Flows, Fluxes and Monads Review

5
This article was downloaded by: [Taylor University] On: 09 May 2014, At: 07:02 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK Parallax Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/tpar20 Flows, Fluxes and Monads: the Conceptual Madness of Experimental Social Ontology Lukas Verburgt a a University of Amsterdam Published online: 21 Jan 2014. To cite this article: Lukas Verburgt (2014) Flows, Fluxes and Monads: the Conceptual Madness of Experimental Social Ontology, Parallax, 20:1, 114-117, DOI: 10.1080/13534645.2014.865327 To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/13534645.2014.865327 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (the “Content”) contained in the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis, our agents, and our licensors make no representations or warranties whatsoever as to the accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinions and views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors, and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Content should not be relied upon and should be independently verified with primary sources of information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for any losses, actions, claims, proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilities whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to or arising out of the use of the Content. This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms & Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms- and-conditions

description

A review of Lukas Verburgt's Flows, Fluxes and Monads: the Conceptual Madness of Experimental Social Ontology

Transcript of Flows, Fluxes and Monads Review

  • This article was downloaded by: [Taylor University]On: 09 May 2014, At: 07:02Publisher: RoutledgeInforma Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registeredoffice: Mortimer House, 37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

    ParallaxPublication details, including instructions for authors andsubscription information:http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/tpar20

    Flows, Fluxes and Monads: theConceptual Madness of ExperimentalSocial OntologyLukas Verburgtaa University of AmsterdamPublished online: 21 Jan 2014.

    To cite this article: Lukas Verburgt (2014) Flows, Fluxes and Monads: the Conceptual Madness ofExperimental Social Ontology, Parallax, 20:1, 114-117, DOI: 10.1080/13534645.2014.865327

    To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/13534645.2014.865327

    PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

    Taylor & Francis makes every effort to ensure the accuracy of all the information (theContent) contained in the publications on our platform. However, Taylor & Francis,our agents, and our licensors make no representations or warranties whatsoever as tothe accuracy, completeness, or suitability for any purpose of the Content. Any opinionsand views expressed in this publication are the opinions and views of the authors,and are not the views of or endorsed by Taylor & Francis. The accuracy of the Contentshould not be relied upon and should be independently verified with primary sourcesof information. Taylor and Francis shall not be liable for any losses, actions, claims,proceedings, demands, costs, expenses, damages, and other liabilities whatsoeveror howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in connection with, in relation to orarising out of the use of the Content.

    This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Anysubstantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing,systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden. Terms &Conditions of access and use can be found at http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions

  • cally and media studied from a subjective

    perspective might be, and they never specify why

    or how individuals might appropriate evil media

    stratagems to take part in a larger oppositional

    movement. They offer only two sparing maxims to

    guide any opposition to what they call con-

    temporary societys stupidity flow (p.166).

    Always bear in mind, they write, that making a

    machine do something you dont want to do

    yourself [ . . . ] shifts the initiative and the operative

    focus of control (p.15), and even more impor-

    tantly, each new form of structuration and

    mediation of the world generates its own kind of

    collateral damage (p.123). Other than these

    advisories, the book is purposefully strategic, not

    prescriptive. It demonstrates that the materials

    and processes to fight and with which to fight are

    all around, ripe for the kind of dialectical

    appropriation called detournement.

    Difficult introduction aside, Evil Media is an

    invigorating book. Its deft witticism and disturbing

    insights invite double- and repeated-dipping

    alone, to be sure, but ideally with discussion

    partners. Evil Media deals one of the stronger blows

    in recent years against grey medias evolving brand

    of media studies cum management theory (p.168).

    It turns scholarly focus back to media philosophy

    and gestalt. Its ending represents a formidable

    wake-up call to readers who are economically

    privileged enough to have enmeshed themselves in

    their media products and processes. Becoming

    more fully connected, in the sense of materially

    linkingmore andmore knowledge resources, within

    and without an organisation, Fuller and Goffey

    write, does not of itself suffice to make anyone or

    anything smarter, even if the broader availability of

    information within an organisation is an important

    prerequisite to making informed decisions (p.169).

    Are they correct in implying that contemporary

    media users are turning into Flauberts Bouvard

    and Pecuchet (p.169), two technocrats who

    tirelessly mistake the compilation and accessibility

    of information for its content, context and

    consequences?10 Time will tell, but so will deeds.

    As Zygmunt Bauman has written, [t]o be moral

    does not mean to be good, but to exercise ones

    freedom of authorship and/or actorship as a choice

    between good and evil.11 As Fuller, Goffey and

    Google know, evil is as evil does.

    Notes

    1 Google Company Webpage, Ten Things We

    Know to Be True ,www.google.com/about/

    company/philosophy. [04/09/13].

