Caste and Disability the Moral Foundations of the ADA

download Caste and Disability the Moral Foundations of the ADA

of 8

Transcript of Caste and Disability the Moral Foundations of the ADA

  • 8/11/2019 Caste and Disability the Moral Foundations of the ADA

    1/8

    Citation: 157 U. Pa. L. Rev. PENNumbra 21 2008

    Content downloaded/printed from

    HeinOnline (http://heinonline.org)

    Sat Apr 26 11:44:36 2014

    -- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance

    of HeinOnline's Terms and Conditions of the license

    agreement available at http://heinonline.org/HOL/License

    -- The search text of this PDF is generated from

    uncorrected OCR text.

  • 8/11/2019 Caste and Disability the Moral Foundations of the ADA

    2/8

    CASTE AND DISABILITY:

    THE

    MORAL

    FOUNDATIONS

    OF THE ADA

    CASS R. SUNSTEIN

    t

    In response

    to

    Elizabeth

    F. Emens, IntegratingAccommodation

    156 U.

    PA.

    L. REV.

    39 (2008).

    The

    Americans

    with Disabilities Act

    (ADA) combats

    certain forms

    of

    social

    exclusion, which produce

    second-class

    citizenship for many

    millions

    of

    Americans. The ADA appears

    to

    reflect

    a judgment that

    the physical

    and cognitive

    impairments

    that produce

    disability are

    irrelevant

    from the moral

    point

    of view,

    in

    he sense that

    they result

    from

    an accident

    of

    nature;' people should not

    be blamed for being

    blind,

    deaf, wheelchair bound,

    or depressed. But because

    of those

    impairments, disabled people are excluded

    from multiple

    domains,

    including the workplace. The

    duty

    of

    reasonable accommodation

    is

    the ADA's statutory

    response. On this account, the ADA should

    be

    regarded

    as

    the clearest reflection,

    in American law,

    of

    an anticaste

    principle

    4

    -a

    principle that

    raises

    questions

    about

    social and legal

    practices that turn a

    morally

    irrelevant difference into a

    systematic

    source

    of

    social disadvantage.'

    Of

    course,

    the

    duty of reasonable

    accommodation is

    not absolute.

    As

    it

    is

    now

    understood, that

    duty

    embodies

    a

    requirement of

    cost-

    benefit analysis, at least in the loose sense that employers

    are not re-

    quired

    to

    undertake measures

    whose

    costs

    are

    grossly disproportion-

    ate

    to their benefits. But what

    are

    the costs

    and

    benefits of accom-

    *Felix

    Frankfurter

    Professor

    of Law, Harvard Law School;

    Harry

    Kalven Visiting

    Professor of

    Law,

    University of

    Chicago

    Law

    School,January

    2009.

    See the

    discussion

    of the

    natural

    lotteiy

    in JO N

    RAWLS, A

    THEORY

    O USTI

    64-65 rev. d 1999).

    See

    e.g.

    42

    U.S.C.

    12101(a)

    7)

    (2000)

    (finding

    that

    individuals

    with

    disabilities

    face

    restrictions and limitations based upon characteristics that are beyond

    their

    con-

    trol .

    See42

    U.S.C. 12112(b)(5)

    (2000).

    4

    See Cass

    R.

    Sunstein,

    he

    nticaste

    Privcipce

    92

    MICH.

    L.

    REV.

    2410,

    2428-33

    (1994) (asserting that there is

    an underlying principle in American society that no

    members

    of any one

    group should

    be treated

    as

    second-class citizens).

    Id

    at

    2429.

    6

    ee

    Vande

    Zande

    v.

    Wis.

