Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

download Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

of 279

Transcript of Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    1/279

      1

    Deduction and Reality:

    Bridging Science, Religion and Metaphysics 

    Patrick D. Bangert

    Table of Contents

    Lecture 1: The Basis of Mathematical Logic...................................................................... 5

    1.1 Introduction to the Course......................................................................................... 5

    1.2 What Is Real? ............................................................................................................ 8

    1.3 The Historical Roots of Logic................................................................................. 10

    1.4 What Is Logic? ........................................................................................................ 14

    1.5 Axiomatics .............................................................................................................. 16

    1.6 The Structure of Mathematical Logic ..................................................................... 181.7 Truth and Falsehood................................................................................................ 20

    1.8 Logical Operations and Relations ........................................................................... 22

    1.9 Conclusions............................................................................................................. 27

    1.10 Appendix: The Dog-Walking Ordinance.............................................................. 29

    Lecture 3: The Structure of an Axiomatic System............................................................ 30

    3.1 Aristotle and His Followers .................................................................................... 303.2 The Axiomatic System............................................................................................ 34

    3.3 The Model Concept for an Axiomatic System........................................................ 36

    3.4 The Equivalence of Two Axiomatic Systems......................................................... 383.5 Consistency ............................................................................................................. 41

    3.6 Independence .......................................................................................................... 42

    3.7 Completeness .......................................................................................................... 43

    3.8 Categoricalness ....................................................................................................... 44

    3.9 Euclid’s Geometry in the Plane .............................................................................. 46

    3.10 Conclusions........................................................................................................... 48

    Lecture 5: Deduction......................................................................................................... 48

    5.1 Primitive Terms of the Logic .................................................................................. 495.2 Basic Definitions in the Logic ................................................................................ 50

    5.3 Axioms of the Logic ............................................................................................... 52

    5.4 Basic Theorems....................................................................................................... 57

    5.5 Syllogism and Proof................................................................................................ 585.6 Developing Mathematics from Logic ..................................................................... 60

    5.7 Conclusions............................................................................................................. 61

    Lecture 7: The Limitations of the Deductive Method....................................................... 62

    7.1 Review .................................................................................................................... 637.2 Induction ................................................................................................................. 65

    7.3 Algorithmic Thinking?............................................................................................ 67

    7.4 Recursion ................................................................................................................ 69

    7.5 Hilbert’s Problems .................................................................................................. 717.6 Gödel’s theorems .................................................................................................... 72

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    2/279

      2

    7.7 Conclusions............................................................................................................. 77

    Lecture 10: General Relativity.......................................................................................... 78

    10.1 Aristotle, Galileo and the Birth of Science ........................................................... 7910.2 The Newtonian Universe ...................................................................................... 81

    10.3 What is Mass? ....................................................................................................... 8410.4 Albert Einstein’s Revolution................................................................................. 87

    10.5 Special Relativity .................................................................................................. 90

    10.6 General Relativity ................................................................................................. 92

    10.7 The Nature of Space and Time ............................................................................. 9710.8 Conclusions........................................................................................................... 99

    Lecture 12: Quantum Theory.......................................................................................... 101

    12.1 A Discrete Space-time?....................................................................................... 10112.2 Postulates of Impotence ...................................................................................... 105

    12.3 Unexplainable Experiments ................................................................................ 107

    12.4 Quantum Theory ................................................................................................. 109

    12.5 Uncertainty.......................................................................................................... 11112.6 Schrödinger’s Schizophrenic Cat........................................................................ 112

    12.7 Quantum Mechanics as a Proof for the Existence of God .................................. 114

    12.8 Causality and Determinism................................................................................. 115

    12.9 Conclusion .......................................................................................................... 117Lecture 13: Quantum Mechanics and Ontology ............................................................. 117

    13.1 The Infinite Potentiality of the Vacuum ............................................................. 117

    13.2 Fundamental Particles Have a “Size” ................................................................. 120

    13.3 The Ontological Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics ..................................... 12213.4 Active Information and Non-locality.................................................................. 123

    13.5 The Uncertainty Principle ................................................................................... 126

    13.6 The Classical Limit ............................................................................................. 12913.7 The Pauli Exclusion Principle............................................................................. 13113.8 Other Interpretations ........................................................................................... 132

    13.9 Unity of the Laws................................................................................................ 135

    13.10 Conclusions....................................................................................................... 136

    Lecture 15: Tibetan Buddhism I ..................................................................................... 137

    15.1 The Four Noble Truths........................................................................................ 140

    15.2 The Wheel of Life ............................................................................................... 142

    15.3 The Six Realms of Existence .............................................................................. 144

    15.4 The Twelve Stages of Life 1: Ignorance ............................................................. 14715.5 The Twelve Stages of Life 2: Karma.................................................................. 148

    15.6 The Twelve Stages of Life 3: Consciousness ..................................................... 14915.7 The Twelve Stages of Life 4: Name and Form................................................... 15015.8 The Twelve Stages of Life 5: Six Senses............................................................ 151

    15.9 The Twelve Stages of Life 6: Contact ................................................................ 152

    15.10 The Twelve Stages of Life 7: Feeling............................................................... 152

    Lecture 17: Tibetan Buddhism II .................................................................................... 153

    17.1 The Twelve Stages of Life 8: Attachment .......................................................... 153

    17.2 The Twelve Stages of Life 9: Grasping .............................................................. 15417.3 The Twelve Stages of Life 10: Existence ........................................................... 156

    17.4 The Twelve Stages of Life 11: Birth................................................................... 157

    17.5 The Twelve Stages of Life 12: Death ................................................................. 157

    17.6 The Western Wheel of Life................................................................................. 159

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    3/279

      3

    17.7 The Tabula Smaragdina ...................................................................................... 161

    17.8 The Eightfold Path .............................................................................................. 163

    17.9 The Concept of Guru........................................................................................... 16617.10 Liberation .......................................................................................................... 168

    17.11 Meditation ......................................................................................................... 16817.12 Conclusions....................................................................................................... 170

    Lecture 19: Dignaga and Dharmakirti ............................................................................ 170

    19.1 Know, Do, Expect!.............................................................................................. 170

    19.2 The School of Dignaga ....................................................................................... 17319.3 Know the World.................................................................................................. 175

    19.4 Reality is like an illusion..................................................................................... 176

    19.5 Probabilistic Actions ........................................................................................... 17719.6 Properties of Objects ........................................................................................... 179

    19.7 Deductions about Reality.................................................................................... 179

    19.8 Conclusions......................................................................................................... 181

    Lecture 21: The Nyaya-Bindu......................................................................................... 18221.1 Perception............................................................................................................ 183

    21.2 Inference.............................................................................................................. 186

    21.2 Syllogism ............................................................................................................ 189

    21.3 The World ........................................................................................................... 19121.4 Knowledge .......................................................................................................... 193

    21.5 Conclusions......................................................................................................... 194

    Lecture 23: The Terms of the Nyaya-Bindu ................................................................... 196

    23.1 Primitive Terms................................................................................................... 19723.2 Some Definitions................................................................................................. 198

    23.3 Some Axioms...................................................................................................... 204

    23.4 Conclusions......................................................................................................... 207Lecture 25: Deducing the Nyaya-Bindu ......................................................................... 207

    25.1 The Three-Aspect Theorem ................................................................................ 208

    25.2 The Hetuchakra ................................................................................................... 210

    25.3 Negation .............................................................................................................. 212

    25.4 Syllogism ............................................................................................................ 217

    25.5 Fallacies .............................................................................................................. 218

    25.6 Conclusions......................................................................................................... 220

