Forming Philosophical Communities of Inquiry in Early Childhood Classrooms

29
DAVID KENNEDY FORMING PHILOSOPHICAL COMMUNITIES OF INQUIRY IN EARLY CHILDHOOD CLASSROOMS Published in Early Childhood Development and Care 120,1 (Fall 1996): 1-14. All rights reserved. A small group of second graders at the University of Chicago Children's School are engaged in a discussion. It has been instigated by Vivian Paley, a kindergarten teacher from the same school who is interested in what slightly older children think about a topic of great significance to her five-year olds--magic. Paley introduces the topic with a little piece of a story, followed by a question, and it goes from there: Teacher:A kindergarten boy once told the class he intended to become a mother lion when he grew up. He said he would do this by practicing magic. Thalia:Magic doesn't make things that people want to be. Teacher:Is there any use for magic at all? Thalia:There are magic tricks. You can learn tricks. Harry:Well, he could put on a disguise and then there could be a tape recorder beside him of a lion and people would think that's a real lion. Thalia:But that would still be a trick. Stuart:Like the magic set my sister gave me. The balls don't really disappear. They're in the cups all the time. Harry:The only kind of magic there really is is superhuman strength. Now that is really true. Allan:If you know how to do a magician's things, you do have to keep practicing until you know how to do it real good. Thalia:But it's still just tricks, Allan.

Transcript of Forming Philosophical Communities of Inquiry in Early Childhood Classrooms

DAVID KENNEDY FORMING PHILOSOPHICAL COMMUNITIES OF INQUIRY IN EARLY CHILDHOOD CLASSROOMS Published in Early Childhood Development and Care 120,1 (Fall 1996): 1-14. All rights reserved. A small group of second graders at the University of Chicago Children's School are engaged in a discussion. It has been instigated by Vivian Paley, a kindergarten teacher from the same school who is interested in what slightly older children think about a topic of great significance to her five-year olds--magic. Paley introduces the topic with a little piece of a story, followed by a question, and it goes from there: Teacher:A kindergarten boy once told the class he intended to become a mother lion when he grew up. He said he would do this by practicing magic. Thalia:Magic doesn't make things that people want to be. Teacher:Is there any use for magic at all? Thalia:There are magic tricks. You can learn tricks. Harry:Well, he could put on a disguise and then there could be a tape recorder beside him of a lion and people would think that's a real lion. Thalia:But that would still be a trick. Stuart:Like the magic set my sister gave me. The balls don't really disappear. They're in the cups all the time. Harry:The only kind of magic there really is is superhuman strength. Now that is really true. Allan:If you know how to do a magician's things, you do have to keep practicing until you know how to do it real good. Thalia:But it's still just tricks, Allan. Allan:Everything isn't tricks, Thalia. Teacher:Even if you practiced for years, could you learn to become an animal? Allan:No, but maybe something else. Stuart:My friend does this--it's not magic, but it's like magic. Like once he believed so hard his father would give him something and when that day came his father really gave him what he believed. Teacher:Is that like wishing? Stuart:No. He was just believing in his mind that his father would give him something.

FORMING COMMUNITIES OF INQUIRY IN EARLY CHILDHOOD CLASSROOMS KENNEDY

2

John:That boy in your class. It was just something he really wanted it to happen but it couldn't happen. It was a fantasy. Harry:Scientists could work hard and make up a formula to make someone into a lion. Thalia:The only kind of magic I've heard of are miracles. Teacher:Is that something like Stuart's friend believing in something real hard? Thalia:A little different. Like you're wishing something will happen but you know it won't and all of a sudden it happens. Sally:I think there might be a potion some day. I don't think it could happen. I mean a potion to make someone a lion. But it might happen. Harry:They might be able to not make him into a lion but make him look like a lion with all the doctors working hard to do it. Sally:You mean to look like a lion but not talking like a lion. Not roaring or anything. But it wouldn't be magic. It'd be something to do with science. (Paley, 1981, pp. 198-200) Within the short period of this transcribed discussion, and with the help of Paley's skilled conversational midwifery, these students have introduced and examined four definitions of magic. There are magic "tricks" which depend on sleight of hand; "superhuman strength"; bringing things about by "believing in [one's] mind"; miracles; and transformations brought about by scientific technology. In the course of the exploration the issue of "real" magic versus the art of illusion is considered, as well as the difference between magic and science. There is a lot of thinking going on in this conversation. Paley's chief interest here is in the gradual transformation of the kindergartners almost willful belief in magical solutions to life's goals and problems, towards the more nuanced view of the seven year old. A close look at the form of the conversation reveals that this gradual social and personal process is being carried along by a powerful undergirding structure: the forms of thinking and talking which are commonly called "critical thinking skills." In this brief glimpse of young children thinking collaboratively, we find them classifying and categorizing, formulating hypotheses, making generalizations, providing instances and illustrations, working with criteria, working with consistency and contradiction, grasping part-whole connections, predicting consequences, and defining terms, to name a handful of skills traditionally identified as "critical" (Lipman, 1991). Members of the group are also building on each other's ideas, correcting their own ideas through dialogue, and working hard to produce a

