeling of bodily extension (McGann,

    Froese, Bigge, Spiers & Seth 2011). 10 nevertheless, it is also evident

    that these tools are not experienced as a

    part of the living body, in the way that a

    hand is (and a prosthesis should be) felt. We

    therefore need to distinguish, following the

    proposal by Helena de Preester and Manos

    tsakiris (2009), between bodily extension

    and bodily incorporation. hey theorize

    that a pre-existing body model normatively

    constrains which kind of tools can become

    incorporated into the living body, namely

    those tools that it within the normal human

    body plan, such as successful prostheses.

    However, the results by Sato et al. hint at an-

    1 | a similar dissociation between objective

    performance and phenomenological report was

    found in a study of alterations in felt embodiment

    based on the rubber hand illusion (Rohde, di

    Luca & Ernst 2011), showing that the inding by

    Sato et al. is not an isolated case.

    other possibility, which is more in line with

    enactive thinking.

    11 he key results found by Sato et

    al. are twofold: (a) that the acquisition of

    skillful tool use is correlated with increases

    in coordinated movements, and (b) that the

    feeling of bodily extension via the tool ad-

    ditionally depends on strong continuous

    physical contact. his dependence on both

    physical and coordinated coupling makes

    sense, because the living body is a physically

    bounded whole of semi-autonomous parts

    (Varela 1991) that are linked by coordination

    dynamics (Kelso 1995). So why did the sub-

    jects not experience bodily incorporation? Is

    it because the tools did not it into the hu-

    man body model? I am not convinced by

    this response. to be sure, Sato et al.s sticks

    and windmills do not have direct counter-

    parts in our normal body morphology, but

    even the designers of the most advanced

    prostheses still face signiicant challenges

    (Kwok 2013). 12 I suggest that the answer has more

    to do with how the movements of the tool

    it with the intended actions of the subject.

    While the tip of a hand-held stick is ro-

    bustly coordinated with the movements of

    my hand (the two always move rigidly to-

    gether), my hand is adaptively coordinated

    with the actions of my arm and body (my

    ingers autonomously and correctly adjust

    their coniguration depending on whether I

    am reaching for my keys or my cofee cup).

    hese micro-actions are neither a purely

    mechanical process nor are they something

    that I intentionally do; they are context-sen-

    sitive behaviors situated in between these

    extremes (Beaton 2013: 302f). I therefore

    suggest that if a tool is to become fully incor-

    porated, its movements have to follow their

    own localized norms, and these norms must

    be in adaptive coordination with the norma-

    tive situation of the agent as a whole (Froese,

    in press). a step in the right direction might

    be to design anticipatory human-computer

    interfaces for which the tool-user relation

    resembles the coordination dynamics of a

    social interaction (Iizuka, ando & Maeda

    2009).

    Tom Froese completed his D.Phil. in cognitive

    science from the University of Sussex in 2009. He is

    currently a postdoctoral researcher at the National

    Autonomous University of Mexico. He investigates

    the relationship between life, mind and sociality

    using a variety of methods, including evolutionary

    robotics, systems theory, and phenomenology.

    Received: 16 october 2013

    accepted: 18 october 2013

    Emergence

    of experience

    Collection of data

    about characteristics

    of user experience

    Design of

    new human-computer

    interface (HCI)

    Interpretation of data

    according to theory

    of lived experience

    Acquisition of

    practical expertise

    in using the HCI

    Artificial

    Embodiment2

    Synthesis

    of interface1

    Analysis

    of experience3

    Generation

    of hypotheses4

    Figure 1: Methodological scheme proposed for a growing ield that, in analogy with the ield of artiicial life, we might call artiicial embodiment. In order to investigate a hypothesis about the embodied mind, a novel human-computer interface (HCI) is constructed with the speciic aim of modulating a users sensorimotor embodiment so as to enable the experimental manipulation of the users irst-person perspective. (Figure adapted from Froese, Suzuki, Ogai & Ikegami 2012).