    Dep't

    of

    Admin.,

    44

    F.3d

    538,

    542-43

    (7th

    Cir

    1995

  • 8/11/2019 Caste and Disability the Moral Foundations of the ADA

    3/8

    CASTE AAD DISABILITY

    modation? Perhaps the most significant contribution of Elizabeth

    Emens's important

    and imaginative article'

    is

    the

    suggestion that

    thus

    far, too little attention has been paid to the existence of

    third-party

    benefits -benefits

    to

    those,

    including

    able-bodied

    people,

    who did

    not

    request

    the

    accommodation

    in question. If,

    for example,

    an

    em-

    ployer

    is required to accommodate asthmatic

    workers

    by providing

    a

    smoke-free environment, many

    nonasthmatic

    employees will also

    benefit.9 Similarly, if

    an employer

    is

    required

    to purchase

    lifting

    equipment

    that accommodates workers

    who

    cannot lift, other workers

    are

    likely to gain from

    the reduced physical

    strain.

    In

    this

    brief

    Response, I want

    to sketch a

    tempting objection to

    Enens's

    argunent one

    that she herself recognizes- and then to

    show

    that the objection

    is unconvincing, in a way

    that helps to

    illumi-

    nate the moral

    and

    political

    foundations of her argument and,

    in-

    deed,

    of

    the

    ADA

    itself. In

    brief, I

    think that Emens's

    claims

    can be

    seen as

    being animated

    by a

    suggestion

    that it is not merely

    crude, but

    damaging,

    to

    divide

    the world into two

    kinds : those who

    are able-

    bodied and those

    who

    are

    not.

    Her emphasis

    on

    third-party

    benefits

    and her distinction between usage

    benefits

    and

    attitudinal

    benefits

    should

    be taken

    as

    an

    effort

    to

    deepen

    our

    understanding of the ADA

    by showing how conventional divisions

    between kinds

    help

    to

    create

    the

    very

    problem that the ADA

    is

    intended to eliminate. By recogniz-

    ing

    third-party

    benefits, particularly benefits to

    those who are not dis-

    abled, we can take a significant step toward eliminating

    those

    divi-

    sions.

    The

    tempting objection to Emens's argument, in

    a

    nutshell,

    is

    that

    because the

    goal

    of

    the

    ADA

    is

    to

    reduce

    the

    exclusion-and

    hence

    the

    subordination-of disabled people,

    an emphasis

    on third-party

    benefits is

    a distraction,

    and potentially

    a

    damaging

    one.

    2

    Suppose

    that an employee asks for an accommodation

    in the form of telecom-

    muting; perhaps

    the employee

    is being treated for depression

    or

    an

    anxiety disorder and needs to

    spend significant time away from the

    workplace.

    It

    is

    possible

    that

    if

    the

    employer adopts

    a

    new

    policy

    that

    (holding that employers

    re

    not required to expend enormous sums in order to bring

    about a

    trivial improvement

    n the

    life

    of a disabled

    employee ).

    7

    See Elizabeth

    Emens,

    InlegmtingAccommodalion

    156

    U.

    PA.

    L.

    REV

    39

    (2008).

    Id at 846-59.

    Id t 851

    1

    Id

    d t 848.

    12

    Id

    t 916-19 (acknowledging

    and answering this objection .

    2 81

  • 8/11/2019 Caste and Disability the Moral Foundations of the ADA

    4/8

    23 UNIVERSITY

    OFPENNSYLV NI

    L WPEVIEW [Vol. 157:21

    PENNu

    mbra

    allows people to work at home, numerous employees will benefit. But

    if courts emphasize

    this point, the objection

    continues, they

    would

    seem to be

    construing the ADA

    in

    a way that loses sight of and even

    obscures

    its

    fundamental

    goals. Why

    should

    the rights

    of

    disabled

    people

    depend

    on the

    extent

    to which

    third

    parties

    benefit

    from rec-

    ognition of

    those

    rights?

    As

    Emens emphasizes,

    we

    are dealing with

    the

    Americans

    with

    Disabilities

    Act,

    not

    the

    Americans

    Act.

    1

    3

    At

    the

    same time,

    Emens's

    suggestion

    would

    seem

    to require

    courts

    to

    undertake an inquiry for which they lack

    adequate tools;

    how can judges assess, in a

    meaningful way,

    the overall

    or

    aggregate

    benefits

    of a large-scale

    change in attendance

    policy?

    The same ques-

    tion

    might be raised

    about any requested

    accommodation that

    confers

    benefits on third parties.

