DD and Ignorance

download DD and Ignorance

of 17

Transcript of DD and Ignorance

  • 8/6/2019 DD and Ignorance

    1/17

    Jay Carlson May 13, 2011

    Deliberative Democracy and IgnorancePhil 735: Cont. Political Philosophy

    Prof. Justin Weinberg

    The intuitive appeal of democratic decision mechanisms and procedures for choosing

    policies is that the ultimate and decisive decision about which policies and leaders are put into

    practice lies in the citizens who live under that democratic regime. The citizensand neither

    a dictator nor a relatively small group of elitesdecide what policies they are to live under

    based on their own preferences and opinions about what should be done. Yet, leaving the

    decisions of public policy to the raw preferences of the populace is also part of the inherent

    flaw of democratic decision mechanisms: are the individual citizens that make up the

    electorate in a position to make adequate decisions about public policy? There are many

    reasons to think that most of the citizens are not adequately equipped to make such decisions.

    Chief among these reasons, as demonstrated by Illya Somin, is that huge swathes of the

    electorate are demonstrably ignorant about many critical factors necessary for making an

    informed decision about political matters.

    This widespread ignorance threatens not only the legitimacy of generic democratic

    mechanisms, but in particular the mechanisms of deliberative democracy, a species of

    democratic theory that is quite prominent in contemporary political philosophy. Since

    deliberative democracy locates the legitimacy of its decisions precisely in the citizens ability

    to make informed and rational political decisions through the procedure of deliberating with

    each other (Freeman 375), if the ignorance of the citizenry is wide spread and ineradicable,

    then deliberative democracy is at best a nave ideal. I intend to show that the ignorance

    Somin claims is so debilitating for deliberative democracy can be overcome.

    In what ways are many voting citizens ignorant? Somin notes that, at minimum,

    voters should be aware of not only that a given issue exists and what each candidates position

  • 8/6/2019 DD and Ignorance

    2/17

    Carlson 2

    on the issue is, but also of which position is most likely to promote the individual voters own

    interests (Somin 1998, 415). Voters also ought to be aware of the ideological consistency

    between positions and the tradeoffs that each position requires: one cannot be an advocate for

    both lower taxes and an expansion of the services the government provides (Somin 1998,

    418). Finally, they must be able to discern which policies or policy leaders are deserving of

    credit or blame for the outcomes that happen after they are put in place. By all of these

    metrics, most citizens in Western democracies fail miserably, with many being unable to

    answer even rudimentary questionnaires about government structure and candidates

    positions, much less the higher-level questions of ideological consistency and blame of

    criticism (Somin 443).

    Some might say that these appalling statistics of is simply a matter of mass

    misinformedness (Talisse 460). There are two problems with this view. First, this period of

    mass ignorance is also a period of unprecedented amounts of high-quality information being

    available, often free of charge on public television and radio stations (Somin 1998, 419). This

    problem of mass ignorance does not seem solvable by a simple increase in information

    availability or quality. Second, the ignorance that Somin describes is more than just a simple

    matter of misinformedness or even of culpable agent-ignorance due to an individuals

    incompetence (Talisse 461). The critical form of ignorance at play here, as first outlined by

    Anthony Downs, is ignorance as the rational outcome of a collective action problem (Somin

    1998, 444). Acquiring sufficient knowledge to be adequately informed about political matters

    is a costly, time-consuming ordeal that many citizens do not have the leisure to pursue

    because occupational and familial responsibilities consume the bulk of their waking hours.

    Furthermore, even if they were to commit large amounts of their resources to becoming

  • 8/6/2019 DD and Ignorance

    3/17

    Carlson 3

    politically well informed, their well informed vote would likely have very little impact on the

    outcome of the election. In an election with an electorate in the hundreds of millions, the

    likelihood of casting the deciding vote is infinitesimal. The well informedness of that vote

    will not raise that probability at all. Thus, the miniscule utility gained by becoming informed

    enough to cast a well informed ballot is almost always offset by the much greater costs

    involved with becoming more politically informed. The conclusion Somin draws is that a

    rational personeven one with relatively altruistic dispositions towards promoting the public

    good of composing an informed electorate (Somin 2010, 260)would not devote the time

    necessary to become politically informed (Somin 1998, 437).

