Conflict in Seneca's Thought

35
Should the Aspiring Wise Man Travel? A Conflict in Seneca's Thought Author(s): Silvia Montiglio Source: The American Journal of Philology, Vol. 127, No. 4 (Winter, 2006), pp. 553-586 Published by: The Johns Hopkins University Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4496934 . Accessed: 28/11/2014 20:25 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . The Johns Hopkins University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The American Journal of Philology. http://www.jstor.org This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

description

philosophy

Transcript of Conflict in Seneca's Thought

Page 1: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

Should the Aspiring Wise Man Travel? A Conflict in Seneca's ThoughtAuthor(s): Silvia MontiglioSource: The American Journal of Philology, Vol. 127, No. 4 (Winter, 2006), pp. 553-586Published by: The Johns Hopkins University PressStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/4496934 .

Accessed: 28/11/2014 20:25

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

.

The Johns Hopkins University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to TheAmerican Journal of Philology.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 2: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

SHOULD THE ASPIRING WISE MAN TRAVEL? A CONFLICT IN SENECA'S THOUGHT

SILVIA MONTIGLIO

Abstract. This article examines the connection between traveling and wisdom in Seneca's writings. It argues that Seneca is ambivalent vis-a-vis traveling: on the one hand, he deems the activity unnecessary or even dangerous, insofar as it is at odds with mental focus and challenges the ideal of happiness as "home" (domestica felicitas); on the other, he admires those who travel for the sake of knowledge and connects the mobility of the body with the "cosmic flight" of the mind. In line with a long-established tradition, Seneca views travel as the first step towards philosophical inquiry. The ambivalence extends to the assessment of imperialistic use of travel. Though Seneca loudly condemns it as a manifestation of greed, he also shows admiration for several Roman conquerors.

INTRODUCTION

WHEN SENECA WRITES, traveling and philosophy are an established pair. Several philosophers are credited with far-reaching travels. In Herodotus' account, Croesus praises Solon for having wandered across many lands for observation's sake and out of love for knowledge (1.30: theories heneka). Theophrastus admires Democritus because he gathered much greater booty in his travels than Odysseus and Menelaus, not wealth but knowledge (68 A 16 DK), and Cicero celebrates Pythagoras, Democritus, and Plato for having traveled to the furthermost lands "on account of their desire to learn" (Fin. 5.19).1 The Roman empire saw a proliferation of itinerant philosophers, especially, but not exclusively, of Cynic orien- tation. The Neopythagorean sage Apollonius of Tyana (according to his biographer Philostratus) spent almost all his life traveling, both to instruct himself and to teach others. Even exile could be turned into extensive and exploratory travel, as in Dio Chrysostom's case: instead of settling down somewhere, he chose to wander the world to its edges and to study a liminal people, the Getae, about whom he wrote a scholarly account. In

1Translations are mine unless otherwise noted.

American Journal of Philology 127 (2006) 553-586 ? 2006 by The Johns Hopkins University Press

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 3: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

554 SILVIA MONTIGLIO

short, traveling had long been the norm among aspiring wise men. The one exception, according to Diogenes Laertius (2.22), was Socrates.

At the same time, the relationship between traveling and philosophy was a complex and controversial one: is the kind of knowledge that one earns through traveling conducive to wisdom? Much learning (polymathia) was systematically contrasted with wisdom by philosophers before Aris- totle,2 and traveling provided precisely the abundance of scattered and erudite information that several philosophers regarded as mindless or even immoral. In addition, going about the world could be perceived as incompatible with the goal of mental focus, which called rather for a relatively stationary lifestyle and even for physical immobility.3 Where does Seneca stand in this debate? What is his position on the relationship between traveling and wisdom?

Seneca explicitly connects traveling and philosophy (Ot. 5). In defense of contemplation, he says that nature has provided us with a curious mind (curiosum ingenium). It is enough for each of us to observe how eager we are to know unknown things (quantam cupidinem habeat ignota noscendi). This eagerness urges some to travel far, whatever the risk, just for the sake of learning something secret and remote: "Navigant quidam et labores peregrinationis longissimae una mercede perpetiuntur cognoscendi aliquid abditum remotumque."4 As the motives for explor- atory travels, cupido and curiositas are positive forces. Traveling for the sake of knowledge is one of the activities that do justice to nature because her beauty and greatness need spectators. The "spectatores of so many great spectacles" (5.3) eventually turn their heads upwards and concen- trate their movement in their eyes and heads (5.4). The eye becomes the traveler: it "opens a road of investigation for itself" (5.5). Traveling is thus the first step towards philosophical inquiry.5

Are we then to imagine that Seneca's aspiring wise man will travel to faraway lands in order to learn remote things? Giovanna Garbarino, in a

comprehensive study of the theme of traveling in Seneca (1996), has argued the opposite: Seneca dismisses traveling as frivolous and unnecessary even when its goal is to acquire knowledge. She identifies three types of travel in Seneca's writings-as risk and transgression, as evasion, and as a means of

broadening our horizons-but does not see any real contradiction between

2Cf. I. Hadot 1984, passim. 31I discuss these issues in Montiglio 2005, esp. chaps. 5 to 9. 4The choice of quidam may suggest that Seneca is cautious not to overstate the case:

few people travel just to discover the world. Cf. Williams 2003, 87 (on Ot. 5.2). 5 Cf. Williams 2003, 87.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 4: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

A CONFLICT IN SENECA'S THOUGHT 555

a positive and a negative evaluation of the activity and concludes that the only philosophical use that Seneca makes of traveling is by drawing a moral lesson from its incidents and nuisances. In her reading, the passage from the De otio that celebrates "philosophical traveling" does not develop the motif as fully as one would expect. She points out that the activity is mentioned together with antiquarian erudition and the interest in fabulous tales, both of which Seneca is far from associating with the quest for wisdom.

Paul Veyne's judgment is even more extreme. In his view the Stoic wise man (Veyne makes no distinction between Seneca and other Stoics in this regard) would hardly travel at all, except to serve his country.6 It is beyond doubt that the ideal Stoic will embrace traveling (like any other activity) if he is required to do so. In Epictetus' words (2.5.25), "to set sail and take risks" might befall one as a cosmic necessity: one might have to leave a place for the sake of the whole just as one might have to die early, and everyone will have to leave the scene of life at some point to make room for others. But Veyne assumes that our obedient citizen of the world would not choose to leave home in order to satisfy his natural inclination to increase his knowledge, his curiosum ingenium. A reconsideration of the evidence will lead us to less clear-cut conclusions.

JOURNEYING IN THE WORLD AND THE JOURNEY TO WISDOM

The early Stoics do not extol travel as a means of acquiring knowledge. On the contrary, Cleanthes gathers men's ruinous ambitions, the pursuit of fame, wealth, or pleasure, under the heading of traveling, to which he opposes the knowledge of Zeus' law (SVF 1, 537.24-30). Traveling is not even praised for promoting a cosmopolitan disposition. This may seem surprising in light of Aristotle's statement: "one can see also in one's wanderings that every man is near and dear to another" (EN 8.1.1155a 21-22). But Stoic cosmopolitanism is based on the recognition of reason as the common denominator of humans, not on empirical observation. There is no need to meet people from distant places in order to discover one's kinship with them as rational beings.

For the early Stoics traveling is at best a neutral action. Chrysippus (SVF 3, 501) lists traveling (apodemein) among the mesa, actions that reason neither endorses nor condemns in themselves, together with speaking, asking,

6Veyne 2003, 93: "The sage might be the best navigator but he would not, I imagine, navigate unless the well-being of his country demanded it."

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 5: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

556 SILVIA MONTIGLIO

answering, and walking. If traveling as such is morally indifferent, the sage is a sage whether he travels or not. If he travels, he does not travel as a sage. Most likely, however, he will not be interested in traveling because he does not even wonder at sights that seem extraordinary to others, such as the caverns of Charon, springs of hot water, and eruptions of fire (Diogenes Laertius 7.123). His being above marveling makes him a bad candidate for traveling. In addition, he does not aspire to a life of pure study and to encyclopedic knowledge but subordinates knowledge to ethics. Whether the early Stoics traveled or not, the ancient sources do not attribute educational travels to them, as they do to Democritus, Pythagoras, or Plato.

In contrast, the middle-Stoic Posidonius traveled widely.7 His penchant for traveling goes together with his unorthodox idealization of the theoretical life, which, in his view, includes the observation of the phenomenal world: one must live contemplating (theorounta) the truth of the world and its order.8 Posidonius, the polymath, defends the choice of a life devoted to virtually any field of study, including those areas, such as geography or natural wonders, that require extensive traveling.9 To go about studying the world is to pay allegiance to its perfection. Posidonius would argue that traveling is not in the least at odds with Stoic doctrine. On the contrary, it can "show that all the facts are worth ascertaining in a universe rationally determined by immanent providence."10

Does Seneca agree with Posidonius on the virtue of traveling or does he embrace the position of the early Stoics? His admiration for exploratory travels seems to suggest that he thinks them worthy of the wise man.'1 He actually mentions the navigator studii causa as an exem- plary pursuer of virtue (Ep. 87.28).12 But at the same time, it is unlikely

7Cf. Strabo 3.1.5, C. 138; 18.3.4, C. 827. 8F 186, 13-15, Edelstein-Kidd. Panaetius had already identified virtue with "theory":

cf. Long 1986 (1974), 213-14. 9 On Posidonius' polymathy, cf. Strabo 16.2.10 and I. Hadot 1984, 41. Posidonius was

also interested in anthropology and specifically with the values of the people he visited, in accordance with his concerns as a moral philosopher: cf. Athenaeus 4.151 and Bevan 1913, 88-90. His travels, however, were largely prompted by his desire to make scientific observations of tides and other natural phenomena.

