Ben Jonson’s Skeptical Friend: Gorgias in the English Renaissance

34
1 [This essay, written in 2004, has not previously been published.] [Index: Ben Jonson, Gorgias, Sir Walter Ralegh] [Date: 2004] Ben Jonson’s Skeptical Friend: Gorgias in the English Renaissance Michael H. Keefer On its first appearance in print, in the quarto of 1605, Ben Jonson’s tragedy Sejanus His Fall was prefaced by commendatory verses from the pens of George Chapman, Hugh Holland, Th. R. (most likely Thomas Roe), John Marston, William Strachey, and three unidentified writers who sign themselves, respectively, “Cygnus,” “Ev. [probably Everard] B,” 1 and “Philo.” My aim in this essay is to identify the source drawn upon by Ben Jonson’s “Friend,” and to speculate 1 The view that this was Edmund Bolton, who wrote commendatory Latin verses for Volpone, is refuted by Philip Ayres, who notes that the reading “ED. B.” in some copies of the quarto was corrected in press to “Ev. B.” (Jonson 1990: 69).

description

This essay, written in 2004, has not previously been published.On its first appearance in print, in the quarto of 1605, Ben Jonson’s tragedy Sejanus His Fall was prefaced by commendatory verses from the pens of George Chapman, Hugh Holland, Th. R. (most likely Thomas Roe), John Marston, William Strachey, and three unidentified writers who sign themselves, respectively, “Cygnus,” “Ev. [probably Everard] B,”1 and “Philo.” My aim in this essay is to identify the source drawn upon by Ben Jonson’s “Friend,” and to speculate on this friend’s identity—some important clues to which may be provided by links between the poem’s source and skeptical tendencies in late-Elizabethan and Jacobean England. With all due respect for the tenuousness of the evidence—and also, one must add, for the skeptical discourses that form a large part of this evidence—I want to suggest that this friend may have been Sir Walter Ralegh.

Transcript of Ben Jonson’s Skeptical Friend: Gorgias in the English Renaissance

Page 1: Ben Jonson’s Skeptical Friend: Gorgias in the English Renaissance

1

[This essay, written in 2004, has not previously been published.]

[Index: Ben Jonson, Gorgias, Sir Walter Ralegh][Date: 2004]

Ben Jonson’s Skeptical Friend:

Gorgias in the English Renaissance

Michael H. Keefer

On its first appearance in print, in the quarto of 1605, Ben Jonson’s tragedy

Sejanus His Fall was prefaced by commendatory verses from the pens of George

Chapman, Hugh Holland, Th. R. (most likely Thomas Roe), John Marston, William

Strachey, and three unidentified writers who sign themselves, respectively, “Cygnus,”

“Ev. [probably Everard] B,”1 and “Philo.” My aim in this essay is to identify the source

drawn upon by Ben Jonson’s “Friend,” and to speculate on this friend’s identity—some

important clues to which may be provided by links between the poem’s source and

skeptical tendencies in late-Elizabethan and Jacobean England. With all due respect for

the tenuousness of the evidence—and also, one must add, for the skeptical discourses that

form a large part of this evidence—I want to suggest that this friend may have been Sir

Walter Ralegh.

The commendatory poem, a sonnet that might have been designed to illustrate the

paradoxical wit of the emergent ‘metaphysical’ lyrical style, reads as follows:

1 The view that this was Edmund Bolton, who wrote commendatory Latin verses for Volpone, is refuted by Philip Ayres, who notes that the reading “ED. B.” in some copies of the quarto was corrected in press to “Ev. B.” (Jonson 1990: 69).

Page 2: Ben Jonson’s Skeptical Friend: Gorgias in the English Renaissance

2

Thy Poeme (pardon mee) is meere deceat.

Yet such deceate, as thou that dost beguile,

Art juster farre then they who use no wile:

And they who are deceaved by this feat,

More wise, then such who can eschewe thy cheat.

For thou hast given each parte so just a stile,

That Men suppose the Action now on file;

(And Men suppose, who are of best conceat.)

Yet some there be, that are not moov’d hereby,

And others are so quick, that they will spy

Where later Times are in some speech enweav’d;

Those wary Simples, and these simple Elfes:

They are so dull, they cannot be deceav’d,

These so unjust, they will decêave themselues.

Philo.

(Jonson 1925-1952: xi.316-17)2

This poem resonates with Jonson’s obsessive concern in Sejanus with what we

might call (in a new-historicist chiasmus) the deceptions of power and the power of

deception; at the same time, it acerbically alludes to what Annabel Patterson has called

“the hermeneutics of censorship”—a practice of reading in which political authorities and

literary authors played games of cat and mouse around the questions of whether, where

and how literary texts might be making allegorical reference to issues of contemporary

political moment (see Patterson 52-66). But the sonnet’s first five lines are also a direct

translation of the ancient sophist Gorgias’s definition of tragedy as “a deception in which

the deceiver is more justly esteemed [or ‘nearer to reality,’ ‘truer’] than the nondeceiver

and the deceived is wiser than the undeceived” (Sprague 65).3

2 In quoting from this and other old-spelling texts, I have silently modernized i/j, u/v, and vv/w; quotations from Greek texts are transliterated.3 George Kennedy, the translator of the Gorgias texts in Sprague, renders dikaioteros as “more justly esteemed.” This is appropriate for the comparative form of a word (dikaios) that in Homer means “righteous, observant of custom and law, civilized.” In later usage, however, the word acquires the meanings of “real, genuine, true” (as in Demosthenes, dikaios sungrapheos [“true historian”]). Mario Untersteiner translates dikaioteros as “nearer to reality” or “conform[ing] more justly to reality” (Untersteiner 113-14; see also 127n.48); I have offered his translation and “truer” as parenthetical alternatives to Kennedy’s rendering.