    The

    initial response

    to this

    objection

    is

    straightforward:

    so

    long

    as

    the idea of reasonable accommodation is

    taken

    to call

    for an

    assess-

    ment

    of

    both

    costs and

    benefits, courts

    should

    take

    account

    of third-

    party benefits,

    simply

    because those benefits are part

    of

    what matters

    to that

    assessment.

    If courts neglect

    third-party

    benefits, their assess-

    ment will be

    partial and distorted. As Emens demonstrates, an analy-

    sis

    that focuses only on the benefits to the disabled person, neglecting

    other benefits,

    will

    be badly incomplete

    4

    For this reason, it is mis-

    leading to ask whether

    the

    rights

    of

    disabled people should

    depend,

    in

    part,

    on the benefits

    of

    accommodation for those who are able-

    bodied.

    The

    statutory

    question

    is

    whether

    an

    accommodation is

    rea-

    sonable-and

    an accommodation that would not

    be reasonable if only

    a few

    people benefit from it might

    well be

    reasonable

    if

    many do so .

    It is true

    that

    an assessment of

    costs and benefits may

    strain

    judi-

    cial

    capacities. But

    as

    Emnens

    shows, there are situations in

    which

    the

    benefits to third parties are

    significant,'5

    and when deciding whether

    an accommodation is reasonable, it is foolish and

    inconsistent

    with

    the statute to

    disregard them. Courts might well be able to develop

    rules of thumb

    that

    enable them to decide whether the third-party

    benefits

    are

    substantial

    or

    trivial.

    Indeed,

    Emnens s

    own analysis goes

    a

    long

    way

    toward

    supplying

    the

    foundations

    of

    such

    rules.'6

    11I.

    at

    883.

    14

    1I

    t

    869-75

    (discussing

    the

    failure

    of

    judicial

    opinions

    to

    consider

    third-party

    benefits).

    15

    d at

    845-59

    (identifying

    the

    variety

    of

    third party

    benefits

    that

    might

    be

    created

    by

    accommodations).

    Id

    at

    861-66

    providing

    a

    basic

    spectrum

    for

    the

    weighing

    of

    third-party

    costs

    and benefits created

    by

    i

    accommodation).

  • 8/11/2019 Caste and Disability the Moral Foundations of the ADA

    5/8

    CASTE D

    DISABILITY

    But there are more fundamental issues in the background.

    Workplace

    practices are constructed by

    and for

    people

    with

    certain

    physical and

    mental characteristics.

    We can

    easily

    imagine alternative

    worlds in which

    human

    beings

    had

    very

    different

    physical

    and mental

    characteristics

    and

    in

    which workplaces

    were

    constructed

    for those

    people. Imagine, for example,

    a world

    consisting

    solely

    of blind peo-

    ple, or deaf

    people,

    or people facing serious anxiety issues, or people

    unable to

    lift

    more than ten

    pounds,

    or people without

    legs. In these

    imaginable worlds, workplaces would be

    constructed

    in a way that

    would fit their needs. Indeed, we could easily imagine alternative

    worlds

    in

    which human capacities, both physical and cognitive, were

    far beyond the

    current

    norm. In

    such

    worlds, practices and expecta-

    tions would be radically different, and those with existing capacities

    would find

    themselves

    at

    a

    systematic

    disadvantage.

    I have urged that

    the

    ADA

    is best taken to

    suggest that that

    in

    our

    world,

    morally

    irrelevant

    differences have been

    turned,

    without

    suffi-

    cient justification, into

    a systematic

    source

    of social

    disadvantage.

    7

    This

    is the sense in

    which

    it

    is

    true that many

    of the disadvantages

    produced

    by disability are socially constructed-under different social

    arrangements, those

    disadvantages

    could

    be

    reduced

    or

    even elimi-

    nated. Indeed, the

    ADA attempts to

    do exactly that.

    But as

    Adam

    Samaha has

    argued,s

    and as Emens recognizes,' the social construc-

    tion

    of disadvantage

    is a

    mere fact,

    rather

    than

    a political

    or moral

    ar-

    gument,

    and an argument

    of

    that sort is necessary to make

    sense

    of

    the

    ADA.