10Long 1986 (1974), 221. 11Seneca's own fascination with natural phenomena qualifies Diogenes Laertius' claim

(above) concerning the Stoic's indifference to the wonders of nature. Seneca's sage has a naive gaze; he marvels each time at the beauty of things: cf. P. Hadot 2002, 230. This attitude is shared by Cicero, who maintains that one of the Stoic arguments for the existence of the

gods is "our wonderment at celestial and terrestrial things" (Nat. deor. 2.75-76). 12The example is not necessarily Seneca's invention because he cites it within the

Peripatetic response to the Stoic syllogism: "That which involves us in evils while we pursue

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 6: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

A CONFLICT IN SENECA'S THOUGHT 557

that he himself traveled for the sake of knowledge in Posidonius' style. Although he alludes to phenomena he has seen while traveling (N. Q. 3.25.8 and 6.21.1), he does not indicate that he was traveling to observe those phenomena. His journey to Egypt as a young man is not the tra- ditional journey of the aspiring philosopher because he apparently went there for health reasons. In addition, we do not know how extensively he traveled. His excursus on the Nile, for instance, is not based on much

personal observation,13 though he studied Egyptian geography and religion and wrote on those subjects.14 Seneca did not even go to Greece, perhaps because the center of philosophy, his main interest, had shifted to Rome. Whatever the reason, the absence of the traditional educational journey to Greece from Seneca's curriculum seems to have been perceived as

peculiar already in antiquity. The scholiast on Juvenal 5.109 reports that Seneca did want to go to Greece when recalled from exile. As Miriam Griffin points out, this may be the scholiast's speculation, an attempt to

explain why Seneca, erudite as he was, never went to Athens.15 More important, Seneca does not recommend traveling to the

aspiring wise man. Although he admires our curious mind, he neither encourages us to obey its dictates by leaving home to study the world nor says that the model-sage engages in this activity (Ep. 109 shows the

sage occupied in pure speculation). On the contrary, against Posidonius, he maintains that navigation is one of the arts discovered by sagacitas, not by sapientia (Ep. 90.24), because the sage would not have invented

anything unworthy of perennial use (ibid. 30). Seneca's argument implies that traveling is irrelevant to wisdom (to say the least). In another letter, he explicitly denies any link between traveling and wisdom: "Traveling does not make doctors or speakers; no art is learnt from being in a place. What then? Can wisdom, the greatest art of all, be gathered on a journey?" (104.19). It is true that the kind of traveling that Seneca stigmatizes here is the restless going places of the unsettled man. But the phrase "no art

it cannot be a good." It is however quite possible that Seneca, in his fondness for concrete

illustrations, added it to the original response, all the more so because he begins this letter

by describing one of his journeys and by drawing a moral lesson from it: his own metaphori- cal naufragium (1) resonates with the literal naufragium (28) of the studious traveler, and, like the Stoic syllogism, Seneca's experiment to travel with a meager equipment is meant to show that wealth is not a good.

13Cf. Griffin 1992 (1976), 43. 14Cf. Grimal 1978, 43-52. '5Cf. Griffin 1992 (1976), 37. Seneca's predisposition to sea-sickness (Ep. 53)

might have discouraged him from extensive traveling (cf. also Ep. 57.1 on his loathing of

navigation).

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 7: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

558 SILVIA MONTIGLIO

is learnt from being in a place" has a broader resonance, which cannot pass unnoticed: it polemically addresses the tradition of the educational journey, according to which the arts, including medicine, oratory, and wisdom, were indeed "gathered on a journey."

Seneca's reluctance to include traveling among the activities that promote wisdom comes to the fore in his interpretation of Odysseus, whom he admires on account of his endurance and contempt for pleasures (Const. sap. 2.1), not his knowledge. By Seneca's time, interpretations of Odysseus as the ideal student of the world were not uncommon among Stoic or Stoicizing writers. Though Horace, like Seneca, primarily extols Odysseus for his endurance and resistance to temptations (Ep. 1.2.17-26), he also sees in the wandering hero the student of the world who "with forethought scrutinized (inspexit) the cities and the customs of many men" (ibid. 19-20).16 Epictetus (3.24.12-13) turns Odysseus into a contempla- tive hero, the exemplar of those who move around "for the sake of the spectacle (theds heneka)." Conversely, Seneca's Odysseus is one-sided: he submits to destiny but does not possess any curiosum ingenium. Seneca does not even offer Odysseus as a model of behavior because he listened to the voice of the Sirens and yet sailed forth. He offers his companions whose ears were plugged (Ep. 31.2). In addition, he identifies the Sirens with the temptations of fashion or common opinion, not with the voice of knowledge. Seneca does not see any cognitive content in the Sirens' song and has no word of praise for Odysseus because he listened to it.17

16Horace is not a Stoic, but his treatment of Odysseus in this poem conjures up Stoic readings of the hero: cf. Mayer 1994, 114. It is true that the phrase "with forethought scrutinized the cities and the customs of many men" is the translation of the beginning of the Odyssey. Nonetheless, Horace puts greater emphasis on Odysseus' inquisitiveness by choosing the verb inspexit, which conveys Odysseus' intellectual activity more strongly than its Greek equivalent iden ("he saw"). Cf., by contrast, AP 141-42, where Horace translates Homer more literally: "dic mihi, Musa, virum, captae post tempora Troiae / qui mores hominum multorum vidit et urbis."

17In Ep. 87.7 Seneca again identifies the Sirens (unnamed, but clearly detectable in the phrase insidiosa blandimenta aurium) with the temptation of pleasures, and in Ep. 123. 12 with the invitations to follow common opinion, which Odysseus did not want to sail by except bound to the mast: quas Ulixes nisi alligatus praetervehi noluit. The double negative (nisi, noluit) emphasizes Odysseus' reluctance to sail by the Sirens at all. In Ep. 56 Seneca likewise casts himself as one of Odysseus' deaf companions. He has been listening to the most unpleasant noises with imperturbable detachment, yet he ends up plugging his ears, that is, leaving the place. The treatment of the Sirens episode is comic: Seneca plays the anti-hero and the Sirens' song is retrospectively identified with din. Cf. Motto and Clark 1993, 182. Seneca's repeated self-presentation as one of Odysseus' unheroic companions bears out his refusal to read a cognitive content into the Sirens' song. His interpretation contrasts not only with middle-Platonic and Pythagorean readings of the Sirens' song as

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 8: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

A CONFLICT IN SENECA'S THOUGHT 559

The aspiring sage, then, will learn from Odysseus how to endure the blows of fortune, not how to look around and explore new avenues of knowledge. Traveling, even for the sake of discovery, would clash with the imperative of caution, one of the "good affections" (eupatheiai) in

early Stoicism and a main characteristic of the sage, including Seneca's.'8 To be sure, Seneca's good man will have an energetic mind (cf., e.g., Vit.

3.3). He will act promptly, daringly, and even aggressively to carry out whatever is required (cf., e.g., Ep. 74.32; 76.18; 82.18-19). He will be like a soldier marching against so-called evils (Ep. 82.19: invadendum), at times enduring a siege, at times courageously launching an attack on the

enemy's walls (Ep. 66.13) or embarking on the most dangerous expedi- tions (Ep. 96.5).19 But his courage is no adventurous rushing forward. It is being able to meet dangers defiantly when they arise: "I disagree with those who plunge into the midst of waves and fight every day against difficulties with a great spirit because they value a stormy life. The wise man will bear these things, not choose them; he will prefer to be at peace than in a battle" (Ep. 28.7).20 Stoic fortitude is self-protective, "most

diligent to preserve itself" (Ep. 85.28: diligentissima in tutela sui fortitudo est). It is not love of dangers (Ep. 85.28) or audacia (Ira 1.20.2). Rather, it builds an unassailable fortress around us (Ep. 113.27). If we wrongly use the term fortis for a gladiator, that is because of the limitations of our language. Seneca does not agree that we should call fortis both "the one who reasonably scorns accidental events" and "the one who

the soul's guide to its unearthly dwelling or as the music of the spheres (cf. Buffibre 1956, 473-81; Pepin 1991, 229), but also with Cicero's glamorization of the Sirens as the allure- ment of scientia and of Odysseus as the sapiens who preferred their call to his fatherland

(Fin. 5.49: "they promise knowledge, which unsurprisingly to a lover of wisdom was dearer than his fatherland").

18 Cf. SVF 3, 175; Seneca Ep. 22.7 ([The Stoics] cautiores quam fortiores sunt); 85.26

(cautio illum decet). On caution, cf. Long 1986 (1974), 244; Long and Sedley 1997 (1987), vol. 1, 65 (with the sources). On the eupatheiai in the context of the Stoic ideal of apatheia, cf. Frede 1986.

19 On military images in Seneca, cf. Lavery 1980, 147-51. For a catalog, cf. Armisen- Marchetti 1989, 76-78; 94-97.

20As the parallel with Ep. 14.7-8 suggests, Seneca is recommending prudence in a

dangerous society. The sage "will never arouse the wrath of the powerful, on the contrary, he will try to avoid it just like a storm during a navigation." The imagery is similar: the temerarius gubernator despises threats (here represented by Scylla and Charybdis), whereas the one who is cautior studies currents and winds and stays clear of whirling areas (for the

imagery, cf. also ibid. 15: "some ships are destroyed in the harbor; but what do you think

happens on the high seas?"). The passage from Ep. 28, however, has a broader area of ap- plication, for it is meant to illustrate the desirability of quiet places over crowded ones.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 9: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

560 SILVIA MONTIGLIO

unreasonably rushes out into dangers" (Ben. 2.34.4).21 The sage will be as watchful as a scrupulous man who takes care of that which has been confided to him (Tranq. 11.2).

The De tranquillitate animi employs metaphors of travel to describe life-choices. When the state is unruly, you should devote more time to leisure and study, "seek a harbor from time to time just as in a dangerous navigation, and not wait until the affairs dismiss you but release yourself from them first" (5.5). Drawing on a familiar image (cf., e.g., Lucretius 5.11-12), Seneca recommends the secure and straight course of philosophy over the dangerous navigation that represents public life in unmanage- able times (in ... tempus minus tractabile). The specification implies that in better times one should not avoid the high seas of public life. But the navigation would not be dangerous because the state would be manage- able. Seneca's ideal lifestyle is then signified by a journey with little or no risk. As he says elsewhere in the essay (9.3), those who spread their sails wide are assailed by storms; one should restrict one's activities (cogendae in artum res sunt) to protect oneself from fortune's weapons.

Accordingly, Seneca's trainee will refrain from actions altogether or at least contain their scope. He will avoid the ones that are not necessary ("where no imperative duty summons us, actions should be prevented" [Tranq. 13.1]); he will set limited goals for himself and stop before being stopped by fortune: "you must put your hands to things that you can, or at least hope to, bring to an end. You must leave aside things that continue further than your action and do not stop where you intended" (Tranq. 6.4); "Nothing will free us as much from these mental fluctuations as always setting a limit to a development. We ought not let fortune decide where we stop, but to stop ourselves much earlier" (Tranq. 10.6). Seneca even denies meaning to any action: "Let us abandon the pursuits that are either impossible or difficult to accomplish and follow what is near and goes along with our hope, but let us know that all these things are equally superficial: they have different appearances from outside, but from inside they are all vain" (Tranq. 10.5).22 Such a guarded person, all intent as he is on staying within limits, is unlikely to venture on long and dangerous journeys, whatever their goal. Indeed, elsewhere (Ep. 101.6)

21On this passage in the context of Seneca's discussion of the inopia sermonis, cf. Setaioli 1988, chap. 1, esp. 17-18.

22 Such passages validate Rist's observation (1969, 248) that "Seneca seems to regard freedom not so much as the opportunity to act as a state in which one cannot be forced to act." Rist calls this ideal one of negative freedom. This negative concept of freedom as

non-acting is already Zeno's (cf. SVF 1, 218).

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 10: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

A CONFLICT IN SENECA'S THOUGHT 561

Seneca mentions navigationes longas among the activities that men fool- ishly plan without considering their impending death.

Seneca deems the avoidance of activity much more important to achieving peace of mind than Plutarch does in his treatise On Tranquillity. The difference comes to the fore in their respective interpretations of a phrase from Democritus' own essay on the same topic (peri euthymies). Plutarch criticizes Democritus for arguing that the man who seeks tran- quillity should not engage in many things, either private or public (465c), whereas Seneca endorses Democritus' phrase and wants to limit activity to instances of imperative duty (13.1, cited above).