FORMING COMMUNITIES OF INQUIRY IN EARLY CHILDHOOD CLASSROOMS KENNEDY

2

warrantable judgment about the phenomenon of magic. These seven-year olds did not arrive at a definitive judgment about magic in one conversation, and we don't know if or how their discussions continued. But this brief transcript allows us a clear and compelling glimpse into the spontaneous and emergent characteristics of a philosophical community of inquiry among young children. WHAT IS COMMUNITY OF INQUIRY? A community of inquiry describes any group of people who communicate together regularly, and who take it as their common project to make a critical and/or creative inquiry into something: to find out how things work, to discover the meaning in things, to make judgments about something important to them--in short, to create knowledge together. Scientists working on the same kinds of problems form communities of inquiry, as do artists who follow each other's work and share influences. Plato's Academy was a philosophical community of inquiry, and the salons of 18th century France were literary ones. Any classroom, in that it is a group of people brought together to inquire in a specific field of study, represents a potential community of inquiry. But what distinguishes a classroom that is a community of inquiry from one that is not? The distinction begins with our idea of how knowledge is generated and acquired. Community of inquiry is associated with two ideas of knowledge. One is that knowledge is communally constructed through the process of dialogue between persons. One person does not bring it and deliver it to the whole group; rather, it grows through the interaction of group members. The other is that it is emergent. It is never complete. No individual or group will ever have the whole picture. When we apply these ideas to the classroom, we get a model of the class as a working group in which each individual contributes in some way to the knowledge being created there, and each individual benefits from the knowledge of the whole group. AN EARLY CHILDHOOD COMMUNITY OF INQUIRY Now imagine a group of people who spend a large part of every day together surrounded by interesting tools, models and model-making materials, all manner of arts and crafts materials, the world's finest literature, intriguing costumes, musical instruments, gymnastic equipment, and so forth. Imagine that group of people to have an almost boundless energy, a strong propensity for playful exploration through both words and action, and a tremendous hunger for knowledge. What we are imagining is a developmentally appropriate early childhood classroom. In such a community, each individual in the group is, to a greater or lesser degree, in a process of co-

FORMING COMMUNITIES OF INQUIRY IN EARLY CHILDHOOD CLASSROOMS KENNEDY

2

construction of knowledge with each other individual, and each individual is in a continual process of internalizing the characteristic knowledge, skills, and dispositions of other individuals, and of the group as a whole. Those three young children building a city in the block area are busy replicating the social world through modeling its built environment, so they could be said to engaged in sociological inquiry. But unit blocks can also be the vehicle of architectural as well as mathematical inquiry. The four children acting out a story theme in the dramatic play area are also involved in sociological inquiry, but in a different modality. They are thinking verbally, kinesthetically, and interpersonally, where the children in the block area are emphasizing the spatial and the logical mathematical (Gardner, 1985, Krichevsky, 1992). The child painting in bold strokes of line and color in the art area is involved in an inquiry into art, the child at the sand table into physics, but both of their inquiries could have social science or literary dimensions as well. The child painting could be depicting her family, or a character from a book; the child at the sand table could be working through the problems of familial conflict through representing "monsters" or dinosaurs locked in combat. Thus there are many overlapping forms of inquiry going on in an active early childhood classroom, in different modalities and combinations of modalities, and in different representational forms--or, to use Malaguzzi's (1987) term, "languages." The teacher circulates, interacting with individuals and small groups. She is in dialogue with each child at his or her particular developmental level, and works tirelessly to promote and integrate the themes of inquiry she sees unfolding around her, to extend and enrich each inquiry, and to put these tireless inquirers into dialogue with each other. But is there one place where all of these active inquirers come together in one place and take up one inquiry in particular? The project method (Katz & Chard, 1991) is a teaching and learning process structure through which a theme for inquiry emerges from the interests of the group itself, and is pursued in a relatively systematic way by all or some of the group members. Then there are large and small group times, where events like reading and story telling, dramatizations and puppets shows, musical listening and playing, demonstrations and focussed exploration of materials, center the whole group in one shared experience. Then there is the planned group discussion. AN EARLY CHILDHOOD PHILOSOPHICAL COMMUNITY OF INQUIRY Imagine that the signal for cleanup is given, and afterwards, children assemble for circle time. During this period the teacher, who is an expert storyteller, tells a tale using two identical felt-board figures. It is a somewhat zany, magical story, about a

