Comay Hegels Last Words

20
7/25/2019 Comay Hegels Last Words http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/comay-hegels-last-words 1/20

Transcript of Comay Hegels Last Words

Page 1: Comay Hegels Last Words

7/25/2019 Comay Hegels Last Words

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/comay-hegels-last-words 1/20

Page 2: Comay Hegels Last Words

7/25/2019 Comay Hegels Last Words

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/comay-hegels-last-words 2/20

142 Rebecca Comay

42

41

40

39

38

37

36

35

34

33

32

31

30

29

28

27

26

25

24

2322

21

20

19

18

17

16

15

14

13

12

11

10

9

8

7

6

5

4

3

2

1 weight of its own accretions, until, abruptly shifting gears – and as if to mimethe synchronicity of its concluding vision (there were of course also, as always,

deadline issues) – it suddenly sprints forward to the finish line. It’s not justthe traumatic abruptness of the last dash but also a curious indeterminacyof the endpoint that intrigues me.

Chronologic

How (and when exactly) does the final leave-taking get registered? Thecontext needs recapitulation. Absolute Knowing, having “won the concept,”has just run through a breathless recapitulation of the entire sequence of itsvarious misadventures – finally vindicated as learning experiences – in theslightly esoteric shorthand that suggests at once a flashcard sequence learnedby rote and the cinematic flipbook of a deathbed vision. Having died athousand deaths on the battlefield of experience, natural consciousness hasmiraculously survived, if only to tell the tale, according to a schema ofallegorical conversion similar to that elaborated in Dante’s  Paradiso : death,narrative resurrection – the metamorphosis of the pilgrimage of experienceinto its own transcription. In a final flashback, absolute knowing suddenlyrewinds and fast forwards, Krapplike, through the highlights of its ownhistory: some 500 pages of tortuously detailed exposition are compressed intonine killingly elliptical paragraphs, which in their paratactic and arbitraryarrangement push to the limit the possibility of prose (as  prorsus or  proversus ,

i.e. linear procession). The shorthand gestures both to the work’s “verselike”reversion to its own origins (its regression to draft, notes, or outline) and toits decomposition into archival detritus: in the absolute present of philo-sophy, sketch and ruin, project and memory, future and past, converge.The repetition announcing the work’s centripetal return-to-self points to theirresistible force of fragmentation and decay. The self-abbreviation ofthe science is thus indistinguishable from its entropic disintegration intodisjoint phrases, titles, or labels, the commemorative labour from compulsivemnemotechnic efficiency – or, as Hegel ridicules it, in the Preface, not quiterealizing that it might be his own work he is describing, “a synoptic table,like a skeleton with scraps of paper stuck all over it” (Hegel 1970: §51).

Such miniaturization both describes and performatively dramatizes theretroactive “annulment” [tilgen ] of time (Ibid. §801): the overcoming of thefatal delay  that had produced consciousness’s fundamental unconsciousnessregarding the significance of its own experiences (Hegel is rigorouslyAristotelian: time is the retarding factor that prevents everything being givenall at once and in advance). The almost illegibly formulaic compression oflanguage in the concluding paragraphs of the  Phenomenology  announces thereversal of the temporal dilation blocking the transparency of self-thinkingthought. To close the book is to cancel the delay symptomatic of an unre-solved gap between knowledge and its object. To “annul” time is, for Hegel,

Swiffen Ch08.indd 142Swiffen-Ch08.indd 142 8/3/2012 9:48:50 AM8/3/2012 9:48:50 AM

Not for Distribution

Page 3: Comay Hegels Last Words

7/25/2019 Comay Hegels Last Words

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/comay-hegels-last-words 3/20

Hegel’s Last Words 143

42

41

40

39

38

37

36

35

34

33

32

31

30

29

28

27

26

25

2423

22

21

20

19

18

17

16

15

14

13

12

11

10

9

8

7

6

5

4

3

2

1 to “sublate” it,1 to release it to its higher truth, that is, to convert it from amere “container” (Hegel 1830: §258) or continuum – an alien “destiny and

necessity” (Hegel 1970: §801) – to the very substance or “filling” of Spirit’sproject.

The shift from Spirit’s provisional appearance in time to its final vindica-tion  as  time involves the recursive self-application of the concept. As the“existent concept” (Ibid.), time needs to be “seized” [erfaßte ] or conceptual-ized [begriffene ] to become adequate to itself, following an alimentary schemawhose superficial proximity to Kant’s own has been justly noted (mosttrenchantly by Werner Hamacher (1997)). Hegel hastens to point outthe differences. In his later lectures on the history of philosophy he willmock with biting sarcasm the “transcen-dental” aesthetic (Hamacher’suncharacteristically bad pun) interpretation of time and space as anoral-sadistic phantasm symptomatic of a disavowed breach between self andworld:

There are things-in-themselves out there, but lacking space and time;now consciousness comes along, which already possesses space andtime within it as the possibility of experience, just as it already possessesmouth and teeth etc as the conditions of eating. The things which areeaten possess neither mouth nor teeth, and just as consciousness imposeseating on things, so too it imposes space and time on them: just asit places things between mouth and teeth, so too it places them in space

and time. (Hegel 1894: 340f/434)

Hegel is ridiculing Kant for reducing subjectivity to the empty voracitythat failing to recognize itself in its object unfailingly reinstates the gulf itseeks to eliminate as it appropriates the object through the jaws of the formalapperceptive apparatus. Such hunger reappears in the practical sphere as the“cold duty” which, forced to make do with itself as its sole enjoyment, is leftgnawing on its own pieties – a “last, undigested lump in the stomach” – andthus displays all the conversion symptoms characteristic of the ascetic ideal:Hegel’s terms are as always prophetically Nietzschean (Ibid. p. 369/461).

Hegel does not exactly renounce this oral phantasm but in a characteristichyper-transcendental move both prolongs and overcomes the Kantian schemaby turning the critical bite back on itself so that the orifice between inner andouter, container and contents, is in turn involuted.

To overcome its “subjective” character as empty intuition, whether as themathematical continuum of linear succession or as its historicist variations,time must turn its own bite back on itself. It must consume itself in the actof consumption; it must submit to its own destructive logic.2 As the “abstrac-tion of consuming,” time not only destroys the independence of its objectsbut must overcome its own formal or external character as “container,”

Swiffen Ch08.indd 143Swiffen-Ch08.indd 143 8/3/2012 9:48:50 AM8/3/2012 9:48:50 AM

Not for Distribution

Page 4: Comay Hegels Last Words

7/25/2019 Comay Hegels Last Words

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/comay-hegels-last-words 4/20

144 Rebecca Comay

45

44

43

42

41

40

39

38

37

36

35

34

33

32

31

30

29

28

27

26

2524

23

22

21

20

19

18

17

16

15

14

13

12

11

10

9

8

7

6

5

4

3

2

1 “stream,” or “river.” It must absorb the seriality that it inflicts – the “not yet”symptomatic of an unresolved breach between knowledge and object – in the

final synthesis that Hegel calls begriffene Geschichte  (Hegel 1970: §808). Inswallowing itself swallowing, time therefore marks itself as not only objectivebut absolute – a “conceptualized and conceptualizing intuiting” rather thana “merely intuited Concept” (Ibid. §801) – a self-seizure in which time “fills”and “fulfils” itself, but also renders itself impotent in its own engorgement:it checks its own violence.3 Time withdraws itself as it draws itself inwards(to evoke a Heideggerean register), a whirlpool arresting the stream ofbecoming (to recall Benjamin’s formulation (1977: 44), an “abstraction”[ abstrahieren ] which in drawing back from the self-presentation of spiritmarks at once the latter’s apogee and its blindspot.4 