As the comparison with Plutarch suggests, Seneca's emphasis on the avoidance of activity is not a stock theme. Rather, it could be related to his own implication in politics (the essay was probably written before 62). In the De tranquillitate animi, Seneca does not advocate withdrawal from the public arena on principle, but only as a last resort, and he identifies even the occupations of a private citizen as a form of public service. His advocacy of cautious action or of inaction altogether could reflect his own "dangerous navigation," his experience of political participation with the arduous maneuvers that it involves. But at the same time, Seneca's recommendations have a larger spectrum of reference (his addressee's malaise has many facets, and ambivalence vis-a-vis engaging in politics is only one of them), as is clearly illustrated by the broadening in the application of the travel metaphor from the specific antithesis negotium/ otium to a general rule of life ("don't spread the sails wide if you don't want to be hit by the winds!").

Traveling for the sake of knowledge clashes even more patently with another mainstay of Seneca's moral ideal, that of domestica felici- tas (Ep. 72.4; cf. also 9.15; 23.3; 94.53 and 64).23 "The Stoic sage," Veyne writes, "puts into serious practice an ironic aphorism by Pascal: 'All of mankind's unhappiness comes from a single thing-not knowing enough to rest quietly in a room."'24 Though Seneca insists that one should be able to stay "at home" inside under any circumstances, he also claims that one cannot withdraw into otium if one keeps looking and moving around (Ep. 69.1-2). In order to contain your soul (animum continere),

23The domestic image is more common in the letters (I have found only two instances of it in the dialogues: Const. 15.5 [the wise man has a domus through the doors of which fortune does not enter] and Vit. 4.4 [against desiring maiora domesticis]), perhaps in con- nection with Seneca's voluntary seclusion. Throughout the writing of them, he rarely left Rome and eventually took to his room: cf. Griffin 1992 (1976), 93 and 358, n. 1. The ideal, however, pervades Seneca's work (cf. also, e.g., Prov. 6.5; Const. 5.4 and 6; Tranq. 14.2).

24Veyne 2003, 79.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 11: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

562 SILVIA MONTIGLIO

you have to avoid exposure to voices and sights that would jeopardize your tranquility, and in order to avoid such exposure, you had better stay put if you can. For any movement in the world-not just a disorderly one (errare)-rekindles your past desires: "each time that you move for- ward, during that very movement something will happen that will renew your desires" (ibid. 2: "quotiens processeris, in ipso transitu aliqua quae renovent cupiditates tuas tibi occurrent"). Moreover, each time that you travel abroad you risk being taken farther than expected. It would have been better for Lucilius not to leave his native Naples for Sicily (Ep. 19.5-6): "If only it had befallen you to grow old within the bounds of your birth! If only fortune had not sent you on the deep! Rapid fortune, a province, its administration, and whatever such things promise carried you far from the sight of a healthy life. Then more tasks will take you in, and from those even more: what will be the result?" Lucilius' social promotion has caused him to travel and perhaps will cause him to travel again and again. He may be taken on an endless journey.

The journey of discovery also risks being endless. In the passage from the De otio in which Seneca expresses his admiration for those who travel for knowledge's sake, he also presents the journey that aims to find "something hidden and remote" as a longissima peregrinatio, the end of which cannot be fixed with certainty: aliquid abditum remotumque is no settled destination. And there may be another goal beyond, another journey.25

The movement of the one who is progressing towards wisdom is the opposite: he keeps going,26 but the destination of his journey will not push him beyond itself because wisdom "knows the confines of things" (Ep. 94.16). Of course, wisdom is no easy goal; few, if any, will reach it, and even they only "late" (cf., e.g., Ep. 94.50). The journey to it, however, no matter how arduous, is not an open search but the pursuit of a well-defined ideal by means of well-defined exercises. Sapientia itself will show the way to the one who is progressing (ibid.). Its goal is communicable (Ep. 6.4) and can be pointed at with a finger (Ep. 71.4). Far from resembling the unpredict- able and dangerous journeys out in the world, the philosophical journey is a tutum iter (Ep. 31.9) along one road, the opposite of the crossing of

25The word-order in the phrase navigant ... remotumque emphasizes the length of the journey. As Williams 2003, 87, on 5.2, perceptively notes, the "separation of the verbs with extended polysyllables intervening suggests the arduous length of such voyages, the final positioning of remotum their ultimate goal."

26On the proficiens as "a perfect philosophical counterpart to the active traveller," cf. Lavery 1980, 153. A list of passages containing the image of "the road to wisdom" is in Armisen-Marchetti 1989, 88-89.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 12: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

A CONFLICT IN SENECA'S THOUGHT 563

deserts, mountains, and straits: "One is the road that leads to wisdom, and straight indeed. You will not go astray. Move on with firm steps ... You will learn from reason towards which objects and in which way to go; you will not fall upon things" (Ep. 37.4).27 The imperative destination of the journey (quo eundum est: Vit. 1.3) shapes its course. It is true that the traveler needs a guide because the road to wisdom is unknown to most (ibid.).28 But once he finds it, nothing on it is governed by chance. Just as wisdom will not fall upon you (in te non incidet: Ep. 76.6), the traveler to it will not fall upon things (non incidet rebus) as it happens to any other traveler, including the one through life (Ep. 107.2: "The condition of life is the same as that ... of a journey: some things will be thrown at you, some will fall upon you [incident]"). To quote Veyne again, "moral progress is not an adventure: we know where we are going."29

In addition, because wisdom is at home, the Stoic traveler can only be homebound. He will learn to behave like Odysseus, to love family and fatherland even in the midst of storms (Ep. 88.7). He will acquire the same centripetal determination. The journey of life inevitably exposes us to many happenings that shift the intended directions of our movements. What shall we do? We shall rely on philosophy as on a star (Ep. 95.46) or a helmsman (Ep.16.3; cf. 108.37) that will guide us to our internal home, where we will stay whatever direction we will be forced to take.30

The centripetal nature of the journey to wisdom demands a highly concentrated mental effort, a relentless vigilance (intentio) that will allow the soul to become one and the learnt arts and precepts to fuse in it (Ep. 84.11). As Pierre Hadot puts it, "philosophy was a unique act which had to be practiced at each instant, with constantly renewed attention, which means constant tension and consciousness, as well as vigilance exercised at every moment."31 Traveling is a threat to intentio because it prevents the mind from taking hold of itself. While Seneca, probably also based on his own experience, acknowledges that moving around and changing

27 On the directness of the road to virtue, cf. also Ira 2.13.1-2. 28 Cf. Lavery 1980, 154.

29Veyne 2003, 78. A similar description of the journey to wisdom is in Armisen- Marchetti 1989, 271: [the navigation of the proficiens] "s'est fix6e une direction dont elle ne se laisse pas distraire." Garbarino 1996, 264, n. 2, cites Armisen-Marchetti, but she herself does not discuss how Seneca's conception of the journey to wisdom affects his assessment of traveling in the world.

30Lavery 1980, 154, beautifully summarizes a paradox in the Stoic metaphor of life as a journey: "If all of life is a journey, the Stoic is always on the road; but, at the same time, he is at home everywhere. The Stoic is a resident pilgrim."

31 Hadot 2002, 138. Cf. also Foucault 1986, 51; Nussbaum 1994, 328, 340.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 13: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

564 SILVIA MONTIGLIO

places can have healing and reinvigorating powers,32 he repeatedly warns us that it does not free us from our internal burden; quite the contrary (cf., e.g., Ep. 28 and 104; Tranq. 2.13-15). The motif was well known when Seneca was writing, as he himself points out by citing Lucretius (in Tranq. 2.14-15).33 It has a tangible sociological relevance in light of the spread of traveling, including vacationing, in the late republican and early imperial periods.34 Indeed, Tranq. 2.13-15 can be read as a satire of the impatient tourist, always looking for new landscapes and experiences. Seneca is ready to admit that a longa peregrinatio can be a pleasant dis- traction (Helv. 17.2) and satisfy our thirst for novelty (Ep. 104.13-14).35 But this pleasant distraction is at odds with the steady work of the mind that Stoic training requires. The one who spends his life traveling touches only upon the surface of things: he has many temporary lodgings but no friendships (Ep. 2.2: "vitam in peregrinatione exigentibus hoc evenit, ut multa hospitia habeant, nullas amicitias").

SENECA'S FASCINATION WITH TRAVELING

In sum, the nature and the destination of Seneca's journey to wisdom are incompatible with the boundless and unpredictable movement of the curious traveler. But why then does Seneca celebrate those who embark on long journeys to increase their knowledge? There is no doubt that traveling to study the world draws his admiration. The passage from the De otio is not isolated. Seneca once again shows admiration for those who travel in search for unknown lands in his description of the setting of life (Marc. 18). He compares entering life (or any important life-event, such as having children) to a trip to Syracuse and compares himself to the guide who describes the good and bad things that the traveler will find if she goes.36 Among the good things that the city of life has to offer,

32Cf., e.g., Tranq. 17.8; Pol. 6.4; Ep. 55, 1-2 (the treatment of the motif perhaps is ironical here: cf. Motto and Clark 1993, 115-24); 78.5. More sources in Garbarino 1996, 272, n. 31.

33More sources in Garbarino 1996, 268-69. La Penna (Saggi e studi su Orazio, Florence, 344-50), as cited by Garbarino (270, n. 26), suggests that the motif goes as far back as Democritus' peri euthymies (which Seneca knew indirectly through Panaetius: cf. Setaioli 1988, 97-110). This is born out by Plutarch's essay on the same topic, which also contains the motif (466c).

34Cf. Casson 1994 (1974), chap. 7.

35 On people's taste for novelty, cf. also N. Q. 7.1.1 and Helv. 6.6, cited below. 361 say "she" because Seneca's immediate addressee is a woman. Manning 1981,

95 (at 17), points to the influence of the suasoria on Seneca's choice of image because in

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 14: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

A CONFLICT IN SENECA'S THOUGHT 565

he mentions the communion of men and gods, grandiose celestial and terrestrial phenomena, animals, and, even prior to the arts, ships seeking unknown lands (navigia quas non novere terras quaerentia).

Seneca is also full of praise for Nero because, amantissimus verita- tis, he sent a mission to investigate the sources of the Nile (N. Q. 6.8.3). Seneca himself follows along the explorers' journey by reporting their findings in detail (ibid. 6.8.4-5). In the same work, he claims that the winds are there to make us discover ulteriora, for man would have been an inexperienced animal if he had been confined within his native land (N. Q. 5.18.14).37 Nature has given us unfettered bodies along with the mental power to break even the limits of humanity: "Consider how much nature has allowed us; how human power (humani imperii) is not required to stay within human limits (intra homines); consider how far our bodies can wander. Nature did not even constrain men within the limits of the earth but sent them to each of its parts. Consider how daring their minds are, how they alone know the gods or try to know them, and follow divine beings sending their minds high above" (Ben. 6.23.6).