FORMING COMMUNITIES OF INQUIRY IN EARLY CHILDHOOD CLASSROOMS KENNEDY

2

boy whose father is an inventor, and constructs a robot who looks and talks and walks and behaves exactly like his son, and the troubles that everyone has telling them apart. The teacher follows her short tale with a lead off question--is the robot a person? When one child answers "No," the teacher asked her why not. Because he's a robot, is the answer. The teacher asks, what is the difference between a robot and a person? Another child chimes in, a person sleeps! But animals sleep too, says another child, because I have a hamster in a cage and he sleeps a lot! Are animals persons? queries the ever-alert teacher. No! is the chorused reply. So the teacher presses on: what can we find that just persons, only persons do or have? she asks. They have arms and legs! shouts an excited child; but almost immediately another child points out that some animals have arms and legs. A discussion ensues about whether animals have "all arms" or "all legs" or both. Monkeys are mentioned. The teacher asks whether there is anything else which only persons have or do. Talk! bursts out a young child. Do animals talk? asks the teacher. A chorus of yesses and no's. Seeing that she is in the yes chorus, the teacher asks a young child who seldom says much in these discussions to explain why she thinks that animals talk. And so on. By the end of the session, which could last anywhere from ten to thirty or more minutes, the group may have established--with helpful summaries by the teacher-one or more necessary conditions for calling someone (or thing!) a "person," or they may not have decided on any. In either case, the teacher summarizes, and promises they will talk about it again. She then suggests that some people may wish to draw and dictate the robot story, or one like it. Perhaps she also has some props in the dramatic play area which encourage playing stories with robots in them. For next week's discussion she may tell another story, she may pick a children's book--The Velveteen Rabbit (Williams, 1975), for example, or Pinnochio (Collodi, 1991), The Steadfast Tin Soldier (Andersen, 1953), or The Gingerbread Man (Hauge, 1973)--or tell a story with doll house figures and props, or act out a short skit with another teacher (Edwards, 1986). She may stick with persons as theme, or present something which suggests another topic. She may solicit direction from the group itself. The teacher in this classroom is conducting a philosophical community of inquiry. It deserves to be called "philosophical" for two reasons. First, because it is a kind of inquiry which focuses on the larger meaning of human experience--how our thoughts work, what is and what has to be, the nature of persons, how to define right and wrong, the good, the fair, the beautiful, and so on. It is a controlled, communal form of wondering about the "big questions." We are also justified in calling it

FORMING COMMUNITIES OF INQUIRY IN EARLY CHILDHOOD CLASSROOMS KENNEDY

2

philosophical because it is, with the help of the teacher-facilitator, a continual process of exploring the conditions of knowledge. Can we give reasons for what we think? Are there good reasons and not so good reasons, and how do we determine? How do we know what we know--what "person" means, for example? What sort of evidence is necessary to make a claim that so and so or such and such is a person, and what would it take to discount it? Philosophy has to do with how we know what we know, and what we mean when we say something is "true" or not. DISPOSITIONS AND SKILLS OF A PHILOSOPHICAL COMMUNITY OF INQUIRY The kind of thinking, talking, and feeling which is going on in this discussion circle is associated with verbal, logical-mathematical, and personal modalities, or intelligences (Gardner 1985). Through their own participation and the teacher's skilled facilitation, young children are practicing dispositions like valuing taking turns, feeling responsible for giving reasons and offering evidence for one's beliefs, determining to respect persons even if we disagree with their ideas, and wanting to build on each other's ideas. The skills of philosophical community of inquiry are those usually associated with critical thinking, such as making generalizations and then evaluating them through offering and evaluating confirming or disconfirming examples, using criteria to guide our judgments (Lipman, 1988a). In the example above, the child who bursts out Talk! when the teacher asks what only persons do, is making a generalization which could be more formally state as the proposition "All persons talk." As like as not, this proposition may immediately bring to the mind of a child sitting across the circle someone she knows who is a deaf mute, or a T.V. program or movie she saw in which a deaf mute played a part. Then the job is to decide whether that constitutes a disconfirming example, i.e. whether it proves that "all persons talk" must be changed to "some persons talk." Another child may point out that deaf mutes can talk with their hands, leading us to call for a definition of talking. This could lead to exercising the major critical thinking skill of evaluating analogous relationships. Is talking with your hands just like talking with your voice? Are the singing of birds and the talking of humans the same or different? Can we say that birds "talk" the way we say humans talk? Ultimately, through this often meandering process of comparison and exemplification, we are working towards identifying some necessary conditions for being a person. If, for example, a person could not talk and still be a person, then talking is not a necessary condition for being a person. Group philosophical dialogue involves two styles of thinking--the critical and

FORMING COMMUNITIES OF INQUIRY IN EARLY CHILDHOOD CLASSROOMS KENNEDY

2

the creative (Lipman, 1991). Critical thinking is rule-governed, meaning we follow the rules of logic, for example taking care not to contradict ourselves, and holding arguments up to the scrutiny of whether they follow logically from each other. We have long understood all experience, including perception itself, to be implicitly rulegoverned (Kant, 1965), so thinking with rules of thought certainly is not a style of experience which must be learned from scratch by young children. The minute, for example, one child generalizes that people have arms and legs, the arms or legs of other animals spring to the listener's mind, and she finds herself comparing the arms and legs of animals and humans. Are they like enough that we can say they are the same, or are they different enough that I can call them something else, and say they are in another class altogether? This kind of patterned thinking goes on even at the level of perception, and categorical thought has been characterized as a "primitive psychological function" (Mandler, 1983, p. 466). Creative thinking involves imagining things in new ways, generating counterfactual notions--for example, if humans had four arms how would they be different?--or seeing connections which are not immediately apparent, as well as thinking in other "languages" (Malaguzzi, 1987; Gardner, 1985) like art, stories, drama, movement, or music. Creative thinking is also rule governed (Lipman, 1991), but its rules are less obvious. It often involves seeing the larger picture intuitively, and proceeds by imaginative leaps, hunches and connections, rather than through a step-by-systematic step process. Community of inquiry theorists speak of the group discussion "following the argument where it leads" as it moves through numerous bifurcations, then circles around in a recursive movement and gather up the themes which it has generated into a larger theme. The movement of the "argument," or the sum of what has been said about the issue under discussion (say, what makes a person a person) is also said to be "self-correcting," in that in dialogue, a response to a statement more often than not offers a correction to the original statement. For example, when you make a generalization and I think spontaneously of an example which disproves it as a generalization, your generalization is being corrected, but this correction occurs through the spontaneous play of our dialogue. Through selfcorrection, the argument becomes more complex and better organized--it builds. But the structure of the argument is emergent, as in the second graders' conversation about magic quoted above. And what drives this emergence is the self-correcting play of the perspectives of each participant (Lipman, Sharp, & Oscanyon, 1979) BUT CAN YOUNG CHILDREN THINK CRITICALLY? There is a strong prejudice in early childhood circles against the notion that