Self-consciousness in this way “enriches itself until … it has sucked intoitself the entire structure of what is essential to it” (Hegel 1970) – a digestion(verdauen ) (Ibid. §808) whereby what is absorbed is already determined asSpirit’s own essence, and thus every bite effectively a self-bite – an involutionof and on the inside. But since such suction has effaced the very oppositionbetween inside and outside, what appears from one angle as ingestion orcontraction must be viewed with equal cogency as an excretion or expansionwhereby spirit “releases” itself towards a zone of untrammelled sensuousimmediacy – time and space as “free contingent happening” – which it positsas a determinate negativity to be recuperated as its own other (Ibid. §807).5 The “continuing existence” of the outside thus reinstates the subject in its

heroic sublimity – a self-possession forged in the act of self-dispossession(Ibid.).Thus the circle closes just where it breaks open: absolute knowing asserts

its “supreme freedom and assurance” (Ibid. §806) in its controlled regressionto a natural prehistory which it embraces in a kind of docta ignorantia  orfeigned amnesia regulated by the analogical, Kantian-style, subjunctive ofthe “as if.” “Spirit has to start afresh as if  for it all that preceded were lost andas if it had learned nothing” from past experience (Ibid. §808). The passagecontinues: “But recollection, the Er-innerung of that experience, has preservedit and is the inner being and in fact the higher form of the substance. …” Thetruth of absolute knowing as recollection is thus the fiction of an absolute

forgetting.Let’s set aside the well-trodden objections, from Nietzsche through

Bataille, which discern in the “supreme assurance” of the philosopher thebogus renunciations and fetishistic disavowals of the loser wins. (“Spirit hasto start afresh as if  all … were lost. … But  memory …”). Let’s also set asidethe interesting paradox lurking in this gesture of willed renunciation – atension amplified in the  Logic  ’s closing reference to the “drive” or “resolve”of the logical Idea to “let itself go” (Hegel 1969: 573/843) – with itsSchellingian residues and its more contemporary resonances, for example, inHeidegger’s notion of Gelassenheit  , in the Proustian “search” for contingency,or indeed in the active forgetfulness of which Nietzsche writes. It’s the

Swiffen Ch08.indd 144Swiffen-Ch08.indd 144 8/3/2012 9:48:50 AM8/3/2012 9:48:50 AM

Not for Distribution

Page 5: Comay Hegels Last Words

7/25/2019 Comay Hegels Last Words

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/comay-hegels-last-words 5/20

Hegel’s Last Words 145

43

42

41

40

39

38

37

36

35

34

33

32

31

30

29

28

27

26

2524

23

22

21

20

19

18

17

16

15

14

13

12

11

10

9

8

7

6

5

4

3

2

1 Saturnine aspect of the operation that fascinates me. Sluggish, torpid, “sunkinto the night of its own self-consciousness,” Absolute Knowing digests what

it encounters and secretes what it has assimilated as its own excrescence(Hegel 1970: §808). The subject simultaneously reaps and lays waste to theharvest of its history in a kind of philosophical potlatch or Saturnalia – amoment of kenotic expenditure in which the speculative reversal from loss togain is in turn reversed. “To know one’s limit is to know how to sacrificeoneself” (Ibid. §807).

What is at stake in Hegel’s decision to end the tale under the sign ofSaturn? The ambivalence of the figure is immediately apparent. A figureof simultaneous prodigality and privation, at once infinite abundance andinsatiable destruction, the “inscrutable Kronos” stands, in Hegel, for thepower of unchecked natural consumption. Having castrated his fatherOuranos, Kronos proceeds to devour his own progeny – monstrous violencecurbed only by a feminine cunning that will parallel that of Reason itself.Tricked by Rhea into vomiting up his own children, the Titan is banished todeepest Tartarus – “at the edges of the world, beyond the limits of self-consciousness” (Hegel 1988: 334n) – a primal repression of nature which forHegel marks the violent inauguration of human history proper. Kronos willresurface as the Roman harvest god Saturn, figure of the golden age of abun-dance and unfettered freedom, whose rituals will involve the utopian rolereversals whereby masters wait on slaves at the beggar’s banquet. Plutarch isthe first to make the phonetic link between Kronos and Chronos – cannibal

father with “sharp-toothed time” – and the Titan’s scythe will henceforthoscillate between castrating knife and agricultural implement, with imagesproliferating of a senile Father Time rapaciously gorging on his own offspring(think, for example, of Goya’s famous painting of Saturn decapitating achild). Oscillating between morose melancholia and obscene enjoyment,between traumatic loss and libidinal excess, such a figure anticipates theperverse father (Lacan’s père-vers ) who makes his cameo appearance in Freud’sTotem and Taboo . Slow, ponderous, weighed down by a gravitas which bythe Renaissance enables the ascendancy of philosophical genius – at once thestony blockage of thought and its essential condition – Saturn will acquireduring the Baroque period the trapping of voracious bibliomaniac learning.

Astrological tradition adds a treacherous quality of indecisiveness, theologi-cally glossed as the hesitancy born of  acedia , the deadly sin of indolence, asportrayed in the icy fifth circle of Dante’s hell. Could such an undecidablefigure – the very figure of indecision – make its comeback as the final figureof the dialectic? Walter Benjamin famously thought so.

Swallowing Schiller

What is at stake in Hegel’s decision to sign off with a quotation fromSchiller? Why is it that at the climax of its peroration Spirit suddenlybites its tongue and interrupts itself mid-sentence? Is philosophy unable to

Swiffen Ch08.indd 145Swiffen-Ch08.indd 145 8/3/2012 9:48:50 AM8/3/2012 9:48:50 AM

Not for Distribution

Page 6: Comay Hegels Last Words

7/25/2019 Comay Hegels Last Words

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/comay-hegels-last-words 6/20

146 Rebecca Comay

44

43

42

41

40

39

38

37

36

35

34

33

32

31

30

29

28

27

26

2524

23

22

21

20

19

18

17

16

15

14

13

12

11

10

9

8

7

6

5

4

3

2

1 complete its own thought, forced to raid the grave and abandon itself tostupid, mechanical citation? Or is there heroism in this self-mortification?

Hegel’s cannibalism of Schiller can be read in opposed ways – either thedereliction of philosophy or its supreme vindication: the fate of speculativereason hangs in the balance.

Every epigram has a fatal ambiguity. A foreign body lodged at the marginsof the text, it simultaneously confirms and undermines the integrity of thework it demarcates; it marks the book’s involution towards an outside whichboth is and is not its own to appropriate, and stages the essential aporia ofall narrative termination. The epigram thus functions as a kind of doubletombstone: it provides an epitaph both for the body of the text whose end itcountersigns and for the corpus of borrowed speech it mangles. What doesit mean to ghost-write one’s own ending so as to survive through one’sown ancestor: who is burying whom? The mortuary logic of this transactionneeds inspection.

According to Hegel’s elliptical account of the transition to AbsoluteKnowing, Spirit is to arise phoenix-like from the ashes of figurative thoughtand language: the final achievement of rationality is to pronounce thefuneral oration for religious and poetic Vorstellung  . This is Hegel’s version ofChristian sacramental theology: Spirit performs the last rites over the corpseof poetry by translating finite body – language in its most recalcitrant, carnalparticularity – into infinite spirit: the worldly object is relinquished by beingintrojected, abbreviated, “digested.” Psychoanalytically, we can regard this as

a work of mourning. This contrasts with the melancholic approach to loss: inthis case, the living corpse would be cannibalistically taken up within thefractured vault of the self, where it forms an indigestible pocket of internalextimacy and imposes a limit to symbolization (Freud 1960).6  In refusingthe substitutive work of language, the melancholic not only maintains thelost object in hallucinatory persistence but congeals language itself into acorpselike thing: words and even the diacritical absence punctuating thesebecome magical fetish objects, stripped of symbolic efficacy – no longersubstitutes for the thing but perversely identified with it – which hover inthe mouth as frozen, inassimilable remainders.