Page 3: Ben Jonson’s Skeptical Friend: Gorgias in the English Renaissance

3

I

Gorgias of Leontini, a contemporary of Socrates, is best known for the dialogue

which Plato named after him, in which he is represented as a dignified but dialectically

inept old man whose rhetorical theories and practices have led his disciples into

disquieting ethical aberrations. But Gorgias may have represented a more significant

threat to Plato and to his philosophical-political program than this dialogue would

suggest: as I have argued elsewhere, Socrates’s real interlocutor in the anxious arguments

against the deceptive and transformative powers of poetic mimesis that Plato develops in

Books II and III of the Republic is not Adeimantus or Glaucon, but the absent Gorgias

(Keefer 165-71).4

The most substantial of Gorgias’s surviving works is a treatise, known under the

title On the Nonexistent or On Nature, in which he argues “first and foremost, that

nothing exists; second, that even if it exists it is inapprehensible to man; third, that even if

it is apprehensible, still it is without doubt incapable of being expressed or explained to

the next man” (Sprague 42). This appears to be a response to the teaching of Parmenides

that Being is indivisible and continuous, like a well-rounded sphere, with no temporal

beginning, no motion, and no end (Kirk and Raven 271, Freeman 43)—and to the famous

paradoxes with which his disciple Zeno had defended this doctrine by refuting the very

notions of plurality and of motion. Although Gorgias’s deployment of the new logic of

the Eleatics rivals Zeno in its oddity, and although there may be some question as to

whether he is refuting or clarifying Parmenides,5 his text is not frivolous—or, if frivolous 4 Gorgias is otherwise implicated in the Platonic canon: Calogero argued that Plato’s Apology contains echoes both doctrinal and verbal of Gorgias’s Encomium of Helen and Defense of Palamedes. 5 According to the traditional view of Guthrie, Gorgias’s text, taking “the Eleatic bull by the horns,” is a parodic “inversion of Parmenides’s arguments” (Guthrie 193-94). Kerferd, explaining a shift towards an understanding of Parmenides in terms of predication, argues that in response to Parmenides Gorgias is raising “the whole problem of meaning and reference” (Kerferd 99). More recently, Carol Poster has argued that “the Parmenidean ontology is entirely without things, making the Gorgiastic ‘it is not’ not a refutation, but, rather, a clarification of the Parmenidean ‘it is’” (Poster 289). According to Poster, Parmenides’ “Way of Truth” enunciates a “singularly unpopulated” ontology within which “truth cannot be derived from empirical observation”—which amounts, she says, to an “austere and theoretical account of how all discourse is essentially fictive and poetic” (Poster 293, 290). She notes that Parmenides then “proceeds to create a cosmological fiction … in his ‘Way of Seeming’” (Poster 290-91), which he introduces by saying, “Here I end my trustworthy discourse and thought concerning truth; henceforth learn

Page 4: Ben Jonson’s Skeptical Friend: Gorgias in the English Renaissance

4

in form, it is not so in intention. (According to Aristotle, Gorgias declared that “the

opponent’s seriousness is to be demolished by laughter, and laughter by seriousness”

[Sprague 63].)

The third section of Gorgias’s argument rests upon the view that logos or the

order of words is wholly separate from the rest of existence, so that in communicating

with our neighbour “we do not reveal existing things … but logos, which is something

other than substances” (Sprague 46).6 If this sense of a radical disjunction of logos,

externally subsisting objects, and our perceptions of them carries tragic implications,

another Gorgian text, the Encomium of Helen, leads us directly into the domain of

tragedy, at the same time offering an understanding of poetry as a supremely

manipulative art in which, paradoxically, wisdom emerges out of sorcery and deception.

The chorus in Aeschylus’s tragedy Agamemnon had called Helen of Troy helenas,

helandros, heleptolis, “the ruin of ships, men, and the city” (Aeschylus ii. 34, ll. 689-90);

in his Encomium Gorgias sets out to prove that she can in no way be blamed for leaving

her husband and going with another man to Troy. For if she did so by the will of fate and

of the gods, they are at fault, and if she was carried off by violence she is to be pitied

rather than blamed.

But if it was logos which persuaded her and deceived her heart, not

even to this is it difficult to make an answer and to banish blame as

follows. Logos is a powerful lord, which by means of the finest and

most invisible body effects the divinest works: it can stop fear and

banish grief and create joy and nurture pity. (Sprague 52)7

Poetry provides a proof of this: “Fearful shuddering and tearful pity and grievous

longing come upon its hearers….” And other kinds of ordered speech reinforce the

argument:

the beliefs of mortal men, listening to the deceitful ordering of my words” (Kirk and Raven 278). She concludes that Gorgias’s work on non-being “carefully mirrors Parmenides’ argument,” and “in its denial of being and knowledge, affirms rather than contradicts Parmenides’ skepticism, and in so doing provides a philosophical substrate for the necessity of rhetoric” (Poster 294). 6 This text is a translation of the report of Gorgias’s treatise preserved by Sextus Empiricus in Adversus mathematicos VII.65-86. Another report, preserved in the pseudo-Aristotelian On Melissus, Xenophanes, and Gorgias, contains interesting elaborations of this argument; see Aristotle ii.1550. 7 In this and the following quotation I have made minor emendations, preserving logos where the translator gives “speech,” and substituting the gender-neutral “sorcery” for “witchcraft” as a translation of goeteia.

Page 5: Ben Jonson’s Skeptical Friend: Gorgias in the English Renaissance

5

Sacred incantations sung with words are bearers of pleasure and

banishers of pain, for merging with opinion in the soul, the power

of the incantation is wont to beguile it and persuade it and alter it

by sorcery. There have been discovered two arts of sorcery and

magic: one consists of errors of soul and the other of deceptions of

opinion. All who have and do persuade people of things do so by

molding a false argument…. What cause then prevents the

conclusion that Helen, similarly, against her will, might have come

under the influence of logos, just as if ravished by the force of the

mighty? (Sprague 52)

Gorgias’s definition of tragedy (which was separately transmitted by Plutarch)

can thus be recognized as belonging to a carefully elaborated skeptical metaphysic which

legitimizes the study and practice of rhetoric. Since knowledge (that is to say, any certain

apprehension of reality) is both unattainable and incommunicable, humans are confined

to persuasions which are unavoidably false, composed as they must be either of errors or

of deceptions. Paradoxically, however, these deceptions can bring wisdom to those who

submit to them. It is noteworthy that although Gorgias’s Encomium transfers blame from

Helen to the power of logos, his instances of that power seem to imply that it is not

ethically neutral, and at the same time to anticipate Aristotle’s account of tragic katharsis:

ordered or incantatory speech evokes fear and pity and “grievous longing,” but also puts

an end to fear, banishes pain and grief, brings joy, and nurtures pity.