    Lecture 27: Extending the Theory beyond the Nyaya-Bindu ......................................... 221

    27.1 Dialetic ................................................................................................................ 22127.2 Emptiness ............................................................................................................ 222

    27.3 The Four Noble Truths........................................................................................ 22527.4 Mahayana Buddhism: Enlightenment entails compassion.................................. 22827.5 Mahayana Buddhism: Global selfishness is local altruism................................. 229

    27.6 Circular Reasoning.............................................................................................. 230

    27.7 Apoha .................................................................................................................. 230

    27.8 Conclusions......................................................................................................... 230

    Knowing the Instant Through Wisdom: A Systematization of the Nyaya-Bindu .......... 233

    Abstract ....................................................................................................................... 2331. Technical Vocabulary and Introductory Remarks. ................................................. 234

    2. Correspondence between Logic the Statements of the Nyaya-Bindu..................... 241

    3. Construction of the Logic and Correspondence to Reality..................................... 245

    4. Logical Systematization of the Nyaya-Bindu (Theorems) ..................................... 250

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    4/279

      4

    Appendix: Nyaya-Bindu: A Short Treatise of Logic ...................................................... 263

    A. Perception............................................................................................................... 264

    B. Inference................................................................................................................. 265C. Syllogism................................................................................................................ 268

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    5/279

      5

    Lecture 1: The Basis of Mathematical Log ic

    1.1 Introduction to the Course

    Welcome to the USC on “Deduction and Reality”. I am Patrick Bangert and he is Paul Crowther. This

    course is called “Deduction and Reality: Bridging Science, Religion and Metaphysics.” So it’s a very

     big course in the sense that it encompasses a great deal of things. So, first of all, I would like to preset

    these words from Lao Tse: “The Tao that can be known is not the true Tao. The word that can be said

    is not the true word.“ This is very true as concerns this course. Anything I will say is an approximation

    to how things should be said and so I hope you will forgive me for explaining things as best as I can

    which is not that well but I shall try. There is a website organized for this course: http://www.knot-

    theory.org/usc. It doesn’t look very good but it contains content; that’s preferable. Here it is and you

    can go and visit it at your leisure.

    You probably want to know what this whole thing is about. Deduction and reality is a very big topic.

    Reality; what is real? What is deduction? How can we approach reality by deduction? First of all, we

    want to get an idea of something about reality which is not immediately obvious. Miyamoto Musashi

    said: “Perceive those things which cannot be seen. … Do nothing which is of no use.”

    What do we want to do? We can approach the universe in many ways. One of them is the rational

    approach to the universe. The universe has many components. How can we approach some of them?

    We perceive things in front of us. Are they real? How can we make some sort of deduction about

    reality and about the universe as a whole? Totality as such, can we approach it in a rational fashion?

    How far is it possible to approach these things in rational fashion? What are the limitations of this

    approach?

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    6/279

      6

     Now, of course, rationality has some sort of foundation from the mathematical angle, which I shall

     present. Those foundations are logic and axiomatics. These two branches of mathematics are very

    tightly interconnected but they are not the same. That’s one fo the points I want to bring out – logic as a

    method and not as truth in itself. And then to what extent is it useful and helpful?

    You might think mathematics is all not useful. Well, it is and I shall try to change your opinion about

    that to some extent. Is it helpful as well as useful to some extent? Can we gain some insight into the

    universe? Yes and no. It can only bring you so far and there is some step of belief involved which

    relates to the axioms of the system and this belief you must generate on your own or not – as you

    choose. So there are limitations to everything and certainly from the mathematical site. I am sure Paul

    will tell us what the philosophers came up with.

     Now as far as this is a course at a university there has to be, unfortunately, some component of

    assessment. There will be lectures. Those are fun. You can attend them as you wish or not. As you can

    see with the microphone in front of me we are recording the lectures. Those will be put on the internet

    in the recorded fashion and the typed up fashion and so it is possible to be downloaded. One big reason

    for this is that I know there are a lot of people interested in this and they are in many countries

    distributed all round the world and they cannot be here. That’s one thing.

    For assessment there will be three things: two essays and one exam. Two essays, one for each of us.

    We have each produced a list of 8 topics twice over. So there is a first essay about the first half of the

    course for each of us and a second essay about the second half, 8 topic for each of us, so 32 topics in

    total. Those can be looked at on the website. For the first essay you choose whether you want to do one

    on my list or his list and for the second essay you have to do an essay from the opposite list. So there is

    one for each of us and you get fair distribution of marks from each of us. For the final exam, of course

    it will be at the end of the semester and you need not worry about that now, there will be the same sort

    of distribution there and so 50% of your grade will come from each of us.

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    7/279

      7

    There will be some required reading for the course. For the philosophical part, Paul assures me that the

    textbooks he has picked out are good books as a whole. For mathematics such a book does not exist.

    This is rather unfortunate especially because of the legal situation of photocopying things. I am not

    allowed to photocopy for you. You must do it on your own. Even though the things get copied the same

    number of times it turns out to be legal if you do it and not if I do it. This is one of the examples where

    logic can no longer get to the answers. The first bit of required reading is right here. I was allowed to

     photocopy this because I wrote it. There is no copyright. You can pick a copy at the end please. It

    represents the combination of lot of research that we did a couple of last years ago about what

    mathematics is about. That gives you a 7 page definition of what it is. I hope its at least a little bit of

    fun to read. Certainly I had that in mind when I wrote it. Last point, I have already mentioned, there is a

    website it will contain the transcripts of the lectures. The website most importantly for the moment

    includes the essay topic. [addresses Paul Crowther] Is there anything you want to say on the game plan

     before I begin?

    Paul Crowther: “Let me just say that Patrick will address the more formalised aspects of logic. On the

    other hand, people who have tried to make sense of the universe as a whole have often made use of

    deductive procedures in a less systematic way while still being systematic in another way. Einstein said

    that the most incomprehensible thing about the universe is that it is so comprehensible. We are asking

    the big questions and not just in the sense of the mystic ones but understanding the universe as a whole

    and this is what the whole course is about. Patrick will give you logic and mathematics, I will give you

    a particular tradition of philosophy, the so called rational philosophy. First, I will do some preparatory

    work and then present arguments for the existence of God and other rational procedures and then I will

    look at a series of particular rational philosophers.”

    Yes, certainly one theme is the unreasonable effectiveness of mathematics in describing the universe.

    So what will I do in his lecture? Paul has given you an idea on what his part is. In the first four lectures,

    I want to present to you logic as a branch of mathematics. What is it? What can it do? What are it’s

    limitations? In the next three lectures, I will go through some axioms that have been used before to

    describe reality: particularly quantum mechanics and general relativity. Don’t be afraid I shall not use

    any formulas for this, I shall just present to you what the underlying assumptions are. Then, in the final

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    8/279

      8

    seven lectures, I will try to develop Tibetan Buddhism as an axiomatic system. This is somewhat new

    and an experiment but not the transcendental part will be presented. It’s Buddhism as a philosophy of

    reality; not the whole meditation and chanting parts of it. If you are interested in that, I am also very

    interested in that and we can talk about it, but not here. We should that in our own private time. What I

    shall do is present the philosophy as reality and that differs substantially from the western tradition in

    some cases and in some other cases it very remarkably similar. So that will be presented and, in my

    opinion, that philosophy is very well amenable to mathematical discussion and that’s why it is

     presented.

    1.2 What Is Real?

    “[Reality is] a child which cannot survive without its nurse illusion.”