Seneca builds a climax between the power of our bodies to move all over the earth and, perhaps, to conquer it,38 and the power of our minds to move beyond it. He is playing on the theme of urbs et orbis in order to celebrate the "exorbitance" of our minds: the Romanum imperium is one with the world, but the humanum imperium reaches further out.39 The passage conjures up Plato's description of the philosopher's mind in the Theaetetus (173e-74a). Plato opposes the philosopher's body, which is constrained to dwell in the city, and his mind, which is borne everywhere, above the sky and below the earth, to study the nature of that which truly exists. The body is stuck within the city and its prejudices (though the philosopher soars above them because he pays no attention to the body), while the soul is a cosmic traveler. The opposition reflects Plato's dualistic vision. Seneca, on the other hand, builds a strong connection

that genre, landscapes, sites, and people were considered "topics particularly suitable for excursive description." The image, however, also fits within the Stoic conception of human life as a journey.

37 On this passage, cf. Morgante 1974, 22-24. 38Seneca repeatedly calls expansionistic traveling "wandering"; cf. also Ben. 7.2.5;

Ep. 59.12; N. Q. 3 praef 10.

39I borrow "exorbitance" from Gillies 1994, passim. Seneca's own scientific project is a journey all around the world (N. Q. 3.1: mundum circumire constitui). On our minds' intolerance of limits, cf. Bellincioni 1978, 49 (with reference to Ep. 102.21). Seneca is draw-

ing on the widespread theme of the journey of the mind through the cosmos, on which cf. Setaioli 1999, 498-504.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 15: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

566 SILVIA MONTIGLIO

between the behavior of the body and that of the mind. He sees a con- tinuity rather than a contrast between the power of our bodies to travel far (they are not stuck in the city) and the power of our minds to travel even farther. The movement of the body prepares the movement of the mind. In the passage from the De otio on traveling and contemplation, Seneca does not fully exploit the motif. But in this passage (Ben. 6.23.6), he develops it with elan.

The conflict between Seneca's conception of the journey to wisdom and his admiration for extensive traveling can be detected even within the same text. A large part of letter 104 is devoted to the condemnation of traveling. As we have seen, Seneca dissociates wisdom from traveling by mockingly alluding to the tradition of the educational journey (Ep. 104.19). He repeats that going places does not heal our soul; it only provides us with new sights that retain our attention for a while (14). But then he lists, and at some length, the discoveries that one can make: "Traveling will inform you of other nations, it will show you new shapes of mountains, unknown stretches of plains and valleys watered by peren- nial rivers; it will put under your observation the peculiar nature of some rivers, whether it is the Nile that swells with its summer growth or the Tigris that is snatched away from the eyes and after running through invisible places returns in all its magnitude, or the Meander, a subject of exercise and divertissement (exercitatio et ludus) for all the poets, entwined with its many turnings and often running its course close to its own bed and again bending away from it before it flows into itself. But otherwise, traveling will make you neither better nor healthier" (15).

A sudden shift of voice occurs in this passage, similar to the one that Catharine Edwards (1997, 33) has observed for letter 63. In that letter, after chastising Lucilius for lamenting the death of a friend immoderately, Seneca confesses: "I, who write this, am the one who has immoderately lamented my dearest friend Annaeus Serenus" (14). The epistolary Sen- eca, Edwards argues, has multiple voices. He himself admits that except for the sage, "no one plays the role of one man, but we are all multiple" (Ep. 120.22). In letter 104, Seneca's voice shifts from stigmatizing the ineffectiveness of traveling to embarking on an alluring journey. He is himself transported by the distracting activity that he censures. Even while he is claiming that traveling is unhealthy for the mind, he travels in his own mind and closely follows the contours of the places he sees in his imaginary journey, and it is not by chance that his fancy is captured especially by rivers, with their surges, twists and turns, and in particular by the Meander, whose serpentine shape visibly challenges the Stoic's

plea for a life governed by centripetal effort and treading upon one

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 16: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

A CONFLICT IN SENECA'S THOUGHT 567

unbending road. The Meander carries the traveling Seneca along its sinuous banks and drives him farther away from his previous focus by conjuring up poetry as sheer entertainment, a playful diversion (ludus) that replicates the playfulness of the river itself (cf. H. f. 683-84: vagus / Maeander undis ludit), a "meandering of the mind" away from the straight path to wisdom.40 After this enraptured detour the traveler shifts voice again to resume the role of an enemy of traveling and curtly repeats his initial message, as if startled out of a reverie.

This text also represents literary practice as a form of travel. The Meander is both a locus communis of poetic composition and a thread that guides Seneca's own writing. Likewise, the comparison of the journey in life with a trip to Syracuse (in Marc. 17) allows Seneca to travel in his mind to the famed city and to put the many spectacles he sees before his addressee's eyes in the same order as they would appear on a real journey from the mainland: first (primum) the island separated from the continent by a narrow strait, then Charybdis, then the spring Arethusa, then the harbor, where Seneca's mind disembarks to venture into the city. Seneca's eagerness to show each sight as he travels on (videbis, "you will see," recurs five times between 17.2 and 17.4) sets the narrative tempo.

Traveling, reading, and writing are indeed intertwined in Seneca's prose. At the beginning of letter 2, Seneca treats the same motif as in letter 104: "traveling does not heal your soul." He praises Lucilius because he does not go about or restlessly change places (non discurris nec locorum mutationibus inquietaris), for a self-possessed mind is stable and dwells at ease with itself. Lucilius' reading habits, however, apparently are marked by the same unrest that Seneca reproaches to the unfocused traveler. He reads many books and from every literary genre, a practice that Seneca describes with an image of travel: vagum. Unstructured travel is both a behavioral equivalent to and a metaphor for dispersive reading.41 This

40The Stoics, Seneca included, do not condemn poetry, provided that it has moral relevance: cf. Mazzoli 1970, chap. 3; Nussbaum 1993. In a passage from Plutarch's Aud. poet. (15D), discussed by Nussbaum (131), the correct way to approach poetry is described by an image of straightness: one should behave like Odysseus tied to the mast of reason and not be borne off course by pleasure. The poetic exercises on the Meander would hardly lend themselves to this kind of "straight reasoning." They are mostly similes in which the river is compared to winding courses of things or actions: for instance, Silius Italicus (7.139) compares it to Hannibal's multiple and undecided planning, and Ovid (Met. 8.162-68) to the labyrinth. Seneca himself compares the Meander to the Lethe (in H. f 683-84, cited

above). On the playfulness of the Meander, cf. also Ovid Met. 2.246 (Quique recurvatis ludit Maeandros in undis).

41Cf. also Ep. 45.1, which employs the same metaphors.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 17: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

568 SILVIA MONTIGLIO

development can be interpreted as a counterpart to the Meander digression in letter 104. In that excursus, Seneca is doing what he condemns here: he is centrifugally "reading" the Meander by following his vagi contours.

Movement (if not extensive traveling) and reading are again asso- ciated at the beginning of letter 84. Seneca tells Lucilius that he has benefited from being carried about on a litter because he did not stop reading. He suggests that this passive exercise (aliena opera exerceor) is congenial to the more passive facet of literary practice, reading. The intertwining of movement and reading is further developed with the paradigm of the bee flying from flower to flower: writers should be like bees, which wander (vagantur) to pick the suitable flowers, then transform them into honey.42 Wandering is a positive image for gathering informa- tion through reading.

Letter 79 establishes a philosophically more complex relationship between traveling and literary practice. Seneca hopes to receive an account of Lucilius' circumnavigation of Sicily. If he is satisfied, he will additionally ask Lucilius to climb Mount Aetna in his honor in order to see whether it is being consumed by its flames, as some argue. Surely Lucilius will do so and will not blame his trip on Seneca because he himself is "ill" (4: morbo tuo) with the desire to climb the mountain. The reason Lucilius cannot be stopped is that he "salivates" (the image is in the Latin: cf. 7) at the prospect of writing a grand poem on Mount Aetna, following in the footsteps of illustrious predecessors. Lucilius, however, modestly only hopes to equal those great poets, not to surpass them.43 This observation builds the transition from the discussion of poetry, with its competitive nature, to the description of wisdom, which, in contrast, cannot be sur- passed once it is reached. Wisdom always stays the same. Perhaps Mount Aetna is being consumed and will disappear; virtue never will.

This letter links travel, poetic composition, and the pursuit of wisdom in succession, and in so doing, it combines the two kinds of journey-to wisdom and out into the world-that Seneca deems incompatible on principle. Mount Aetna will take Lucilius first to the variable heights of poetry, then to the absolute summit of wisdom.44 The relevance of the

42Ep. 84.3. In combining the two moments of literary activity, reading and writing, Seneca is more original than Cicero insofar as he puts a premium on personal elaboration. See Setaioli 2000, 206-15.

43Lucilius' alleged modesty suggests that Seneca shared in the widespread senti- ment that Roman literature had reached its peak in the Augustan period: cf. Setaioli 2000, 201-5.

44 Littlewood 2004, 6, rightly observes that in this letter Seneca blends nature, art, and ethics, but he is not concerned with the theme of traveling.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 18: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

A CONFLICT IN SENECA'S THOUGHT 569

journey for the acquisition of wisdom is highlighted by a verbal echo: the verb ascendere describes both Lucilius' climbing (2: ascendas) and the climbing to wisdom (8: ascenditur). By ascending the mountain, Lucilius will be urged to ascend the road of moral improvement, and by imagin- ing Lucilius ascending the mountain, Seneca's mind also travels upward along that road: when you reach the top (8: cum ad summum perveneris) refers to wisdom and the "you" is impersonal, but the image is imme- diately prompted by Seneca's fancy about his friend ascending Mount Aetna. Finally, the landscape of Lucilius' trip offers Seneca material for a meditation on the nature of virtue. In sharp contrast with letter 104, in which the discoveries made by traveling provide nothing more than an alluring diversion, here travel is integrated into the very quest for moral perfection.45 As we shall see in the next section, Seneca's ambivalence

vis-a-vis traveling affects even his treatment of imperialistic expansion.