FORMING COMMUNITIES OF INQUIRY IN EARLY CHILDHOOD CLASSROOMS KENNEDY

2

young children can think logically. This prejudice seems to arise from a combination of a lack of appreciation of the categorical logic which is found in perception, experience, and language itself (Nelson, 1985), and from the incorrect interpretation of Piaget's notion of "pre-operational" to mean "non-logical." In fact Piaget's theory places the origins of logic in action, and if that is the case, then the young child is thinking in logical structures from the beginning, whether in sensory-motor schemes or concepts (Piaget, 1954; Langer, 1980). Cognitive scientists have been arguing for at least 20 years that a fundamental logic is in place from the start of psychological life (Fodor, 1975, Chomsky, 1985, Bower, 1989). This is all too easy to say about children who are hardly speaking yet; but what about 3 and 4 year olds? Are they able to apply general rules to specific cases, or evaluate general rules by considering specific cases? Consider a 2-year old who lives in a house with a dachshund, and sits for the first time, safe in her mother's arms, before a Great Dane. She shouts, in awe and delight, "Doggie!" In doing so she is implicitly applying a general rule to a specific case, as follows: General rule: All dogs have four legs, fur or hair of some kind, a head shaped in a certain way, and a certain manner of self-presentation ("dogginess"). Particular case: This creature before me has four legs, fur or hair, a head shaped a certain way, and a "doggy" self-presentation. Therefore, although it is bigger than any such creature I've ever seen, it is probably a dog. Another example: a father stands before a fence, holding his child of 3, and examining a horse, who is standing on the other side of the fence. The horse lifts his head over the fence and towards the two humans, and its lips draw back slightly, exposing large teeth. The child asks her father, "Does he eat people?" In this case the child appears to be thinking, albeit unconsciously, in classic syllogistic form, in which there are two premises and a conclusion, and a carry over relationship from one class to another: All animals with large teeth are carnivores. All carnivores are potentially dangerous to people. Therefore: All animals with large teeth are potentially dangerous to people. The little girl's information is incorrect--she has not yet made the critical distinction between the sharp teeth of carnivores and the blunt teeth of herbivores-but her reasoning is not. It is spontaneous and structural and semi-conscious: if you asked the child to state the syllogism, she would not have a clue what you were asking for, but this fact does not make the pattern of her reasoning any less syllogistic. This is possible because the basis of reasoning is the spontaneous mental

FORMING COMMUNITIES OF INQUIRY IN EARLY CHILDHOOD CLASSROOMS KENNEDY

2

activity of assimilating individual cases to general categorical schemes and rules (Dewey, 1991; Piaget, 1952), and thereby continually accommodating as well, i.e. reconstructing those schemes to better approximate the way things are since the new case was assimilated. If we think of these schemes as theories, or pieces of theories, then we see that young children are just as spontaneously theory-driven as adults (Carey, 1985; Wellman, 1990). Recent research even points to the capacity of young children to formulate verbal syllogisms apart from any empirical situation, using make believe animals and things in reasoning games (Hawkins et al, 1984). The tendency to characterize young children as illogical is especially difficult to overcome because it is associated with a noble cause, which is the effort to protect the young child from the oppression of push-down curriculum (Elkind, 1993). But the essential difference between children and adults is not about logic but lack of experience, and the child's weaker or more rudimentary conceptual framework in which the experience is organized. And this is made up for by the fact that, as Tizard and Hughes (1984) have pointed out, children ages 3 to 5 year old are characterized by a "persistent intellectual curiosity." They explain this as the result of "the flexible and incomplete structure of their conceptual framework, and also because of [their] growing awareness of the many confusions and misunderstandings that occur." They emphasize the importance of "the role of verbal exploration--that is, puzzling and thinking--in 4 year old children," as well as the "the child's interest in the social world of adults, and the role which adults can play in helping the child toward understanding through dialogue" (p.126). Young children are already, on the level of perception, action, and interpersonal interactions, making the fundamental logical moves associated with critical thinking. When they practice these skills which they already have in some degree in the controlled environment of the philosophical community of inquiry, the difference is twofold. First, it is a situation where language rather than action becomes the exclusive medium of thought; second, it is a group dialogue situation. In dialogue, the other person, in responding to my statement, provides the contradiction or limitation which leads me to reformulate it. Each reformulation by members of the dialoging group offers the possibility of leading to a clearer picture of the the topic around which the dialogue is taking place, without the personal threat which often accompanies one-on-one dialogue. If, for example, I have the more or less unconsciously held assumption (as some 4-year olds do) that all doctors are men, and I never bring that assumption into dialogue with others, it remains in an unreflective state. If in a group conversation about doctors, medicine, hospitals, etc., I am moved