    Sir Arthur Stanley Eddington

    So let me begin with some background. Eddington is, if you don’t know him, a very famous physicist

    of the 19th

     century. He claims that reality needs illusion and of course this is one of the basic principles

    of Buddhism.

    What is real? That is a very crucial question for course on reality. We need to know what reality is?

    Can we actually define reality? The complications with definition is that you define things in terms of

    other things. And then those things have to be defined in terms of yet other different things. When do

    you stop? That’s a crucial point that shall be addressed. You can approach reality in many ways and

     pretty much every human being himself or herself will decide distinct method of reaching reality. There

    are, in my opinion, two main extremes of doing things. One is the operational and other is the

    transcendental. The operational method basically says we want things to be useful. We want to make

     prediction on paper that in a way that can be tested in the laboratory. In other words, we want to make

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    9/279

      9

    statements about perception. This is what natural sciences do. Then there is the transcendental approach

    which, sort of says: I want to go to heaven after I die and I want to receive enlightenment and I have to

    achieve this in some sort of intuitive approach which is certainly not based on logical scientific

    measurable principles.

    I think those are the main two methodologies by which one can approach reality. For me it will be the

    main object of this course to discuss the operational approach by logic and mathematics and, starting

    from a few little bits which we have to believe, how we can then develop the whole rest of the universe.

    The transcendental approach is of course very much connected to the operational one, especially in the

    Buddhist section that I will discuss later. First, because the actual practical Buddhist wants to gain

    enlightment and this necessitates the transcendental meditational approach so it will come up many

    times in the course. But the main thrust will be the operational deduction.

    So what is reality? How can we achieve it? For example, is this table real? I can see it. I can touch it. If

    I drop it, it hurts. So is it real? Fundamentally I have to make a decision whether I shall regard that

    thing as real or not. It is not an a priori given, that it is real.

    There is a famous skeptical argument of the “brain in a vat.” Imagine that what really exitst is not your

    whole body but only your brain. In the laboratory, your brain is connected up to some machine. The

    machine is very fancy. It can stimulate the brain exactly such a way that your sense perceptions, your

    sight, your smell and all the other perceptions are controlled by the machine. It can therefore play a

    kind of reality as a movie to you and because your sense perceptions are entirely controlled by the

    machine, it is impossible for you to trust your sense perceptions alone to distinguish reality (that you

    are a brain in a vat) from what is being played to you. Of course the machine doesn’t exist, yet it can be

    conceived. So the thought is: “How can we distinguish it?” The answer is that we have to make a

    decision. Are we going to regard sense input as real or not? This is one of the axioms.

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    10/279

      10

    It will be one of the axioms in the Buddhist part that you must, or that we shall agree to, regard sense

     perceptions as real. However what do you do if there are some defects? Say I am colorblind. I cannot

    distinguish between green and red for example. Clearly in traffic that’s a problem. But it’s still ok

     because most people are not colorblind. So we have a sort of vote. Is that thing green or not? I disagree

    with you but there are dozens of you. So I will basically take your word for it. This democratic

    approach to reality fails in some circumstances. Imagine that you are a schizophrenic person. Most of

    you should have seen “A Beautiful Mind,” right? The main character in “A Beautiful Mind” saw

     people that were not real. How is he supposed to know that these people are not real? He sees them; he

    can touch them; he can speak to them; they answer him. Everybody else, with exception of his

    imagined people, can not see these people. Of course those people see themselves. So we can have a

    vote in the class. He is lecturing, so all his students vote “no, we don’t see them.” He votes we see them

    and his extra people also vote “yes.” We have 30 against 4 and the class wins. Now lets say the

    schizophrenic person imagines a big army full of people and he has a friend beside him. The friend

    knows that they are not there but everyone in this huge collection sees each other of course. Now the

    imagined collection of people votes that they see everyone else and they win in a democratic system.

    Who shall we trust? Is my friend, who does not see everybody else, going to let all these votes count?

     No because they are not there. But I see they are there. So we cannot really agree. At some point we

    must make decision to believe.

    1.3 The Historical Roots of Logic

    So sense input is flawed. But we have to have some starting point and this is where the historical roots

    of logic lie. Logic and deduction are, of course, very very old. However, the first actually recorded

    system comes to us from a little piece of the Rhind papyrus, from Egypt about five thousand years ago

    and it includes many mathematical formulae for calculating various things such as the volume of

     pyramids. One of the problems it mentions is land surveying. This was a crucial problem for ancient

    Egypt. If you remember your history, what happens in Nile Delta is that once a year the Nile brings a

     big flood and deposits soil, which is rich in minerals for the plants, over the lands. Then the water

    retreats again and because of the new fertile soil, Egypt became great civilization – they were able to

    grow lots of food, more then they needed. They could trade the grain to obtain money and power. Now

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    11/279

      11

    how did one farmer say: “This is my land.” Basically what they did was to use a post of wood or a

    large stone to mark the boarders of their land. If a particularly big flood comes along, those marks are

    lost. That’s a problem because then I can put my stone further away from where it was before thus

    stealing land from my neighbor. That cannot be allowed. Of course Egypt is a big civilization. There

    has to be some record of who owns how much. And then there has to be some method for going along

    and measuring out this much and putting new markers on the ground so that I receive the 10 acres of

    land that I used to own, not that I can somehow steal more or get less because someone else steals

    something. So how to do this?

    The most important point is that we agree. We must use one system of measurements of area.

    Everybody involved, all the farmers and central administrators must agree to use one system of units so

    that it it clear what an acre is. And everyone must agree on the rules of the measurement process. These

    rules must be constructed in such a way that somebody else, later on, after the current people are dead,

    can still apply the rules because my property gets inherited to my children who shall inherit it to their

    children and the bureaucracy 200 years down the line must be able to follow the rules such that the 10

    acres I own now shall remain 10 acres during my grand childrens’ life. So we must agree on the rule

    and the results of the rule. The results of the rule must be uniform. The 10 acres of land here remain 10

    acres over there and the rules must be able to be executed by people later on. This is the basic principle.

    In ancient Egypt they used ropes with knots in them. From this knot to that knot is so units and you

    measure it off. That is ok for the measurement of land.

    But we want to discuss many more things. So we have to develop rules that are much more general.

    Logic will get us much further than surveying land. It will be able to deduce many things from given

    sets of assumption.

    Aristotle constructed a system of logic( I prefer “a system of logic and not “the system of logic” and

    that’s the main point later on) which contains three basic rules:

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    12/279

      12

    1.  Anything is itself.

    2.  Any statement has a truth value and this can be true or false.

    3.   No statement may have more than one truth value.

    Rule 1 can be regarded as the definition of the verb “to be:” Anything, such as this table, is this table.

    This statement is called the Law of Identity. It is a vacuous statement unless you consider it as the

    definition of equality embodies by the verb “to be.”

    Rule 2 is very important because statements could potentially be not true and false but something else.

    One could, for instance, consider “nonsense” to be a valid truth value for sentences that do not conform

    to the definitions of the terms. Alternatively, if we lack information, we could assign probabilities as

    truth values.

    Rule 3 is very crucial – it is the most important one of the three. Any statement has one definite truthvalue and that shall be very crucial in all systems of logic. Definiteness is the very essence of logical

    deduction and if a statement could have two truth values at the same time then it would really mess the

    system up.

    There are many other system of logic possible. This is the first big message in this course. Logic is not

    one thing – it is many. You have to decide which logic you are going to use and this decision isarbitrary. If, of course, what you want to do is lay down axioms about reality, about a physics

    experiment and make deductions that are going to be the results of the future physics experiment, then

    your choice of logic must be guided by these principles such as you want the results to be real

    whatever that may mean.