    Standard democratic procedure states that decisions about public policy are made by

    citizens registering their preferences by voting for one candidate or another (Freeman 373-4).

    Insofar as these aggregations of raw preference accounts of democracy presuppose adequately

    informed votes (Freeman 375), voter ignorance seems to question the viability of said

    democratic procedures. But the fact of voter ignorance is even more troubling to deliberative

    democracy. Deliberative democracy critiques raw preference accounts of democracy, saying

    that they require too little of voters, and that only a more rigorous form of decision making

    would be able to weed out unreasonable preferences and deliver truly acceptable public

    policies. The procedure of free deliberation among equal [citizens] is the source of a

    political decisions legitimacy (Cohen 3).

    What does such a procedure expect of its participants? The procedure is largely a

    discussion over what constitutes the common good of all citizensor at least as many citizens

    as possible (Freeman 375). Effective deliberation requires participants to abstract from their

    own personal preferences and consider a situation from the most impartial point of view

  • 8/6/2019 DD and Ignorance

    4/17

    Carlson 4

    possible. Frequently this impartial point of view is cashed out in terms of the principles of

    civility and reciprocity, where one appeals only to reasons that are considered public and that

    other deliberators might find acceptable (Freeman 398). Thus, this rigorous procedure is

    more demanding on participants in terms of requiring them to be able to tease out which

    reasons they have for their preferences are sufficiently public and acceptable to others. Somin

    notes that deliberation might even include sophisticated moral and philosophical issues as

    well as subtle empirical issues, all of which must be handled rationally (Somin 2010, 257). If

    voters fail to meet even the basic benchmarks required of them in a relatively generic

    democracyindeed, if they fail to correctly identify basic factual informationthen they are

    even more inadequate for the higher standards required of them by deliberative democracy

    (Somin 1998, 440).

    If voter ignorance is a specific outcome of a collective action problem, then the

    solution might come from two directions: either one could reduce the costs on individuals for

    acquiring knowledge leading to sufficient informedness or increase the efficacy of a well

    informed vote. The first avenue is usually approached by informational shortcuts that, in

    theory, shift the burden of knowledge acquisition away from individual citizens and onto a

    myriad of other entitiese.g. political parties and punditsthat have less of an opportunity

    cost to acquire political knowledge than the individual citizen. Somin reviews many

    variations on this shortcut theme, and his assessment is not optimistic: many of these

    shortcuts are more prone to engendering myopic, unjustified bias than cultivating clarity and

    full-informedness (Somin 1998, 431). Shortcuts are therefore often more harmful than they

    are helpful. Furthermore, Somin notes that when individuals do engage in political debate it

  • 8/6/2019 DD and Ignorance

    5/17

    Carlson 5

    is frequently done in a way that confirms their antecedent beliefs (Somin 2010, 254).1At best,

    effective use of shortcuts requires a pre-existing base of background knowledge that many

    voters lack (Somin 2010, 262). The other flank, of increasing the efficacy of well informed

    votes, to solving this problem, has been less popular in the literature. John Stuart Mills

    suggestion that more well informed votes should count for more votes stands as perhaps the

    most prominent way of directly increasing the efficacy of well informed votes. Giving weight

    directly to one set of voters, however, is blatantly undemocratic, and thus undercuts the very

    aim of democracy that deliberative democrats wish to defend. Such a strategy would also

    vindicate Somins worries that deliberative democracy would privilege certain people who

    had the skills and training necessary for effective deliberation, turning an explicitly

    democratic project into an essentially oligarchic setup (Somin 1998, 443).

    Nevertheless, one approach that attempts to attackboth flanks of the collective-action

    problem of rational ignorance through the use of deliberation is Bruce Ackerman and James

    Fishkins proposal of a deliberative holiday in their bookDeliberation Day. On this holiday,

    presidential candidates give an initial presentation to a cross-section sample of the population.