FORMING COMMUNITIES OF INQUIRY IN EARLY CHILDHOOD CLASSROOMS KENNEDY

2

to state my assumption, and someone in a flash returns, "Uh uh! My doctor is a woman!" the example has just been offered which disproves it. Therefore I must reorganize my proposition from an "all" to a "some" statement, i.e. from "All doctors are men" to "Some doctors are men." This self-correction is less likely to happen if it is not brought into dialogue, but when it is, it happens quite naturally. And if it is brought into a group dialogue like the community of inquiry, it forms part of a collaborative inquiry into the necessary and sufficient conditions for being a doctor, and is internalized as knowledge by all the participants (Vygotsky, 1978). BUT DO YOUNG CHILDREN CARE ABOUT THESE KINDS OF QUESTIONS? Another common belief among early childhood practitioners is that young children do not really care about the "big questions," like how to define a person, how thinking works, what language is, whether there is such a thing as magic, etc. Ever since the reaction against Froebelian curriculum at the turn of the century, practitioners have been encouraged to begin with the concrete and close to home in children's experience, since they were assumed either to be confused by or not interested in abstract concepts, ideas, or larger framework of issues (Shapiro, 1983). But in fact the child's first form of deliberate abstract conceptual work is dramatic play. Vygotsky (1978) offers the example of two sisters who decide to play "sisters," and thereby enter a conceptual world where they are acting according to their generalized ideas of how brothers and sisters act, and have risen beyond their own relationship, into the realm of universal categories (p. 95). Likewise, Egan has pointed out that young children think in "powerful abstract oppositional concepts . . . that they use to explore and organize the world and experience" (1994, pp. 28, 29). He refers to binary concepts like security/danger, courage/cowardice, and hope/despair, all of which lend themselves to philosophical exploration. Egan identifies fairy tales as vehicles for this exploration. The philosophical community of inquiry, as we have seen, can use such stories to present and pursue these larger conceptual preoccupations of young children through dramatization and discussion. But even if young children are moved by "powerful abstract concepts," are they even aware of them on a conscious level? And even if they are, are they really interested in discussing them? In fact, wondering-- questioning the world and one's experience--is a natural activity, as natural as playing, or making music (Matthews, 1980, 1994), and more characteristic of the 3-5 year old than of older children or adults (Tizard & Hughes, 1984). This drive to "puzzle and think," fueled by a greater state of intellectual disequilibrium than most adults experience, is regularly

FORMING COMMUNITIES OF INQUIRY IN EARLY CHILDHOOD CLASSROOMS KENNEDY

2

overlooked by adults, especially in preschool or child care settings, where teachers encounter children mostly on the level of management statements and requests (Wood, McMahon & Cranstoun, 1980). Tizard and Hughes (1984) have demonstrated experimentally that young children actually do more thinking and puzzling at home with their mothers, even when their mothers don't put that great a value on that kind of thinking and talking. When young children's tendency to puzzle and think is allowed to take place on a regular basis in a community, facilitated by a leader who is sensitive both to the philosophical preoccupations of young children, and to their ways of thinking and talking, the educational implications are significant. Through an internalization process which Vygotsky (1978) has characterized as the "intrapsychical reproduction of the interpsychical," the individual appropriates the critical thinking skills and dispositions which are occurring in the group as a whole. To the extent that the group, led and encouraged by the teacher, regularly asks for reasons for statements or ideas, the individual learns to question her own thinking. To the extent that members of the group build on each others' ideas in their dialogue, the individual learns to sequence and connect her own ideas in her own personal thinking. To the extent that the group dialogue, as it grows and changes, is self-correcting, the individual is increasingly freed from the need to always be right. And so on. The modeling and practice from an early age of the skills and dispositions of the community of inquiry give children powerful basic tools in their own search for meaning. LEARNING THE SCRIPTS AND DISCOURSE MODELS OF DIALOGUE Since young children are novices in philosophical community of inquiry, a large proportion of time in early childhood settings is typically spent teaching the implicit rules of group discourse. Two bodies of research shed light on what is being learned here, and how. First, researchers in school discourse (Ripich & Spinelli, 1985; Willes, 1983) point out that children must learn classroom discourse patterns like the "cue-bid-nomination" move, that is, the call for an answer to a question, a raised hand, and the bestowal on the one cued of the right to speak. The discourse patterns of the community of inquiry are less dependent on a single adult than the traditional classroom model. The teacher's goal is to get group members talking between each other, so she functions, not so much as group center and authority, as arbiter of turn disputes, maintainer of topic across turns, and initiator of conversational repairs when necessary--i.e., as moderator. She models and coaches children in dialogical skills and dispositions like addressing the point which was just made, taking care to criticize ideas rather than persons, not interrupting, asking for restatements and