SENECA ON THE IMPERIALISTIC USE OF TRAVELING

As is well known, Seneca loudly condemns expansion. The most infamous avatar of the expansionistic traveler is Alexander the Great, whom Sen- eca presents as a violator of the natural order. Alexander breaks "the fences of the world" (Ep. 119.7: mundi claustra perrumpit), removes every boundary, and reaches beyond "nature's limits" (Ben. 7.2.6; cf. also Ep. 94.63: ipsi naturae vim parat). He sends his thought across the Ocean (Ep. 91.17) and cannot bear the existence of territories uncharted by him: "He will seek what lies beyond the big sea and will be resentful that there is something beyond himself" (N. Q. 5.18.10). His movement is endless and compulsive. It is as if he were driven on by an unconscious internal motor: "He does not want to go, but he cannot stay, like a weight thrown headlong, the course of which ends only when it lies motionless" (Ep. 94.63). His compulsive traveling is like those movements of the mind that happen not nostro arbitrio, but suo arbitrio (Ira 2.35.2).46

45Garbarino 1996, 280, undermines the meaningfulness of travel in this letter by emphasizing that the journey is attributed not to Seneca himself but to his friend. This

argument does not seem compelling to me because the distinction between teacher and

pupil in the Letters is far from clear-cut: both are imperfecti. 46 Seneca's interpretation of Alexander as the violator of nature is not idiosyncratic. In

Seneca the Elder, Suasoriae 1,Alexander stands at the mouth of the Indus and contemplates a voyage into the ocean to discover new worlds. The student was asked to persuade him not to challenge the "bond of the whole world" (Suas. 1.2). In Lucan, Alexander is the mad

conqueror whom only death can stop. His action confounds and defiles rivers (10.32-33). On Seneca the Elder's Suasoria, cf. Gillies 1994,20. On the Alexander legend in this period,

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 19: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

570 SILVIA MONTIGLIO

This portrait of Alexander as a compulsive traveler can be compared with a later interpretation of his restless moving on as an existential search. The Italian poet Giovanni Pascoli (late nineteenth, early twentieth century) imagines Alexander at the end of the world, longing for the beginnings of a movement that he then thought unlimited: "oh! Piti felice, quanto piui cammino / m'era d'innanzi; quanto piti cimenti, / quanto piui dubbi, quanto pii destino! ... Figlio d'Amynta! Io non sapea di meta / allor che mossi" (Alexandros, II and IV).47 Pascoli's Alexander is propelled by the excitement of facing more and more challenges. Likewise, Seneca's Alexander is urged to reach farther and farther. But Seneca, contrary to Pascoli, shows no sympathy for the unhappy hero. He sees Alexander's urge to travel as the very translation of passion, which the Stoics conceived as an excessive drive: hormi pleonazousa (SVF 1, 206). Like Alexander's movement, that of passion is headlong and cannot be stopped: "When people's bodies are thrown headlong, they have no control over them- selves and cannot choose either to hold back or to delay. Their irrevocable fall cuts off every power of decision and repentance, and they inevitably reach the place which it would have been in their power not to reach. In just the same way our soul, if it hurls itself into anger, love, and the other passions, is not allowed to check its impetus: its own weight and the downhill nature of its vices must carry it and take it to the bottom" (Ira 1.7.4). Alexander's movement not only resembles the impetus of anger, a passion with which he was richly endowed; it is also caused by it, by mad cruelty (Ep. 94.62: "agebat infelicem Alexandrum furor aliena vastandi et ad ignota mittebat").

The violation of the natural order brought about by greedy traveling assumes cosmic proportions in the second choral ode of Medea (301-79), which recounts the navigation of the Argo and its consequences. An act of excessive daring (301: audax nimium), that journey put an end to moral purity and initiated cosmic destruction by forcing its way through boundaries perceived as natural.48 The Argo broke, cut, and whipped the

cf. also ibid. 195, n. 61; Romm 1992, 137-40. Fears 1974 argues that Stoic interpretations of Alexander are not consistently negative. Cf. also Rudich 1997, 69-70.

47In a literal translation: "How much happier I was the longer the way before me, the more the trials, the more the doubts, the more the destiny! ... Son of Amyntas! I knew of no goal as I set out."

48For a persuasive interpretation of this ode as a vision of cosmic destruction, cf. Biondi 1981 and 1988 (1984), followed by Romm 1992, 168-71; Schmitz 1993, 146. I have said "moral purity" following Nussbaum 1994, 421,466-67, who notes that Seneca's Golden

Age differs from the traditional one in a significant respect: it is not an age of abundance but of frugality and self-contentment.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 20: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

A CONFLICT IN SENECA'S THOUGHT 571

sea (302, 305,337); it removed "the covenants of a well-separated world"

(335). The sea had to suffer the blows (337). The immediate reward for that violation was another violator of the natural order, Medea.49

Two episodes in particular announce the apocalyptic effects of that

expedition: the failure of the Argonauts to immobilize the Symplegades and the sudden silence of Orpheus. In Greek myth, the fixing of float- ing islands marks a progression from disorder to order, from chaos to cosmos. Geological stabilization characterizes even the consolidation of the Olympian family-the ultimate establishment of the cosmic order-in the myth of the birth of Apollo, which coincides with the fixing of both a wandering island, Delos, and a wandering goddess, Leto.50 Apollonius of Rhodes had already undermined the power of the Argonauts to tame nature. In his version, the Argo does succeed in fixing the rocks by its

passage (2.604-6) but only thanks to divine help.51 Seneca, however, does not even mention the stilling of the Symplegades (along with any divine

help). Quite the contrary, he presents the passage of the Argo as an

unsettling act. The rocks are significantly called the "fences of the deep sea" (342: claustra profundi). They used to contain the water's expanse and prevent its flooding, like dikes.52 At the ship's approach, the sea can no longer be contained and even touches the stars (344-45). This detail, absent from Apollonius' narrative, "emphasizes the catastrophic mixing of the elements."53

Seneca does not even take the Argo to the other side of the strait but leaves it hanging at the passage, as it were, by creating an uncanny suspension of action and sound: daring Tiphys becomes pale (the oxy- moron palluit audax at 346 drastically modifies audax nimium in the

49Like the Argo, Medea aims to remove boundaries: "let Corinth which delays [sailors] by its double shore be burnt, and join its two seas!" (35-36). She, too, knows no limits (397). Her crime is new (794) like the laws imposed by the Argo on the winds (319) and like the worlds that will replace the current one (377). A mythic link between Medea and the Argo is Phaethon who broke the "sacred covenants of the world" (605-6). Medea sees herself as a successful Phaethon (32-34). Later in the play (1012-13), her violation of her own body builds another parallel with the Argo's violation of geographical boundar- ies: cf. Segal 1983, 178.

50Cf. Montiglio 2005, 14-15. The main source is the Homeric Hymn to Apollo. Cal- limachus' treatment of the myth in his Hymn to Delos is less reassuring: the rooted island retains its feet. Cf. Nishimura-Jensen 2000, 291.

51Cf. Nishimura-Jensen 2000, 307. 52Biondi 1988 (1984), 118 translates claustra as "dikes." He also notes that Seneca

normally uses claustra for the underworld. The flood caused by the Argo is as deadly as an imaginary flood of Hell.

53 Biondi 1988 (1984), 117.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 21: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

572 SILVIA MONTIGLIO

opening line of the ode) and lets the reins fall from his failing hand; the ship loses its divine voice; and Orpheus stops singing while his lyre sleeps (348). Orpheus' exceptional silence conveys his equally exceptional fail- ure to control the cosmos and to elicit universal sympathy by his art.54 Orpheus is uncharacteristically unable to charm the rocks just as the Argo is unable to fix them. The paralysis of his voice signifies the threat that looms over the cosmos as the Argo is crossing through the Symplegades. The loss of harmony between man and nature initiated by this passage soon silences Orpheus forever: his severed head has no voice as it runs down the Hebrus (631), again, contrary to mainstream tradition."55

Subsequent to the Argo's passage, traveling becomes the "natural" mode of existence in a shifting landscape. Any number of insignificant boats now wander the deep (368: altum . . . pererrat). Their pervasive movement (per-errat) completes the dissolution of the cosmos by erasing all the dividing lines (369: terminus omnis motus). The world is permeable, less resisting, everywhere open to travel (372: pervius). It removes and displaces its own components (371-74). This loss of unity results in the relaxation of the very bonds that keep things together (375-76: Oceanus / vincula rerum laxet), that is, in Stoic terms, in the undoing of the cosmos.56 With Ocean losing his tension, the earth spreads everywhere, immense (376-77). The final disappearance of the sea marks the end of the world in Stoic theory.57

54 In Seneca's drama, Orpheus symbolizes the power of art to create a perfect accord between man and nature: cf. Segal 1989. Orpheus' silence at the passage of the Symplegades is all the more remarkable because in the Orphic Argonautica (680-711), it is Orpheus' music that fixes the rocks: cf. Nishimura-Jensen 2000, 307.

55 Cf., e.g., Ovid Met. 11.51-53; Silius Italicus 11.478-80; Virgil Georg. 4.525-27. More references in Bomer 1980, 239, 250; Nagy 1990, 210-12. The episode of the singing head, to be sure, is directly related to Orpheus' love for Eurydice, which Seneca does not men- tion. Nonetheless, the singing head is also a symbol of the eternal power of poetry over

physical death, a power that the voyage of the Argo has defeated. Orpheus is the second of the Argonauts to die (after the pilot, Tiphys), and he dies entirely (cf. the emphatic non rediturus at 633).

56On the metaphor of cosmic bonding, cf. Lapidge 1980 (though Seneca is not discussed).

57Cf. Biondi 1988 (1984), 139. The end of the world consists in the prevailing of the dry element, fire. Cf., e.g., Cicero Nat. deor. 2.118. More sources in SVF, s.v. ekpyrosis. Nonetheless, Seneca is unsystematic: flood and conflagration are alternative ways of end-

ing the cosmos (cf., e.g., N. Q. 3.28.6-7). Medea as a whole privileges fire in the process of cosmic destruction because Medea is the daughter of the Sun, that is, a creature of fire. But even in this play Seneca takes pains to balance the two elements by connecting Medea to the sea (362-63) and by imagining that the fire that her poisons cause is fed, rather than

quenched, by water (889-90), an unrealistic detail absent from Euripides' and Ovid's ac- counts of her crime.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 22: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

A CONFLICT IN SENECA'S THOUGHT 573

The incompatibility between navigation and the ideal of self-content- ment comes to the fore in the so-called Dawn Song of Hercules furens in which sailing brings disturbance into the picture of tranquilla quies (160) that characterizes rural existence: "the sailor, uncertain of his life, entrusts the sails to the winds, which fill their loose folds with their breath" (152-54). It is true that sailing is not condemned in these lines. Far from putting an end to pristine innocence and tranquility, as in the Argo ode, it counts among the peaceful and carefree activities of country-life as opposed to the anx- ious pursuits of city-dwellers. Seneca has been inspired to mention sailing by his model, the parodos of Euripides' Phaethon,58 which lists navigation among the activities that the new day awakens along with tending cattle and hunting. Seneca expands on Euripides: besides building a contrast between peaceful and worrisome occupations, he develops the description of the pastoral setting and adds fishing. But, curiously, while he expands on Euripides he reduces the mention of sailing to less than three lines from the entire strophe that it occupies in his model (Diggle 1970, 79-86).59 Seneca minimizes the presence of sailing in his depiction of rural existence, and, possibly, he even conflates or replaces this activity with fishing (which he describes in much more detail).60 At the same time, his portrayal of the sailor introduces a strong element of uncertainty suitable to prefiguring the disruption that Hercules--whom this play casts as impatient of quiet-will bring into the cosmos: the sailor is dubius vitae.61 There is no equivalent of dubius vitae in Euripides. Seneca, while minimizing the presence of sailing, adds this anxious note. Ultimately, then, the function of traveling in this ode matches its condemnation in Medea: it foreshadows cosmic upheaval.