When in Book II of the Republic Socrates condemns the poets’ habit of

representing the gods as taking on different shapes, or as deceiving us into thinking that

they do, he is also attacking the Gorgian view that poetry, the exemplary form of ordered

speech, is rightly and intrinsically both magical and deceptive. In Socrates’ view, it is not

possible that a god could ever be “false in speech, or false in deed by putting forth a

phantom of himself.” This is the case because “true falsehood”—a distinctly Gorgian

paradox which Socrates unfolds as meaning a willing deception of one’s “truest and

highest part” about the “truest and highest matters”—is “hated of all gods and men.” For,

he says (in what sounds very much like a rejoinder to Gorgias’s definition of tragedy),

“deceiving, or being deceived and uninformed, about realities in his very soul, and in that

Page 6: Ben Jonson’s Skeptical Friend: Gorgias in the English Renaissance

6

part to have and embrace falsehood, is what every man will least tolerate” (Plato 381e,

382a-b, p. 147).

II

But was anything resembling the understanding of Gorgias outlined here

accessible in late sixteenth- and early seventeenth-century England? Gorgias’s two

surviving orations, the Encomium of Helen and the Defense of Palamedes, had been

printed early in the sixteenth century by Aldus Manutius.8 Gentian Hervet’s Latin

translation of the Pyrrhonist skeptic Sextus Empiricus’s Adversus mathematicos (and

therefore also of Gorgias’s On the Nonexistent, a version of which is preserved in

Adversus mathematicos VII. 65-86) was printed in Paris in 1569, along with a reprint of

Henri Estienne’s 1562 Latin version of Sextus’s Outlines of Pyrrhonism (Schmitt 237).

Gorgias’s fragment on tragedy, which is quoted in Plutarch’s essay “On the Fame of the

Athenians,” was available through the editions of Plutarch’s Moralia printed by Aldus

(1509) and Estienne (1572-73), as well as in Philemon Holland’s English translation,

printed in 1603. However, since these texts remained dispersed, it is questionable to what

extent “Gorgias,” the skeptical rhetorician reassembled for us by the classical scholarship

of the past century, can be said to have existed in Ben Jonson’s lifetime. There are,

nonetheless, tantalizing traces of a current of interest in Pyrrhonist skepticism, and in the

earlier skepticism of Gorgias—a current in which the sonnet of Ben Jonson’s “Friend”

appears to have participated.

I would not include within this Gorgian-Pyrrhonist current—although it may be a

related phenomenon—that highly artificial prose, laden with parallelisms, antitheses,

assonances, alliterations and rhymes, which enjoyed a brief vogue in such works as

George Pettie’s Petite Palace of Pettie his Pleasures (1576) and John Lyly’s Euphues:

The Anatomy of Wit (1578). This fashion did arise out of a rediscovery, however indirect,

of the stylistic mannerisms with which Gorgias had so impressed late-fifth-century

B.C.E. Athenians: as C. S. Lewis gloomily observed, “those who inquire most learnedly”

8 Diels, while basing his edition of Gorgias’s orations on two independent manuscript sources, makes frequent reference in his apparatus to Aldus’s emendations (see Diels ii. 249, 253-55, 258-63).

Page 7: Ben Jonson’s Skeptical Friend: Gorgias in the English Renaissance

7

into the sources of the euphuistic style “find themselves driven back and back until they

reach Gorgias” (Lewis 312). But what seems to have caught the attention of Pettie and

Lyly was the Gorgias of the orations—or rather, one part only of that Gorgias: the

practitioner whose highly figured prose appropriated all the artifices of poetry, but not the

thinker who also theorized the persuasive power of verbal incantation.

The dramatic rhetoric of Christopher Marlowe is another matter altogether:

Stephen Greenblatt has described as thoroughly Gorgian Marlowe’s fascination with “the

magic violence of speech” (Greenblatt 215, quoting Untersteiner 106). Greenblatt

brilliantly articulates the uncanny resonance between the predicaments of Gorgian

humankind and of Marlowe’s protagonists, who are alike “forever cut off from the

knowledge of being, forever locked in the partial, the contradictory, and the irrational,”

and hence obliged “through the power of language [to] construct deceptions in which and

for which they live” (Greenblatt 215). Significantly, although Greenblatt does not remark

on the fact, there is positive evidence that Marlowe was familiar with Gorgias’s skeptical

formulation of a tragic epistemological distance between human discourse and its

referents.

In the opening lines of his first speech, Marlowe’s Doctor Faustus dismisses

Aristotle’s Analytics, and with it the art of logic, on the grounds that he has already

attained its end of disputing well:

A greater subject fitteth Faustus wit,

Bid Oncaymaeon farewell, Galen come,

Seeing, ubi desinit philosophus, ibi incipit medicus.

(Marlowe 1950: 164 [A text: 41-3])

As has been recognized for some decades, the italicized word in the second of these lines

is a transliteration of the Greek words on kai me on—and a direct quotation from one of

the first sentences of Gorgias’s On the Nonexistent or On Nature: “oute de to on estin …

oute to me on … oute to on kai me on …” (“[N]either does the existent exist nor the

nonexistent … nor the existent and nonexistent…” [Diels ii. 243, Sprague 43]).9 It seems

fitting, given the patterns of deception, self-deception and misreading which Marlowe

constructs in this play, that Faustus should dismiss Aristotelian logic with a tag, not from

9 Diels (ii. 243) supplies the missing particle in the last phrase: “oute to on kai {to} me on” (“nor the existent and {the} nonexistent”). One may suspect that its omission was deliberate, a Gorgian enallage.

Page 8: Ben Jonson’s Skeptical Friend: Gorgias in the English Renaissance

8

“Aristotles workes” (A text: 35), which he purports to be reading, but from a thinker who

was radically opposed to any such constructive project. (Only when Faustus moves on to

medicine, with two Latin quotations which one might think would be from Galen, does

he actually quote Aristotle [Marlowe 1991: 6].)