    2 Google Investor Relations Webpage, Code ofConduct ,www.investor.google.com/corporate/

    code-of-conduct.html. [04/09/13].3 Matthew Fuller, Media Ecologies (Cambridge,

    MA: MIT Press, 2007).4 Guy Debord, The Society of the Spectacle [1967],

    trans. Donald Nicholson-Smith (New York: Zone

    Books, 1994).5 Raoul Vaneigem, The Revolution of Everyday Life

    [1967], trans. Donald Nicholson-Smith (Oakland:

    PM Press, 2012).6 Roland Barthes, Mythologies [1957], trans.Jonathan Cape (New York: Farrar, Strauss and

    Giroux, 1972).7 Michel de Certeau, The Practice of Everyday Life[1980], trans. Steven F. Rendall (Berkeley:

    University of California Press, 1984).8 Julian Assange, The Banality of Dont be

    Evil, New York Times (June 1, 2013) ,www.

    nytimes.com/2013/06/02/opinion/sunday/the-

    banality-of-googles-dont-be-evil.html. [04/09/

    13].9 Wikileaks About Webpage, The importance of

    principled leaking to journalism, good govern-

    ment and a healthy society,www.wikileaks.org/

    About.html. [04/09/13].10 Gustave Flaubert, Bouvard and Pecuchet [1881],

    trans. Mark Polizotti (Normal: Dalkey Archive

    Press, 2005).11 Zygmunt Bauman, Life in Fragments: Essays in

    Postmodern Morality (Oxford: Blackwell, 1995), p.4.

    q 2014 Jennifer StobColgate University

    E-mail: [email protected]://dx.doi.org/10.1080/13534645.2014.865326

    Flows, Fluxes and Monads: theConceptual Madness of Experimen-tal Social Ontology

    Tony D. Sampson. Virality: ContagionTheory in the Age of Networks.(Minneapolis and London: University of Minne-sota Press, 2013)

    Tony D. Sampsons Virality is one of the first

    articulate attempts to experiment with Gabriel

    Tarde, rather than summarily theorize the status

    of this nineteenth-century sociologist as a fore-

    father of actor-network theory.1 For Sampson, to

    experiment with, or resuscitate, Tarde means to

    loosely combine it with a Deleuzian-inspired

    Book Reviews

    114

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [T

    aylor

    Univ

    ersity

    ] at 0

    7:02 0

    9 May

    2014

  • event-philosophy and to relate it to recent

    research in neuroscience, marketing, epidemiol-

    ogy, group psychology and (social) network

    studies, all the while eschew[ing] the organiz-

    ational capacity of linguistic categories [which]

    tend to block [ . . . ] conceptual freedom (p.4).

    This results, for example, in Sampsons character-

    ization of Virality on page 5 (!) as exploring a

    continuous space of encounter that is full of

    multiple monadic singularities, located in an

    epidemiological [ . . . ] world of things [ . . . ]

    emotions, sensations, affects and in which a

    continuous generation of neurophysiological

    ecosystems [is] boosted by the cultural ampli-

    fiers of [ . . . ] commodities [ . . . ] such as caffeine,

    sentimental novels and pornographic works

    (p.5). Some pages later the reader is kindly

    requested not to take such conceptual madness as

    metaphorical, but rather as ontological.

    If this is a beautiful example of misplaced

    concreteness, it must be seen as the argumentative

    core of Virality for what Sampson aims at is to set

    up two kinds of virality against each other; on the

    one hand, the molar (representational, organiz-

    ational, discursive, analogical and metaphorical)

    virality of biopower and, on the other hand, the

    molecular (non- or subrepresentational, acciden-

    tal, happenstance, flowing, desiring and ontologi-

    cal) virality of small, unpredictable events (pp.5

    6). Although these are both part of the same

    monadological process of (deterritorialized, mol-

    ecular) becomings turning into (territorialized,

    molar) beings and vice versa Sampson, on a

    methodological level, does not deal with them as

    such. His central goal in Virality is not only to

    indicate that where the molar kind of virality

    explains the process from the (Durkheimian)

    viewpoint of the territorialized beings, the

    molecular kind of virality does so from the

    (Tardean) viewpoint of the deterritorialized

    becomings, but also to argue that this second

    approach is a better explanation. Firstly, insofar as

    it is not a representative image of the social but

    actually captures the vibratory events [that]

    spread out and connect everything to everything

    else (p.7). Secondly, because it somehow exceeds

    the hegemonic symbolism of (bio)capitalism

    connected to the molar virality of the Durkhei-

    mian.