    The sample population is also given independent information on the issues. Then participants

    break down into small groups and deliberate about which questions should be asked about

    each candidates platform. When the groups come to a consensus on which questions should

    be asked, the questions are then presented to the candidates who will then be given time to

    respond. There are several rounds of this discursive to-and-fro. At the conclusion of this

    1 Political programming is often advertised with phrases such as reasoned or fair and

    balanced, leading some to think that reasoned engagement remains an important selling point

    in political advertising (Talisse 464). Nevertheless, the advertisements indication that theproducers of these programs cherish reasoned discussion frequently belies the actual content

    and procedures of these shows, leading one to conclude that reason is only used in

    advertisements to attract viewers, not to actually engage in its use.

  • 8/6/2019 DD and Ignorance

    6/17

    Carlson 6

    deliberative day, the sample populationhaving been given the chance to listen to sustained

    presentation of candidates messages, reflect and deliberate with other citizens, pose questions

    to the candidates and hear their responsesthen votes on which candidate they think is the

    superior one. This sample population, Ackerman and Fishkin claim, would represent how a

    well informed populace might evaluate a set of candidates.

    How does this holiday proposal solve the collective action problem of rational

    ignorance? It does so by changing the incentive structure that makes ignorance otherwise

    instrumentally rational (Ackerman and Fishkin 2002, 133). There are several ways that a

    deliberative holiday reduces the costs and the efficacy of attaining knowledge about politics.

    First, by taking place on a holiday when many businesses are closed anyway and by providing

    a small financial stipend to participants (Ackerman and Fishkin 2004, 29), the opportunity and

    financial costs of taking the time to deliberate on presidential candidates are either mitigated

    or compensated for. Second, the efficacy of the participants opinions and reasons has the

    potential to increase as well, though in the indirectmanner of influencing other peoples

    opinions and preferences. While in deliberation, each participant has the potential to persuade

    other participants that certain difficult questions must be asked about a candidates otherwise

    attractive proposal. Their voices are not lost in an endless sea of ballots, but all are given a

    forum to speak in small groups, where they are engaging with other individuals face to face

    (Ackerman and Fishkin 2002, 134).

    Furthermore, the individual participants efficacy extends not only to the other

    participants, but even to non-participants as well. The participants contributions to the well

    informed opinion of the holidays final results by be seen by non-participants as an opinion

    they ought to take seriously in deciding how to cast their own ballot. What Ackerman and

  • 8/6/2019 DD and Ignorance

    7/17

    Carlson 7

    Fishkin conclude is that even citizens who are normally rationally compelled to be ignorant

    about politics are more than capable of living up to the demands of deliberative democracy

    provided that they are given good reasons to think that living up to that standard would be

    efficacious (Ackerman and Fishkin 2004, 7).

    While this deliberative holiday proposal might work toward mitigating the costs of

    political knowledge acquisition and increasing the ceiling of efficacy of well informed votes,

    there are still outstanding questions over whether this proposal can actually achieve, (1) the

    very difficult standards that deliberative democracy sets out, and (2) achieve (1) in a way that

    individual citizens could have rational incentive to participate.

    First, What reason do we have to think that deliberation can sufficiently overcome the

    antecedent ignorance of the participants? Ackerman and Fishkin note that there are a few

    days of preparation where the participants are given reading and information to prepare them

    for their deliberative exercises (Ackerman and Fishkin 2004, 70), but why should we think

    that this would overcome the ignorance the participants already have? Somin notes, if actual

    voters tend to be close-minded and unwilling to accept opposing evidence, it seems unlikely

    that many of them can engage in the sort of unbiased dialogue deliberative democrats

    champion, which leads Somin to predict that deliberation is likely to degenerate into just

    repetitive talking points, if not something more hostile and confrontational (Somin 2010,

    264). But Somins prediction that deliberation will almost certainly degenerate in such a

    spectacular fashion does not fit the experimental findings. In many instances of deliberative

    polling, a small-scale cousin to the deliberative holiday, Fishkin found that deliberation

    changed the opinion on up to 2/3rds of the questions the participants answered before the

    deliberation took place (Ackerman and Fishkin 2004, 52). There is also anecdotal evidence to