Is Hegel a mourner or a melancholic? In signing off with this scrap of

Schiller, does he contradict or confirm his own infamous pronouncement ofthe supersession of the “poetry of Vorstellung  ” by the “prose of  Denken ” (Hegel1975: 123)? Is this the triumphant absorption of the aesthetic or a testimonyto its inassimilable persistence: display of a trophy or confession of defeat?These questions are not intended to revive the weary quarrel between philos-ophy and poetry, but to explore what might still be at stake in it. If Hegel’schannelling of Schiller invites two incompatible explanations – it could pointeither to the transparent potency of thought or to a surd of irreducibleopacity – this uncertainty has implications not only for the fate of languagein the narrow sense, but for everything tied up with this: history, religion,

Swiffen Ch08.indd 146Swiffen-Ch08.indd 146 8/3/2012 9:48:50 AM8/3/2012 9:48:50 AM

Not for Distribution

Page 7: Comay Hegels Last Words

7/25/2019 Comay Hegels Last Words

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/comay-hegels-last-words 7/20

Hegel’s Last Words 147

44

43

42

41

40

39

38

37

36

35

34

33

32

31

30

29

28

27

26

2524

23

22

21

20

19

18

17

16

15

14

13

12

11

10

9

8

7

6

5

4

3

2

1 politics, the whole theatre of the body and its pleasures (and of course itshungers).

Why quotation, why poetry, why Schiller, why this poem, why these lines,and why this peculiar rendition? These questions have a cumulative force.Why, at the pinnacle of the subject’s self-affirmation, does it suddenly resortto the stammering of the mechanical memory? (Hegel 1971a: §§ 461–4) Andwhy is it poetry it chooses to recite? The Encyclopaedia will also end witha quotation, but to a very different effect: in this later work it will be aphilosopher, Aristotle, who is recruited, under his own name, writingin Greek and of a God whose vigilant self-sufficiency and uninterruptedproductivity will collect and redeem the scattered moments of our owndiscontinuous existence as surely as day follows night. Not even the intrusionof a dead language and a foreign script can cloud the transparency ofself-thinking thought (Ibid. §577).

Why this poet? A self-described “hermaphrodite”7  – half-poet, half-philosopher – Schiller will be sliced up and repeatedly cannibalized byHegel to the very end of his life. Snippets of his verse keep resurfacing,usually unattributed, throughout Hegel’s work: Hegel will quote him repeat-edly – in the later lectures on religion, in the History of Philosophy , and in amuch reviled passage in the Philosophy of Right  , to which I’ll return. He willcontinue to quote him despite or because of his own deepest misgivings aboutSchiller’s project. Despite the poet’s failure to “break through the Kantianbarrier,” to bridge the abyss between noumenal freedom and corporeal

enjoyment8

 – in short, his failure to be the thinker of fulfilled modernity –Hegel will not stop serving up the poet’s membra disjecta, mangled butrecognizable, like half-chewed morsels. The stakes are sharply political: it is1806, Napoleon is at the door, the Revolution, or at least its carcass, is beingshipped over to Germany – that “unreal land” where, it was once thought,the tempest of French revolutionary freedom could be parried by the forces ofspiritual advance (Hegel 1970: §595). Having already undergone its ownreligious  revolution by way of the Protestant Reformation, Germany wouldhave been immunized against the fever of  political   revolution, leaving itfree to seek out its most important battles in the cultural arena. Schillerexpresses the wager of an entire generation: we don’t need that   kind of

revolution. Only through aesthetic  revolution can we forestall the short-circuitof politics into terror. Only through beauty do we inch our way towardsfreedom. When Schiller dies in 1805, just one year before the completionof the Phenomenology , he takes to the grave the promise of unrealized revolu-tionary possibility.9 

Why this particular poem? Hegel is not the first to get his hands on it.First published in 1782, “Die Freundschaft” has already been pulverized,recycled, and parodically reinvested, by none other than Schiller himself, whostarted to filch from it almost immediately upon publication. In a patchworkprose work of 1786, the  Philosophische Briefe , a disenchanted protagonist,

Swiffen Ch08.indd 147Swiffen-Ch08.indd 147 8/3/2012 9:48:50 AM8/3/2012 9:48:50 AM

Not for Distribution

Page 8: Comay Hegels Last Words

7/25/2019 Comay Hegels Last Words

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/comay-hegels-last-words 8/20

148 Rebecca Comay

44

43

42

41

40

39

38

37

36

35

34

33

32

31

30

29

28

27

26

2524

23

22

21

20

19

18

17

16

15

14

13

12

11

10

9

8

7

6

5

4

3

2

1  Julius –Schiller’s thinly disguised alter-ego – regurgitates scattered linesof the earlier poem as an embarrassing specimen of his own irretrievable

youthful enthusiasm. “Die Freundschaft” was from the outset condemned toruinous citationality.10 

Why these lines, with their lightly veiled Eucharistic content and hints ofSaturnalian enjoyment? As the scene of creation coalesces with the scene ofresurrection, the book loops back to its own beginnings: absolute knowingrevisits sense-certainty’s initiation into the “Eleusinian mysteries of consump-tion” just as it recalls the Bacchanalian revel of natural experience from thesober perspective of the last judgement. In the twilight of recollection,the fever of pre-philosophical experience is retrieved as “transparent andsimple repose” (Hegel 1970: §27).

And why, finally, this particular rendition? Hegel’s version effaces the deepambiguity pervading Schiller’s own lines. In cutting off the final couplet fromthe immediately preceding verses, Hegel exactly reverses the force of Schiller’sverse. The final stanza describes an isolated Creator – a “friendless world-master” – forced to seek company in his own mirror image. When the poemwas first published, in 1782, Schiller had appeared to celebrate this fusionalmodel of reconciliation, but there is no question that by the mid-1780s,when he starts recycling his own verses, he has begun to suspect the narcis-sism of the scenario.11  “Die Götter Griechenlands” – whose three versionswould have been well-known to Hegel (he dwells on it obsessively in the Aesthetics ) – uses identical imagery to describe the unbearable alienation of the

modern Christian world: a friendless God rules in splendid isolation onSaturn’s toppled throne, encountering only his own image which he hasprojected into the void.

Why close off the story of Spirit’s self-fashioning with this image offormless excess and evanescence – foam overflowing its own container and asephemeral as the froth of the sea? Does Schiller’s distich overflow the marginsof Hegel’s book as a kind of hallucinatory reminder of what has been fore-closed in the drive to symbolic reparation? Or is the chalice a kind of HolyGrail – a promise of succour both to the wounded subject, pilloried on thepathway of despair, and to the wounded text, fractured on the crux of its ownillegibility? Or (these options are not mutually exclusive) perhaps the foam

recalls the  aphros  – the semen dripping from the dismembered phallus ofOuranos, first victim of Kronos’ violence – sea-foam from which pleasure-giving Aphrodite is born; this precious substance was once thought toprovide euphoric counterweight to the melancholia afflicting dry, coldsouls.12 

On every point one could amass competing arguments to produce thedouble column of responses that captures the range of contemporaryreactions to Hegel. As a renunciation of authorial sovereignty, the recourse toquotation could spell either the subject’s regression to the stammering of theunhappy consciousness or its accession to the universal spiritual community.

Swiffen Ch08.indd 148Swiffen-Ch08.indd 148 8/3/2012 9:48:50 AM8/3/2012 9:48:50 AM

Not for Distribution

Page 9: Comay Hegels Last Words

7/25/2019 Comay Hegels Last Words

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/comay-hegels-last-words 9/20

Hegel’s Last Words 149

40

39

38

37

36

35

34

33

32

31

30

29

28

27

26

25

2423

22

21

20

19

18

17

16

15

14

13

12

11

10

9

8

7

6

5

4

3

2

1 The appearance of poetry could indicate either a regression to the vagaries ofVorstellung   or a sign of philosophy’s most prodigious powers of absorption.

