Compositionality

70
Compositionality

description

Compositionality. Wilhelm von Humbolt famously described language as a system that “makes infinite use of finite means.”. Infinite Noun Phrases. There are infinitely many noun phrases: you can always make another one by adding another adjective: D og Old dog Smelly, old dog - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Transcript of Compositionality

Page 1: Compositionality

Compositionality

Page 2: Compositionality

Wilhelm von Humbolt famously described language as a system that “makes infinite use of finite means.”

Page 3: Compositionality

Infinite Noun Phrases

There are infinitely many noun phrases: you can always make another one by adding another adjective:• Dog• Old dog• Smelly, old dog• Brown, smelly, old dog• Big, brown, smelly, old dog

Page 4: Compositionality

Infinite Adjective Phrases

• Old• Extremely old• Probably extremely old• Invariably probably extremely old• Predictably invariably probably extremely oldUsed in a sentence: “Residents of nursing homes are predictably invariably probably extremely old.”

Page 5: Compositionality

Infinitely Many VPs and DPs

And of course there are infinitely many verb phrases, and even “determiner phrases”:

• John’s mother.• John’s wife’s mother.• John’s wife’s lawyer’s mother.• John’s wife’s lawyer’s dog’s mother.

Page 6: Compositionality

Infinitely Many Sentences

It follows that there are infinitely many sentences, because (for example) each sentence NP + VP can be lengthened to AP + NP + VP, then to AP + AP + NP + VP, and so on.

Page 7: Compositionality
Page 8: Compositionality

Infinitely Many Sentences

In addition, there are infinitely many sentences because you can take any sentence S and add “so-and-so believes that” to the front:• S• John believes that S• Mary hopes that John believes that S• Sam doubts that Mary hopes that John believes

that S

Page 9: Compositionality
Page 10: Compositionality

Recursion

This is in general possible because language is recursive. Suppose I’m throwing a party. I start writing the invite list:• My friends are invited.• Friends of my friends are invited.• Friends of friends of my friends are invited.• Friends of friends of friends…It seems like I’ll never finish!

Page 11: Compositionality

Recursive Loop

But suppose instead I said:INVITE LIST:(i) My friends are invited.(ii) If x is a friend of someone who is invited,

then x is invited.

This captures all the cases, by going in a loop. (ii) defines who is invited in terms of who is invited.

Page 12: Compositionality

Recursion and Language

Here’s how language might do it:NOUN PHRASE:(i) “man” is a noun phrase(ii) If NP is a noun phrase then “old” + NP is a

noun phrase.

From this recursive definition, it follows there are infinitely many noun phrases.

Page 13: Compositionality

Infinite Use of Finite Means

This is one sense in which language “makes infinite use of finite means.” There are finitely many words, and the rules of grammar are presumably finite. But recursion generates infinite complex expressions from a finite “base.”

Page 14: Compositionality

Understanding

But this raises another question. Each of the infinite distinct sentences in English has a different meaning.

We cannot learn the meaning of each one separately. But we can understand any English sentence, even one we’ve never heard before.

Page 15: Compositionality

Novel Utterance

“Last week a former Royal Marine who is the boyfriend of the model Kelly Brooks crashed into a bus stop while driving a van carrying a load of dead badgers.”

Page 16: Compositionality

Compositionality

How is it possible for us to understand a potential infinitude of novel utterances? The most common solution in philosophy and linguistics is to maintain that the meanings of complex expressions depend on– and depend only on– the meanings of their simple parts and the ways that those parts are organized (put together by the grammar). This is called compositionality.

Page 17: Compositionality

Compositionality

How does this solution work?

Since there are only finitely many simple expressions (words/ morphemes) in English (or any other language), each language user only has to learn finitely many meaning facts: what all the simple expressions mean.

Page 18: Compositionality

Compositionality

Then when that user encounters a novel utterance she just uses the already-learnt meaning facts about words and the grammar of the utterance to work out its meaning. Compositionality says that’s all she needs! “The meaning of the whole depends on (and only on) the meanings of the parts and the way they are combined.”

Page 19: Compositionality

Non-Compositionality

What does this claim rule out? Here’s an example of a non-compositional arithmetical function #:(n # m) := n + m, if (n # m) appears alone.(n # m) := n + m + x, in the context (x # (n # m)).In this example the value of (n # m) depends not just on the values of n and m, but sometimes on other values (e.g. x).

Page 20: Compositionality

Locality

In this sense, compositionality is local. In the expression [old [brown dog]] what “brown dog” means cannot depend on what “old” means, even though that’s also part of the expression containing “brown dog.”