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    13/279

      13

    In generating other logics, you have to modify the starting points of Aristotle’s system. The second rule

    is the one most frequently denied by people introducing more truth values than two. You must decide

    which logic to use based on the application you wish to follow. The choice is essentially up to you.

    For thousands of years, geometry, starting with the Greek school around Euclid and Pythagoras, was

    regarded to be true in the sense of absolutely corresponding to reality. There is one geometry that

    guides the universe and that’s it. Euclid wrote the book and that was the last word for a long time.

    Surprisingly, from a modern point of view, Euclid’s work was used as a textbook ever since was it was

    written up until about 50 years ago in high schools. This very popular book that enjoyed a monopoly on

    the truth for a long time, was then shown to be wrong. Not only is it wrong in the claim that this

    geometry corresponds to reality but it is also wrong in the sense that its theorems do not actually follow

    from the assumptions it proposes. Mathematically it is a pretty bad book. The only reason that I

    mention it here is because it has turned out to be so popular. Many mathematicians investigated

    Euclid’s axioms and theorems got inspired by them, in particular by the errors in Euclid’s deductions. It

    is fair to say that the investigation of the errors of Euclid has lead to a very large portion of modern

    mathematics. The book had great influence not only on mathematics but also on philosophy.

    Particularly Kant decided to build a whole system upon this and he regarded the geometrical axioms

    that Euclid proposed as a priori truths.

    What does a priori mean? It means: “True before you do anything.” It is supposed to be clear to you in

    itself. Just by sitting on your chair and looking around you these truths are meant to be absolutely self-

    evident. They do not need a proof because they are so obviously true. But they do not need to be

    assumed either because they are true. This is what Kant claims of the axioms of geometry.

    Through the work of many mathematicians, it has been possible to construct many geometries, in fact

    infinitely many geometries that are all consistent, all different from each other and all different from

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    14/279

      14

    Euclid’s one. So there are many geometries. If you then introduce the principle that you want this

    geometry to correspond to the universe as a whole then you have to perform some sort of physics

    experiment to see which one matches experimental evidence. Eddington actually did this experiment.

    He went to a solar eclipse and measured the position of stars before and after the solar eclipse. The

    observations revealed that the position changed. This was the first direct verification of Einstein’s

    theory of relativity and it showed that the space of our universe is curved. Curved space acts in a way

    that parallel lines may intersect which contradicts one of Euclid’s assumptions and Eddington thus

    showed that we live in a non-Euclidean universe. This makes Kant’s claim of a priori truth of Euclid’s

    axioms doubly wrong. Not only are they not a priori true but they are not true of the universe at all.

    What happens is that the gravitational attraction of the sun is so strong because it has so much mass

    that it can bend light. We consider the rays of light as straight lines according to the general theory of

    relativity. During a solar eclipse, I can look at a star which is just beside the solar disk and measure its

     position. Then I wait until the sun has moved and I measure the position again. These two

    measurements are found to differ and thus we conclude that the presence of the sun in the path of the

    light has curved the path of the light so as to fool the observer into thinking the star was elsewhere.

    Even though Euclid’s geometry is not true of the universe, it is possible to have Euclid’s geometry as a

     perfectly acceptable mathematical system. It has axioms and it has theorems that you can deduce from

    the axioms if you clean up the mess that Euclid made and its perfectly fine. You just must not claim

    that it is real.

    1.4 What Is Logic?

    The same thing happens with logic. Over thousands of years, Aristotle’s system of logic was regarded

    to be the system similar to Euclid’s geometry. Only recently, in the middle of the last century, some

    mathematicians got together and decided to construct other systems of logic based on different

    assumptions. This is a crucial thing to realize: Logic itself is based on assumptions.

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    15/279

      15

    Aristotle’s three rules are assumption of logic – they define what that particular logic is. If you deny

    one of them, introduce a fourth or make some other fundamental change, then you construct a different

    system and this new system is perfectly acceptable. It has axioms and theorems that you can deduce

    from them. You just must not claim that any of these systems correspond to reality. If you do, then you

    have to form some sort of experiment.

    Most of you have probably read some stories of Sherlock Holmes, the famous detective of the 19th

     

    century. He says that: “When you have eliminated all which is impossible, then whatever remains,

    however improbable, must be the truth.” This is a very good statement of logic. In classical logic,

     probabilities are not counted. Something is true or it is false. It is not more likely than something else.

    If you have deduced that all these things are false then the negation of all these things must be true.

    Logic is a method that begins from assumptions and obtains conclusions. Changing the method,

    changes the conclusions. You must not claim that what logic produces is transcendent truth. The

    assumptions are agreed to be true in the sense that the axioms have an associated truth value which is

    equal to true. We must not say that the axioms are absolutely true of reality. Logic is then a method that

     produces conclusions that are true in the same way that the assumptions are true – based on agreement,

    not on reality. The conclusions clearly depend on the premises or assumptions. We lay down some

     premises that we agree to hold up, then we get conclusions and the truth values of the conclusions

    depend integrally on the truth values of the premises.

    Judging the actual truth of the premises is not within logic. No logic, no systems of axioms must claim

    that its axioms are true of reality. That is a judgment that is outside of the system. If you want to claim

    that your assumptions are true then you are in natural sciences or in philosophy but not within logic,

    not within mathematics. Within mathematics the assumptions are agreed upon. We shall not make

    claims of reality. For the mathematician, “true” is an operational word. It is always relative to a given

    set of assumptions that are agreed upon. The set of assumptions are like a point of view. From a

    different point of view (different assumptions), the same statement may have opposite truth values. For

    the mathematician this is fine as the two statements can not be compared being true relative to different

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    16/279

      16

     basic rules. For the natural scientist this is a cause to abandon at least one of these two points of view as

    unrealistic. If we claim that a statement is true of reality or of the universe, then we are making an

    entirely different claim that has to be verified.

    We must have premises. If we have no assumptions, we can do nothing. We take a statement that we

    can prove mathematically from other statements. These statements are in turn proved by others.

    Circular reason is not allowed as it is obviously senseless. So the circle must be broken somehow. It

    can only be broken if we agree on one or more particular statements and accept them as basic to our

    theory. Those are the premises of the system. We cannot do without premises.

    1.5 Axiomatics

    Axioms are formulated in terms of primitive terms. This is one more step towards being elementary. So

    we have agreed now that we have to have premises. We have to have at least one statement that we

    shall simply agree upon. This statement uses words or symbols. It has some content and we must also

    agree what the objects that appear in the axiom are.

    The terms used in stating the axioms are either primitive or defined in terms of primitives. Primitive

    terms are terms which we use without definition, they are the analogue of axioms. I will give you an

    example of an experiment that we did about a year and half ago of very large systems of axioms. The

    English language has many words. All words in English language have definition in English. They are

    given in a dictionary. If you do not know a word, you look it up. You read the definition to understand

    what the words means. For this looking-up procedure to work, you need to know some words to begin

    with. Otherwise you ca not read the definition and you do not understand the new word.

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    17/279

      17

    You do not have to know all the words’ definitions because you can deduce some of them from

    context. So knowing some percentage of the words in the definition that you find in the dictionary is

    enough to understand the new word. The dictionary we used for this is Webster’s dictionary; it contains

    over 99000 words different words. The words used in the definitions are themselves defined in the

    dictionary. We ask: “What is the least number of primitives for the system?” In other words: “What is

    the least number of words I must know in order to be able to learn all the other words?” If we knew no

    words, we could not learn any word but we also do not need to know all words as the purpose of a

    dictionary would then vanish, so this number is not trivial. It turns out that from the system of more

    than 99000 English words you only need to know 244 in order to learn all the others. This is an

    enormous reduction of complexity. As all words can be understood in terms of the basic 244 words, we

    could conceivably communicate using just these few words, the others are merely abbreviations of

    collections (definitions) of the basic words. These basic words, whose meaning has to be fixed outside 

    the system, are called primitive terms.