    2

    The most convincing such

    argument

    is

    Rawlsian in spirit

    2

    '

    it

    stresses

    the need to ensure that unfortunate outcomes in the natu-

    ral

    lottery

    (blindness, deafness,

    impaired mobility)

    are

    not translated

    into very

    bad

    or tragic outcomes.

    For

    her part,

    Emens is largely agnostic

    on the moral foundations

    of

    the ADA. In arguing for recognition of

    third-party benefits, she

    does

    not attempt

    to

    take any

    particular stand

    on

    the foundational

    is-

    sues.

    But I believe that the

    moral roots

    of

    h r argument have every-

    thing

    to

    do

    with

    an anticaste

    principle of

    a

    Rawlsian

    kind-indeed,

    I

    7

    See

    sulna

    text

    accompanying

    note

    2.

    Is

    See

    Adam

    M. Samaha,

    What

    ood

    is

    the

    ocial

    Model

    I

    Disability?

    74

    U.

    CHI.

    L.

    REv. 1251 (2007) (claiming that the social model of disability assumes no policy

    or

    normative considerations).

    See

    Emens,

    suIna

    note

    7

    at

    889

    n.158.

    20

    Samaha,

    sun

    note

    18

    at 1253-54

    ( The

    social

    model

    has

    essentially

    nothing

    to

    say about

    which [normative] framework to use. ).

    21

    See

    sotur e

    cited stipra niote

    1 and

    accompanying text.

    2 8

  • 8/11/2019 Caste and Disability the Moral Foundations of the ADA

    6/8

    25 UNIVERSITY

    OFPENNSYLV NI

    L WPEVIEW

    [Vol. 157:21

    PENNu

    mbra

    believe

    that

    Emens's claims offer

    an

    intriguing and novel twist on how

    that

    principle

    should be

    understood, at

    least in the context

    of

    the

    ADA

    Let

    me

    elaborate.

    mens

    is

    concerned

    with

    two

    kinds

    of third-

    party

    benefits:

    usage benefits and attitudinal benefits..

    2

    If

    for

    exam-

    ple,

    an employer adopts a broad-based

    telecommuting policy, many

    workers

    will gain

    simply

    because they can

    take

    advantage

    of that

    pol-

    icy.

    Alternatively, coworkers'

    experience with

    the accommodation

    might

    alter

    their

    attitudes

    toward disabled

    people and

    the ADA

    They

    might,

    for

    example, think

    of disabled

    people

    not

    as

    abstract, frighten-

    ing, or contemptible others, but instead

    as

    fellow

    human

    beings

    struggling with a

    difficult

    (but not

    insuperable)

    condition.

    Indeed,

    they

    might

    even

    come to

    think

    that

    disabled people struggle in part

    because

    of

    social

    practices

    that might

    be

    otherwise-they

    might

    come

    to

    see how the

    practices,

    and not the

    condition, help to

    constitute the

    disability. Or

    they

    might come to conclude that

    the

    ADA is not an

    il-

    legitimate and somewhat confusing

    imposition into

    the workplace but

    is instead

    an

    effort

    to ensure

    that

    those who are, in

    relevant

    respects,

    similarly situated are

    given

    a

    decent

    chance to work

    on similar

    terms.

    When

    accommodations

    produce usage and attitudinal

    benefits,

    they promote the integrationist goals of

    the ADA in a

    way

    that we

    would not see

    if

    we were to

    focus

    solely

    on

    the benefits

    to

    the disabled

    person.

    Most

    people benefit from cleaner air or from reduced physi-

    cal strain. If

    nondisabled people gain from an

    accommodation, then

    they should be able

    to see

    that

    disabled people are less fundamentally

    different

    than

    they

    might

    have thought.