Page 21: Compositionality

Non-Compositionality

The second thing compositionality rules out is that the meaning of a complex depends on more than just the meanings of the parts. For example consider the count function C, it counts the number of symbols after it, ignoring their values:C(8) = 1C(5 + 3) = 3C(2 + 2 + 2 + 2) = 7

Page 22: Compositionality

Semantic Closure

1. “Lois Lane loves Clark Kent.”

2. “Lois Lane loves Superman.”

Page 23: Compositionality

Semantic Closure

We cannot say that the reason they have different meanings is that “Clark Kent” and “Superman” are different words.

Compositionality says that different meanings are possible for complex expressions only if their parts have different meanings (not diff words).

Page 24: Compositionality

INTERPRETATIONS OF COMPOSITIONALITY

Page 25: Compositionality

Compositionality

The meanings of complex expressions depend on– and depend only on– the meanings of their simple parts and the ways that those parts are combined.

Page 26: Compositionality

Compositionality

Different views regarding what compositionality is result from different views of what meaning is and what dependence is.

Page 27: Compositionality

Functions

Page 28: Compositionality

Compositionality

The meanings of complex expressions depend on the meanings of their simple parts and the ways that those parts are combined.

Page 29: Compositionality

Functional Dependence

The meanings of complex expressions are a function of the meanings of their simple parts and the ways that those parts are combined.

Page 30: Compositionality

The Substitutability Criterion

An equivalent version of functional dependence:

“For any sentence S(E) containing some expression E as part, if E and E* have the same meaning, then S(E) and S(E*) have the same meaning.”

Page 31: Compositionality

Problems with Functional Dependence

1. Any language that contains no synonyms is automatically compositional.

2. The fact that the meaning of a complex expression is a function of the meanings of its parts & the way they’re combined does not guarantee that we can calculate the meaning of the complex expression from the meanings of its parts & the way they’re combined.

Page 32: Compositionality

Problem #3: Systematicity

• Le chien aboie. The dog barks.• Le chat aboie. The cat dances.• Le chat pue. The skunk eats.

Page 33: Compositionality

Computational Dependence

The meanings of complex expressions are a computable function of the meanings of their simple parts and the ways that those parts are combined.

Page 34: Compositionality

Solves Problem #2

Page 35: Compositionality

The Empirical Conception of Dependence

We could understand “dependence” as whatever relation obtains between the meaning of a complex expression and that expression’s syntax and the meanings of its parts that in fact explains our ability to learn and understand a language containing an infinity of expressions.

Page 36: Compositionality

The Empirical Conception of Dependence

That is, some philosophers think: we know that language is compositional, but it is an empirical question as to just what compositionality consists in. (What notion of dependence is correct.)

Page 37: Compositionality

ARGUMENTS FROM COMPOSITIONALITY

Page 38: Compositionality

What’s at Stake?

Before we consider arguments for or against compositionality, let’s look at what’s at stake. At various points, compositionality has been used to argue against all of the theories of meaning we have considered in class.

Page 39: Compositionality

Vs. the Idea Theory

According to the idea theory, the meaning of a word is an idea, where ideas are construed as something like “little colored pictures in the mind.” Let’s consider an example: what’s your idea of a pet?

Page 40: Compositionality

Idea of a Pet

Page 41: Compositionality

OK, now what’s your idea of a fish?

Page 42: Compositionality

Idea of Fish

Page 43: Compositionality

Now try to combine those ideas into the idea of “pet fish.”

Page 44: Compositionality
Page 45: Compositionality

Vs. the Idea Theory

That clearly doesn’t work. Notice that we cannot say that in the context of “____ fish” “pet” means something other than . This would make the meaning of “pet” non-local (depend on surrounding context) and that’s not allowed on any compositional theory. Conclusion: the idea theory violates the principle of compositionality.

Page 46: Compositionality

Vs. Verificationism

Let’s suppose that the meaning of a sentence is the set of experiences that it probably causes you to have.

So a cow will probably cause you to hear cow-sounds, so cow-sounds are part of the meaning of “cow.” In other words the probability of cow-sounds is increased by the presence of cows.

Page 47: Compositionality

Color Animal Threat LevelBrown Dog SafeBrown Ant SafeBrown Pig SafeBrown Goat SafeBrown Cow DANGER!

Red Cow SafeWhite Cow SafeBlack Cow Safe

Orange Cow Safe

Page 48: Compositionality

Cows are Safe

Let’s suppose that the vast majority of cows are safe.