    Using this approach, it is possible to reduce a large complicated system to a small simple one. The

    original one can be restored by applying some basic rules to the small one. The small system is called

    an axiomatization of the original one and the rules to obtain the original from its axiomatization is

    called logic. Clearly there can be all sorts of different rules of transformation depending on the

    application and that is why there are many different logics and no logic is better than another.

    This is simplification process is what I want to do in the Buddhist part of this series. There are

    documents that have many statements about reality that are heavily interdependent. It will be our goal

    to resolve some of these interdepencies and thus make it look much simpler.

    Primitive terms are those terms we must agree on the meaning of. Axioms are statements in terms of

    these primitive terms and we again agree to uphold them. In mathematics an example of a primitive is

    “set.” Set theory is a very basic branch of mathematics that deals with discussion of collections of

    things. The word “set” can not be defined without introducing other words. In set theory, it is agreed

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    18/279

      18

    that the word “set” shall be used and theorems proven about it but that its meaning is to be ascribed to

    it outside of the system known as set theory.

    Primitives are the substance in terms of which axioms are stated. One may view the axioms as relations

     between the primitives, as rules by which we may modify collections of primitives or as definitions of

    how the primitives act in a given situation but not as definitions of the primitives themselves. An axiom

    might say: “A table has a four legs.” So table and leg are primitive terms of that system as well as some

    number system that tells us what “four” denotes. The primitives gives us the substance of the theory

    (the names of the objects which will appear) and the axioms tells about them.

    The truth of axioms or the meaning of the premises is not to be questioned. We agree on them and that

    is all. It is, of course, desirable to have few axioms as in the dictionary example. It is actually useful in

    a very practical manner to say that these particular 244 words will enable you to learn the rest of the

    language. In fact, language books that teach people English as a second language are actually based

    upon lists of this kind.

     Now of course we have in the back of our mind some theory that we want to obtain. We have to

    construct primitives terms and axioms in such a way that we obtain what we want. Later on we shall

    want to obtain Buddhist theory and we must find some primitive terms and axioms that would give it to

    us.

    1.6 The Structure of Mathematical Logic

    Logic is used to systemize the whole endeavour. From a few basic things, we build up something large.

    Together the primitives, assumption and logic will enable us to make conclusions; together they build

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    19/279

      19

    the very foundations of mathematics and of any axiomatic system. Of course, it is possible to have

    many distinct sets of axioms that will give rise to the same theory.

    Logic, starting from the axioms, gets to conclusions. But how does it do this? There are some actions

    that logic has to perform upon the axioms to reach conclusions. There are two such rules in classical or

    Aristotelian logic: Modus ponens and Substitution.

    Modus ponens tells us that if we are given that if some statement is true then another one is true and wehave somehow determined that the first one is tue then we are allowed to deduce the second one. This

    looks like a vacuous statement but it is not because this statement if A then B is a claim in the system,

    it is possibly an axiom or a theorem depending on previously assumed axioms. So it’s a claim. It is not

    necessarily actually true. But within the system it is a claim and we shall treat it as if it were true for

    argument’s sake. Then if we determine that A is true, then B is true. The statement “if A, then B”

    simply connects the truth values of A and B, it makes no statement about the truth of A. If we find out

    the truth of A by some means, then the truth of B is to be concluded. This is the rule of modus ponens.

    If you have a long list of dependencies such if this then this then this then this and if the first one is

    true, then you can deduce the last one. This is the essence of mathematical proof.

    Substitution tells us that we may substitute a particular object for a general term in a logical deduction.

    Suppose we have the following statement: For every table, the table has four legs. The rule of

    substitution says that the general term “table” can be replaced by a reference to a particular individual

    table we happen to consider and so will allow us to deduce that this table has four legs. From general

    statements, we may deduce particular statements.

    Those are the only two rules we need for classical logic. Put together some primitives, axioms and

    these two rules of manipulating the axioms and they give us logic: mathematical logic. In the case of

    Aristotle, the primitives are “equal,” “true,” “negation” and “and.” The axioms are: (1) A equals A, (2)

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    20/279

      20

    A is true or false, (3) A and negation of A can not both be true where “false” is defined as the negation

    of true and “or” is defined as the negation of the negation of A and the negation of B. Already you can

    see this is getting complicated without the use of symbols. Introducing symbols, we can shorten the tale

    a great deal. They may look scary at first but they allow us to write complicated arguments in a neat

    way so that we may better see if we are making any logical errors. Discovering logical errors while

    using a language familiar to us from daily life is very difficult indeed.

    An important fact is that any statement is a theorem if and only if it is a tautology. Recall that a

    theorem is a statement which follows from the axioms by applying the rules of logic. A tautology is

    any statement that is true, no matter if the statements involved in it are true themselves. An example is

    “A or the negation of A.” As the statement A is allowed to either be true or false, one of the two

    statements A or the negation of it must be true and hence this claim is always true, no matter what truth

    value A has.

    Saying that something is something else if and only if   some condition is satisfied is a typical

    mathematical way of saying that what preceeds the “if and only if” is the same statement as that which

    follows it. The phrase “if and only if” is typically abbreviated by “iff.” So we can write a mathematical

    theorem like this: A iff B. This means that A is true if B is true and only if B is true, i.e. if B is false, A

    is also false. Thus the truth value of A must be equal to that of B whatever it may be. Therefore we can

    say that A and B are the same statement with respect to truth content.

    1.7 Truth and Falsehood

    “Whatsoever is descendent from the tree of cognition carries the dichotomy in it.”

    The Sefer Zohar

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    21/279

      21

    Logic enables us to deduce statements from premises while keeping the truth content of them constant.

    Plato liked to believe that the universe is a poor reflection of the ideal universe in which all the ideas

    that we use, such as tables, exist in the pure state. He claimed that this truth was absolute truth. Hilbert,

    on the other hand, was a mathematician who made the opposite claim that mathematics is just

    manipulating marks of ink on paper and has absolutely no connection whatsoever to reality. All you do

    is you set up a few axioms, you mark down a few bits of ink on your paper and you make up a few

    rules for transforming those marks of ink into other marks of ink. Applying the rules and seeing ever

    more complex patterns of ink emerge is mathematics according to Hilbert. He was one of the best

    mathematicians who ever lived and, of course, it is an extreme case but it deserves to be considered.

    The possible truth values according to Aristotle are only two: truth and falsehood. Buddhism adds a

    third: nonsense. Its possible to say true and false statements but also nonsense. Actually most things

    according to Buddhism fall under the category of nonsense. The most popular statement that they

    choose to exemplify nonsense is “a flower in the sky.”. A flower needs to be on the ground. It can not

     be up in the sky and therefore that statement is nonsense. It is against the definition of what a flower is

    to be in the sky.

    Some logics add varying degress of may be. I can state that my car is on the parking lot. Bue I am not

    exactly 100% sure. Somebody could have stolen from when I saw it last and I would not know. From

    my point of view this statement has to be a probable statement with a certain, hopefully, high degree of

     probability. Because of lack of information, this probability is necessarily less than 100%. That leads us

    to fuzzy logic which is an engineering system that has been built quite recently and which incorporates

    degrees of uncertainty because of lack of evidence.

    Q: Is your car not definitely on the parking lot or off, why does it matter that you can not see it?