The tribute to Schiller could indicate either a residue of unresolvedKantianism or the tombstone to a safely buried past. The invocationof friendship could testify either to the lure of narcissism or to the inextin-guishable pungency of the revolutionary fraternal ideal. And the dollopof foam? This could mark either the self-putrescence of the system or thevestige of nature – nothing so monumental as even a remnant or residue,but a last fleeting apparition of meaningless contingency as it fizzles intooblivion.

To be sure, Hegel almost imperceptibly tips the balance by subtlyrewriting Schiller’s words. Torn out of context and from a less than perfectmemory – neither strict citation nor free paraphrase, neither perfectlyembalmed nor fully metabolized – the verse hovers in the limbo betweenreceptivity and spontaneity, between repetition and interpretation. Howexactly does Hegel remember Schiller at this junction? Here is the Schillercouplet, in context, as it concludes the final stanza from “Die Freundschaft”in the original version of 1782. Every word, every mark on the page, shouldbe strictly noted.

Freundlos war der grose WeltenmeisterFühlte Mangel  – darum schuf er Geister,Sel’ge Spiegel seiner  Seligkeit! –

Fand das höchste Wesen schon kein gleiches,Aus dem Kelch des ganzen SeelenreichesSchäumt ihm – die Unendlichkeit.

[Friendless was the great world-masterFelt a lack – and so created spirits,Blessed mirrors of his own blessednessBut the highest being still could find no equal.From the chalice of the whole realm of souls

Foams up to him – infinitude.]

Here is Hegel’s revision, also in context, as the interminable final sentenceof the Phenomenology suddenly lurches to a halt:

The goal, absolute knowing, or Spirit that knows itself as Spirit, has forits path the recollection of the Spirits as they are in themselves and as theyaccomplish the organization of their realm. Their preservation, seen fromthe side of their free existence appearing in the form of contingency, ishistory; but regarded from the side of their comprehended organization,it is the science of knowing in the sphere of appearance: the two together,comprehended history [begriffene Geschichte ], form alike the inwardizing

Swiffen Ch08.indd 149Swiffen-Ch08.indd 149 8/3/2012 9:48:50 AM8/3/2012 9:48:50 AM

Not for Distribution

Page 10: Comay Hegels Last Words

7/25/2019 Comay Hegels Last Words

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/comay-hegels-last-words 10/20

150 Rebecca Comay

42

41

40

39

38

37

36

35

34

33

32

31

30

29

28

27

26

25

24

2322

21

20

19

18

17

16

15

14

13

12

11

10

9

8

7

6

5

4

3

2

1 [Erinnerung  ] and the Calvary of absolute Spirit, the actuality, truth, andcertainty of its throne, without which it would be lifeless and alone;

only –

from the chalice of this realm of spiritsfoams forth for Him his own infinitude.[aus dem Kelche dieses Geisterreichesschäumt ihm seine Unendlichkeit.]

(Hegel 1970: §808)

A series of elisions manages to neutralize what in Schiller’s original pointsto a surd of inassimilable alterity. The rephrasing of Spirit’s isolation – therewriting of indicative description (Schiller: “friendless was the great world-master”) as counterfactual subjunctive (Hegel: “without which it would belifeless and alone”) – siphons away from the verse the painful reference todivine lack, which is absorbed within the block of philosophical prosesurrounding the poem, where “actuality, truth and certainty” serenelycontinue to assert their power. In the penultimate line, Hegel’s substitutionof “dieses Geisterreiches” for “des ganzen Seelenreiches” not only convertspassive soul (the sleep of reason, anthropological immediacy) into the infiniterelation of finite and infinite Spirit.13 By rewriting Schiller’s definite articleas a demonstrative Hegel manages to recast the whole scene as a sacramentalperformative: “this” is tethered to the universality of the concept and assumes

the redemptive potency of the Eucharistic hoc est. Hegel’s substitution of a possessive pronoun for Schiller’s definite article,in the last line, grammatically binds infinity with its maker – an effectreinforced by the erasure of both the poet’s italics (visually highlightingGod’s isolated particularity) and his dash (graphically separating creaturefrom creator): Hegel provides a typographical suture of the ontologicalfissure separating God from world. In Schiller the transition from lack tosatisfaction, from loneliness to friendship, is as precipitous as the dashthat announces it. Hegel smoothes over this transition. Both traumatic lackand its correlative on the battlefield of enjoyment – friendlessness, on theone hand, the foaming surplus of jouissance, on the other – are absorbed

in the philosophical rewriting that erases context, grammar, and punctuation.Between Schiller’s last word and Hegel’s lies the almost imperceptible differ-ence between the bad infinite of lack, finitude, or indeterminacy and itsphilosophical homonym. A gesture of erasure marks without ever quiteremarking on this difference.

Has Hegel here bitten off more than he can chew? Might it be that the costof swallowing poetry, of remembering Schiller’s words speculatively, without“accent” or punctuation, is the reduction of language itself to an indigestibleremainder? In his mature philosophy of language, Hegel will argue that thespeculative purification of language requires a mortifying passage through

Swiffen Ch08.indd 150Swiffen-Ch08.indd 150 8/3/2012 9:48:50 AM8/3/2012 9:48:50 AM

Not for Distribution

Page 11: Comay Hegels Last Words

7/25/2019 Comay Hegels Last Words

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/comay-hegels-last-words 11/20

Hegel’s Last Words 151

42

41

40

39

38

37

36

35

34

33

32

31

30

29

28

27

26

25

24

2322

21

20

19

18

17

16

15

14

13

12

11

10

9

8

7

6

5

4

3

2

1 the mechanical memory: language must disintegrate into a succession ofmeaningless signifiers in order to be semantically reinvested as the medium

of  Denken  (Hegel 1971a: §§461–4).14  Rote memorization – habit-inducedidiocy – permits the cathartic forgetfulness that marks the birth of thought.In order to use language philosophically we must empty it of all previousassociations: Evacuated of meaningful content, the mind becomes a tabularasa for self-thinking thought. And yet vacuums can also fill, and mechanismparalyse. Hegel elsewhere compares a hypertrophic automatism to thedyspepsia of an organism unable to assimilate what it ingests. His examplesare conventional but revealing: excessive reading, writing, the numbingrituals of organized religion (Hegel 1991: §195).15 

Eating, ReadingHegel’s readers, from Schelling through Deleuze, have never stopped seizingon the rapaciousness of a thought which by finding sustenance in itsown antithesis has come to epitomize the imperialism of a system whichmanages to assimilate even its own excrement as food for thought. (Suchself-consumption corresponds precisely to Nietzsche’s definition ofnihilism.16 ) “The Spirit is the belly turned mind and rage is the mark of everyidealism …” (Adorno 1973: 23). While the visceral energy of the attacksmight suggest an addictive fascination (why this obsession with Hegel’sdiet? why keep snapping at this stale bait?), the polemics often overlook

just how peculiarly the alimentary metaphor actually functions. If frombeginning to end – from Bacchanalian tumult to foaming chalice, from theEleusinian mysteries to the cabbage heads on the scaffold – if Hegel neverstops ruminating on the figure of digestion, if he voraciously seizes on theimage, obsessively keeps reworking it, it is as if to digest, soften, assimilateprecisely what in the image resists metabolization.

The spirit and the letter are at odds. The tension between the figurativeand the literal senses of consumption, between spiritual absorption andcorporeal ingestion, highlights an essential ambiguity lurking in thevery concept (of course a metaphor) of Er-innerung. The literal truth of“innering” turns out to be anything but what it figuratively posits – an

ambivalence that also introduces a crucial dissonance between Hegel’s ownfigural practice and the metafigural theory which would contain it.