FORMING COMMUNITIES OF INQUIRY IN EARLY CHILDHOOD CLASSROOMS KENNEDY

2

clarifications, and thinking to return to the subject after a digression. Second, young children are learning what researchers refer to as the "script," or "general event representation" (Nelson et al, 1986) of community of inquiry. The adult general event representation of community of inquiry would go something like this: we all sit together in a circle and there is a text of some kind, which is shared communally; after it's shared, everybody shares the questions that the reading made them think of; then we talk about the questions. They are "big" questions, which usually don't seem to have any one right or final answer. We talk in a certain way, which involves above all expecting that what we say conforms to logic--i.e. is reasonable, "makes sense," "follows," or is "warrantable." In order to do this, we must be open to being corrected in our thinking by another member of the group, or the group as a whole, since we recognize that each of us represents only one perspective among all the perspectives of the group members, and the group as a whole represents one large, emerging perspective. The goal of the process is to come to agreement about the answer to some of these questions, although we recognize that these questions are not the kind that have one right answer, and therefore can be talked about again and again. This is quite a complicated script, with many slots, default values, and fillers, and is learned over time, with much reinforcement and repetition, and a teacher who models and coaches the skills and dispositions involved. As with any script, it grows more flexible and more inclusive with time and use. The skilled teacher learns to identify children operating spontaneously in the skills and dispositions of the discourse model, and reinforce them. For example, when the child in my group offers the counterexample mentioned above--"Uh uh! My doctor's a woman!" I can say, "So Joanna just gave an example that shows not all doctors are men. That's all it took--just one example to make the whole idea not true! But we can say some doctors are men, can't we?" The skillful teacher maintains the scaffolding of the discourse model, confident that, as each individual in the group practices the skills and dispositions of community of inquiry, the group learns to regulate itself. CURRICULUM IN PHILOSOPHICAL COMMUNITY OF INQUIRY The materials for doing community of inquiry with young children, because they are stories, are abundant. Many children's books lend themselves to philosophical inquiry with young children, especially those which evoke the "powerful abstract oppositional concepts" to which Egan (1988, 1994) has referred. Beatrix Potter's Peter Rabbit (1902), for example, evokes a number of these concepts--for example good and naughty, accidents and things on purpose, animals

FORMING COMMUNITIES OF INQUIRY IN EARLY CHILDHOOD CLASSROOMS KENNEDY

2

and humans, children and grownups, danger and safety (Kennedy, 1993). Teachers can prepare discussion plans which focus on these issues, which they can use to steer, to clarify, or even to redirect the discussion. The question of what's an accident is an important one for the young children, whose concept of causality is still closely tied to purpose (Piaget, 1929, Carey, 1985). The following discussion plans, taken from a set developed for Peter Rabbit (Kennedy, 1994) focuses on this issue. The teacher holds these questions in reserve, and uses them only when they seem appropriate, whether because the issue of accidents has been raised by the children themselves, or because she feels it is worth introducing the issue herself. ACCIDENTS Was it an accident that Peter's father was killed and eaten by Mr. McGregor? Was it an accident that Peter went to Mr. McGregor's garden? Was it an accident that Peter lost his coat and shoes? Did Peter go to Mr. McGregor's garden on purpose? How can you tell if something is an accident? How can you tell if something is on purpose? BY ACCIDENT OR ON PURPOSE? The sun rises in the morning The sun comes out from behind a cloud A train wreck Someone gets angry It starts raining A doctor hurts someone with a needle You were born It gets dark Numerous other children's books lend themselves to philosophical inquiry (Matthews, 1980, 1988), in particular the works of Arnold Lobel (1971, 1975, 1977, 1978, 1979). In addition to such texts, teachers can make up stories and skits themselves which evoke the questions they are interested in having children explore together, for example the story which focused on the notion of persons above, or the skits developed in Edwards (1985). There are also texts with accompanying discussion plans developed specifically for purposes of doing philosophical community of inquiry in early childhood, (Lipman, 1988b; Lipman & Gazard, 1988). For example The Doll Hospital (Sharp, 1994), developed for young children in preschool settings, tells the story of Jesse and her doll. The story is arranged in short episodes, which are designed to stimulate wonder about philosophical issues. The