The fact that Marlowe quotes Gorgias in Greek is puzzling, since the Greek text

of Sextus Empiricus’s Adversus mathematicos, in which Gorgias’s On the Nonexistent is

preserved, was not printed until 1621 (Popkin 253 n.9). Marlowe may have encountered

the Gorgian tag in some now untraceable manuscript commonplace book. Or he might

possibly be back-translating from Hervet’s Latin text of Sextus—in a manner analogous

to what he does twenty-seven lines later in the same speech, when Faustus picks up

“Jerome’s Bible,” the Latin Vulgate, and reads two verses from it in a Latin differing

from the Vulgate text, which appears to be Marlowe’s own back-translation from an

English version, probably the Geneva Bible of 1560 (Marlowe 1991: 7). It seems more

likely, however, that Marlowe had access to a manuscript of the Greek text of Sextus

Empiricus, probably the one owned by Henry Savile, of Merton College, Oxford.10

Greenblatt’s intuition of a parallel between Marlowe’s dramatic rhetoric and a

Gorgian understanding of poetry as a form of power at once magical and deceptive raises

the possibility that Marlowe knew the Encomium of Helen. We are on somewhat firmer

ground if we speculate that, since the poet was apparently familiar (whether through the

Greek text of Sextus Empiricus’s Adversus mathematicos or through Hervet’s Latin

version) with Gorgias’s view of language as divorced from substantial reality, he may

have had some association with the dissemination of Pyrrhonist skepticism in late

sixteenth-century England. This dissemination included the circulation of an English

translation of Sextus Empiricus, to whom Thomas Nashe referred in 1591 as a thinker

“whose works [had been] latelie translated into English, for the benefit of unlearned

writers” (Nashe iii. 332).

10 The Sextus manuscript owned by Henry (subsequently Sir Henry) Savile (1549-1622) is preserved in the Bodleian Library (MS Savile 11), and another Greek manuscript of Sextus, owned by Isaac Casaubon, is held by the British Library (Royal MS 16D XIII); these two were the basis of Thomas Stanley’s 1659 English translation of the Outlines (see Hamlin 38). Marlowe would not have seen Casaubon’s manuscript, since that scholar moved to England only in 1610. Savile’s manuscript, however, may have been among those which he purchased during his travels on the continent in 1578; Marlowe could have been given access to it during (or after) his years at Cambridge.

Page 9: Ben Jonson’s Skeptical Friend: Gorgias in the English Renaissance

9

R. B. McKerrow, though he believed this English translation to have been lost,

was able to show that Nashe, despite his proud display of learning, made extended use of

it in his more than two dozen borrowings from Sextus, as did Samuel Rowlands in a

catch-penny tract entitled Greene’s Ghost Haunting Conycatchers (1602) (Nashe iv. 428-

31). However, the fact that Nashe and Rowlands fed their anecdotal mills with material

drawn only from Book I of the Outlines of Pyrrhonism may suggest that the translation

was quite limited in scope, and that Nashe’s plural reference to “works” must have been

either careless or misleading. This view is confirmed by William H. Hamlin’s recent

demonstration that the translation in question has actually survived, both in four

divergent manuscript versions, and also as Sir Walter Raleigh’s Sceptick, the lead text in

a volume of Ralegh’s literary remains that was printed by John Milton in 1651 (Hamlin

35-40). The different versions of The Sceptick, none of which is much more than three

thousand words in length, offer a slightly abbreviated translation of I. 40-98 and I. 129-30

of Sextus’s Outlines. According to Hamlin, the version used by Nashe was “in all

likelihood simply an earlier manuscript copy of The Sceptick than any of those now

extant” (Hamlin 36)—earlier, that is also to say, than the version from which the text

ascribed to Ralegh was printed.

Hamlin follows Pierre Lefranc in doubting that Ralegh himself translated The

Sceptick (see Hamlin 35 n.5, and Lefranc 48-49, 66-67, 427). One may suspect that it was

ascribed to him only because of the manuscript’s presence among his posthumous papers

—though in the absence of detailed comparative analysis of the surviving manuscripts

and the 1651 text, it remains possible that Ralegh could have done the translation, or

could have commissioned it from one or another of the writers whom he patronized.11

Whether The Sceptick was Ralegh’s through his own labour, through an appropriation of

commissioned work, or through the simple possession of a manuscript, it can in any case

be read as material that he made his own.

But by what means did this sample of Pyrrhonist skepticism reach him? Marlowe

and Nashe both knew of Sextus Empiricus; since they appear to have been not just

acquaintances, but literary collaborators, one can speculate that whichever one first made 11 According to Ben Jonson, The History of the World, published by Ralegh in 1614, is a patchwork of commissioned work: Jonson told Drummond of Hawthornden that Ralegh “esteemed more of fame than conscience / The best wits of England were Employed for making of his historie. Ben himself had written a piece to him of ye punick warre which he altered and set in his booke” (Jonson 1925-52: i. 138).

Page 10: Ben Jonson’s Skeptical Friend: Gorgias in the English Renaissance

10

such a find would have alerted the other.12 There exists more substantial evidence that

Marlowe communicated his own particular understanding of skepticism to Ralegh.