    The first chapter provides a provocative, albeit

    somewhat sketchy, account of Tardes social

    ontological framework as developed in his The

    Laws of Imitation, Social Laws: An Outline of Sociology

    and Monadology and Sociology. Sampson emphasizes

    that it is impossible to understand Tarde on the

    basis of the Durkheimian categories of macro

    (institutions) versus micro (individuals) insofar as

    Tarde was concerned with currents, waves and

    vibrations of belief and desire that function as the

    pre-individual forces constituting the subject. At

    this level, existing below (infra) the cognitive

    awareness (p.20) [original emphasis], it does not

    make sense to make a distinction between either

    individual and social or social and biological;

    the beliefs and desires, governed as they are by

    three social laws (imitative repetition, adaptation

    and opposition), are both non-conscious, anti-

    habitual and infra-psychological. For example,

    in the case of internet hypes or fashion it is not the

    subject who enter[s] into the network [ . . . ] but

    the imitative ray that [ . . . ] makes the agent part of

    an assemblage of relationality (p.29) [original

    emphasis]. That is why Tarde famously argued

    that society is imitation and imitation is a kind of

    somnambulism and why Sampson speaks of an

    hypnotic magnetism that exerts control over a

    mostly unconscious monadic social space (p.27).

    In direct opposition to the twentieth-century

    Durkheimian separation of sociology from psy-

    chology and biology, Sampsons Tardean social

    ontology is premised on the eclectic mixture of

    these domains. That is also to say that it wants to

    end the Durkheimian social or, for that matter,

    refuses to begin with it as Deleuze once put it.

    For Tarde, as for Sampson, sociology is the

    Baroque science of a pre-social, pre-biological,

    pre-psychological chaos from which social actors

    and social wholes arise on the basis of processes of

    individuation and actualization.

    Chapter two is devoted to critiquing the

    contemporary neo-Darwinian attempt to, first,

    biologize this chaos and, second, algorithmatize

    these processes on the basis of the meme or gene.

    Sampson uses the example of a viral video posted

    by Lonelygirl15 to show that the molar

    metaphor of the mechanistic memetic algorithm

    a modern combination of Darwins theory of

    natural selection, Mendels study of biological

    inheritance and Spensers (sic) application of

    evolutionary theory to civilizations is unable to

    explain what spreads. His main point is that this

    metaphor negates the creativity and novelty of

    chance-encounters in favour of a deterministic

    evolutionary code (p.78). More problematic are

    Sampsons claims that the neo-Darwinian position

    is an analogy, whereas the Tardean position

    pertains to how things are and that where the

    meme does not exist, the flowing and vibrating

    beliefs and desires undeniably do. This is a

    consequence of Sampsons experimental, rather

    than comprehensive, reading of Tarde; he forgets

    parallax

    115

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [T

    aylor

    Univ

    ersity

    ] at 0

    7:02 0

    9 May

    2014

  • that Tarde was first and foremost interested in

    using statistics as a measure of belief and desire

    and as a demonstration of the imitative power

    from which they result.2 For instance, in his essay

    Quantification and social indicators of 1897

    Tarde wrote that social statistics must never lose

    sight of their special mission, which is to measure

    as exactly as possible, by all the direct or indirect

    means at their disposal, the imitative propagation

    of a belief or desire.3 Although Sampson is,

    perhaps, justified in noting that the imitative ray

    is not [ . . . ] reducible to a unit [and] is not intrinsic

    or essential [but] insubstantial or inessential (p.87)

    [original emphasis] he leaves the argumentative

    force of the statement that unlike the assumed

    substance of the [meme], the incorporeal [imita-

    tive ray] has a distinct ungraspability (p.95)

    totally unexplained. It seems somewhat preposter-

    ous to claim that the meme, as an explanatory

    metaphor, must be rejected in favour of an

    ungraspable, unknown, unknowable and perhaps

    even not-yet realized phenomenon. In this context,

    the reader may also despair when Sampson

    proposes that the imitative ray is to be grasped

    [ . . . ] in a topological diagramming of tendencies

    and understood as a degree of freedom that is yet

    to come (p.88). Again, to allude to Deleuzes

    Whiteheadian adage, must not the abstract itself

    be explained instead of used as an explanation?

    In the third chapter, Sampson does examine the

    issue of diagramming the imitative ray of belief

    and desire when he discusses the contemporary

    notion of a network. As in the case of the neo-

    Darwinian position, the image of the network

    space is criticized not only for its apolitical

    naturalness and capacity [ . . . ] to become a

    tyranny as constraining as any hierarchical chain

    of command, but also for its tendency to ignore

    the occasional and chaotic overflow of aperiodic

    events (p.98). At this point, Sampsons focus of

    attention shifts to the status of these accidental

    events in the work of Tarde. More precisely,

    Sampson asks whether accidents themselves define

    the social or whether accidents can be influenced

    so as to redefine the social. This topic, when

    suitably fleshed out, would be of major import-

    ance, for instance, to the further development both

    of chance as an explanatory element (rather than

    as a residue) in social theory, as well as of the

    connection between a relational ontology of the

    pre-individual and actor-network theory.4 Samp-

    son, however, merely notes how small, rare, non-

    periodic and random factors (of affect) play an

    important role in financial markets (and economic

    bubbles), but leaves it at that at least as far as

    the theorization of chance is concerned. Following

    Nigel Thrift, Alberto Toscano5 and Laurent

    Mucchielli6, Sampson goes on to accuse Tarde of

    political conservatism for overestimating the

    importance of accidentality and ignoring the

    fact that (neuro)marketeers are capable of guiding

    spontaneous events and making them look like an

    accident of chance encounter [by dipping] below

    conscious awareness (p.117).