Seneca's treatment of the Argonauts' expedition, however, is not unambiguously negative. Columbus' son saw the reference to Ultima Thule at the end as a prophecy of his father's discovery of the New World.62 Several modern readers have followed in his footsteps: Seneca,

58This source was already identified by Wilamowitz: cf. Diggle 1970, 96-97, followed

by Rose 1985, 107, and by Billerbeck 1999, 242-44. 59 Cf. Billerbeck 1999, 254 (on 152-58). 60Rose 1985, 111, maintains that the sailor and the fisherman are the same person,

based on the hic (rather than ille) at 154. But hic can be used to mark a transition. Moreover, the fisherman is leaning from rocks on the shore (153-54); he is not at sea like the sailor. The association of the two figures is however undeniable. As Billerbeck has pointed out

(1999, 254, at 152-58), the passage is reminiscent of Ovid Met. 13.920-23, a description of various activities related to fishing.

61Cf. Rose 1985, 112. On Hercules' obsessive restlessness, cf. Galinsky 1972, chap. 8. Nonetheless, the character is not at odds with the Stoic picture of the hero: cf. Billerbeck 1999, 29.

62Cf. Costa 1980 (1973), 379. Cf. also Motto and Clark 1993, 22.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 23: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

574 SILVIA MONTIGLIO

they argue, is envisioning not the end of the world but its expansion, not the destruction of order but the prospect of new discoveries. Far from watching a catastrophe, he is celebrating the unlimited freedom of human power and the taming of nature.63

A progressive reading of the Argo ode is not sustainable. Both con- text and vocabulary leave no doubt that Seneca is retracing the inevitable course towards the destruction of our cosmic order. But an undercurrent of admiration for world discoveries can be detected in the text. A comparison with Horace's treatment of the nefas Argonauticum in Carmina 1.3, which Seneca doubtlessly had in mind,64 highlights the latter's more ambivalent interpretation of the theme. While Horace extends his condemnation of seafaring to other manifestations of human inventiveness and ends his ode with the gloomy vision of a giant-like attack on the sky,65 Seneca ends his own with the captivating image of Ultima Thule. Charles Segal (1989, 107) rightly perceives a dissonance between the beginning of the song, the condemnation of Tiphys' daring, and its end, in which he even reads "the optimism of limitless exploration." Martha Nussbaum (1994, 464-75) analyzes the dissonance in greater detail. It is curious, she notes, that in an ode allegedly meant to denounce the voyage of the Argo and the consequent spread of navigation, and to celebrate our forefathers for living an innocent life at home, Seneca finds little inspiration to sing about the latter. He even chooses a pejorative word, "lazy" (piger, 331), to "praise" it. By contrast, the final strophe has an excited, vibrant pace. Seneca seems to be carried away by the loathed prospect of discoveries and removal of boundaries. Maria Grazia Bajoni (1996) likewise remarks that the initial recognition of the nefas Argonauticum is not followed by a total condemnation of it and takes the phrase laxare vincula (376) positively to refer to the disclosure of a boundless universe. While this reading does not fit the Stoic conception of the universe (there is no boundless universe in Stoic thought), it captures the ode's ambivalence: as we read about the revelation of new worlds, we are prone to forget

63The strongest advocates for a progressive reading of the ode are Lawall 1979, who

regards it as an expression of "happy optimism" (420 and passim) and Bajoni 1996, who sees in its end the granting of unconditional freedom to human action (75). Morgante 1974, 21, also speaks of Seneca's "unshaken faith in future progress."

64The parallels between the two poems are numerous and specific: both identify cosmic order with a separation of the elements (cf. in Horace, abscidit [21], Oceano dis- sociabili [22], non tangenda [24], semoti ... leti [32-33]; cf. also perrupit [36, of Hercules], and audax [25, 27]). For more parallels, cf. Costa 1980 (1973).

65 Cf. Nisbet and Hubbard 1970, 40-45. Nisbet and Hubbard provide a useful list of Greek and Latin poems developing the topical theme of the folly of navigation.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 24: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

A CONFLICT IN SENECA'S THOUGHT 575

that in Stoic terms the novi orbes can only exist after the disappearance of this one, and instead our imagination is drawn to see new worlds opening up within our own. We are left with the exalted vision of future discoveries, beyond Ultima Thule.

One can read a specific reference to Roman imperialism into this ode. As Cedric Littlewood argues (2004, 167-68), at the end "the boundaries of the world are magnified to a Roman imperial scale." He contrasts Seneca's prophecy of an unbounded world with Virgil's vision of a bounded empire (Aeneid 1.287: imperium Oceano, famam qui terminet astris) and concludes that the ode celebrates "the flawed sublimity of an empire which refuses to observe Virgilian and Augustan boundaries."

Seneca's ambivalence vis-a-vis imperialistic expansion affects the logic of a long passage in the Consolatio ad Helviam (6.6-7.8) that jux- taposes opposite representations of mobility and migration. Seneca has a compelling argument against the fear of exile: "I find people who say that in our spirit there is a natural impulse to change places and to transfer residence. For man is endowed with a mind which is mobile and rest- less; it never stays within limits but spreads itself and sends its thoughts everywhere, to known and unknown places, wandering, impatient of quiet and most happy with novelty" (6.6). The theme of the mind's unlimited journeying provides Seneca with a justification for our inborn need to change places (though Seneca is not speaking in his own voice but report- ing what others say: invenio qui dicant). Nevertheless, the recognition of our soul's mobile disposition is immediately illustrated, not by a celebra- tion of traveling but by a gloomy and vertiginous account of migratory movements. Seneca's censure surfaces from a sweeping phrase: "through inaccessible, unknown places, human inconstancy has tossed itself" (per invia, per incognita versavit se humana levitas) (7.2).66 A list of displace- ments follows: "They have dragged sons, wives, and parents heavy with old age. Some, driven about in long wandering, have not chosen a place with judgment but occupied the closest one out of exhaustion; others have established their rights in someone else's land with weapons; some people, while seeking unknown places, have been swallowed by the sea, some have settled down where they were left by a lack of means. And not all have had the same reason for leaving their homeland and seek- ing another one: some have escaped the destruction of their land by the enemy's forces and, deprived of their goods, have been thrust into the

66For a parallel, cf. Ep. 13.16 ("quam foeda sit hominum levitas cotidie nova vitae fundamenta ponentium"). In this letter also, one manifestation of levitas is the preparation for travels even in old age.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 25: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

576 SILVIA MONTIGLIO

goods of others; some have been expelled by civil war; others have left to ease the pressure of overpopulation; others have been thrown out by a plague or by repeated earthquakes or by some unbearable defect of a barren soil; yet others have been tempted by the fame of a fertile land, too highly praised." Our soul's intolerance of quiet suggests to Seneca this dismal assessment of our movements in the world, marked by impi- ety (in the dragging of defenseless family members), violation (in the appropriation of others' lands), destruction. The narrative's last word, corrupit, spells out its mood.

The following development, however, culminates in an unqualified celebration of the Roman empire. Seneca lists Antenor, Evander, and Diomedes as examples of fugitives who founded new settlements, and he remarks: "The Roman empire itself looks back to an exile as its founder, a fugitive whose fatherland had been captured. With a few survivors, he was seeking faraway lands, driven to Italy by necessity and fear of the enemy. But then how many colonies these people have sent out to every province! Wherever the Romans conquer, they dwell. They were willing to put their names down for this change of place, and even old men, leaving their altars, followed the settlers across the sea" (7.7). This appraisal of the origin of Roman power reverses the negative judgment on migrations that precedes it. The initial displacement, exile, is turned into the motor (if not the precondition) for imperial expansion. Passivity and helpless- ness give way to a collective initiative in which even old men willingly participate, in sharp contrast with the previous account of migrations in which "parents heavy with old age" were dragged along.67 Seneca thus suggests that the Roman empire, far from being hybristic, originates in the predicament of exile and is the legitimate outgrowth of it.

Seneca's positive assessment of Roman imperialism is borne out by his undisguised admiration for several Roman conquests and conquerors. In the Consolatio ad Polybium, he wishes that Claudius may "open up Britain" (13.2) and commends Tiberius' brother Drusus for his expedition into the heart of Germany and for submitting "those most savage peoples" to Roman rule (15.5). He evokes Drusus' conquest also in the Consolatio ad Marciam (3.1) and with no polemical intent. Drusus "penetrated deeply into Germany and fixed Roman standards where it was hardly known that there were Romans at all." Caesar, too, was "wandering all over Britain

67 In the phrase "They were willing to put their names down for this change of place, and even old men, leaving their altars, followed the settlers across the sea," "old men"

(singular in the Latin) occupies the emphatic final position.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 26: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

A CONFLICT IN SENECA'S THOUGHT 577

and could not even contain his happiness within the ocean" (ibid. 14.3). Why does Seneca approve of these expansionistic missions?

His expressions of sympathy for Claudius' project in the Conso- latio ad Polybium (and, possibly, his praise of Drusus in the Consolatio ad Marciam) sound like flattery.68 Nonetheless, his overall treatment of expansionistic traveling shows that political opportunism cannot be the main motive behind his admiration for those expeditions. As we have seen, his flattering account of Nero's mission to the sources of the Nile in the Naturales Quaestiones emphasizes only its intellectual goal: Nero is amantissimus veritatis. Seneca knows how to please an emperor for his commitment to explorations while at the same time ignoring his imperialistic aims.

Seneca's treatment of this particular mission could rather suggest that he saw a strong interconnection between conquests and knowledge. Even in the Argo ode from Medea, the condemnation of greedy traveling is coupled with the vision of worlds beyond. Seneca seems to be grappling with the question: "is it possible to advance our knowledge of the world without advancing our claims over it?" He holds scientific progress, in the sense of an ever increasing knowledge of nature's mysteries, as the only good kind of progress, provided that no manipulation of nature follows.69 But he also sees how difficult it is to protect that desirable and never-ending acquisition of knowledge from utilitarian motives and applications.

68The Consolatio ad Marciam contains the most appreciative picture of Tiberius, perhaps in line with. Caligula's reversed tolerance towards the senate and his parallel rehabilitation of the former emperor in 39: cf. Griffin 1992 (1976), 23. In this climate, a

praise of Tiberius' brother could please Caligula. On the other hand, Seneca's admiration for Caesar's conquests may have been sincere and durable. Rudich 1997, 56-57, argues that Seneca is not utterly unsympathetic to Caesar. Griffin (184) notes that in Ep. 94.65, Caesar's negative ambition is illustrated only by the civil wars, which may indicate that Seneca's position vis-a-vis the conquests remained positive. This is not certain, however, because the appreciative statements all come from the Consolationes. Indeed, in the pas- sage from the Naturales Quaestiones that condemns those who make use of the winds to seek enemies across the sea, the main target could be Caesar for his expedition to Britain

(cf. Canfora 2000, 176-77), the same expedition mentioned in a positive light in the Con- solatio ad Marciam.