  • 8/6/2019 DD and Ignorance

    8/17

    Carlson 8

    suggest that small deliberation groups can bring even deeply prejudiced people to a greater

    degree of mutual understanding (Ackerman and Fishkin 2002, 141). We need not be

    completely quixotic that deliberation will suddenly transform intransigent devils into

    conciliatory angels, but the evidence does not seem to fit with Somins rather dismal

    prediction. Furthermore, the disinclination of the participants to look foolish or unprepared at

    a very public event might have an anticipation effect which incentivizes private study by

    individuals to equip themselves for the holiday (Ackerman and Fishkin 2002, 140).

    A central part of Ackerman and Fishkins thesis that a deliberative holiday can be an

    effective way to cultivate an engaged, well informed populace is that deliberation does appear

    to have an effect on participants. Nevertheless, change in opinion does not necessarily entail

    that the updated opinions would satisfy the lofty standards of deliberative democracy that

    Somin described. A changed opinion can be just as ill informed as the original one. Yet it

    seems that the requirements for deliberative democracy is less about cognitive possession than

    Somin suggests. Somin seems to conflate where individual citizens begin the deliberation

    with where the deliberations collective decision ends. Deliberation does not require ready-

    made, fully informed deliberators at its outset: if that were the case, then deliberation would

    be unnecessary. It seems more plausible to suggest that deliberative democracy desires that

    whatever decision the deliberators reach, it should be one that is fully informed by all the

    interests and preferences that are affected, not that any one person possesses knowledge of

    that from the outset. The deliberative forum seems designed to be more of a hermeneutical

    space in which a dialectic takes place among participants with less than perfect information.

    What deliberative democracy generally does require over and above that of generic

    democracy has less to do with the cognitive possessions of the participants, and more to do

  • 8/6/2019 DD and Ignorance

    9/17

    Carlson 9

    with the attitudes they bring to the deliberative situation. Yes, all individuals would probably

    have to learn to limit the scope of reasons they could utilize to persuade others. But it does

    not seem clear that accepting something like the principles of reciprocity and civility is such

    an overly intense cognitive demand. If anything it encourages the exercise of a persons non-

    cognitive faculties such as imagination or moral sentiments (Freeman 383). And far from too

    demanding, acceptance of these principlesor something like themseems like a necessary

    requirement, given the time constraints, that people pare down their reasons they have for

    their viewpoints that they are willing to share and defend. There is even reason to believe that

    the process of deliberation itself will effectively weed out arguments or viewpoints that

    cannot withstand deliberative scrutiny or compromise the moral integrity or equality of the

    fellow deliberators (Dryzek and List 14). In addition, deliberation also has an effect on

    achieving proximity to single-peakedness, a sufficient condition for achieving a Condorcet

    winner and frequently indicative of some level of meta-agreement among participants about

    how to semantically conceptualize the available alternatives, even given substantial

    disagreement about how to rank those alternatives (List et al. 6, 9). To the degree that

    deliberation does seem to effect change in participants opinions, we have reason to think that

    deliberation is doing the job it was intended to do.

    A second question is whether the change in opinion might be due to what Somin calls

    agenda setting effects where simply presenting new informationor perhaps even

    presenting it in a new formatto uninformed people results in a change of opinion (Somin

    1998, 442). The time constraints on this holiday entails that a certain selection from the vast

    array of policy issues on the agenda must take place, and as a result could allow for

    candidates or presenters to manipulate the deliberators (Somin 2010, 268). Yet there are

  • 8/6/2019 DD and Ignorance

    10/17

    Carlson 10

    reasons to think the bias of presentations or the framing effects of what topics are discussed

    are not serious problems for the deliberative holiday proposal. First, there is evidence to think

    that deliberation in general gives rational incentives to the presenters to give an honest

    portrayal of their view. When people are held responsible for the claims they make by

    recurrent interaction with others, there are serious long-term risks with being labeled as a liar

    or manipulator (Dryzek and List 9). The proposed Deliberation Day gives two ways of

    ensuring positive and negative incentives for speaking honestly and straightforwardly. The

    equal time given to opposing candidates ensures that even well entreched incumbents can

    receive a thorough vetting by their opponents (Ackerman and Fishkin 2004, 101). They will

    not be able to get away with a blatant mischaracterization of their opponents position.