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    22/279

      22

    That is the whole dispute. I am myself. You are a figment of my imagination. But even though I see

    you, you might not exist. This is really quite difficult to determine. Is the statement true? What does

    true mean? Is it true in an absolute way? Is there some God-like observer who determines what is true

    and false and I am simple too stupid to find out? Or is only that true that I personally, as an individual,

    determine to be true myself. This is of course the operational approach of engineering. Only those

    things are true which I have observed to be true. I do not observe my car, therefore it is not necessarily

    where I think it is. Even though some God-like being might exist who does see it. So this is a matter of

     philosophy. You must decide whether you are going to allow the existence of absolute truth in the

    absence of the possibility of verification or not.

    Q: What exactly do you mean by “nonsense,” does it apply to the so-called “logical paradoxes?”

     Nonsense refers to any statement which you cannot determine to have one definite truth value. A

    statement essentially goes against the definition of the very thing, such as “flower in the sky.” It is

    against the definition of a flower to exist without ground. Logical paradoxes will fall in that category.

    1.8 Logical Operations and Relations

    “For I am the first and the last. I am the honored and the scorned. I am the saint and the prostitute.”

     Nag Hammadi

     Now we start with the symbolism. If something is true then the negation of it is false. If something is

    false then the negation of it is true.

    TF

    FT

    -A A

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    23/279

      23

     Now this table is called the truth table. A will be a symbol, a variable. It can be equal to any statement.

    A is equal to “green cheese” is not allowed because it is not a statement which has a truth value. A

    logical statement must make a claim. So A is equal to “there is green cheese on this table” is a valid

    statement. It has to be a statement of a fact.

    Any statement is either true or false according to Aristotle’s system. The negation is just the opposite.

    We shall meet more complicated truth tables later on. But negation is actually the most complicated of

    all logical operations. All the other ones are simple. Negation is like the complement of a set. Let us

    say we have a set. The set is defined as the set of all people. With negation I want to say “not people,”

    the set of all things that are not people. Taking the set of all things which are not in a given set is called

    complementation. This already is complicated. The set of all people is well defined. There is a finite

    number of people and the set of all people contains all of them. But what is not people? Not people is

    everything minus a little bit, people. But what is everything? With respect to what am I to negate, from

    what am I going to subtract people? With respect to what do we negate statements?

    In the case of Aristotle, it is simple. There are two truth values and negation chooses the other one. As

    soon as there are more than two things, we must be very careful with defining negation or

    complementation, especially when it includes an infinite number of things such as everything.

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    24/279

      24

    Russel’s paradox makes the problem with negation very apparent. We ask for sets of things and we ask

    if the members of those sets can be members of themselves or not. For example the set of all teacups is

    a set and clearly not itself a teacup and thus an example of a set which does not include itself. The set

    of all non teacups is a set which is not a teacup and thus this is an example of set which does include

    itself.

    Being convinced that both self-inclusive and self-exclusive sets exist, we ask whether the set of all set

    which are self-exclusive is itself self-inclusive. If it is self-inclusive then we get a contradiction because

    the set has only such sets as members which are self-exclusive. So we think that it must be self-

    exclusive. If it is, then it can not include itself but it was defined as the set of all  sets which are self-

    exclusive. So both possibilities lead to a contradiction and thus we have a paradox. This illustrates how

    difficult the use of the operation of negation and the use of the word “all” can be. Much caution is

    required in their use particularly if the set of “everything” with respect to which one negates is infinite.

    I will not discuss this paradox further here. Much can be said and the resolution of Betrand Russel to

    his own paradox is a three volume work. We will look at paradoxes to some extent in the exercises.

    The resolution is that we agree, as an extra axiom of the system. We define that sets of objects are of

    first “type.” Sets of sets of objects are of second type and so on. The axiom is that one must not

    compare sets of different type. That’s an additional axiom of set theory that Russel introduced and with

    that the paradox is resolved because the set of all sets is of higher type than the set itself.

    FFF

    FFT

    FTF

    TTT

     A ?  BB A

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    25/279

      25

    So A and B are two different statements. They can be true or false. There are two possibilities each.

    “And” is a relation between two statements and it is going to be defined to be true only if both

    components are true. If any one of them is false, then the combination is false.

    FFF

    TFT

    TTF

    TTT

     A ?  BB A

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    26/279

      26

    The relation “or” is slightly more complex from an everyday point of view. For example: “Do you

    want your coffee with milk or sugar?” Is it acceptable to want both or not? Clearly it is ok to say I want

    sugar. It is also clearly ok to say I want milk. But is it allowed in the system, if I view this on a strict

    level, to say I want both milk and sugar. Well, that has to be agreed upon, if that is going to be allowed.

    Is it an exclusive “or” which forces me to pick one but not both. It is an inclusive “or” which allows me

    to choose both. In the truth table, you can see that we have defined an inclusive “or.”

    TFTTFF

    TFFTTF

    FTTFFT

    TFFTTT

    - A ?  -B A ?  -B-B A ?  B A

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    27/279

      27

    Two statements may be connected in the form “if A, then B.” If something is true then something else

    must be true also. If A is true then the whole claim is true if and only if B is also true. If A is false

    however, the whole statement is true regardless of whether B is true or false.

    Q: Why?

    You must not ask why? This is a definition of the concept “if …, then …” This is one of the crucial

    things. You must not question its truth. It is simply a definition. The only reason we introduce thearrow notation is to make writing simpler in the future. We do not need it as I am going to illustrate

     below.

    Consider negating B and combining it with A using the “and” relation. The results are shown in the

    truth table. Lastly, negative this whole combination and we see that the truth values are exactly the

    same as the ones for the arrow. As far as truth behaviour goes (and this is all we care about in logic),those two operations are identical. In this way we may use the last column as a definition for the

    dependence relation “if …, then …” Later we shall find it convinient to use the dependence relation

    directly and this is why it is notationally nice to introduce here. From a fundmental point of view, it is

    unnecessary as it is the same as a certain combination of negations and intersections. This is the

    equivalence of two syntactically distinct statements. Syntactically distinct but still equivalent, that is

    important. You can have many statements that look different but are actually the same.

    1.9 Conclusions

    Logic itself is based on assumptions. We must   assume something. There are many distinct logics of

    which I have presented the one that Aristotle invented. The consistency is the most important

    characteristic. Consistency is the third Aristotle rule that nothing may have two truth values at the same

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    28/279

      28

    time. If that were allowed, then your whole reasoning indefinite. But everything else, you are allowed

    to deny. Even the statement that a is equal to a, you are allowed to deny. So, to sum it up, a logical

    theory must have these things. It must have primitive terms. It must have axioms that are only stated in

    terms of primitive terms. It must have a logic. In other words, a method to transform axioms into

    conclusions and the correspondence to reality is something all together different. It is something

    outside the system.

    Q: What is the difference between Kant’s a priori truths and Aristotle’s logic axioms as presented here?

    The difference is in belief not in content. I state the system and I say it is an assumption. We shall

    simply agree upon axioms and take it from there. Kant says that the axioms are actually

    transcendentally true of reality itself. That is, it is not an assumption to him but a statement of a

     property of reality. For me, it is an assumption without claim at the truth. The content of the statements

    is exactly the same, they differ in the extent to which they are claimed true of reality.

    Q: Is Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory the most eligible one to describe Russell’s paradox?