On the one hand: the metaphor of eating presents a model of interiorizationunderwritten by the hermeneutic fantasy of the liquifaction of the materialsign – the “convivial communication” (Schlegel, quoted in Kittler 1990: 70)uniting a community of readers nourished by the unimpeded flow of thought.Friedrich Kittler has argued that such an oral fantasy defines the “discoursenetwork around 1800” – a fantasy connected to the pedagogical practices ofthe epoch, and culminating in Goethe’s maternal phantasmagoria of readingas a sucking at the “breasts” or “wells of life” (Goethe 1984: 22). The fantasy

Swiffen Ch08.indd 151Swiffen-Ch08.indd 151 8/3/2012 9:48:50 AM8/3/2012 9:48:50 AM

Not for Distribution

Page 12: Comay Hegels Last Words

7/25/2019 Comay Hegels Last Words

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/comay-hegels-last-words 12/20

152 Rebecca Comay

45

44

43

42

41

40

39

38

37

36

35

34

33

32

31

30

29

28

27

26

2524

23

22

21

20

19

18

17

16

15

14

13

12

11

10

9

8

7

6

5

4

3

2

1 assumes the priority of the signified as the guarantor of translatability:Goethe’s “pure perfect substance” which survives the translation of poetry

into prose. For Hegel this is expressed as the ultimate interconvertibility ofthe arts: in the  Aesthetics, poetry notoriously enters as the “total art” whichmetabolizes all the other arts into its own medium while submitting to itsown paraphrase into conceptual language. Reduced to a sonorous membrane,entirely saturated with spiritual content, the poetic medium deflates into a“mere external designation” which dissolves without residue into thought(Hegel 1975: 262, 627, 228, 964, 234, 968).

On the other hand: if the metaphor speaks of translation, the literal invoca-tion of the drives points to a somatic residue that threatens to impede thepassage to the ideal. This is spelled out in Hegel’s analysis of desire (Begierde). Failing to elaborate the object, the voracious subject keeps on demolishing it,only to relapse into the repetitive circle of mere life. Every act of assimilationthus exacerbates the exteriority it wants to cancel: it generates a mere “feel-ing” of unity (Hegel 1970: §171) that reinforces the melancholic vacancy atits core. Since such a blockage defines every act of digestion, it is curious toencounter this as the figure for absolute knowing and its hermeneutic.Analysing the Eucharist, in the  Spirit of Christianity  (1798–1800), Hegelexplores an analogy between the trope of consumption and the trope of read-ing.17 The interpretation of the written word, like the swallowing of the wineand bread, would seem at first glance to dissolve the mortified objectivity ofthe thing, performing the negation of the negation – the “destruction of the

soulless” – that presages the event of resurrection. If the analogy breaksdown as soon as it is introduced (Hegel emphasizes that, unlike the host, thetext resists metabolization, it fails to vanish as a thing), it is immediatelyreinstated, in that the permanence of script and the evanescence of foodprove to be symmetrical manifestations of the same failure to mediate. Bothtestify to an intransigent non-identity. The disappearance of the host signalsthe irremediable split between faith and sensation – between “living forcesand the corpse” (Hegel 1971b: 368/252) – while in its stony persistence thetext presents a surd of unsurpassable materiality.

Eating and reading therefore culminate in their absolute antitheses:the empty mouth, the fractured text – unnourishing, illegible alterity.

Eating concludes in a moment of radical inedibility – “something divine waspromised and it melted away in the mouth” (Ibid. p. 369/253) – just asreading confronts the stony opacity of the written text. The destructiveenjoyment of the thing betrays a profound failure to mediate the materialworld, which returns in the form of obscene, death-bearing, infectious matter.Hegel alludes to the churchgoer’s obsessional fantasies of contamination.“Many a man is afraid he will catch from the common chalice the venerealinfection of the one who drank before him” – a fear dramatized by thefunereal clothing which stages the sacramental ritual as a rite of death;community is reduced to the contagious promiscuity and hypochondriacalsuspicion which spell the disintegration of every social bond. Communion is

Swiffen Ch08.indd 152Swiffen-Ch08.indd 152 8/3/2012 9:48:50 AM8/3/2012 9:48:50 AM

Not for Distribution

Page 13: Comay Hegels Last Words

7/25/2019 Comay Hegels Last Words

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/comay-hegels-last-words 13/20

Hegel’s Last Words 153

42

41

40

39

38

37

36

35

34

33

32

31

30

29

28

27

26

2524

23

22

21

20

19

18

17

16

15

14

13

12

11

10

9

8

7

6

5

4

3

2

1 revealed as an event of absolute expenditure, “purposeless destruction for thesake of destruction”18 (Hegel 1971b: 316) – a negativity that points both to

the “infinite pain” of Christianity (Hegel 1986: 563) its “mournful hungerfor the actual,” but also to a kernel of obscene enjoyment.

These two aspects are intimately connected in the young Hegel’s analysisof Christianity. Christianity’s failure to mediate its antitheses condemns thebeliever to an “endless, unquenchable, unappeased craving” (Hegel 1971b:417/300) where the positivity of the object continues to affront the subject asthe “stain” of contingent, unworked matter (Ibid. p. 409/292).19 Such a stainappears in the rotting body of Christ – the “real human form” that accompa-nies the risen saviour as an extraneous appendage weighing him down withthe gravitational tug of all fleshly matter (Hegel 1971b: 409/293).20  Anunbridgeable schism thus arises between an otherworldly God and the “ruinsof this body” (Ibid. p. 426/318). In producing only a “monstrous combina-tion” rather than an “actual unification” (Ibid. p. 410; 412/293; 296) of itsantitheses, religion condemns humanity to “the truth and harshness of [its]Godlessness” (Hegel 1802/1977: 432/191). In the sacramental meal “enjoy-ment is overleaped” (Hegel 1986: 563). It fails precisely to the extent that itsucceeds all too well: jouissance is missed precisely in that it comes alwaysalready too soon. Thus the ultimate degradation of the host to excrement: toworship the holy wafer is, according to Hegel’s gleeful reductio , alreadyto worship the mouse shit to which this may be contingently reduced,etc (Hegel 1894: 538; 1995: 55) (the Catholic Church lodged a complaint

about this),21

  and announces the perversion of Christianity itself into “themost disgusting and revolting spectacle that was ever witnessed” (Hegel1894: 460, 1995: 382).

Blanking Out

In the Philosophy of Nature , Hegel dwells on the human mouth as the physi-ognomic signpost of speculative union of contraries: as the switching stationof ingestion and expression it not only stages an essential reciprocity betweeninside and outside22 but provides a “concrete center” in which the “highest”and “lowest” functions of humanity, speaking and eating, find common

abode.23 The mouth is one of those “knots” – a “point of unity” that by link-ing heterogeneous somatic functions allows the organism to transcend theentropic chaos of mere life. As Hegel’s description proceeds the adverbialconnectives pile on with increasingly anxious insistence.

Thus the mouth, for example, belongs to the particular system of sensi-bility for example, insofar  [insofern ] as it contains the tongue, which is theorgan of taste, as a moment of the theoretical process. The mouth further-more  [ ferner  ] has teeth, which are its extremities, their function beingto seize upon what is outside, and to grind it. The mouth is besides [ außerdem ] the organ of the voice and speech; other related sensations 

Swiffen Ch08.indd 153Swiffen-Ch08.indd 153 8/3/2012 9:48:50 AM8/3/2012 9:48:50 AM

Not for Distribution

Page 14: Comay Hegels Last Words

7/25/2019 Comay Hegels Last Words

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/comay-hegels-last-words 14/20

154 Rebecca Comay

42

41

40

39

38

37

36

35

34

33

32

31

30

29

28

27

26

25

2423

22

21

20

19

18

17

16

15

14

13

12

11

10

9

8

7

6

5

4

3

2

1 [ andere verwandte Empfingungen ] such as thirst are  also  [ auch ] locatedthere; laughing, and  also  [ auch ] kissing are matters for the mouth  as

well   [ gleichfalls ]. The mouth therefore  unifies the expressions of manysensations.