    Second, even if an opposing candidate fails to examine a questionable position from their

    opponent, the format of the small group deliberation allows for the individual participants to

    ask pointed questions.2 The focus of these small groups is less about deliberating directly

    about the merits of the candidates positions, but rather what is left out or unclear about a

    candidates position. This second avenue is important, since though framing effectseven

    non-malicious oneswill inevitably occur in the procedure, there is always the possibility for

    the participants to challenge those effects and point out where elisions are manipulative or

    misleading. Additional empirical studies have also demonstrated that where change of

    preference does occur, it is not simply due to unreflective following of cues from moderators

    and presenters, as subjects of deliberative polls increased significantly in knowledge of even

    less prominent matters of deliberation (List et al 17). Ultimately, it does not seem that

    2 It should be noted that the format also prevents the questions from being overly hostile or

    inflammatory, as the questions would need to be moderate enough that they would be agreed

    to by the rest of the small group (Ackerman and Fishkin 63-4).

  • 8/6/2019 DD and Ignorance

    11/17

    Carlson 11

    agenda-setting effects are very serious worries.

    A third and final question that a deliberative holiday proposal raises is how the results

    of Deliberation Day carry over to the wider population. Ackerman and Fishkin claim that the

    final poll results signal to the wider population the final results of fellow citizens who have

    reflected and deliberated about the presidential candidates platforms. Their results provide

    the rest of the population with an approximation of what a well informed vote might look

    like, which might sway non-participants to rethink their own position. But Ackerman and

    Fishkin do not address two critical questions about the strength of that signal, and thus the

    actual efficacy of it: how strongly would the poll results transmit the ideal of a well informed

    vote, and how strongly would that signal be received by non-participants?

    Why should we regard a deliberated preference as proximate to a well informed

    preference? One strong reason to consider a thoroughly deliberated opinion as proximate to

    the ideal of a well informed opinion is that it takes seriously the pluralism of race, gender,

    class, and ideology that exist in modern societies. For each political decision, there are

    always numerous kinds of people whose lives are in some way affected. A well informed

    opinion is one that has considered as many different perspectives as possible to determine

    which possibility is best when taking everything into consideration. On the other side, for

    those who are affected, it seems only an extension of the fairness and freedom that traditional,

    generic democracy champions that they be able to express their opinions and interests about a

    decision to a wider audience.

    Why should non-participants seriously regard the results of Deliberation Day? As

    Fishkins research with Deliberative polling suggests, deliberation creates a surprising number

    of swing voters, voters who begin the deliberation with one opinion and end with either a

  • 8/6/2019 DD and Ignorance

    12/17

    Carlson 12

    different opinion or a heavily modified version of the original. The non-participant cannot

    discount out of hand the idea that if she were one of the deliberators, she might be one of

    those swing voters who switched sides as well. It might be rational for them to consider if

    their current position is somehow inadequate. Others might see the results as an informational

    shortcut that is superior to the other available shortcuts to political information (e.g. political

    parties, opinion leaders, common sense, etc.). Furthermore, Deliberation Day seems like the

    only informational shortcut that goes to great lengths to remove any specter of myopia by

    including a full representation of the pluralism present in western societies, with each equally

    having the freedom and forum to voice their interests and their preferences. Conversely, if the

    demographic composition of the event included too many of one class at the expense of others

    who would have added more balance to the proceedings, then one has reason to not take the

    results as seriously as one would otherwise.3

    Also, for Ackerman and Fishkin, deliberation day is not just a one-off part of the

    electoral season that is discretely separated from the rest of the year. In their eyes, the

    anticipation of a day of sustained discussion could shape both candidate, participant, and even

    non-participant behavior throughout the year. Politicians would no longer rely blindly on just

    raw poll numbers of an unreflective population, but will form their opinions knowing that

    3 One should note that Ackerman and Fishkin are under no delusions that the results

    from deliberation are infallible such that it removes the rationality of opposition (Ackerman

    and Fishkin 2002, 145). It might be perfectly reasonable for some reasonably open-minded

    citizens to stick with their opinions even if they do not coincide with the deliberators overall

    conclusions. The option of ultimate dissent must remain open as a live, viable option.