Their association, and the fact that the courtier-poet’s circle included several of

the playwright’s friends or acquaintances, is well known. Ralegh answered Marlowe’s

lyric “Come live with me and be my love” with his own “If all the world and love were

young”; moreover, their connection was attested to in the spring of 1593 by the claim of a

former government agent (as reported by an informer to the Privy Council) “that one

Marlowe is able to shewe more sounde reasons for Atheisme then any devine in Englande

is able to geve to prove devinitie & that Marloe tolde him that hee hath read the Atheist

lecture to Sr Walter Raliegh & others” (Boas 255).13

“Atheist” or not,14 Ralegh was of a skeptical turn of mind. One small sign of this

—and an indication that he was not above the labour of translation when it pleased him—

may be his rendering of the second line of a sonnet from Philippe Desportes’ Diane, in

which “l’erreur de mes yeux pleins de temerité” becomes “my daies of endles doubt”

(Ralegh 1962: 11, 107). More significantly, the Cerne Abbas commission of inquiry into

suspicions of atheism and apostasy in Ralegh’s household, which convened in March

1593/4, heard evidence that in conversation he had voiced doubt as to the nature of God

and the soul: “heitherunto in this pointe (to witt what the reasonable soule of man is) have

12 Nashe’s name appears below Marlowe’s on the title page of Dido Queen of Carthage (1594); see Marlowe 1968: xxi-xxv for suggestions as to possible traces of Nashe’s hand in the text. It is also possible that Nashe may have collaborated with Marlowe on Doctor Faustus, as author of one or more of the comic scenes (see Marlowe 1990: xviii-xix, xxi). As to the possibility that they shared reading enthusiasms and discoveries, it can be noted that in Doctor Faustus Marlowe shows signs of an attentive reading of the German humanist and occult philosopher Henricus Cornelius Agrippa (see Marlowe 1991: viii-ix, xlv-xlvi, 181-99), whom McKerrow identifies as one of Nashe’s favourite authors (Nashe v. 115, 118, 121, 123-24, 126, 134-35). But Agrippa is so obviously relevant to the subject of this play that there is no need to suppose that Nashe put Marlowe on to him. 13 Nicholl has speculated that this and other accusations against Marlowe were part of a campaign to discredit Ralegh conducted by agents of the Earl of Essex (Nicholl 291-301, 308-10, 322-23); this interpretation has been strongly challenged by Hammer. 14 The man who smeared Marlowe and Ralegh as “atheists” was himself accused by the same informer of describing the members of the Privy Council as “all Athiestes and Machiavillians” (Boas 254)—one sign of the freedom with which such terms were deployed in this period. “Atheism” was regularly deduced as the grounds out of which arose any disaffection from the state church, or any critical awareness of the manner in which religion served, in words attributed to Marlowe by another government informer, “to keep men in awe” (MacLure 37). Thus, for example, a doggerel response, attributed to the Earl of Essex, to Ralegh’s poem “The Lie” (in which Ralegh had bitterly denounced the self-deception and hypocrisy of church and state, deflating pretensions of zeal, honour, wisdom, justice, faith, and much else besides) declared it to have a “discent / … over base to tell; / to us it came from Italy, / to them it came from hell” (Ralegh 1962: 135). Ralegh, in other words, is identified as a Machiavellian and atheist.

Page 11: Ben Jonson’s Skeptical Friend: Gorgias in the English Renaissance

11

I not by anye benne resolved…. Neither coulde I lerne heitherunto what god is”

(Bakeless i. 133).

This report of Ralegh’s table-talk is at least partially confirmed—if one can speak

in this manner of a text published two decades later—by his Preface to The History of the

World (1614). Here, after quoting from Pierre Charron’s La Sagesse (1601, revised

edition 1604) a central statement of his and his master Michel de Montaigne’s Pyrrhonist

skepticism (“Tout[e] proposition humaine a autant d’authorit[é] que l’autre, si la raison

n’[e]n fait la difference; Euery humane proposition hath equall authoritie, if reason

makes not the difference” [Ralegh 1614: sig. D2v]), Ralegh challenges the dogmatic

assertiveness of Aristotle and his followers:

But for my selfe, I shall never bee perswaded, that GOD hath shut up

all light of Learning within the lanthorne of Aristotles braines…. That

these and these bee the causes of these and these effects, Time hath

taught us; and not reason: and so hath experience, without Art. The

Cheese-wife knoweth it as well as the Philosopher, that sowre Rennet

doth coagulate her milke into a curde. (sig. D2v)

He then proceeds to bring down the pride of a creature who is capable of

understanding neither nature nor himself:

But man, to cover his ignorance in the least things, who cannot give a

true reason for the Grasse under his feete, why it shoulde bee greene

rather than red, or of any other colour; that could never yet discover

the way and reason of Natures working …; that hath in his memory

but borrowed knowledge; in his understanding, nothing trulie; that is

ignorant of the Essence of his owne soule, and which the wisest of the

Naturalists (if Aristotle bee hee) could never so much as define, but by

the Action and effect, telling us what it workes (which all men know

as well as hee) but not what it is, which neither hee, nor any else, doth

know, but GOD that created it…. (Ralegh 1614: sig. D2v-D3)

The sequence of the argument is derived from Charron—and, through him, from

Montaigne, in whose “Apologie of Raymond Sebond” a critique of the inability of

Aristotle and many others to understand either the world, or the human soul by which its

Page 12: Ben Jonson’s Skeptical Friend: Gorgias in the English Renaissance

12

truths are purportedly known (“for [Aristotle] neither speaketh of the essence, nor of the

beginning, nor of the soules nature, but onely noteth the effects of it” [Montaigne 1904-

06: ii. 284]), follows directly upon Montaigne’s enunciation of the same principle that

Ralegh quotes:

Those that argue by presupposition, we must presuppose against them

the very same axiome which is disputed of. For, each humane

presupposition, and every invention, unlesse reason make a difference

of it, hath as much authority as another. So must they all be equally

balanced, and first the generall and those that tyrannize us.

(Montaigne 1904-06: ii. 281)

If questioning of this kind is “atheism”—an offense of which Montaigne himself

was posthumously accused (Popkin 63)—one may wonder whether Marlowe’s “atheist

lecture” perhaps amounted to little more than a sharing of skeptical resources. According

to the opening sentence of the Sextus Empiricus translation attributed to Ralegh, “The

Sceptick doth neither affirm nor deny any position, but doubteth of it, and opposeth his

reasons against that which is affirmed or denied to justify his not consenting” (Hamlin

42).15 The skeptic’s discursive strategy, then, is to subvert dogmatism through an

oppositional deployment of “contrarieties”—a term which, as William Hamlin acutely

observes, occurs in this translation, in Montaigne’s “Apologie of Raymond Sebond,” in

Ralegh’s Preface to The History of the World, and also in Richard Baines’ 1593

denunciation of Marlowe to the Privy Council (Hamlin 49 n. 48). It may be helpful to

compare these occurences of the term.