(Hegel 1830: §355, slightly modified)

The syntax of this astonishing passage should be noted: Hegel moves fromconjunction to adjunction to near asyndeton as he continues to heap upincreasingly vacuous connectives, right up to the dazzling non-sequiturwhich concludes the series. Even as Hegel claims to be inferring spiritualunity from the scattered oral functions of the organism, the splintered gram-mar of his language undoes the integrity it is deductively asserting. Lest youthink I’m being whimsical, just recall that it is Hegel himself who teaches usto notice such details and to appreciate the significance of this kind of fissurebetween rhetoric and logic. The second chapter of the Phenomenology describesthe dissociative stammer of consciousness in the throes of self-annihilation.Marooned on its own contradictions, the subject spits out its conjunctions(the salt is white and it is  also  cubical and it is  also  salty; I see, and I  also hear and I  also  smell…) like magical talismans designed to ward off thefragmentation at its core.

This anxiety also hovers in the Aesthetics , where Hegel dwells on the artisticchallenge of representing a body part that hovers between bestial andspiritual attachment and thus demands the most rigorous measures of

containment. After identifying the face as the spiritual focus of the body,Hegel emphasizes the need to contain the visual disruption threatened by themouth: not only is it a snout-like reminder of animal hunger but tends togenerate an inexhaustible repertoire of disconnected emotional display.24 Hegel describes the sculptural methods available for converting a devouringmouth into a speaking mouth: the accentuation of the “Greek profile” (thespiritual alignment of nose with forehead which diminishes the visual impactof the hungry orifice) (Hegel 1975: 385f/729f); the construction of the“Greek chin” (the rounded evocation of satiety which announces freedomfrom material want) (Ibid. 394/736); and the various ways of hiding the teethand expunging from the lips all traces of animal desire. In the middle of this

catalogue of Hellenic perfection, Hegel suddenly thinks of Schiller’s mouth.Neither too thin nor too full, the poet’s lips demonstrate an exquisite freedomfrom appetite and a perfect exemplification of aesthetic Bildung  .

[Sculpture] has to remove from the shape and the cut of the lips whatis purely sensuous and indicative of natural needs. Therefore it soforms the mouth as to make it, in general, neither over-full nor tight …sculpture makes the lower lip fuller than the upper one, as was the casewith Schiller; in the formation of his mouth it was possible to read thesignificance and richness of his mind and heart. This more ideal form of

Swiffen Ch08.indd 154Swiffen-Ch08.indd 154 8/3/2012 9:48:51 AM8/3/2012 9:48:51 AM

Not for Distribution

Page 15: Comay Hegels Last Words

7/25/2019 Comay Hegels Last Words

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/comay-hegels-last-words 15/20

Hegel’s Last Words 155

41

40

39

38

37

36

35

34

33

32

31

30

29

28

27

26

25

24

2322

21

20

19

18

17

16

15

14

13

12

11

10

9

8

7

6

5

4

3

2

1 the lips, in contrast to the animal’s snout, gives the impression of a certainabsence of desire, whereas when the upper lip protrudes in an animal we

are reminded at once of dashing for food and seizing on it …(Ibid.)

One could choke on such language, and perhaps Hegel did. An eyewitnessaccount of Hegel’s lecturing style at Berlin describes his strange way ofspeaking and the peculiar strangulated quality of his voice. The passage needsto be read at length:

I shall never forget the first impression of his face. Livid and loose, allfeatures drooped as if dead … When I saw him … lecturing, I was unableat first to find my way into … the train of his thought. Exhausted, morose,he sat there as if collapsed into himself, his head bent down, and whilespeaking kept turning pages and searching in his long folio notebooks,forward and backward, high and low. His constant clearing of his throatand coughing interrupted any flow of speech. Every sentence stood aloneand came out with effort, cut in pieces and jumbled. Every word, everysyllable detached itself only reluctantly to receive a strangely thoroughemphasis from the metallic-empty voice with its strange Swabian accent,as if each were the most important. Nevertheless, his whole appearancecompelled such a profound respect, such a sense of worthiness, and was soattractive through the naiveté of the most overwhelming seriousness that,

in spite of all my discomfort, and though I probably understood little ofwhat was said, I found myself captivated forever … He faltered even inthe beginning, tried to go on, started once more, stopped again, spokeand pondered; the right word seemed to be missing forever, but then itscored most surely; it seemed common and yet inimitably fitting, unusualand yet the only one that was right … Now one had grasped the clearmeaning of a sentence and hoped most ardently to progress. In vain.Instead of moving forward, the thought kept revolving around the samepoint with similar points. But if one’s wearied attention wandered andstrayed a few minutes before it suddenly returned with a start to the lec-ture, it found itself punished by having been torn entirely out of the

context. … [T]he most wonderful stream of thought twisted and pressedand struggled, now isolating something, now very comprehensively;occasionally hesitant, then by jerks sweeping along, it flowed forwardirresistibly. But even those who could follow with their entire mind andunderstanding, without looking right or left, felt the strangest strain andanxiety. …

(Hotho (1835) cited in Kaufmann 1966)

Despite the auditor’s efforts to reign in the anxieties provoked by Hegel’sbody language and by the bodily pressure of his language – the speaker’s

Swiffen Ch08.indd 155Swiffen-Ch08.indd 155 8/3/2012 9:48:51 AM8/3/2012 9:48:51 AM

Not for Distribution

Page 16: Comay Hegels Last Words

7/25/2019 Comay Hegels Last Words

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/comay-hegels-last-words 16/20

156 Rebecca Comay

44

43

42

41

40

39

38

37

36

35

34

33

32

31

30

29

28

27

26

2524

23

22

21

20

19

18

17

16

15

14

13

12

11

10

9

8

7

6

5

4

3

2

1 sagging body is uplifted by his majesty of spirit, the awkward sputtering ofhis voice is dignified by the seriousness of his message, the jerkiness of his

argument is smoothed over by his intellectual composure – the descriptioncontinues relentlessly for pages, as if it cannot exorcise the pressure of thisstrange voice that seems to prolong itself through its interruptions and todraw energy from its defeat. In the cough, signification is suspended andlanguage comes to the brink of silence.

If the dash is the written equivalent of the cough or stutter – a graphichiatus – Hegel’s final gamble is to erase this fissure within Schiller’s text. Hiselision effaces not only the ontological gap between creator and created, andnot only the fault line between philosophical prose and the poetry it wouldmetabolize as conceptual fodder. It also erases the scar within language itselfwhich the body bears witness to its own hungers. In this sense there are nolast words in, of, or by Hegel, but only the imperceptible gesture of efface-ment on which the transparency of his own language rests. But precisely as agesture, the erasure returns language to the body at the moment of abjectingit. If Hegel effaces the traces of his own interventions with the stealth of aburglar, adjusting the dative of “ Kelch ” to fit the new metrical requirements,lest the ear hesitate, or the tongue falter,25 he cannot efface the violence of hisown effacement. It leaves its mark in unexpected places.