    There are many set theories. All set theories are created equal and there are no pigs amongst them that

    are more equal than others. Even within the Zermelo-Fraenkel system there is a lot of dispute about

    some of the axioms, particularly the axiom of choice. No set theory is more applicable than another.Russell’s paradox occurs in almost all of them. That is to say in all set theories that have not been

     patched by the theory of types which was Russell’s answer to his own paradox. In fact, Russell’s

     paradox came up in the review of Frege’s book on set theory. So historically it can be viewed as a

    direct attack on Frege’s particular version of set theory.

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    29/279

      29

    1.10 Appendix: The Dog-Walking Ordinance

    The following selection makes the importance of clear expression in logical conversation very

    apparent. It is taken from “The Reader Over Your Shoulder: A Handbook for Writers of English Prose”

     by Robert Graves and Alan Hodge (Random House, 1979).

    “From the Minutes of a Borough Council Meeting:

    Councillor Trafford took exception to the proposed notice at the entrance of South Park: ‘No dogs must

     be brought to this Park except on a lead.’ He pointed out that this order would not prevent an owner

    from releasing his pets, or pet, from a lead when once safely inside the Park.

    The Chairman (Colonel Vine): What alternative wording would you propose, Councillor?

    Councillor Trafford: ‘Dogs are not allowed in this Park without leads.’

    Councillor Hogg: Mr. Chairman, I object. The order should be addressed to the owners, not to the

    dogs.

    Councillor Trafford: That is a nice point. Very well then: ‘Owners of dogs are not allowed in this Park

    unless they keep them on leads.’

    Councillor Hogg: Mr. Chairman, I object. Strictly speaking, this would prevent me as a dog-owner

    from leaving my dog in the back-garden at home and walking with Mrs. Hogg across the Park.

    Councillor Trafford: Mr. Chairman, I suggest that our legalistic friend be asked to redraft the notice

    himself.

    Councillor Hogg: Mr. Chairman, since Councillor Trafford finds it so difficult to improve on my

    original wording, I accept. ‘Nobody without his dog on a lead is allowed in this Park.’

    Councillor Trafford: Mr. Chairman, I object. Strictly speaking, this notice would prevent me, as a

    citizen, who owns no dog, from walking in the Park without first acquiring one.

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    30/279

      30

    Councillor Hogg (with some warmth): Very simply, then: ‘Dogs must be led in this Park.’

    Councillor Trafford: Mr. Chairman, I object. This reads as if it were a general injunction to the

    Borough to lead their dogs into the Park.

    Councillor Hogg interposed a remark for which he was called to order; upon his withdrawing it, it was

    directed to be expunged from the Minutes.

    The Chairman: Councillor Trafford, Councillor Hogg has had three tries; you have had only two …

    Councillor Trafford: ‘All dogs must be kept on leads in this Park.’

    The Chairman: I see Councillor Hogg rising quite rightly to raise another objection. May I anticipate

    him with another amendment: ‘All dogs in this Park must be kept on the lead.’

    This draft was put to the vote and carried unanimously, with two abstentions.”

    Lecture 3: The Structure of an Ax iomatic System

    3.1 Aristotle and His Followers

    “Common sense is not what you need if you’re going to find out anything worth knowing; it is

    uncommon sense.”

    Prof. Z as quoted by Eric Temple Bell

    “Whatever is, is right.”

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    31/279

      31

    Alexander Pope

    This professor Z that has been quoted by Eric Temple Bell is a famous mathematician, who at the time

    did not want to reveal his identity; that is why he is called professor Z. This is an opinion of very

    qualified person. Bell himself is a famous mathematician. And it is true. This is what is going to apply

    with logic because if you want to find out anything truly fundamental you have to modify, not the

    super-structure, but the basics. So anything “common” you do not want – you want to modify the very

    fundamental assumptions of reality as a whole. Then you can find something really worthwhile.

    Alexnder Pope was an English poet and his claim was that “whatever is, is right”. So he defines reality

    as true or truth as that which is real. We can view this quote on a few different levels. We can treat

    either truth or reality as previously defined or basic and then take Pope’s statement as a definition of

    the other concept, i.e. a definition of a synonym for the previously known word, or we can view both

    concepts as previously known and Pope’s statement as a claim for a theorem. Everything depends upon

    the basis of the system.

    Atistotle and his followers used what were in the last lecture called conceptual truths, which are

    sometimes called a priori truths. What they are meant to be is that they are supposed to be self-evident.

    In another words they are not in need of any logical proof. Logical proof in the mathematical sense is

    only possible if you make certain assumptions. Any theorem that you may prove is true in relation to

    the assumption and you must not question the assumptions, of course. But this is not what is meant by

    self-evident. They mean self-evident in the sense that they are clear regardless of anything that you

    might throw at them. There are true without any experience. Even if you are alive without sensory

    input: no eyes, no ears and so on, you should be able to regard these statement as true. So we do not

    look at reality or hear something and then make deductions from this and come to the conclusions that

    such and such statements about reality is true. Conceptual or a priori truths are true totally independent

    of any experience that we might have.

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    32/279

      32

    A conceptual truth is not derivable from premises, it is a premise which is regarded to be true in and of

    itself. If it were derivable from premises it would be proven in terms of them, i.e. it would be a

    theorem. So it is not deductive. It is not inductive either. Induction is when I make a few experiences

    and generalize those to all possible experiences of a certain type that I might possibly have. That is

    induction but it is still based on some experience. I have to have made a certain few experiences before

    I can induct to the general one. The conceptual truth is completely self-evident. Out of innate ideas this

    statement is regarded to be true. Aristotle and his tradition have had a very profound influence on

    mathematics as a whole. From the time Aristotle wrote it until approximately 1930 when a few

    Hungarians came up with some more logics, Aristotle’s logic was regarded, even by mathematicians to

     be “the only single logic” possible. This is a pretty major statement now that we know that there are

    many logics, in fact an infinite number of logics.

    For a long time and during the lifetime of most of the famous mathematicians you hear about, this was

    not at all regarded to be such. They really thought that the logic of Aristotle was ‘the’ single logic and

    it was self-evidently true. With the advent of questioning logic, which came together with questioning

    geometry, several schools of thought formed within mathematics. The mathematicians began to really

    think about what truth actually is. For millenium we thought that the Aristotle was the answer. Now we

    know that he is one answer among many. Somehow we must choose intelligently between them in

    some fashion. We cannot choose logically because of course that is the very thing that we are trying to

    choose.

    There are two main schools of thought in mathematics which differ very extremely. The intuitionist

    mathematicians are different from the philosophers who call themselves intuitionists. The intuitional

    mathematicians are basically Platonists. They believe that a mathematical idea actually exists in a super

    reality of ideas and exists in a pure state independently of us who are thinking about it and the way we

    formulate it. The way we think about it is a poor man’s version of the real idea that lives in the ideal

    space. To sum it up, an intuitional mathematician, when he proves a theorem, makes a discovery. He

    discovers something, which is true, which has already existed in this realm of ideas for all eternity until

    this mathematician simply manages to discover it. In that sense mathematics is a science that discovers

    things.

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    33/279

      33

    On the other hand you have the formalist mathematician. This is David Hilbert’s school which

     basically says that the axioms and the rules to transform axioms are nothing more than marks of ink on

     paper. They have no meaning whtsoever. They have no relation to reality whatsoever. Questioning

    their truth or their meaning is entirely senseless. We simply modify marks of ink into other marks of

    ink and if you attach a meaning to this or if you claim any of this is true, you are no longer a

    mathematician – you have become a natural scientist or philosopher. From this point of view the

    mathematician can never discover anything. He can only invent things and the only question of any

    relevance is if such an invention is in any way useful. The question “is it true?” is totally irrelevant to

    the formalist from the point of view of mathematics. If you want to apply any of these inventedmathematical concepts to the natural sciences, the question “is it true?” becomes very relevant. But as

    far as mathematics in and of itself is concerned, for the formalist, it is invention entirely and, for the

    intuitionist, discovery entirely. To this day, there exist these two schools and several others of medium

    flavor and the mathematician has to choose to which school he or she belongs. It is up to you.

    Personally I belong to the formalist school. I think that if you demand that things are true about the

    reality, you are no longer doing mathematics, you have suddenly jumped to physics or to another

    natural science. I do not believe that mathematical ideas exists in an ideal state. So I would say any

    discovery I have made is not a discovery at all, it is an invention. I dream it up and it has its own

    reality, within the minds of those who read about it. There are many others who are of the intuitional

    variety. There can be many fights between these two schools but because they differ in fundamental

    assumptions, it is not really fair to compare the two. That statement in itself is a formalists statement of

    course because to the intuitionist the fundamental ideas which form the assumptions exists in a pure

    state and so should be capable of comparison. This is why you can fight but you must not become

    angry because the two are just different starting points for developing mathematics.

    In the last lecture, four concepts were mentioned that Aristotle made to describe his metaphysics and a

    long explnation was given of each. Form the point of view of mthematics we would have to regard

    these four concepts as “primitive terms.” They essentially incapable of a definition within the system.

    A definition can be given but that definition is necessarily outside of the system and so this definition

     becomes a mere motivation for introducing that new term. We were given these terms, such as

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    34/279

      34

    substance and cause, and we understand to some extent what those mean. But this understanding is not

    within the system. They are meta or outside the system, hence the term “metaphysics”.

    3.2 The Axiomatic System

    “Through natural things, we obtain physical powers; through abstract, mathematical and heavenly

    things, we obtain transcendent powers.”

    Heinrich Cornelius Agrippa von Nettesheim (1510)

    Agrippa already claimed that mathematical thinking and mathematical inventions are more important

    than natural sciences. You can have some insight into the nature of reality that goes beyond sense

     perception. Physics and chemistry and such of course deal only with things that we can perceive with

    the senses and abstract mathematical and heavenly things can go beyond that and that is why they are,

    in some sense, better. We shall meet the alchemists again later on, for the moment that is all I want to

    say about them.

    We know that we must have primitive terms from our previous discussions. Let us me make a

    distinction. Primitives can come in three flavours. First of all they may be objects. Those are, if you

    will, proper nouns. I can say “table” or “set” for example. Those are objects in and of themselves. They

    can have a meaning. Of course the meaning is not within the system. But they are to be regarded as

    things. Then there can be relations. These are also primitive terms. The relation “between,” for

    example. In geometry, we have the relation “between” applied to three points. It is not, however, an

    object. It requires objects to make sense. The third kind of primitive is an operation, for example,

    negation. While a relation connects several objects, an operation changes one object into another one.

    The operation of negation changes the statement A into the statement “not A.” Those are the three

    kinds of primitive terms and, in general, we need all three of them to construct an axiomatic theory. In

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    35/279

      35

    other words, to make meaningful conclusions we have to have objects to talk about, a method to

    change an object into another and a method to connect several objects together.

    Q: Can you operate upon an operation?

     No. Once you have operated once, the result is a changed object. You may operate again but then this

    operation is upon the changed object and not the operation. You may think that the usual law of double

    negation, i.e. “not not A is the same as A” is an operation upon an operation but it is not. First youoperate upon A with negation and get the changed object “not A” then you operate again to obtain “not

    not A.” It just so happens, because of the way “not” was defined that negating twice brings us back to

    the starting point.

    The axioms, which are the basic statements that we agree to be true for the system, are formulated only

    using these primitives. So you have to somehow make sentences out of the primitives to form theaxioms. As an analogy consider the the English language. Objects are nouns, relations are verbs and

     pronouns and operations are adjectives and adverbs. The axioms here are sentences that we agree are to

    hold. As we know from grammar, we need nouns, verbs, pronouns, adjectives and adverbs to make

    meaningful sentences.

    All the words that appear in the axioms must be either primitives or other words that have been definedin terms of the primitives. The primitives themselves have no definition. As we discussed in my last

    lecture with the dictionary example, every word in the English language has a definition in terms of the

    others words in the English language. But you must, at some point, pick a set of words that we simply

    agree are known to be able to learn the others. Those few are incapable of a definition within the

    system unless you allow circularity. Of course, circularity shall not be allowed because that would

    remove any meaning from the system whatsoever. You must have a starting point. So primitives in

    Aristotle’s case, for example substance and cause, are simply words. If we agree that they mean

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    36/279

      36

    something we are outside of a logical system based on these words. If we define them in terms of other

    words, some of these other words must be basic terms. The axioms that we formulate in terms of these

     basic primitives are not conceptual truths. They are simply statements that we agree to be true; true as

     parts of the system, not true absolutely or true of reality. Many mathematicians have regarded such

    axioms to be conceptual truths. A long time ago, Euclid formulated his famous geometrical axioms. He

    regarded them as conceptual truths and for thousands of years mathematicians followed along until

    very recently this was shown to be wrong.

    So axioms are regarded to be true, agreed to be true but they are not self-evidently true. In such a way

    the axioms are like a rule of a game. Chess and the rules of chess are not true; neither are they false.

    You simply agree to uphold them. If you cheat, if you disobey any rules of chess, you suddenly play a

    different game. The new game you play is not true or false but it is contradictory to the original rules

    laid down for the game called “chess.” If you disobey the rules of a game, you are playing a different

    game; truth does not come into it. This brings us to an important point about “fallacies.” Many authors,

     particularly philosophical authors, spend a great deal of time talking about fallacies – obtaining

    conclusions that do not follow from the axioms. A fallacy is a claim which does not follow from the

    given axioms. It is thus the result of disobeying a rule of the game which the axiomatic theory

    embodies. So from the mathematician’s point of view a fallacy is simply ignoring or applying

    incorrectly one of the rules of the game. That is all I want to say about them but in philosophical

    textbooks you will find a lengthy discussions on various types of fallacy.

    Axiomatic systems can have several properties. The five most important ones will be discussed here:

    Equivalence, Consistency, Independence, Completeness and Categoricalness. The last two are really

    the same property and equivalence is not a property of a single axiom system, it is a relation between

    two of them.

    3.3 The Model Concept for an Axiomatic System

  • 8/17/2019 Deductionandreality_patrick D Bangert

    37/279

      37

    The formalist views axioms as sentences in terms of primitive terms and not as conceptual truths and

    logic as a method to transform these statements into other statements called theorems. To the formalist,

    this transformation process is mathematics.

    If we want to talk about the axioms, we are doing “metamathematics,” i.e. going beyond the system

    that is mathematics. You do metamathematics if you talk about primitives and axioms using normal

    language. For example, if you write a book about it or explain concepts to others. When you read a

    textbook about mathematics, there are lots of explanations about what the technical terms mean and

    how the proofs are constructed. All of this is metamathematics. Only the actual symbols, formulae and

    the derivations within the proofs are mathematics. All the rest is explanation. Of course the explanation

    is crucial for understanding and communication but it is important to differentiate between the

    substance and the presentation.

    In theory you should not need all these explanations. The explanations are just there to expediate the

    learning process of mathematics. It is not essential. That is why it is metamathematics. It gives these

     basic terms, the primitives and the axioms some meaning and the axioms some truth. And this is called

    a model.

    A model is some object for which the primitives have a meaning and the axioms are true. An example

    is Euclid’s geometry. Euclid’s geometry is an axiomatic system that has primitives such as “point