Montaigne wrote that “the Pyrrhonians,” should you side with their opinion, will

promptly “undertake to maintaine the contrarie” (Montaigne 1904-06: ii. 229)—a

procedure which he subsequently describes as a Socratic “science … of opposing” (ii.

237).16 Protagoras, he says, “told us pretty tales, when hee makes a man the measure of

all things,” but was “so contrary in himselfe, and one judgement so uncessantly

15 This sentence conflates elements from several statements in the early chapters of Sextus’s Outlines, including most notably the sentence translated by R. G. Bury as follows: “The main basic principle of the Sceptic system is that of opposing to every proposition an equal proposition; for we believe that as a consequence of this we end by ceasing to dogmatize” (Outlines I.12, Sextus Empiricus i. 9). 16 Montaigne’s French: “Si vous prenez la leur, [les Pyrrhoniens] prendront aussi volontiers la contraire à soustenir” (Montaigne 1962: i. 558); he later writes that “Socrate … dict n’avoir autre science que la science de s’opposer” (i. 565).

Page 13: Ben Jonson’s Skeptical Friend: Gorgias in the English Renaissance

13

subverting another,” that we cannot but “conclude the nullity of the Compasse and

Compasser” (ii. 304).17 The fact that we do not experience incitements “to contrarie and

resist” supposedly universal natural laws as a forceful violation, is one sign for

Montaigne that such laws do not exist (ii. 335).18 In human law, on the other hand, he

proposes that “any case admitting contrarietie” can be resolved only by an arbitrary

judgment (ii. 338).19 The Sceptick informs us, in similar terms, that “To believe what all

men say of one and the same thing is not possible, for then we shall believe

contrarieties…” (Hamlin 49); and Ralegh in his Preface declares that “there [is] nothing

wherein Nature so much triumpheth, as in dissimilitudes. From whence it commeth, that

there is found so great diversity of opinions; so strong a contrariety of inclinations … in

Mortall Men” (Ralegh 1614: sig. Av). Richard Baines, finally, claimed of Marlowe that

almost into every Company he Cometh he perswades men to Atheism

willing them not to be afeard of bugbeares and hobgoblins, and utterly

scorning both god and his ministers…. he saith likewise that he hath

quoted a number of Contrarieties out of the Scripture which he hath

given to some great men who in Convenient time shalbe named.

(MacLure 36)

But Baines has already hinted at the identity of one of these “great men”: earlier in the

document he declares that Marlowe “affirmeth that Moyses was but a Jugler & that one

Heriots being Sir W Raleighs man Can do more than he” (MacLure 36-37).

However reluctant one may be to trust in any way the word of an informer, it

seems plausible that the author of Tamburlaine, Doctor Faustus, The Jew of Malta, and

The Massacre at Paris should have given an anti-Christian twist to the tropes of

skepticism (a twist that Montaigne, Charron, and the other “nouveaux Pyrrhoniens” were

usually very careful to avoid). And although Ralegh, who read Charron’s French in the

early 1600s, could just as easily have read Montaigne’s French ten or fifteen years

17 Montaigne’s French: “Vrayement Protagoras nous en contoit de belles, faisant l’homme la mesure de toutes choses, … estant en soy si contraire et l’un jugement en subvertissant l’autre sans cesse, cette favorable proposition n’estoit qu’une risée qui nous menoit à conclurre par necessité la neantise du compas et du compasseur” (Montaigne 1962: i. 625). 18 If universal natural law existed, “non seulement toute nation, mais tout homme particulier, ressentiroit la force et la violence que luy feroit celuy qui le voudroit pousser au contraire de cette loy” (Montaigne 1962: i. 652). 19 The phrase in French is “quelque matiere agitée de plusieurs contrarietez” (Montaigne 1962: i. 655).

Page 14: Ben Jonson’s Skeptical Friend: Gorgias in the English Renaissance

14

previously, the surviving evidence suggests that he encountered skepticism in a

distinctively Marlovian form in the early 1590s—that is to say, in a form which

remembered the sophist Gorgias as an important precursor of the contrarian tropes of

Sextus Empiricus, and which also took the risk of deploying these corrosive skeptical

tropes against powerfully entrenched orthodoxies.

Let us ask, then, whether there existed a context within which, if Ralegh

encountered the Gorgian fragment on tragedy in the course of a reading of Plutarch, he

could have placed this witticism. Or, to be less indirect, could Ralegh himself have been

Jonson’s unidentified Philo, and author of the commendatory sonnet published with

Sejanus? I am not aware of solid grounds for a positive ascription.20 I would like to

conclude, nonetheless, by raising the teasing possibility of Ralegh’s authorship.

III

Ralegh had good reason to be amicably disposed towards the author of Sejanus.

The play’s first performances followed by a few weeks his conviction on a charge of

treason; and as Philip Ayres has shown, there are close parallels between Ralegh’s trial,

one of the most scandalously unjust in English legal history, and the trial of Caius Silius

in Act III of Sejanus (Jonson 1990: 16-22). Henry Lord Howard (created Earl of

Northampton by James I in 1603) had conducted from 1601 to 1603 a secret—and

formally treasonous—correspondence with the future king of England, in the course of

which he amply prejudiced him against Ralegh. In 1603 Northampton organized the

treason charges against his enemies Ralegh and Lord Cobham, and, with what his

Dictionary of National Biography entry calls “a stupendous want of principle,” served as

a commissioner for their trial (Jonson 1990: 18). Recognizing, no doubt, the similarities

between Ralegh’s ably conducted defense and Silius’s scornful dismissal of his

prosecutors’ “unkind handling, / Furious enforcing, most unjust presuming, / Malicious,

and manifold applying, / Foule wresting, and impossible constructions” (Sejanus III. 226-

29; Jonson 1925-52: iv. 400), Northampton summoned Jonson before the Privy Council

20 A much more substantial text would be required for a test of authorship by word frequencies to be meaningful.

Page 15: Ben Jonson’s Skeptical Friend: Gorgias in the English Renaissance

15

to face an accusation “both of popperie and treason” (Jonson 1925-52: i. 141). On that

occasion Jonson presumably defended his “integrity in the Story” by the same means as

in the 1605 quarto he was able to repel, with elaborate identifications of his

appropriations from Tacitus, Suetonius, Seneca and others, “those common Torturers,

that bring all wit to the Rack” (Jonson 1925-52: iv. 350).