    Viralitys political message presented in chapters

    4 and 5 seems to be that this Tardean ability to

    hypnotize the unconscious may be transformed

    into a molar spreading of fear by corporate and

    political (neo-Con) persuaders. Although it is

    stated on the back cover of the book that for

    Sampson such abilities are not necessarily a

    positive or negative force, he directly opposes a

    capitalist terror contagion to the transformative

    potential of revolutionary love (p.144). Sampson,

    thus, writes that [i]n contrast to the microbial

    contagions of the neo-Cons, and their appeal to

    the political unconscious through the cold,

    emotionless channels of advisors like Cheney and

    the fearmongering of Rumsfeld, Obamas cam-

    paign of hope and change managed to emphati-

    cally tap into the infectable emotions of manyU.S.

    voters (p.155). These conclusions, however

    attractive and justified they might be, raise serious

    doubts about both the neutrality of Sampsons

    account as well as the necessity of grounding them

    on the basis of a Tardean-Deleuzian monadologi-

    cal ontology as such. But, obviously, the hunch of

    this new ontology is to pulverize the world of

    positivist Durkheimian conservatism by spiritua-

    lizing the dust of monadological progressiveness.

    The thoroughly political aim of Virality is to think

    up new ways in which [ . . . ] exercises of biopower

    can be discerned, resisted [and] escaped or the

    potential for revolutionary countercontagion can

    be actualized (p.159).

    This is at the same time the greatest merit and the

    biggest weakness of Virality. Although there is

    much that speaks in favour of attempting to

    question capitalism by understanding its foun-

    dations and functioning better than it does itself, it

    is doubtful whether Sampson manages to prevent

    this goal from completely intruding on his

    presentation of a new social theory that explains

    how society comes together. Sampson does

    provide the initiative for a full-blown Tardean

    microsociological worldview, but too much in

    Virality rests on dubious claims about the reality of

    its, sometimes amazingly, abstract terminology

    vis-a`-vis the metaphors and analogies of the

    positions it rejects. This is most prominent in the

    central opposition between the molar virality of

    Book Reviews

    116

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [T

    aylor

    Univ

    ersity

    ] at 0

    7:02 0

    9 May

    2014

  • neo-Darwinian theories of memetics and themolecular virality of Tardes imitative ray;

    where the first is dismissed for the fact that the

    meme is lacking, the second is advocated because

    of its ungraspable incorporeality. The statementthat Sampsons virality is as established as that of

    the meme only adds to this utter confusion.

    Notes

    1 See, for instance, the essays in Matei Candea,

    ed., The Social After Gabriel Tarde: Debates and

    Assessments (London and New York: Routledge,

    2012); David Toews, The New Tarde: SociologyAfter the End of the Social, Theory, Culture &

    Society, 20 (2003), pp.8198; Bruno Latour,

    Gabriel Tarde and the End of the Social

    ,www.bruno-latour.fr/node/181. [4/2/2013].2 See Gabriel Tarde, On Communication and Social

    Influence: Selected Papers, ed. and intr. Terry

    N. Clarke (Chicago and London: The University

    of Chicago Press, 1969), Part V.

    3 Gabriel Tarde, On Communication and SocialInfluence, p.229.4 On the issue of chance in social theory see, for

    instance, Mike Smith Changing Sociological

    Perspectives on Chance, Sociology, 27 (1993),

    pp.513531 and Vilhelm Aubert, Chance in

    Social Affairs, Inquiry: An Interdisciplinary Journal of

    Philosophy, 2 (1959), pp.124.5 Alberto Toscano, Power of Pacification: State

    and Empire in Gabriel Tarde, Economy and Society,

    36 (2007), pp.597613.6 Laurent Mucchielli, Tardomania? Reflexionssur les Usages Contemporains de Tarde, Revue

    dHistoire des Sciences Humaines, 3 (2000), pp.161

    184.

    q 2014 Lukas VerburgtUniversity of Amsterdam

    E-mail: [email protected]://dx.doi.org/10.1080/13534645.2014.865327

    parallax

    117

    Dow

    nloa

    ded

    by [T

    aylor

    Univ

    ersity

    ] at 0

    7:02 0

    9 May

    2014