In punctuation marks, writes Adorno, the cheque the writer draws onlanguage is refused payment (Adorno 1991: 96). The puncture in the text isthe ejected remainder of the process of symbolization: it marks not only the

remnant left behind by Spirit’s self-interiorization but its presupposition.Noting a modern discomfort in the presence of such notations, Adornoremarks that reason has good reason to suppress these marks; it needs to effacethe trace of its own bodily inscription. Quotation marks remind Adorno ofhungry mouths: they betray an unappeasable thirst for the stuff we canneither quite remember nor quite forget within the recycled swill of history.Dashes, he continues, mark the hiatus of thought – “mute lines into the past”through which the unappeased demands of history make their continuedclaim. With a single stroke, Hegel erases Schiller’s dash, and with it thedashed hopes of an entire generation. For Germany, the failure is double.Marx’s famous quip about Germany being the only country that is forced to

suffer restoration without having undergone its own revolution articulatesthis doubleness – the paradox of a trauma coiled around the kernel of themissed moment.

Hegel’s elision thus cannot fail to evoke the crisis of signification embodiedby the Terror – the “coldest and meanest of all deaths, with no moresignificance than chopping off a head of cabbage or swallowing a mouthful ofwater” (Hegel 1970: §591). Lest this culinary metaphor seem haphazard(and the gulp of water – emphatically not wine – evokes Hegel’s descriptionof a modernity so parched in abstraction, so thirsty for content, that itgladly settles for a sip of water (Ibid. §8)) we must recall that the Terror was

Swiffen Ch08.indd 156Swiffen-Ch08.indd 156 8/3/2012 9:48:51 AM8/3/2012 9:48:51 AM

Not for Distribution

Page 17: Comay Hegels Last Words

7/25/2019 Comay Hegels Last Words

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/comay-hegels-last-words 17/20

Hegel’s Last Words 157

45

44

43

42

41

40

39

38

37

36

3534

33

32

31

30

29

28

27

26

2524

23

22

21

20

19

18

17

16

15

14

13

12

11

10

9

8

7

6

5

4

3

2

1 persistently troped as cannibalistic: print after grisly print depicts theguillotine as a flesh-eating monster. In  Dantons Tod   Georg Büchner will

compare the Revolution to a Chronos devouring his own children. In detach-ing itself from this melancholy consumption, Hegel’s final erasure unfailinglyrepeats the traumatic effacement it would evade. The almost unreadablegrammar of Hegel’s final clause, the strange anacolouthon of its coda –a lonely monosyllabic “nur,” followed by a superfluous dash (erased,tellingly, in Miller’s translation), followed by a line break, followed by thequotation – points to a residual fissure within the finished book.

In this light we should reconsider the infamous hyphen in Er-innerung  (Hegel 1970: §808). Even while graphically emphasizing the intensificationof interiority, the mark registers a split within the self-remembering self.At this point of fracture thought is forced to pause at the memory ofpossibilities still unachieved. As late as 1831 Hegel will identify theRevolution as a “knot whose solution history has to work out in the future”(Hegel 1894: 535, 1995: 452).

We might also in this light reread Hegel’s most infamous quotation,again pilfered from Schiller, and sutured without attribution or graphicdemarcation into the Philosophy of Right  (where the words are invariably readas Hegel’s own) – “Weltgeschichte als Weltgericht…” The jury is out as towhether Schiller could have intended anything like resignation in the poem“Resignation” from which the phrase is taken. In the original poem, thewords are suspended opaquely between quotation marks, stripped of reference

and determinacy. Behind the triumph of the final judgement [Gericht  ] we canstill feel the gnawing hunger of an interminable mealtime [Gericht  ].

Notes

1 “Time is the Concept that is there [da ist  ] and which presents itself to consciousness as emptyintuition; for this reason, Spirit necessarily appears in Time, and it appears in Time just aslong as it has not grasped  its pure Concept, that is, has not annulled [ tilgt  ] Time.” (Hegel1970: §801). The verb tilgen (with its hint of abstract negativity) is replaced in the nextsentence with the more accommodating term aufheben : “[Time] is the outer  , intuited pure Selfwhich is not grasped  by the Self, the merely intuited Concept; when this latter grasps itself itsupersedes [ aufhebt] its Time-form, conceptualizes is intuiting, and is a conceptualizing and

conceptualized intuiting” (translation modified).2 “The Kronos which engenders all and destroys that to which it gives birth” (Hegel 1830:§258 Anm).

3 “Time does not resemble a container in which everything is as it were borne away andswallowed up in the flow of a stream. Time is merely this abstraction of destroying. Thingsare in time because they are finite; they do not pass away because they are in time, butare themselves that which is temporal. Temporality is their objective determination. It istherefore the process of actual things that constitutes time, and if it can be said that timeis omnipotent, it must be added that it is completely impotent. The present makes atremendous demand, yet as the individual present it is nothing, for even as I pronounce it,its all-excluding pretentiousness dwindles, dissolves, and falls into dust” (Hegel 1830: §258Zusatz).

Swiffen Ch08.indd 157Swiffen-Ch08.indd 157 8/3/2012 9:48:51 AM8/3/2012 9:48:51 AM

Not for Distribution

Page 18: Comay Hegels Last Words

7/25/2019 Comay Hegels Last Words

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/comay-hegels-last-words 18/20

158 Rebecca Comay

53

52

51

50

49

48

47

46

45

44

43

42

41

40

39

38

37

36

35

34

33

32

31

3029

28

27

26

25

24

23

22

21

20

19

18

1716

15

14

13

12

11

10

9

8

7

6

5

43

2

1   4 Cf Hamacher (1997: 225f).5 The ejection of Nature involves a double genitive: Spirit’s self-excretion into Nature as

well as Nature’s own self-excretion. Life (nature in its highest form) is defined as aprocess of self-disgorgement – the “primal act of scission [Ur-teil  ] and expulsion of thesun and everything else” (Hegel 1830:§357 Zus). The organism turns against its ownexternality: it “separates itself from itself ... expels its struggle, the bile which it hasexcreted, from itself” (Hegel 1830: §365 Zus).

6 Cf Abraham and Torok (1994).7 Cf Schiller’s letter to Fichte of Aug 3–4, 1795, quoted by Kittler (1990: 156).8 The ambivalence is palpable: “It has to be admitted that the artistic sense of a profound

and philosophic mind has demanded, and expressed, totality and reconciliation … asagainst that abstract endlessness or ratiocination, that duty for duty’s sake, that formlessintellectualism, which apprehends nature and actuality, sense and feeling, as just a barrier,just contradicting it and hostile. It is Schiller  who must be given credit for breaking throughthe Kantian subjectivity and abstraction … by intellectually grasping the unity and recon-

ciliation as the truth and by actualizing them in artistic production.... Even so, one feelsthat at one period of his life he busied himself with thought more than was advantageousfor the naive beauty of his works of art. …” (Hegel 1975: 89/61).

9 Cf Comay (2011).10 Note the citational subtitle of the first edition of “Die Freundschaft (aus den Briefen Julius

an Raphael; einem noch ungedruckten Roman),” appeared in Schiller (1962: 111ff).Schiller’s own rewriting of the poem in the  Philosophische Briefe already involves substitu-tions (Wesenreiches  for  Seelenreiches ) and typographical elisions (the erasure of the originaldashes and two of the three original italics). The final stanza in this version reads as follows:“Freundlos war der große Weltenmeister,/ fühlte Mangel, darum schuf er Geister,/sel’geSpiegel seiner  Seligkeit./ Fand das höchste Wesen schon kein Gleiches/ aus dem Kelch desganzen Wesenreiches/ schäumt ihm die Unendlichkeit” (Schiller 1963: 125). WhileSchiller’s revision anticipates Hegel’s, there is no evidence that Hegel had this version at his

disposal when composing the Phenomenology .11 David Pugh argues that the disillusion sets in as early as 1783. For a more

pronounced expression of the crisis, see letter of 5 October, 1785 to Huber, cited in Pugh(1997: 183).