FORMING COMMUNITIES OF INQUIRY IN EARLY CHILDHOOD CLASSROOMS KENNEDY

2

teacher typically reads to the children, solicits questions, and writes them on chart paper or chalkboard, which is an opportunity for experience with language in print. Through collecting the questions in this way, the children themselves are constructing the discussion agenda, and the teacher encourages children to decide which question to start the discussion with. In the dialogue that follows, participants ask for and give reasons for their thinking, built on each others ideas, and, with the help of the teacher, "follow the argument where it leads," through its self-correcting movement. The teacher introduces all or parts of discussion plans which focus on specific issues which have been raised by the text, which move the group toward the examination of overarching regulative ideas.i Finally, the teacher encourages further response to the questions in other "languages" or expressive modalities, such as the telling or writing of stories, drawing and painting, dramatic play, puppetry, music, model play with sand or blocks, block building, and so forth. CONCLUSION: THE COMMUNITY OF INQUIRY AND THE DEMOCRATIC PERSONALITY Every classroom, from early childhood to postgraduate, has the potential for becoming a community of inquiry. The developmentally appropriate early childhood classroom is structurally closer to a community of inquiry than the traditional classroom, because it operates according to individual student initiative and principals of emergent curriculum, rather than exclusive teacher control and pre-set curriculum (Kennedy, 1994). It is a dialogical, horizontal structure, rather than a onedirectional, vertical one. Every community of inquiry--whether of art, history, dance, science, politics, economics, etc.--has the potential for becoming a philosophical community of inquiry, because every discipline has a philosophical understructure which can be explored. The philosophy of art has to do with how art means to us when we make or behold it, how we define art, how we judge good and bad art, and so forth. The philosophy of science concerns how we determine what a scientific "fact" is, admissible and inadmissible evidence in making scientific "proofs," the larger, nonscientific paradigms which guide scientific practice, and so forth. In other words, the philosophical dimension of any field of inquiry has to do with its larger meaning dimensions, the "big questions" which it inspires in us when we really to try to inquire into what it is and how it works. In keeping with the concept of the "spiral curriculum," or the proposition that "the foundations of any subject may be taught to anybody at any age in some form" (Bruner,1966), the "philosophy of" this or that can

FORMING COMMUNITIES OF INQUIRY IN EARLY CHILDHOOD CLASSROOMS KENNEDY

2

be done by young children at their particular level. For example, the discussion about magic quoted above is an example of young children doing philosophy of science, because the participants are evaluating claims about the power to manipulate nature through technologies of one sort or another in a critical manner. Above and beyond the educational implications of community of inquiry, the process is a training ground for the skills and dispositions associated, not just with creative and critical thinking, but with the autonomous, democratic personality (Sharp, 1991). The constant dual encouragement both to think for oneself and to think "in community" forms the basis for a way of solving social problems and dealing with conflict which is both autonomous and socially engaged. The high value placed on working through issues as a group, on giving and asking for reasons, and the emphasis on evaluating logical arguments, not the persons who hold them, provides a fundamental context for the learning of tolerant, non-biased attitudes towards others, and for the formation of healthy self-concept (Lago, 1990). As children become skilled in the discourse of CI, they are able to apply its form of social problem solving to issues of fairness, equity, or personal conflict which arise in the community of the classroom. CI provides the discourse setting for a moral community. Community of inquiry theory and methodology represents a form of pedagogy and a model of classroom practice which is both consonant with the most advanced early childhood theory, and also embodies the aspirations of the 20th century Western reform movement in education, which is directed towards the evolution of a citizen who is capable of what Barber (1984) has characterized as "strong democracy." The "strong" democratic personality is individuated and autonomous, but also highly collaborative, and holds a "conflict model" rather than an "order model" of social process (Chesler & Crowfroot, 1975), meaning she feels it is possible to use conflict in the interests of positive change and development. The community of inquiry's emphasis on the social construction of knowledge, and on truth as a process rather than a given; its emphasis on group process, on collaboration, problem-solving, and emergence, make of it a developmentally appropriate form of education for the cultural and social goal of the democratic personality. Recent advances in our understanding of children's thinking have allowed us to see that it is not too early, provided we are sensitive to young children's limitations and lack of experience, to start toward this goal in the early years. Nor should we forget how deeply we as adults stand to be enriched as we assist at young children's collaborative construction of meaning.

FORMING COMMUNITIES OF INQUIRY IN EARLY CHILDHOOD CLASSROOMS KENNEDY

2

REFERENCES Andersen, H.C. (1953). The steadfast tin soldier. New York: Scribner. Barber, B. (1984). Strong democracy. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press. Bower, T.G.R. (1989). The rational infant: Learning in infancy. New York: W.H. Freeman. Bruner, J. (1966). The process of education. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Carey, S. (1985). Conceptual change in childhood. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Chesler, M. & Crowfoot, J. (1975). Toward a conflict model for understanding the organization of schooling in America. Report to Northwest Regional Laboratories, Portland, OR. Ann Arbor: Community Resources Ltd. Chomsky, N. (1980). On cognitive structures and their development. In Language and learning. M. Piatelli-Palmarini, Ed. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Collodi, C. (1991). Pinnochio. Prince Frederick, MD: Recorded Books. Dewey, J. (1991[1910]). How we think. Buffalo, NY: Prometheus Books. Edwards, C.P. (1986). Promoting social and moral development in young children: Creative approaches for the classroom. New York: Teachers College Press. Egan, K. (1988). Primary understanding: Education in early childhood. New York: Routledge. Egan, K. (1994). Young children's imagination and learning: Engaging children's emotional response. Young Children 49,6 (September): 27-32. Elkind, D. (1993). Images of the young child. Washington: NAEYC. Fodor, J. (1980). On the impossibility of acquiring more powerful structures. In Language and learning. M. Piatelli-Palmarini, Ed. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Gardner, H. (1985). Frames of mind. New York: Basic Books. Hauge, M. & C. (1973). The gingerbread man. Racine, WI: Golden Press. Hawkins, J, Pea, R.D., Glick, J. & S. Scribner (1984). "Merds that laugh don't like mushrooms": Evidence for deductive reasoning by preschoolers. Developmental Psychology 20 (4): 584-594. Kant, I. (1965). Critique of pure reason. Trans. Norman Kemp Smith. New York: St. Martin's Press. Katz, L. & Chard, S. (1991). Engaging children's minds: The project method. New York: Ablex.