69Cf., e.g., N. Q. 7.25.5: "veniet tempus quo posteri nostri tam aperta nescisse mi- rentur." On the relationship between science and ethics in the Naturales Quaestiones, cf. De Vivo 1992; Parroni 2000. On progress in Seneca, cf. Morgante 1974, 19-33, with further

bibliography; De Vivo 1992, passim, esp. 88-89; Motto and Clark 1993, 21-39; Fedeli 2000. Fedeli (44) maintains that Seneca does not systematically condemn human intervention on nature. Although Marc. 18 suggests as much, the passage is isolated and its content

very general.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 27: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

578 SILVIA MONTIGLIO

The difficulty surfaces from his discussion of the function of the winds (N. Q. 5.18.14). His claim that the winds are there for us to travel begs the question: why should we travel at all? We have seen that Seneca advocates knowledge as the correct, natural goal: ad ulteriora noscenda. But he also mentions convenience: "[god] gave the winds in order that the advantages (commoda) of each region could be shared, not that people should lead legions and cavalry." Seneca is suggesting that contact with foreign people is desirable not only because it broadens our mental hori- zon but also because it brings us "advantages," namely, it increases our

options and improves our lives. We can even read an endorsement of trade in this passage, for commoda embrace all the preferable things, including material goods.70 Seneca shifts from the acquisition of knowledge to the practical benefits of traveling. Nonetheless, since his Stoic self maintains that commoda are not real goods, he does not go into more detail but reverts to the condemnation of military aggressions.

Likewise, the climax that he builds between our power (imperium) to move all over the earth and our mind's power to move even beyond it (Ben. 6.23.6, cited above) is an indication that he could hardly envisage a disinterested kind of traveling completely disjointed from its appropriative and manipulative counterparts, including expansion. The distinction was especially difficult in ancient times because only some people (as Seneca himself says in Ot. 5.2) traveled with the sole purpose of increasing their knowledge. Explorers cleared the way for colonization and conquest.

Seneca's mention of traveling in his description of the city of life (Marc. 18) further complicates the issue. We recall that this symbolic city counts among its attractions "ships that seek unknown lands." Seneca does not specify the motives for their travels. This vagueness, while it bears out the intertwinement of intellectual and acquisitive traveling in Seneca's mind, also suggests that he admires expansion even regardless of the progress of knowledge that it brings. He concludes: "You will see that there is nothing left untried for human daring and you will be both a spectator and yourself a great participant in those attempts." Travel- ing far, whatever the purpose, does not violate nature but harmonizes with it. Seneca mentions the ships right after the aquatic animals, as their "natural" descendants. The ocean, vinculum terrarum, this time has remained intact (18.6).

It is true that Seneca's model for the praiseworthy conqueror is

70 Seneca stigmatizes commerce and the traveling that it requires in, e.g., Vit. 2.1; Helv. 10.5-6; Phaedr. 530. He seems to approve of it in Ep. 87.21, where he also distinguishes between commodum and bonum (36).

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 28: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

A CONFLICT IN SENECA'S THOUGHT 579

Hercules, the selfless pacifier of the world, the antithesis of Alexander (Ben. 1.13.3), and a major Stoic hero. Hercules' travels do not clash with the Stoic ideal of detachment from externals because they are imposed on him as a service to mankind. But, as Miriam Griffin has pointed out, Seneca's application of the "Herculean standards" to Roman conquerors is complicated by occasional acknowledgments of the traditional military conception of virtus.71 Among our passages, at least the image of Caesar's unrestrained happiness as he roams all over Britain barely fits the Stoic- Herculean standards. Seneca's ambivalent treatment of the imperialistic use of traveling shows him addressing a difficulty shared by the politics and literature of the period, namely, how to balance containment and expansion.72

CONCLUSIONS

We can now go back to Garbarino's and Veyne's interpretations. We shall agree that Seneca's sage, and aspiring sage, will only feel compelled to travel in order to serve his country (as Hercules also did, his country being the entire world). Otherwise, traveling, even for the sake of knowledge, is not a way towards wisdom and can even prevent its acquisition.73 Seneca, to be sure, exploits travel for moral reflection, but he puts any other life- experience (such as renting an apartment above noisy baths) to the same use.74 His focus on the inner self clashes with the endorsement of travel as a means of acquiring knowledge of the world because such knowledge is (at best) inessential for self-improvement. But at the same time, on several occasions Seneca shows admiration for exploratory traveling, so much so that he even approves of imperialistic missions. More generally, he is inconsistent in his assessment of human mobility: he stigmatizes restless- ness, yet he praises our inborn urge to move about by connecting it with the power of our mind to travel across the cosmos. In letter 79, the ascent of a fabled mountain merges with the very vision of wisdom.

71 Griffin 1992 (1976), 223. 72 Cf. Pagin 1999, esp. 315. Further bibliography on the subject can be found in this

article. Cf. also Littlewood's reading of the end of the Argo ode in Medea (167-68). 73Mazzoli 1989, 1832, summarizing Ep. 28, says that in that text traveling neither

harms nor favors virtue. I think that this is true for the hypothetical sage (because virtue can neither be lost nor increased) but not for the one making progress, whom traveling distracts from his "centripetal journey."

74 Cf. Bellincioni 1978,114. On Seneca's habit of looking for morally profitable things wherever he is, cf. Ep. 55.3.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 29: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

580 SILVIA MONTIGLIO

One could play down the inconsistencies by invoking context as a decisive factor. Seneca's arguments are not always statements of principle but are strongly influenced by rhetorical factors. Vasily Rudich has stated the problem clearly in his study of Seneca's inconsistent political views: "meticulous listing and discussing of all the passages relevant to a par- ticular set of political connotations in order to determine Seneca's 'true' views or attitudes methodologically misleads: his thought and sympathies continue to remain elusive. It is more promising to concentrate on a few motifs which recur throughout the corpus without much variance, espe- cially when their presence is not urged by the text's immediate subject matter. Where a serious contradiction on a major theme is discovered, a judicious inquiry is needed to determine whether it arises from spe- cifically rhetorical, or rather from political and psychological factors."75 Nevertheless, the celebration of traveling for the sake of knowledge is

precisely one of the motifs that occur repeatedly and in different con- texts: at one time Seneca is discussing the function of the winds (in the Naturales Quaestiones), at another the value of contemplation (in the De otio), at another the setting of life (in the Consolatio ad Marciam), at another a Stoic syllogism according to which a thing cannot be good if its pursuit may cause evils (in Ep. 87.28), at yet another the care that god devoted to the making of man as a rational being (in the De beneficiis). Furthermore, the positive mentions of travel in these passages cannot be

explained simply by rhetorical considerations. Possibly the reader will expect an encomium of travel in a defense of philosophical contempla- tion (the motif was topical) or in a discussion about the function of the winds, but not necessarily as the exemplary virtuous action, as a good thing to find in the city of life, or as evidence for our god-given rationality. More important, we have seen that Seneca's mind itself enjoys taking off to marvelous sites (the Nile, the Meander, Scylla and Charybdis, Mount Aetna). For these reasons, I take his inconsistencies concerning traveling as indicators of a real ambivalence.

Martha Nussbaum's reading of the Argo ode in Medea provides a

good point of departure to explain the ambivalence. She interprets the tension in that ode between the intended praise of the immobile life and an unavowed fascination with its opposite as betraying a conflict in Seneca's own mind. Seneca seems to be at odds with his own philosophical convictions, implicitly questioning Stoic morality because, if rigorously interpreted, it entails inactivity. Tragedy, Nussbaum argues, is the ideal medium for Seneca's critical dialogue with himself insofar as the genre

75 Rudich 1997, 52.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 30: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

A CONFLICT IN SENECA'S THOUGHT 581

endorses the values that Stoicism rejects, namely, attachment to externals (though the tension, as we have seen, surfaces in his prose writings as well). Nussbaum's insight challenges Veyne's somewhat blunt statement (2003, 79) that "the thought that living like this [= unadventurously] would lead to death from boredom never even crossed the Stoics' mind." According to her, it did cross Seneca's, and uncomfortably so.

This interpretation does justice to Seneca's exacting thinking, but it runs the risk of opposing the philosopher to his own school (a position that is generally refuted)76 and of disregarding important differences of

opinion concerning traveling within Stoicism itself. Rather than reflect-

ing a conflict between his adherence to Stoic dogma and his criticism of it, Seneca's contradictory statements about travel could reflect a conflict between his Posidonian sympathies and his fundamental agreement with the older Stoics. Seneca's treatment of travel in the De otio indeed shows both his undermining of the Posidonian position and his attraction for it. Seneca is likely to have in mind Posidonius' encomium of the theoretical life.77 At the same time, his failure to exploit the connection of traveling with contemplation (as noted by Garbarino) can be read as a refusal to

espouse the Posidonian model wholeheartedly. As far as travel is con- cerned, Seneca expresses his attraction to that model indirectly, even deviously, in contexts that do not deal with travel per se.

Seneca's unresolved relation to Posidonius is apparent in his com-

plex position on erudition, more open than the older Stoics' position but not as open as Posidonius'-and travel, in Seneca's own interpretation, is bound together with erudition.78 As is well known, Seneca's inward-look-

ing conception of wisdom undermines the importance of any specialized field, including the artes liberales (most famously in Ep. 88). One should

study to know better, not more (Ep. 89.23). Too much is always a vice: Vitiosum est ubique quod nimium est.79 His dismissal of encyclopedic education is mirrored in the positive image of the progress to wisdom as a straight and unadventurous journey and in the negative one of the omnivorous reader as a restless traveler (as in Ep. 2). But Seneca allows

76 Cf., e.g., Mazzoli 1993 (1991), 177. 77Williams 2003,72, cites the Posidonian fragment on the theoretical life in connection

with Ot. 5. On Seneca's overall position on the theoretical life, cf. Mazzoli 1970, 35-43. 78The issue of erudition in Seneca can only be treated very briefly here. For excellent

discussion, cf. Mazzoli 1970, chap. 1. 79 Tranq. 9.6. Seneca's target here is those who buy many books for display, whereas

he would readily forgive people if "they erred because of an excessive desire to study" (studiorum nimia cupidine erraretur, 9.7). But we have just heard him (9.4-5) condemn the

distracting readings of many books.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 31: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

582 SILVIA MONTIGLIO

for more inclusiveness than this schematic distinction between erudi- tion and wisdom could suggest. As Giancarlo Mazzoli has pointed out, he praises the study of beneficial subjects even if it does not have an immediate practical effect: "pursuing salutary studies is laudable, even if they do not have practical results" (studiorum salutarium etiam citra effectum laudanda tractatio est, Vit. 20.1).80 Seneca criticizes Posidonius in letters 88 and 90, but at the end of letter 78, largely devoted to the healing power of study against bad health, he endorses Posidonius' claim that "one day of an educated man lasts longer than the longest life of the ignorant" ("unus dies hominum eruditorum plus patet quam imperitis longissima aetas": Ep. 78.28-29).

However, resorting to a doctrinal debate is perhaps not the most satisfactory way to explain Seneca's contradictory pronouncements about travel because Seneca does not always speak as a Stoic. Catha- rine Edwards' concept of Seneca's polyphonic self may be more helpful. Seneca is playing different roles when he says different things about travel, and none of those roles is more authoritative or authentic than another. The voice that praises travel belongs to the Seneca involved in worldly projects and particularly fond of natural wonders, whereas the one which stigmatizes the activity belongs to the inward-looking searcher for happiness. This does not mean that there is no conflict, which would be tantamount to privileging one voice over the others as more truth- ful.81 Rather, Seneca's manifold views of travel are one expression of his tormented versatility.82

UNIVERSITY OF WISCONSIN e-mail: [email protected]

80Cf. Mazzoli 1970, 14. 81Habinek 2000, 286, n. 55, criticizes the notion of "dissimulation" in Rudich's dis-

cussion of Neronian culture because it assumes an "authentic" personality independent of its manifestations.