    Too many able-bodied

    peo-

    ple

    do not know or do not work with people who

    are blind, deaf, or in

    wheelchairs. Too many nondisabled people

    do not

    know,

    or at least

    do not know that they know, people with serious psychological prob-

    lems. If nondisabled people are actually

    working

    with

    disabled peo-

    ple,

    the

    very

    fact of

    integration should help to combat

    the

    establish-

    ment of second-class

    citizenship. To the

    extent that accommodations

    are made

    and

    are

    visible,

    and

    to

    the

    extent that

    they

    benefit

    a wide

    range

    of

    people,

    the

    anticaste

    goals

    of

    the

    ADA will

    be

    significantly

    promoted-not in spite of the emphasis on third-party benefits but be-

    cause

    of

    that

    very

    emphasis.

    As I

    read Emens,

    her

    exploration

    of third-party benefits is ani-

    mated in large part

    by

    a

    sense that the ADA should be

    understood

    to

    combat

    the idea that

    disabled people

    and

    able-bodied

    people

    are

    Emens, supi not 7

    at

    848.

  • 8/11/2019 Caste and Disability the Moral Foundations of the ADA

    7/8

    CASTE D

    DISABILITY

    fundamentally

    different

    from one another. Consider, for example,

    her emphasis

    on those

    who have

    some kind of impairment, but not

    enough to obtain the protection of the statute;

    2

    her

    emphasis on the

    importance

    of

    publicizing

    third-party benefits;

    2

    her

    rejection

    of

    the

    idea

    that the

    ADA is a

    kind

    of one-way redistribution;,

    2 5

    and

    her

    ob-

    jection to a view that would accept the baseline

    set

    by existing prac-

    tice When Einens stresses the effort to interrogate the world as it

    is

    currently

    structured,

    2

    I

    think

    that what she

    wants to challenge

    is

    a set

    of structures

    that separates the world

    into

    two distinct kinds: those

    who

    are

    able and

    those

    who

    are

    not.

    A recognition of third-party

    benefits

    breaks

    down that

    distinction.

    It suggests that there is a

    con-

    tinmln here, not

    a

    sharp dichotomy, and that the perception of

    a

    di-

    chotony is

    not a reflection of brute facts but itself a product of social

    and

    legal

    practices

    that

    could be

    otherwise.

    Of course, it is true that because of the natural lottery, some peo-

    ple are

    bound to have a harder time

    than others

    and that for

    certain

    purposes,

    it

    makes

    sense

    to

    think

    in terms of dichotomies.

    Those who

    cannot hear, see, or walk

    lack

    certain

    capacities; those who

    suffer

    from

    chronic depression or from acute anxiety face obstacles that no re-

    structured workplace

    can

    eliminate.

    Emphasizing

    this

    point

    a

    famil-

    iar understanding

    of

    the ADA-rooted in the idea

    of

    a natural

    lottery

    and a commitment to charity-says there but for the grace of God

    go I.

    But

    there is

    a

    less familiar understanding which questions the

    familiar

    one,

    which does not invoke charity at all. For those

    who hold

    this

    different

    understanding,

    the purpose of

    the

    ADA, rightly con-

    ceived, is to break down distinctions that

    have

    their current force

    only

    because

    of

    social

    practices

    that have

    been

    so

    taken for granted that

    they

    are often unseen

    as

    practices

    at

    all.

    I believe

    that the

    less

    familiar

    understanding is the better one and

    that Emens is speaking firmly on its

    behalf. In my view, her emphasis

    on

    third-party

    benefits,

    and her insistence

    on their importance,

    is best

    seen not as a diversion from the fundamental goals

    of the ADA, but as

    an effort

    to

    reconceive

    and

    deepen

    them.

    23

    Wi

    t

    842-43, 851-52.

    4

    Wi

    t 912-13.

    2

    i t

    896.

    6

    Id

    27

    Id.

    2 8

  • 8/11/2019 Caste and Disability the Moral Foundations of the ADA

    8/8

    27

    UNIVERSITY

    OFPENNSYLVANIA

    LAW PEVIEW

    PENNumbra

    [Vol.

    57: 21

    Preferred

    Citation:

    Cass

    Sunstein, Response,

    Caste

    and

    Disability

    The

    Moral Foundations

    of

    th ADA 57 U. PA L REV PENNUTMBRA 21

    2008), http://www.peinnnbra.coin/responses/10-2008/

    Stmstein.pdf.