FORMING COMMUNITIES OF INQUIRY IN EARLY CHILDHOOD CLASSROOMS KENNEDY

2

Kennedy, D. (1992). Using Peter Rabbit as a philosophical text with young children. Analytic Teaching 13, 4 (Fall): 53-58. Kennedy, D. (1994). The community of inquiry and educational structure. In Thinking, Children, and Education. M. Lipman, Ed. Dubuque, IA : Kendall Hunt. Krechevsky, M. (1991). Project Spectrum: An innovative assessment alternative. Educational Leadership 48,5 (February): 43-48. Lago, J.C. (1990). The community of inquiry and the development of self-esteem. Thinking 9,1: 12-16. Langer, J. (1980). The origins of logic: Six to twelve months. New York: Academic Press. Lipman, M., Sharp, A. & F. Oscanyan (1979). Philosophy in the classroom. Philadelphia: Temple University Press. Lipman, M. (1988a). Critical thinking: What can it be? Educational Leadership 46,1 (September): 38-43. Lipman, M. (1988b). Elfie. Upper Montclair, NJ: Institute for the Advancement of Philosophy for Children. Lipman, M. & Gazzard, A. (1988). Getting our thoughts together: Instructional manual to accompany Elfie. Upper Montclair, NJ: Institute for the Advancement of Philosophy for Children. Lipman, M. (1991). Thinking in education. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Lobel, A. (1970). Frog and Toad are friends. New York:Harper & Row. Lobel, A. (1971). Frog and Toad together. New York: Harper. Lobel, A. (1975). Owl at home. New York: Scholastic. Lobel, A. (1977). Mouse soup. New York: Harper & Row. Lobel, A. (1978). Grasshopper on the road. New York:Harper & Row. Lobel, A. (1979). Days with Frog and Toad. New York: Scholastic. Malaguzzi, L. (1987). The Hundred languages of children. Exhibit catalogue. City of Reggio Emilia: Department of Education. Mandler, J.M. (1983). Representation. In Mussen, P.H., Ed. Handbook of child psychology. Fourth Edition. Volume III: Cognitive development, J.H. Flavell & E.M. Markman, Eds., pp. 420-494. New York: Wiley. McCall, C. (1988). Young children generate philosophical ideas. Thinking 8,2: 2241. Matthews, G.B. (1980). Philosophy and the young child. Cambridge, MA: Harvard

FORMING COMMUNITIES OF INQUIRY IN EARLY CHILDHOOD CLASSROOMS KENNEDY

2

University Press. Matthews, G.B. (1988). The philosophical imagination in children's literature. In Imagination and education. K. Egan & D. Nadaner, Eds. New York: Teachers College Press. Matthews, G.B. (1994). The philosophy of childhood. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Nelson, K. (1985). Making sense: The acquisition of shared meaning. New York: Academic Press. Nelson, K. et al (1986). Event knowledge: Structure and function in develoment. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. Paley, V.G. (1981). Wally's Stories. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Piaget, J. (1929). The child's conception of the world. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Piaget, J. (1952). The origins of intelligence in children. New York: International Universities Press. Potter, B. (1902). Peter Rabbit. Frederick Warne. Ripich, D.N. & Spinelli, F.M. (Eds.). (1985). School discourse problems. San Diego: College Hill Press. Shapiro, M.S. (1983). Child's garden: The Kindergarten movement from Froebel to Dewey. University Park: Pennsylvania State University Press. Sharp, A.M. (1991). The community of inquiry: Education for democracy. Thinking 9,2: 31-37. Sharp, A. (1994). The doll hospital. Upper Montclair, NJ: Institute for the Advancement of Philosophy for Children. Tizard, B. & Hughes, M. (1984). Young children learning. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Vygotsky, L. (1978). Mind in society. Cambridge: Harvard University Press. Wellman, H. (1990). The child's theory of mind. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Willes, M.J. (1983). Children into pupils: a study of language in early schooling. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. Williams, M. (1975). The velveteen rabbit. New York: Avon Books. Wood, D., McMahoun, L., and Y. Cransoun (1980). Working with under fives. Ypsilanti, MI: High/Scope Press. MORE CHILDREN'S BOOKS FOR PHILOSOPHICAL DISCUSSION Asch, F. (1982). Happy birthday moon. New York: Simon & Schuster. Asch, F. (1985). Bear shadow. New York: Simon & Schuster.

FORMING COMMUNITIES OF INQUIRY IN EARLY CHILDHOOD CLASSROOMS KENNEDY

2

Gordon, G. (1992). Duckat. New York: Scholastic. Steig, W.(1969). Sylvester and the magic pebble. New York: Simon and Schuster. Steig, W. (1984). Yellow and Pink. New York: Farrar, Straus & Giroux. Myller, R. (1962). How big is a foot? New York: Dell. Williams, B. (1974). Albert's toothache. New York: Dutton. Wiseman, B. (1959). Morris the moose. New York: Harper & Row. Zolotow, C. (1986). I know a lady. New York: Viking.

i

. McCall (1988) includes an extended transcript of a discussion among second-graders, based on a reading of a short section of Lipman's novel Elfie (19