821 wish to thank Jim McKeown, Carole Newlands, and Victoria Pagain for reading previous drafts of this article as well as Barbara Gold and two anonymous readers for their generous and helpful comments.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 32: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

A CONFLICT IN SENECA'S THOUGHT 583

BIBLIOGRAPHY AND ABBREVIATIONS

Armisen-Marchetti, Mireille. 1989. Sapientiae facies: etude sur les images de Se-

neque. Paris: Les Belles Lettres.

Bajoni, Maria Grazia. 1996. "I1 tema dei mondi sconosciuti in Seneca, Med. 375-79." In Nove studi sui cori tragici di Seneca, ed. Luigi Castagna, 75-85. Milan: Vita e Pensiero.

Bellincioni, Maria. 1978. Educazione alla sapientia in Seneca. Brescia: Paideia. Bevan, Edwin R. 1913. Stoics and Sceptics. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Billerbeck, Margarethe, ed. 1999. Seneca, Hercules Furens. Leiden: Brill. Biondi, Giuseppe G. 1981. "Il mito argonautico nella Medea. Lo stile 'filosofico'

del drammatico Seneca." Dioniso 52:421-45. . 1988 (1984). Il nefas argonautico. Mythos e logos nella Medea di Seneca.

Bologna: Patron. Bimer, Franz. 1980. Ovidius Naso. Metamorphosen. Buch X-XI. Heidelberg:

C. Winter. Buffiere, F6lix. 1956. Les mythes d'Homere et la pensee grecque. Paris: Les Belles

Lettres. Canfora, Luciano. 2000. "Seneca e le guerre civili." In Seneca e il suo tempo. Atti

del convegno internazionale di Roma-Cassino 11-14 novembre 1998, ed.

Piergiorgio Parroni, 161-77. Rome: Salerno. Casson, Lionel. 1994 (1974). Travel in the Ancient World. Baltimore: Johns Hop-

kins University Press. Costa, C. D. N., ed. 1980 (1973). Seneca. Medea: Oxford: Clarendon Press. De Vivo, Arturo. 1992. Le parole della scienza. Sul trattato de terrae motu di

Seneca. Salerno: P. Laveglia. Diggle, James, ed. 1970. Euripides Phaethon. Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press. DK = Diels, Hermann, and W. Kranz, eds. 1995-98. Die Fragmente der Vorsokra-

tiker, 6th ed. 3 vols. Zurich: Weidmann. Edelstein-Kidd = Edelstein, Ludwig, and I. G. Kidd, eds. 1972. Posidonius: The

Fragments, 3 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Edwards, Catharine. 1997. "Self-Scrutiny and Self-Transformation in Seneca's

Letters." G&R 64:23-38. Fears, J. Rufus. 1974. "The Stoic View of the Career and Character of Alexander

the Great." Philologus 118:113-30. Fedeli, Paolo. 2000. "Seneca e la natura." In Seneca e il suo tempo. Atti del con-

vegno internazionale di Roma-Cassino 11-14 novembre 1998, ed. Piergiorgio Parroni, 25-45. Rome: Salerno.

Foucault, Michel. 1986. The Care of the Self. Trans. Robert Hurley. New York:

Vintage Books. Frede, Michael. 1986. "The Stoic Doctrine of the Affections of the Soul." In The

Norms of Nature, ed. Malcolm Schofield and Gisela Striker, 93-110. Cam-

bridge: Cambridge University Press.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 33: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

584 SILVIA MONTIGLIO

Galinsky, Karl. 1972. The Herakles Theme. Oxford: Blackwell. Garbarino, Giovanna. 1996. "Secum peregrinari: il tema del viaggio in Seneca." In

De tuo tibi. Omaggio degli allievi a Italo Lana, 263-85. Bologna: Patron. Gillies, John. 1994. Shakespeare and the Geography of Difference. Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press. Griffin, Miriam T. 1992 (1976). Seneca: A Philosopher in Politics. Oxford: Clar-

endon Press. Grimal, Pierre. 1978. Seneca: Macht und Ohnmacht des Geistes. Trans. Karlhans

Abel. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft. - . 1992. "Le vocabulaire de l'int6riorit6 dans l'oeuvre philosophique de

S6nbque." In La langue latine, langue de la philosophie. Actes du colloque organise par l'Ecole frangaise de Rome, 17-19 mai 1990, 141-59. Rome: Ecole franqaise de Rome.

Habinek, Thomas. 2000. "Seneca's Renown: Gloria, Claritudo, and the Replication of the Roman Elite." Cl Ant 19:264-303.

Hadot, Ilsetraut. 1984. Arts liberaux et philosophie dans la pensde antique. Paris: Etudes Augustiniennes.

Hadot, Pierre. 2002. What Is Ancient Philosophy? Trans. Michael Chase. Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

Lapidge, Michael. 1980. "A Stoic Metaphor in Late Latin Poetry: the Binding of the Cosmos." Latomus 39:817-37.

Lavery, Gerard B. 1980. "Metaphors of War and Travel in Seneca's Prose Works." G&R 27:147-57.

Lawall, Gilbert. 1979. "Seneca's Medea: the Elusive Triumph of Civilization." In Arktouros. Hellenic Studies Presented to B.M.W Knox, ed. Glenn Bower- sock, Walter Burkert, and Michael C. Putnam, 419-26. Berlin: Walter De Gruyter.

Littlewood, Cedric. A. J 2004. Self-Representation and Illusion in Senecan Tragedy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Long, Anthony A. 1986 (1974). Hellenistic Philosophy: Stoics, Epicureans, Sceptics. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.

Long, Anthony A., and David N. Sedley. 1997 (1987). The Hellenistic Philosophers. 2 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Manning, C. E. 1981. "On Seneca's "Ad Marciam." Leiden: Brill (Mnemosyne, Suppl. 69).

Mayer, Roland, ed. 1994. Horace. Epistles, Book 1. Cambridge: Cambridge Uni- versity Press.

Mazzoli, Giancarlo. 1970. Seneca e la poesia. Milan: Ceschina. -. 1989. "Le 'Epistulae Morales ad Lucilium' di Seneca. Valore letterario e

filosofico." In ANRW II 36.3, 1823-77. Berlin: Walter De Gruyter. . 1993 (1991). "La prosa filosofica, scientifica, epistolare." In La prosa

latina. Forme, autori, problemi, ed. Franco Montanari, 145-227. Rome: La Nuova Italia Scientifica.

Montiglio, Silvia. 2005. Wandering in Ancient Greek Culture. Chicago, Ill.: The University of Chicago Press.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 34: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

A CONFLICT IN SENECA'S THOUGHT 585

Morgante, Filippo. 1974. "I1 progresso umano in Lucrezio e Seneca." RCCM 16:3-40.

Motto, Anna Lydia, and John R. Clark. 1993. Essays on Seneca. Frankfurt: P. Lang. Nagy, Joseph. E 1990. "Hierarchy, Heroes and Heads: Indo-European Structures in

Greek Myth." In Approaches to Greek Myth, ed. Lowell Edmunds, 200-237. Baltimore, Md.: Johns Hopkins University Press.

Nisbet, Robin G. M., and Margaret Hubbard, eds. 1970.A Commentary on Horace: Odes, Book 1. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Nishimura-Jensen, Julie M. 2000. "Unstable Geographies: The Moving Landscape in Apollonius' Argonautica and Callimachus' Hymn to Delos." TAPA 130:287-317.

Nussbaum, Martha C. 1993. "Poetry and the Passions: Two Stoic Views." In Passions and Perceptions: Studies in Hellenistic Philosophy of Mind. Proceedings of the Fifth Symposium Hellenisticum, ed. Jacques Brunschwig and Martha C. Nussbaum, 97-149. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

•- . 1994. The Therapy of Desire: Theory and Practice in Hellenistic Ethics.

Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press.

Pagain, Victoria E. 1999. "Beyong Teutoburg: Transgression and Transformation in Tacitus Annales 1.61-62." CP 94:302-20.

Parroni, Piergiorgio. 2000. "Le Naturales quaestiones fra scienza e morale." In Seneca e il suo tempo. Atti del convegno internazionale di Roma-Cassino 11-14 novembre 1998, ed. Piergiorgio Parroni, 433-44. Rome: Salerno.

P6pin, Jean. 1991. "The Platonic and Christian Ulysses." In Odysseus/Ulysses, ed. Harold Bloom, 228-48. New York: Chelsea House Publishers (first published in Neoplatonism and Christian Thought, ed. Dominic J. O'Meara, 3-18. Norfolk, Va.: International Society for Neoplatonic Studies, 1981).

Rist, John M. 1969. Stoic Philosophy: London: Cambridge University Press. Romm, James S. 1992. The Edges of the Earth in Ancient Thought. Princeton, N.J.:

Princeton University Press. Rose, A. R. 1985. "Seneca's Dawn Song (Hercules furens, 125-58) and the Imagery

of Cosmic Disruption." Latomus 44:101-23. Rudich, Vasily. 1997. Dissidence and Literature under Nero: The Price of Rhetori-

cization. London: Routledge. Schmitz, Christine. 1993. Die kosmische Dimension in den Tragodien Senecas.

Berlin: Walter De Gruyter. Segal, Charles. 1983. "Boundary Violation and the Landscape of the Self in Sen-

ecan Tragedy." A&A 29:172-87. . 1989. "Dissonant Sympathy: Song, Orpheus, and the Golden Age in

Seneca's Tragedies." In Orpheus: The Myth of the Poet, 95-117. Baltimore, Md.: Johns Hopkins University Press. (first published in Seneca Tragicus [Ramus 12], ed. Anthony J. Boyle, 229-51. Berwick, Victoria: Aureal Pub- lications, 1983).

Setaioli, Aldo. 1988. Seneca e i Greci. Citazioni e traduzioni nelle opere filosofiche. Bologna: Patron.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

Page 35: Conflict in Seneca's Thought

586 SILVIA MONTIGLIO

. 1999. "L'impostazione letteraria del discorso di Pitagora nel XV libro delle Metamorfosi." In Ovid. Werk und Wirkung. Festgabe ftir Michael von Albrecht zum 65. Geburtstag, I, ed. Werner Schubert, 487-514. Frankfurt am Main: Peter Lang Verlag.

-- . 2000. Facundus Seneca. Aspetti della lingua e ideologia senecana. Bologna: Phtron.

SVF = von Arnim, H., ed. 1903-1905. Stoicorum Veterum Fragmenta, 3 vols.

Leipzig: Teubner.

Veyne, Paul. 2003. Seneca. The Life of a Stoic. Trans. David Sullivan. London:

Routledge. Williams, Gareth D., ed. 2003. Seneca. De otio, de brevitate vitae. Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press.

This content downloaded from 181.118.153.129 on Fri, 28 Nov 2014 20:25:27 PMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions