Critique on Kantian Account on Passion

download Critique on Kantian Account on Passion

of 13

Transcript of Critique on Kantian Account on Passion

  • 8/11/2019 Critique on Kantian Account on Passion

    1/13

    Dela Cruz 1

    2011-17384

    Alexis Dela Cruz

    Philosophic Problems

    Prof. Samuel Vera Cruz

    The Significance of Passions on our Moral Judgments

    Kants ethics undermines and gives little or no moral worth at all to our actions,

    which are non-intellectually motivated. An action with moral worth, for Kant, is not of

    those, which are motivated by passions, even if it is a positive one. Motivations must come

    from the reverence to the law of our moral principles and the action must be done in

    accordance to our duty. The action with moral worth is that of someone who, despite the

    fact that he does not feel any sympathy for others still helps them because it is his duty to

    help others. In this paper, I would discuss Kants account on passion and how some

    philosophers reacted against it, specifically David Hume and part of the ethics of Adam

    Smith, as well as my own arguments against Kants undervaluing of human passions.

    I.

    Kants account on passion and our Duty of Apathy

    Kant argues that we have a duty of apathy, meaning we have a duty to act without

    affect and passions. Kant defined affect in his work The Metaphysics of Morals, as a strong

    and powerful burst of feelings, which is often short lived. Passion on the other hand lingers

    longer. Kant argues that we have a duty to remain indifferent to these feelings because it

  • 8/11/2019 Critique on Kantian Account on Passion

    2/13

    Dela Cruz 2

    inhibits us from reflection. (Formosa, 2011) In his ethics, moral judgment must be done out

    of the operations of reason not out passion. That is why; we must develop a character,

    which could withstand the dictates of affect and passions. This he calls the proper self.

    (Kant, 1785)

    Why must our moral judgments not come out of passions and affect? Affect,

    according to Kant, is a sudden burst of emotion, which restricts us from making a rational

    judgment and could lead us to wrong choice of action. Kant made a distinction between

    affect and passion in the context of the duration that it stays; but for the sake of this

    discussion both along with emotions would be used interchangeably. Every affect, he says,

    is blind. He argues that, it makes a man beside his own self, in such a way that he has no

    control over himself. Imagine a woman who caught her husband cheating on her in

    flagrante delicto. Emotions such as hatred, disgust, hurt could be evoked. If she had acted

    out of the dictates of her passions she could have hurt the other woman, or even kill her out

    of extreme hatred. We are all aware that killing is not a right action but because of passion

    there is a possibility for us to act in such a way that is not in accordance to our knowledge

    of the right action. That is why our judgment must come out of the operations of reason,

    because passion has the tendency to make us do the wrong action despite our knowledge of

    which is appropriate. Kant also argues that judgment and emotions does not necessarily

    coincide with each other because what we feel good or bad is not necessarily what we

    rationally approve and disapprove. Lets go back to the wife who caught her husband

    cheating, she may feel better if she hurt his husband and his mistress than not doing

    anything at all. Then again, her rational mind tells her that inflicting pain on other people is

    not a good thing to do. Her feeling of hurt and hatred may subside by hurting the other

  • 8/11/2019 Critique on Kantian Account on Passion

    3/13

    Dela Cruz 3

    party but then again it doesnt necessarily coincide with what her knowledge of right and

    wrong tells her hence, she do otherwise. Her decision therefore, at the end lies on her

    reasoning and is more appropriate to do so.

    To what extent are we blamed for our passions? Since passions and affect are

    faculties that we have no control over, meaning we cannot choose what kind of emotions

    we would have and when we are to have it, hence, we cannot be blamed by having them.

    What we are responsible of is how we manage our emotions and act rightly. It is absurd to

    even think that we have a duty to have feelings, meaning to feel this and that at a particular

    kind of situation, because we have no control over what feelings to invoke. In other words,

    you do not blame the wife from feeling hatred and having the desire to hurt her husband

    and his mistress because those are things the she cannot control. Nonetheless, we could

    control our actions and restrain ourselves from blindly acting upon our emotions.

    Even if we cannot choose what emotions to invoke we could, according to Kant,

    learn what to feel in a certain kind of situation. For example, we can learn how to

    sympathize or empathize with people and that is praiseworthy. This is done through

    reinforcement and habituation, which could develop into virtuous. Kant defined virtue as

    an aptitude of a persons will to determine ones self to act through the thought of the law.