  • 8/6/2019 DD and Ignorance

    13/17

    Carlson 13

    they will have to answer to the reflective discourse of Deliberation Day. Deliberation Day

    also gives a politician no comfort that some unpopular or unseemly action will go unnoticed:

    before a deliberative audience, potentially every act is a high visibility act (Ackerman and

    Fishkin 2004, 79). Participants would find it advantageous to become informed through their

    own study, which would likely include at least some informal discussions with non-

    participants.

    For Somin, the pervasiveness and ineradicability of voter ignorance is in part due to

    the massive scope of modern states (Somin 1998, 444). Modern governmental plays such a

    wide variety of roles in society that it is impossible for individual voters to be informed about

    more than a narrow sliver of the governments overall functioning (Somin 1998, 431).

    According to Somin, if the scope of government is inversely proportionate to voters ability to

    be informed about governmental affairs, then the best way to solve the ignorance problem is

    to reduce the scope of government that voters must be informed about. Narrowing the scope

    of government, specifically transferring more power to more state and local government

    where voters have a more manageable number of issues about which they can be informed.

    Somin also notes that these more localist alternatives are even compatible with even some

    measure of deliberative democracy (Somin 2010, 264), the chief difference being that it starts

    and ends in the local setting. Such a local setting with a smaller population of participants

    also increases the amount of individual opinion and vote efficacy, potentially resulting in a

    decrease of rational ignorancethough its more intimate, personally-connected setting could

    also lead to preference falsification, where people silence their dissenting viewpoints because

    of social pressures (Somin 2010, 271).4

    4 It should also be noted that Ackerman and Fishkin do not quibble with the necessity of

    localized operations in their proposal (Ackerman and Fishkin 2002, 147).

  • 8/6/2019 DD and Ignorance

    14/17

    Carlson 14

    There are several questions that need to be asked about this proposal, however.

    Joshua Cohen points out that we should be skeptical that purely localized deliberative arenas,

    with no feeder into a larger network of arenas. Such atomized arenas are unlikely to generate

    the sustained, open-ended deliberation that deliberative democracy aims for, as a local area

    usually includes only a narrow range of interests and opinions that would be affected by

    policy (Cohen 10). Another question about Somins proposal is its vagueness in regards to

    what should and should not be within the scope of government.5 Presumably attempting to

    responsibly narrow government would require knowledge of what government can reasonably

    do, as well as what the social consequences of such narrowing would be. If citizens are

    generally ignorant about political matters, it seems hardly plausible to expect them to have the

    kind of knowledge about what government can and cannot do. But even if we ignored the

    knowledge required to effect the transition Somin suggests, it does not seem that a reduced

    knowledge burden required of citizens follows from a more narrowly focused government.

    Under this plan, whatever current government functions fall outside the new, streamlined

    government would still need to be addressed by citizens. The knowledge these citizens would

    need to effectively carry out these functions would not decrease by localizing government and

    might even increase.

    Somin admits that the knowledge burden might not decrease, only to point out that in

    5 There is also the possibility that Somins suggestion is not as radical as narrowing the scopeof government itself, so much as narrowing what voters have control over, namely from voter

    control over all public policy to simply voter control over the officials elected to office

    (Somin 1998, 445). It is, first, unclear how that is different from that current politicalsituation, nor, second, how this overcomes the ignorance that is demonstrably at work in most

    citizens. If citizens cannot accurately assign blame or credit for current situations, then

    Somins argument leads one to the conclusion that citizens should have no vital role inselecting either individual policies or leaders. Third, limiting the voter control to the selection

    of leaders is consistent with parts of Ackerman and Fishkins proposal (Ackerman and

    Fishkin, 157).