Nine years later, in the preface to his anonymously published History of the

World, Ralegh in analogous fashion challenged from his place in the Tower of London

the interpretations of hostile readers:

It is enough for me (being in that state I am) to write of the eldest

times: wherein also why may it not be said, that in speaking of the

past, I point at the present, and taxe the vices of those that are yet

lyving, in their persons that are long since dead; and have it laid to

my charge. But this I cannot helpe, though innocent. And

certainely if there be any, that finding themselves spotted like the

Tigers of old time, shall finde fault with me for painting them over

a new; they shall therein accuse themselves justly, and me falsly.

(Ralegh 1614: sig. E4; cf. Patterson 138)

The commendatory sonnet written in 1605 by Jonson’s Friend participates in the same

discourse, though perhaps with greater complexity.

The first five lines of the sonnet, which translate the Gorgian paradox, enunciate a

doubled binary division: the “juster” poet who deceives is contrasted to those “who use

no wile,” and the wiser readers who submit to this deceit are contrasted to “such who can

eschewe thy cheat.” The poem then modifies this Gorgian scheme by bifurcating the

latter category: the dullards (“wary Simples”), who cannot be deceived or moved by

poetry, are distinguished from those “simple Elfes” who are so purely malicious “that

they will spy / Where later Times are in some speech enweav’d.” The readers of Jonson’s

play are thus divided into three categories—an act of division into contrarieties which

instantly undoes itself, since the newly introduced category of the malicious spy-reader,

upsetting the Gorgian symmetry, also overlaps with the category of the wiser reader to

which it is being opposed.

Page 16: Ben Jonson’s Skeptical Friend: Gorgias in the English Renaissance

16

The poem’s overt message is that malicious, spying readers are intruding into the

domain of poetic creation, where justice is properly correlated with deception; their

injustice makes them bad poets, whose deceptions will be credited only by themselves.

But there is nothing in the wording to suggest that they are actually mistaken in noticing

the weaving of current issues (“later Times”) into a drama supposedly set in the past—

even though wiser readers, those “who are of best conceat,” are apparently weaving past

and present together in a different fashion when they “suppose the Action now on file.”

This metaphor may make us pause: what precisely is meant by “now on file”?

Philip Ayres hesitantly glosses “on file” as “perhaps ‘in process’—a sense not given in

O.E.D.” (Jonson 1990: 68). Ayres’ guess is astute in a way the near-synonymous “under

way” would not have been, though he may be wrong in thinking that he cannot draw

support from the O.E.D. “Now on file” does, I believe, mean something like “in

process”—more particularly so if we hear punning overtones of a legal trial in the

expression. The O.E.D. defines “file,” in a now-obsolete sense, as “a string or wire, on

which papers and documents are strung for preservation and reference,” and especially

“one in a court of law to hold proceedings or documents in a cause” (sense 3.b.) The

figurative meaning of “file” as “the thread, course or tenor” of a narrative sequence is

illustrated by several citations: “We hang uppe this accusation also upon the file of your

other slaunderous lyes” (1581); “the file and dependance of the text” (1560-1); “the File

of my doleful Narration” (1612).

The action of Jonson’s play is thus “suppose[d]” by those of “best conceat” to be

locating itself within a coherent discursive sequence, as a document of relevance both to

current proceedings and to the formation of judgments about them. The difference

between good readers and malicious readers is therefore not so much one of

understanding as of ethical (and political) orientation. In Sejanus, the loyal Germanicans

and the spies and sycophants who accuse them and bring them down share a common

understanding of the power structure they inhabit, but act within it in diametrically

opposed ways. Similarly, the two categories of Jonson’s interpretatively active readers

recognize that current issues are woven into Sejanus His Fall, and understand the play

itself to be “on file” within the discourses that inform these issues. For one group, this

Page 17: Ben Jonson’s Skeptical Friend: Gorgias in the English Renaissance

17

recognition enables an informed judgment; for the other, it provides material for

accusations of sedition.

The sonnet, like the play which it praises, might thus be said to rehearse the same

dynamic of contrariety and aporia that is outlined by Montaigne in a passage from which

I have already quoted:

I have heard it reported of a Judge who, when he met with any

sharp conflict betweene Bartolus and Baldus [two celebrated

fourteenth-century legal authorities], or with any case admitting

contrarietie, was wont to write in the margin of his book, ‘A question

for a friend,’ which is to say, that the truth was so entangled and

disputable that in such a case he might favour which party he should

thinke good. (Montaigne 1904-06: ii. 338-39)

But there is also a clear difference. Montaigne puts this aporetic conclusion under some

pressure when he adds, in passing, that “The Advocates and Judges of our time find in all

cases byases too-too-many to fit them where they think good” (ii. 339). But the

commendatory sonnet, like Jonson’s play, superimposes upon the skeptical aporia a

reminder of the structures of political power that shape and condition immoral biases and

malicious misinterpretations.

It is piquant to think of Ralegh as author, from the Tower of London where he

was held under suspended sentence of death, of a commendatory sonnet which

simultaneously denies and reasserts the resonances between his own trial and that of

Silius in Jonson’s play. In the sonnet which he wrote in praise of Sir Arthur Gorges’s

translation of Lucan’s Pharsalia (1614), Ralegh condemns dissimulation: “Had Lucan

hid the truth to please the time, / He had beene too unworthy of thy Penne” (Ralegh 1962:

54); in the Sejanus sonnet he would be, not so much dissimulating, as inviting the reader,

whether loyal Germanican or malicious spy, to engage with him and with Ben Jonson in a

dangerous game of what George Gascoigne (another writer for whom, early in his career,

Ralegh had written commendatory verses) had called “supposes.”

Which is, come to think of it, an apt description both of the subject-matter and of

the interpretive procedures of this essay—for, in Gascoigne’s words, from the preface to

his translation of Ariosto’s I suppositi:

Page 18: Ben Jonson’s Skeptical Friend: Gorgias in the English Renaissance

18

Some percase will suppose we meane to occupie your eares with

sophisticall handling of subtle Suppositions. Some other will

suppose we go about to decipher unto you some queint conceiptes,

which hitherto have bene onely supposed as it were in

shadowes…. (Gascoigne B2v)

Works Cited

Aeschylus. Eschyle. Ed. and trans. Paul Mazon. 2 vols. Paris: Les Belles Lettres, 1920-

1925.

Aristotle. The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation. Ed.

Jonathan Barnes. 2 vols. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984.

Bakeless, John. The Tragicall History of Christopher Marlowe. 2 vols. 1942; rpt.

Hamden, Conn.: Archon Books, 1964.

Boas, F. S. Christopher Marlowe: A Biographical and Critical Study. Oxford: Clarendon

Press, 1940.

Calogero, Guido. “Gorgias and the Socratic Principle Nemo sua sponte peccat.” In

Sophistik. Ed. Carl Joachim Classen. Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche

Buchgesellschaft, 1976. 408-21.

Diels, Hermann, ed. Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker. 4th ed. 3 vols. Berlin:

Weidmannsche Buchhandlung, 1922.

Freeman, Kathleen, trans. Ancilla to the Pre-Socratic Philosophers. 1948; rpt.

Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1983.

Gascoigne, George. A Hundreth sundrie Flowres bounde up in one small Poesie. 1573;

facsimile rpt. Menston, Yorkshire: Scolar Press, 1970.

Greenblatt, Stephen. Renaissance Self-Fashioning: From More to Shakespeare. Chicago:

University of Chicago Press, 1980.

Page 19: Ben Jonson’s Skeptical Friend: Gorgias in the English Renaissance

19

Guthrie, W. K. C. The Sophists. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1971.

Hamlin, William M. “A Lost Translation Found? An Edition of The Sceptick (c. 1590)

Based on Extant Manuscripts [with text].” ELR 31 (Winter 2001): 34-51.

Hammer, Paul E. J. “A Reckoning Reframed: The ‘Murder’ of Christopher Marlowe

Revisited.” ELR 26.2 (Spring 1996): 225-42.

Jonson, Ben. Ben Jonson. Ed. C. H. Herford, Percy Simpson, Evelyn Simpson. 11 vols.

Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1925-1952.

----. Sejanus His Fall. Ed. Philip Ayres. The Revels Plays; Manchester and New York:

Manchester University Press, 1990.

Keefer, Michael. Lunar Perspectives: Field Notes from the Culture Wars. Toronto:

House of Anansi Press, 1996.

Kerferd, G. B. The Sophistic Movement. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981.

Kirk, G. S., and J. E. Raven., eds. and trans. The Pre-Socratic Philosophers. 1957; rpt.

Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977.

Lefranc, Pierre. Sir Walter Ralegh Écrivain. Laval: Armand Colin, 1968.

Lewis, C. S. English Literature in the Sixteenth Century, Excluding Drama. 1954; rpt.

London, Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press, 1973.

MacLure, Millar, ed. Marlowe: The Critical Heritage 1588-1896. London: Routledge &

Kegan Paul, 1979.

Marlowe, Christopher. Marlowe’s Doctor Faustus 1604-1616: Parallel Texts. Ed. W. W.

Greg. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1950.

----. Dido Queen of Carthage and The Massacre at Paris. Ed. H. J. Oliver. The Revels

Plays. London: Methuen, 1968.

----. The Complete Works of Christopher Marlowe. Vol. II: Dr Faustus. Ed. Roma Gill.

Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1990.

----. Christopher Marlowe’s Doctor Faustus: a 1604-version edition. Ed. Michael

Keefer. Peterborough, ON and Lewiston, NY: Broadview Press, 1991.

Montaigne, Michel de. The Essayes of Michael Lord of Montaigne. Trans. John Florio. 3

vols. London: Oxford University Press, 1904-06.

----. Essais. Ed. Maurice Rat. 2 vols. Paris: Éditions Garnier Frères, 1962.

Page 20: Ben Jonson’s Skeptical Friend: Gorgias in the English Renaissance

20

Nashe, Thomas. The Works of Thomas Nashe. Ed. Ronald B. McKerrow, with corrections

by F. P. Wilson. 5 vols. 1958; rpt. Oxford: Blackwell, 1966.

Nicholl, CharlesThe Reckoning: The Murder of Christopher Marlowe. 1992; rpt. London:

Picador, 1993.

Patterson, Annabel. Censorship and Interpretation: The Conditions of Reading and

Writing in Early Modern England. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1984.

Plato. The Republic. The Dialogues of Plato, vol. 4. Trans. Benjamin Jowett, ed. R. M.

Hare and D. A. Russell. London: Sphere Books, 1970.

Popkin, Richard H. The History of Skepticism from Erasmus to Spinoza. Berkeley:

University of California Press, 1979.

Poster, Carol. “Persuasion in an Empty Ontology: The Eleatic Synthesis of Philosophy,

Poetry, and Rhetoric.” Philosophy and Rhetoric 27.4 (1994): 277-99.

Ralegh, Sir Walter. The History of the World. London: Printed for Walter Burre, 1614.

----. Remains of Sir Walter Raleigh: Maxims of State, Advice to his Son, His Son’s Advice

to his Father, His Sceptick…. London: Printed for Henry Mortlock, 1702.

----. The Poems of Sir Walter Ralegh. Ed. Agnes M. C. Latham. 1951; rpt. London:

Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1962.

Riggs, David. The World of Christopher Marlowe. London: Faber and Faber, 2004.

Schmitt, C. B. “The Recovery of Ancient Skepticism in Modern Times.” In The Skeptical

Tradition. Ed. Myles Burnyeat. Berkeley, Los Angeles, London: University of

California Press, 1983. 225-51.

Sextus Empiricus. Sextus Empiricus. Ed. and trans. R. G. Bury. 4 vols. 1933; rpt.

London: Heinemann, and Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1967.

Sprague, Rosamond Kent, ed. The Older Sophists. Columbia, SC: University of South

Carolina Press, 1972.

Untersteiner, Mario. The Sophists. Trans. Kathleen Freeman. Oxford: Blackwell, 1954.