    (Kant, 1788)In other words that is the capacity to withstand, that which opposes our moral

    dispositions. Being virtuous means being able to control our passion when it opposes our

    moral dispositions. Hence, even if we cannot control what emotions we evoke, we have the

    responsibility not to act on it irrationally and that is a kind of virtue. We do not blame the

    wife for her passions but she could be blamed for not acting rationally in her situation. If

    she had developed a good state of character however, for example, the character of being

  • 8/11/2019 Critique on Kantian Account on Passion

    4/13

    Dela Cruz 4

    kind hearted at all times even to those who had done her wrong, which is praiseworthy.

    However, do not mistake being praiseworthy of having moral worth. For Kant, if the wife

    did not hurt her husband and his mistress because of her aversion to violence or feeling of

    pity to those who are hurt then that action has no moral worth. Although positive passions

    are good as well, the moral worthiness of an action is if it is done out of duty. In other

    words, if the wife has not attempted to hurt the two, not because she pity the hurt but

    because it is her duty to not hurt anyone then that is the time when her action has moral

    worth.

    II. Humes argument against reason

    A lot of philosophers had reacted against Kants moral theory of having to disregard

    passions in coming up with a moral judgment. One of them is Kants predecessor, David

    Hume. Unlike Kant who grounded his moral theory to a prioriprinciples, Hume was an

    empiricist. He is famous for his words that reason is and ought only to be the slaves of

    passions, and can never pretend to any other office than to serve and obey them (Treatise of

    Human Nature: Book II. 1739), which is contrary to Kants philosophy of putting aside our

    passions, and leave our judgments to the operation of reason. Hume discussed the role of

    passions in our moral judgments in his work, The Treaties of Human Nature, specifically

    book II and book III.

    The reason why Hume thought that reason is slaves to our passion is because reason

    alone cannot cause actions. (Zimmerman, 2007) We are able to restrain from our bodily

    pleasure not just because of an understanding alone. It is always aided with other

  • 8/11/2019 Critique on Kantian Account on Passion

    5/13

    Dela Cruz 5

    passions which value overrides the other. For example, the wife who was cheated by her

    husband, she would have restrain from killing the mistress not just because of some

    rational process that happened in her but it was aided by passions such as fear of the

    consequences in the future, which Hume calls prudence, or even feeling of humanity. Even

    if she had knowledge of the right thing to do, if it is not at some point affect her then it is

    not enough for her to restrain herself from doing the action. It is very hard to imagine a

    person who is detached or does not feel any sentiments towards the consequences. Hume

    thinks that reason alone cannot motivate actions. He thinks that a person, to be able to have

    genuine moral considerations, that person at some point must have sympathy with the

    others. He also thinks that a person naturally have aversion to any form of sufferings both

    in the present and the future. It is therefore unavoidable that we think of the future

    consequences of an action and this what motivates us from refraining from the action; and

    this cannot be derived from the work of reason alone.

    It does not however follow that Hume believes that reason does not have a role in

    making judgments. Nonetheless, its job does not include making actions, that is the job of

    our passions, nor can it control or overcome passion. (Zimmerman, 2007) The role of

    reasons is to generate data. Humes first argument aboutthe role of reason is that its job is

    to demonstrate the relations of ideas with each other and to draw out causal inference from

    the information. (Hume, 1739) For example, when the wife sees her husband acting with

    unnecessary intimacy with another woman in a restaurant, the job of reason is to gather

    the facts and infer from it. Such as, her husband is in a restaurant alone with an unknown

    woman, he is treating her intimately, the wife knows that the woman is not a relative;

    therefore the husband must have been cheating. Humes second argument about the role of

  • 8/11/2019 Critique on Kantian Account on Passion

    6/13

    Dela Cruz 6

    reason is that it is a discovery of truth and falsehood.(Hume, 1739) One of its jobs is to

    accumulate true beliefs. For example, the wifes belief that the woman is not a relative of

    her husband and hence must have been a mistress. Passions however, cannot be true or

    false for it is a faculty innate in an individual.

    Hume emphasizes the role of prudence in our decision-making. By prudence I mean,

    caring for the consequences of the future. Hume argues that we have an aversion to pain

    and sufferings and so to those that will happen in the future. Going back to the wife,

    presuming that she has the urge to kill the woman at that moment, then again she fears of

    her sufferings in the future, such as loosing the love thats left for her from her husband,

    going to jail, and be tormented by the guilt of killing someone. If fear of these future pains

    overrides her urge of killing the mistress, then she will restrain from doing the act but if the

    urge overwhelms her fears then she is bound to do otherwise.