  • 8/6/2019 DD and Ignorance

    15/17

    Carlson 15

    this scenario, citizens have more informational feedbacksnamely pricesthat could

    increase their ability to make more informed decisions than they would have as citizen-voters.

    It is relatively easy, Somin thinks, to connect performance to quality of a product based on its

    price, but very difficult to connect the social outcomes to public policy (Somin 1998, 446).

    Yet if decisions come down to prices and more local considerations, it seems that this would

    encourage a myopia in the resulting decisions: the decisions that cost the least for an

    individual are preferred, even if their cost on more distantor futurepeople are much

    greater (Ackerman and Fishkin 2002, 143). And while this localist, more consumerist,

    alternative avoids the problem of a rationally ignorant electorate, with Somins proposal there

    becomes an equally troubling prospect of a rationally myopic electorate who votes primarily

    on what is in their immediate best interest. Somins advocacy for a local-only alternative also

    runs afoul of Somins own very salient point against the use of daily experience as an

    informational short cut: many problems are not immediately encountered on a daily basis

    (Somin 1998, 420-421). Deliberation Day strives to resist the equally unattractive

    possibilities of a rationally ignorant and a rationally myopic electorate by providing a context

    in which engaging reflectively on the difficult and wide-ranging policy questions can be

    considered a rational endeavor for many citizens.

    In his concluding remarks on his survey of the literature of deliberative democracy,

    Samuel Freeman notes that the most difficult obstacle for deliberative democracyas is true

    of perhaps all political idealsis in making it a feasible enterprise for the imperfect rational

    practitioners that humans are (Freeman 418). I hope to have shown that deliberative

    democracy through the implementation of Deliberation Day makes great strides in

    overcoming the vexing problem of rational ignoranceand perhaps of even more general

  • 8/6/2019 DD and Ignorance

    16/17

    Carlson 16

    ignorancewithin the electorate. This is far from the final word, as Deliberation Day

    remains simply a hypothetical construct at this point. Ackerman and Fishkins proposals and

    inferencesas they themselves recognizeare exercises in utopian realism (Ackerman and

    Fishkin 2002, 130) and thus are largely speculative in the ways that their deliberation day

    proposal would operate. Yet they have given us reasons to be at least cautiously optimistic

    about the ability of the electorate to deliberate effectively about political decisions and public

    policy.

    Works Cited

    Ackerman, Bruce and James Fishkin. Deliberation Day. New Haven, CT:Yale University Press. 2004.

    ---. Deliberation Day. The Journal of Political Philosophy. 10.2 (2002):

  • 8/6/2019 DD and Ignorance

    17/17

    Carlson 17

    129-152.

    Cohen, Joshua. Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy. The GoodPolity: Normative Analysis of the State. Ed. Alan Hamlin and PhillipPettit. New York: Blackwell, 1989.

    Dryzek, John and Christian List. Social Choice Theory and DeliberativeDemocracy:A Reconciliation. British Journal of Political Science. 33.1 (2003):1-28.

    Freeman, Samuel. Deliberative Democracy: A Sympathetic Comment.Philosophy & Public Affairs 29.4 (2000): 371-418.

    List, Christian, Robert C. Luskin, James S. Fishkin and Iain McLean.Deliberation, Single-Peakedness, and the Possibility of MeaningfulDemocracy: Evidence from Deliberative Polls. (April 25, 2006).PSPE Working Paper No. 1. Accessed Thursday May 12, 2011.http://eprints.lse.ac.uk/20069/

    Somin, Ilya. Voter Ignorance and the Democratic Ideal. Critical Review.12.4 (1998) : 413-458.

    ---. Deliberative Democracy and Ignorance. Critical Review, Vol. 22.2-3(2010):253-279.

    Talisse, Robert B. Does Public Ignorance Defeat DeliberativeDemocracy?Critical Review 16.4. (2004): 455-64.