So the meaning of “cow” does not include the experience of bodily harm, because encountering a cow lowers, rather than raises, the chances that you’ll experience bodily harm.

Page 49: Compositionality

Brown Things are Safe

Let’s also suppose that brown things are in general safe.

So again, “brown” doesn’t have the experience of bodily harm as part of its meaning either.

You’re less likely to experience this around brown things than around other-colored things.

Page 50: Compositionality

Brown Cows are Dangerous

However, suppose that the small number of dangerous cows and the small number of dangerous brown things are all brown cows. Thus the meaning of “brown cow” contains the experience of bodily harm. That experience confirms the presence of brown cows.

Page 51: Compositionality

Brown Cows are Dangerous

But how is this possible? Neither the set of experiences that is the meaning of “brown” nor the set of experiences that is the meaning of “cow” contains the experience of bodily harm.

Page 52: Compositionality

Brown Cows are Dangerous

The meaning of “brown cow” thus seems to depend on something other than the meanings of its parts, “brown” and “cow”: verificationism violates the principle of compositionality.

Page 53: Compositionality

The Causal-Historical Theory

Let’s call that baby ‘Feynman’

FeynmanFeynmanFeynmanFeynman

Page 54: Compositionality

The Causal-Historical Theory

Let’s call that baby ‘Feynman’

FeynmanFeynmanFeynmanFeynman

Historical Chain of Transmission

Page 55: Compositionality

The Causal-Historical Theory

Denotation

FeynmanFeynmanFeynmanFeynman

Page 56: Compositionality

No Connotations

The causal-historical theory, unlike the other theories we’ve considered so far, does not use a connotation (idea, experience, definition) to determine the denotation.

Denotations are determined by non-mental facts.

Page 57: Compositionality

Direct Reference Theory

The resulting view is known as direct reference theory.

This is just the claim that names and natural kind terms “directly” refer to their denotations, and that connotations aren’t involved in mediating the process.

Page 58: Compositionality

Direct Reference Theory

The meaning of a name, for example, is the person named. There is nothing more to meaning than reference/ denotation.

Page 59: Compositionality

Semantic Closure

TRUE: Lois Lane believes Superman can fly.

FALSE: Lois Lane believe Clark Kent can fly.

Page 60: Compositionality

Vs. Direct Reference

But notice that the two sentences differ only in that parts with the same meaning (reference) have been swapped: ‘Superman’ and ‘Kent.’

So it seems like if compositionality is true, then the direct reference theory is false.

Page 61: Compositionality

Vs. the Use Theory

Does knowing how word W1 is used and how W2 is used suffice for knowing how [W1 W2] is used?

This seems unlikely.

Page 62: Compositionality

Imagine teaching a Martian how the word ‘black’ is used.

We might show it color samples or something.

Page 63: Compositionality

Similarly we might teach the Martian how ‘people’ is used, by giving examples.

Page 64: Compositionality

Black Person?

Page 65: Compositionality

Fundamental Acceptance Property

Recall that for Horwich, the fundamental acceptance property underlying all uses of ‘black’ is to apply ‘black’ to surfaces that are clearly black. Suppose we taught a Martian this. And suppose we taught a Martian how to apply ‘human’ or ‘person’ (distinguishing us from other apes). Could the Martian work out how to use ‘black person’? I think not.

Page 66: Compositionality

Interests in Exaggeration

We (humans) have a vested interest in exaggerating differences in skin tone in order to effect a certain constructed social order.

Page 67: Compositionality

Interests in Exaggeration

Unless you know about this proclivity to exaggerate, (which doesn’t affect normal color ascriptions), then you can’t predict ascriptions of the form ‘COLOR + person.’

Page 68: Compositionality

Interests in Exaggeration

Using ‘black’ (or ‘red’ or ‘yellow’) for a color and using ‘person’ for a certain sort of animal doesn’t determine how to use the ‘COLOR + person’ form.

Page 69: Compositionality

Vs. The Use Theory

The point is that complex expressions can acquire uses that aren’t determined by the uses of their parts.

Consider the English insult “Mama’s boy.”

Page 70: Compositionality

Vs. The Use Theory

If you’re a child, and a male, it’s not insulting to be called a ‘boy.’ Nor is ‘Mama’ an insult. But put them together, and that’s insulting, even if you are a Mama’s boy. Just learning the use of the parts won’t tell a second-language learner of English that the whole is insulting.