    This is where the state of character plays its role. To Hume, for us to make ourselves

    predispose in being prudent and not be overwhelmed by negative passions there is a need

    for the strength of character, which is achieved through habituation. The strength of

    character as Hume defined is the prevalence of the calm passion over the violent. (Treatise of

    Human Nature: Book II. 1739)In other words, training and habituation would help us to

    predispose ourselves in evoking prudence over blind aggression. If the wife is a person

    who has the virtue of prudence, meaning she is predispose to care for the future

    consequences, her immediate actions to situations would be that of which is derived from

    the evaluation of the future benefits and sufferings. Hence, at that moment the wife will be

    more likely to refrain from acting out of blind aggressiveness because she had developed a

    character not to act upon it. Another factor of moral judgment that Hume discusses is

  • 8/11/2019 Critique on Kantian Account on Passion

    7/13

    Dela Cruz 7

    sympathy. By sympathy I am referring to the feeling of sorrow or pity for the other. It is

    part of our human nature to feel a certain degree of sympathy; thinking of the pain that

    could inflict on the other would make us feel bad. It is natural for the wife to resent her the

    woman and would therefore have the urge to kill her. Then again it is possible for her to

    feel sympathy for the possible pain that the woman would experience or if not the

    sufferings of the family of the woman. This will make her feel bad and would have the

    tendency to be repulsed by the action. Humes moral theory therefore, in contrast to Kant,

    argues that our passion, which makes us repulsive or approve of a certain action,

    determines our moral judgment.

    III.

    Smiths account on sympathy and approbation

    Another philosopher, who argued against Kant, was Adam Smith. Adam Smith in his

    book, The Theory of Moral Sentiments, argues that our moral judgments start with our

    evaluations of people. (Sayre McCord) We tend to disapprove on the action of a person base

    on our judgment of that person. When we judge that person we think of what they do and

    why they do it on the basis of sentiments or affection which the action precedes. He said

    that we base our judgment with two considerations, that of which what motivates the

    action and the consequences that may possibly follow. The first one he regard as the

    Judgment of Propriety. When we judge an action to be right or wrong we consider the

    appropriateness of the action. This is where passion plays its role through sympathy. By

    sympathy, what I mean is the ability to understand and share the feelings of another. When

    we judge if the action is proper in that situation we try to imagine ourselves in that

  • 8/11/2019 Critique on Kantian Account on Passion

    8/13

    Dela Cruz 8

    situation and if we would have done what the person did that is when we would have

    approved that action. For example, when the wife restrains herself and does not kill the

    mistress, we would have approved her action because if we imagine ourselves in that

    situation we would have done the same. If the one judging, however, was more inclined to

    hatred, then when the wife kills the woman the judge would have understand why the wife

    did the action and possibly would not have deemed her wrong.

    The other consideration Smith discusses is theJudgment of Merit. In here we judge

    the rightness or wrongness of an action through the consequences if it breeds resentment

    or gratitude from the people affected. If what follows brings misfortune to the other person

    then our sympathy towards the person doing the act, even if it was appropriate, would be

    gone. Going back to the wife, if the action the she chose to do was to kill the mistress at that

    moment we would have thought that the wife has appropriate motivation in her action.

    Then again, her action would have caused sufferings to the other woman and possibly the

    family and the people who care for that woman. Hence, we would have disapproved with

    that action. Now there are two underlying elements in accounting for our judgments, first is

    our capacity for sympathy and second our capacity for approbation. Our sympathy,

    towards the person doing the act and towards the person the act is done upon, is what

    gives rise to our approval and disapproval. Moral judgments for Smith, therefore, are

    derived from our sentiment of sympathy towards the agents that are involved in the action.

    IV.

    The role of sympathy and human relations on moral judgments

  • 8/11/2019 Critique on Kantian Account on Passion

    9/13

    Dela Cruz 9

    I myself simply cannot agree with Kant when he argues that passions are unreliable

    source of moral judgment. I am more inclined in choosing passion as a source of moral

    judgment and I think as a human being, we cannot have a moral judgment free from

    passion. I am basing this belief from two premises. First, I agree with Smith when he say

    that it is part of human nature to have some degree of sympathy; and that is where I believe

    that moral judgment commences. Second, Kant does not give any account on our personal

    relations with other people. I simply cannot think of any human affairs, which personal

    relations do not count. I would first discuss my idea of sympathy. When I feel that I have

    done something that is not right, there is a feeling of something bad that is happening

    inside. For example, if I had cheated on an exam, there is something within me that is

    repulsed with my action and that is when I know that what I did was wrong. If I do a good

    action on the other hand there is a good feeling that is happening within me. For example,

    if I helped an old lady from crossing the street I would feel good about what I did. These

    feelings that are invoked in my actions are what motivates me to do or not to do an action. I

    believe that the passions, which motivate the action, are what make it morally worthy. Kant

    argues that the moral worthiness of an action is derived from our sense of duty. This

    statement I cannot agree. If we are doing an action out of duty, this means that we are

    compelled to do so. It is in nature of a morally worthy action to be praise worthy as well.

    For example, it is the duty of a policeman to protect the people from criminals and it is

    expected of him to do so. If he is protecting the people because it is his job to do so, he is

    acting in accordance to the nature of his job. What he is doing is good but he is doing it

    because that is what we expect him to do and I do not see anything praise worthy with that

    because it is just natural for him to so. We do not praise something that is what is expected

  • 8/11/2019 Critique on Kantian Account on Passion

    10/13

    Dela Cruz 10

    for us to do. I mean, we do not praise a teacher for teaching. However, if there are positive

    passions that follow then the action is worthy of praise. For example, if the policeman was

    doing his job because of his love for peace and repulsion of evil then we praise that man for

    his kindness. If the teacher was teaching because he wants to impart his knowledge to the

    children to improve the state the we praise the teacher for having those sentiments. For

    me, therefore, a morally worthy action is that of which there is a passion and volition to

    arrive at something better through that action. When I help the people who were

    devastated because of a hurricane and I do it because I want to relieve them from their pain

    then that is when my action becomes morally worthy. If I helped the people because I just

    believe that I have the duty to help other people but I do not necessarily feel sympathy or

    care towards them then the action is just a sense of compulsion. The action is good but it is

    not morally worthy. Only an action with the hope of something better would come out of it

    is a morally worthy action. It does not follow however that I believe that the worth of an

    action is based on the consequences. I am a consequentialist at some degree but I believe

    that there are morally worthy actions which does not necessarily produced a good

    consequences for consequences cannot be calculated, there is a need for an element of luck

    and chances for the calculations to be correct.

    My second argument against Kants account on passions is that of the role of our

    personal relations to our moral judgments. As I was saying a while ago, I cannot think of

    any human affair, which does not account for personal relations. How I treat a friend maybe

    different from how I treat a stranger. For example, if I were a surgeon how I feel about

    operating on a stranger would be different from how I would feel about operating on my

    own mother and therefore would have acted differently. I could have refused to operate on

  • 8/11/2019 Critique on Kantian Account on Passion

    11/13

    Dela Cruz 11

    my mother because of some sentiments in me that is repulsed with the idea of operating on

    my mother. It is like having to punch someone who you love and punching someone you

    bare extreme hated for, if you are compelled to do it the degree of force that you would

    invoke would vary because of the difference in sentiments that you hold for the two. What I

    am trying to say here is that, how we personally relate with other people may affect how

    we arrive at a moral judgment, which Kant did not account for. Imagine a mans son who is

    need of a blood transplant, the man and his son are both Muslims hence, donating blood is

    forbidden in their religion. If that man was asked to donate his blood to a total stranger

    there is a high possibility that the man would refuse because it is immoral to do so, as what

    was said in their religion. If the person who is in need however was his son and if he does

    not do the transfusion his son would die, at this situation unlike that with the stranger,

    there is a much higher possibility that the man would donate his blood to his son.

    V.

    Conclusion

    I disagree to the account of Kant regarding passion but I do not entirely disagree

    with his ethical theory. I would not go as far as Hume to say that reasons is a slave to our

    passion. I also believe that our passions sometimes blind us from coming up with the better

    option that is I believe in the significance of reflection. However, as what I was arguing a

    while ago the beginning of moral judgment is still our passions, such as compassion and

    sympathy, but reason also have its role, which is to traffic our emotions. Our passion gives

    us the capacity for moral consideration while reason puts our passions in the right place.

    Both therefore, are equally necessary in coming up with the right moral decisions. I would

  • 8/11/2019 Critique on Kantian Account on Passion

    12/13

    Dela Cruz 12

    end my discussion with a quote from the Confucian idea ofxin, which perfectly

    encapsulates my idea of the relation of reason to passions Reason is what regulates

    behavior but it nonetheless originates from the emotions of human heart.

  • 8/11/2019 Critique on Kantian Account on Passion

    13/13

    Dela Cruz 13

    Bibliography:

    Geoffrey Sayre-McCord. Sentiments and Spectators: Adam Smiths Theory of Moral

    Judgment.University of North Carolina. Article. Print.

    Aaron Zimmerman. Humes Reason.University of California, Sta. Barbara. Article. Print.

    Paul Formosa.A Life without Affect and Passions: Kant on the Duty of Apathy.

    Parrhesia. 2011. Article. Print.

    David Hume. Treatise of Human Nature book II: the Passions.Translated by, Jonathan

    Bennett. 2010. Print.

    Kung Fu Tzu. The Analects. Translated by R. Eno. 2012. Print.

    Immanuel Kant. Ground Work for the Metaphysics of Morals. Translated by Allen Wood.

    Yale University Press. 2002. Print.