12 Cf Aristotle (1984: 935b31f). See the magisterial study by Klibansky, Panofsy, and Saxl(1964).

13 On the transition from anthropology to phenomenology see Hegel (1971a: §412).14 See Derrida (1982).15 In his rectoral address at Nuremberg Gymnasium, Hegel underlines the relationship

between linguistic mastery and digestion. “For it is the mechanical that is foreign tothe mind, and it is this which awakens the mind’s desire to digest the indigestiblefood forced upon it, to make intelligible what is at first without life and meaning, andto assimilate it” (Hegel “Rede zum Schuljahrabschluß am 29. September 1809,” in Werke, 

vol 4, 319.16 Cf Nietzsche (1967: §1066). “The new world-conception. — The world exists; it is not

something that becomes, not something that passes away. Or rather: it becomes, it passesaway, but it has never begun to become and never ceased from passing away – it maintainsitself in both – it lives on itself: its excrements are its food.”

17 Werner Hamacher (1997) brilliantly explores the hermeneutics in Pleroma , see especiallypp. 101–110.

18 Hamacher (1997: 181) sees here a key transition to absolute speculation: destruction marksthe relationless relation to the absolute. The moment of unproductive consumption – themeal that does not nourish – marks the delay inherent in the movement of absolutization.

19 Cf Hegel (1971b: 412/295).20 Compare Hegel (1971b: 414/297) and Hegel (1971b: 408/292).

Swiffen Ch08.indd 158Swiffen-Ch08.indd 158 8/3/2012 9:48:51 AM8/3/2012 9:48:51 AM

Not for Distribution

Page 19: Comay Hegels Last Words

7/25/2019 Comay Hegels Last Words

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/comay-hegels-last-words 19/20

Hegel’s Last Words 159

50

49

48

47

46

45

44

43

42

41

4039

38

37

36

35

34

33

32

31

30

29

28

27

26

25

24

23

22

21

20

19

18

17

16

15

14

13

12

11

10

9

8

7

6

5

43

2

1  21 See Hegel’s letter to von Altenstein, 3 April 1826, responding to a priest’s complaint(Hegel 1970b: 68–71).

22 “The mouth … has the dual function of initiating the immediate conversion of food intoorganic structures in the animal organism and also , in contrast to this inwardizing of theouter, of completing the objectification of subjectivity occurring in the voice.” (emphasismine, Hegel 1971a: §401).

23 “In many animals, the excretory and genital organs, which constitute the highest andlowest features of animal organization, are intimately connected; just as speech and kissing,on the one hand, and eating, drinking and spitting, on the other, all focus on the mouth.”(Hegel 1830: §365 Zus).

24 “It can vividly present the finest shades of derision, contempt and envy, the whole gamut ofgrief and joy, by means of the faintest movements … similarly, in repose it indicates charm,seriousness, sensitiveness, shyness, surrender, etc.” (Hegel 1975: 394/736).

25 By changing Schiller’s “aus dem Kelch” to “aus dem Kelche” – substituting a slightlyarchaic form of the dative – Hegel preserves the iambic pentameter. Thanks to John

Zilcolsky for clarifying this.

References

Abraham, N., and Torok, M. (1994) The Shell and the Kernel  , vol. 1, trans. N. T. Rand, Chicago:University of Chicago Press.

Adorno, T.W. (1973) Negative Dialectics , New York: Continuum.—— (1991) “Punctuation Marks,” in  Notes to Literature , vol. 1, trans. S.W. Nicholson,

New York: Columbia.Aristotle (1984) “Problems,” in The Complete Works of Aristotle  ,  vol. 2, J. Barnes (ed.)

 New Jersey: Princeton University Press.Benjamin, W. (1977) Origin of the German Tragic Drama , London: Verso.

Comay, R. (2011)  Mourning Sickness: Hegel and the French Revolution , Palo Alto CA: StanfordUniversity Press.Derrida, J. (1982) “The Pit and the Pyramid: Hegel’s Semiology,” in  Margins of Philosophy ,

Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Freud, S. (1960) “Mourning and Melancholia,” in J. Strachey (ed.)  Standard Edition of the

Complete Psychological Works , vol. 18, London: Hogarth Press.Goethe, J.W. (1984) Faust  , Munich: C.H. Beck.Hamacher, W. (1997)  Pleroma: Reading in Hegel  , Palo Alto CA: Stanford University

Press.Hegel, G.W.F. (1802) Glauben und Wissen  , trans. Walter Cerf and H.S. Harris (1977) Faith and

 Knowledge  , Albany NY: SUNY.—— (1830)  Philosophie der Natur  , in Enzyklopädie der philosophischen Wissenschaften im

Grundrisse , in Werke , vol. 9, Zusatz; trans.M. J. Petry (1970) Hegel’s Philosophy of Nature ,

3 vols, London: George Allen and Unwin.—— (1894) Vorlesungen über die Geschichte der Philosophie , vol. III in Werke  XX; trans. E.S. Haldane and F. H. Simson (1995) Lectures on the History of Philosophy , vol. III, LondonNE: University of Nebraska Press.

—— (1969) Wissenschaft der Logik II, Werke VI; trans. A.V. Miller, Hegel’s  Science of Logic  London:Allen and Unwin.

—— (1970) Phänomenologie des Geistes , inWerke , 20vols, E. Moldenhauer and K.M. Michel (eds);trans. A.V.Miller, Phenomenology of Spirit  , Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

—— (1970b) Berliner Schriften 1818-1831 , Werke XI, E.Moldenhauer & K.M. Michel (eds)Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

—— (1971a) Die Philosophie des Geistes , Enzyklopädie III, Werke X; trans. W. Wallace, Philosophyof Mind  , Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Swiffen Ch08.indd 159Swiffen-Ch08.indd 159 8/3/2012 9:48:51 AM8/3/2012 9:48:51 AM

Not for Distribution

Page 20: Comay Hegels Last Words

7/25/2019 Comay Hegels Last Words

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/comay-hegels-last-words 20/20

160 Rebecca Comay

24

23

22

21

20

19

18

1716

15

14

13

12

11

10

9

8

7

6

5

43

2

1  —— (1971b) “Der Geist des Christentums und sein Schicksal,” in Werke , vol. 1; trans. T.M. Knox, “Spirit of Christianity” in Early Theological Writings , Philadelphia: University of

Pennsylvania Press.—— (1975) Vorlesungen über die Ästhetik I in Werke XIII; trans. T.M. Knox, Aesthetics: Lectureson Fine Art  , Oxford: Oxford University Press.

—— (1986) “Aphorismen aus Hegels Wastebook” (1803–1806), in Werke , vol 2, Frankfurt:Suhrkamp.

—— (1988) Vorlesungen über die Philosophie der Religion  , in Werke , vol. 17; trans. P. Hodgson (ed.) Lectures on the Philosophy of Religion, The Lectures of 1827 , Berkeley and Los Angeles CA:University of California Press.

—— (1991) The Encyclopaedia Logic  , trans. T.F. Geraets, W.A. Suchting, and H.S. Harris,Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company.

Kaufmann, W. (1966) Hegel: A Reinterpretation , Garden City NY: Anchor Books.Kittler, F. (1990) Discourse Networks 1800/1900 , Stanford CA: Stanford University Press.Klibansky, R., Panofsy, E., and Saxl, F. (1964) Saturn and Melancholy: Studies in the History of

 Natural Philosophy, Religion, and Art  , New York: Basic Books.Nietszche, F. (1967) The Will to Power  , trans. Walter Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale,

W. Kaufmann (ed.) New York: Random House.Pugh, D. (1997)  Dialectic of Love: Platonism in Schiller’s Aesthetics , Montreal: McGill-Queen’s

University Press.Schiller, F. (1962)  Schillers Werke, Nationalausgabe , vol.1, J. Petersen and F. Beißner (eds)

Weimar: Hermann Böhlaus Nachfolger.—— (1963) Nationalausgabe, Philosophische Schriften , Benno von Wiese and Helmut Koopman

(eds) Weimar.

Not for Distribution