b10403-14

download b10403-14

of 17

Transcript of b10403-14

  • 7/28/2019 b10403-14

    1/17

    183

    13 PainismA New EthicsRichard Ryders MoralTheory and Its Limitations

    Hans Werner Ingensiep

    IntroductIon

    The British psychologist Richard D. Ryder (born 1940) is amous or his role as one

    o the pioneers o the modern animal liberation and animal rights movement. Ryder

    is well known or the introduction o new ethical ideas in the past 30 years and espe-

    cially or coining o the term speciesism, which he rst used in a privately printed

    leafet in Oxord 1970 and then in many subsequent publications (1,2). In Cavalieri

    contents

    Introduction ............................................................................................................ 183

    Can They Suer? ................................................................................................ 184

    Ryders Painism: A Middle Way between the Scylla o Utilitarianism and the

    Charybdis o Rights Theory? ................................................................................. 185

    Is Pain Necessary or Sucient or Moral Status? ................................................. 186

    Painism and Sentientism ........................................................................................ 187

    Hurting and Harming ............................................................................................. 188

    PainThe Only Evil? ............................................................................................ 188

    Pain in Nonhuman Others: SpeciesismNormative and Descriptive

    Dimensions ............................................................................................................ 189

    Species, Individuals, and Pain ................................................................................190

    PainismSome Applications and Questions ......................................................... 191

    Painism and Biotechnology ............................................................................... 191

    Painism and Environmental Ethics.................................................................... 191

    Painism and Plants ............................................................................................192

    Painism and Euthanasia ..................................................................................... 192

    Brain, Pain, Persistent Vegetative State, and Extreme Cases ............................ 193

    Who Is the Maximum Suerer? ......................................................................... 194

    Concerning the Vegetative Language about Human Beings beyond

    Sentience and Pain ............................................................................................ 195

    Conclusion .............................................................................................................196

    Acknowledgments .................................................................................................. 197

    Reerences .............................................................................................................. 197

    2011 by Taylor and Francis Group, LLC

  • 7/28/2019 b10403-14

    2/17

    184 Maldynia: Multidisciplinary Perspectives on the Illness of Chronic Pain

    and Singers Great Ape Project and other papers, Ryder argued or Sentientism

    (2) against the leading moral concepts emphasizing that only the capacity to eel

    pain is morally relevant. In 1990 Ryder coined the term Painism to describe A

    Modern Morality (35). For Ryder, pain is always pain o an individual and can-

    not be aggregated. Painism argues not only against the traditional anthropocentric

    personism based on qualia o persons like consciousness, intelligence, or rationality

    (e.g., Kant) but also against modern utilitarianism (6,7) and against an animal rights

    position based on an inherent value o each individual (8). Ryder, Singer, and Regan

    try to integrate pain into their ethical concepts in dierent ways. They all criticize

    the speciesism o traditional ethics and try to extend their approach to general ethics

    and politics.

    cAn they suer?These contemporary approaches to animal ethics and bioethics are the recent prod-

    ucts o a long historical and cultural debate in Western societies about the role o sen-

    tience, pain, and suering. Concerning animals, or instance, Plutarch or Montaigne

    inspired the discussion about Descartes concept o beasts as machines and led, in

    the Enlightenment, to extensive philosophical debates on animal pain that became an

    important ethical bridge between animals and humans (9). Pain, in general, played

    an important role in culture (10) and has also been recognized as a actor in the

    history o the modern sensibility (11) (e.g., concerning the problem o vivisection).

    While perhaps most amous is Jeremy Benthams crucial question in a ootnote:Can they suer? (12, p. 412), less known is the dictum o Humphry Primatt, one

    o the pioneers in animal ethics in the eighteenth century: Pain is painwhether it

    be inficted on man or beasts (13, p. 21). But, on the other hand, according to John

    Stuart Mill, it is better to be a human being dissatised than a pig satised (14,

    p. 18), indicating that there seems to be a dierent quality concerning pleasure and

    pain in animals and humans. These statements illustrating the ethical and cultural

    bridge between humans and animals are an important oundation or current eorts

    to integrate all sentient beings into general ethics.

    This chapter ocuses on ethical aspects and problems in Ryders Painism. Thereare many problems with the denitions and distinct boundaries or nonhuman organ-

    isms having a moral status within bioethics (15,16), and these give rise to conficts

    with traditional concepts o ethics (e.g., Kants deontology concerning animals and

    plants) (17,18). Kantian ethics seems to be a prototype or a deontologic personism

    that attracts reproaches oanthropocentrism and speciesism. Conversely, the new

    ethical model o an expanding circle (19) o entities having values or rights leads

    to boundary problems, reductions, and allacies in argumentation, and unicriterial

    approaches to what and why beings have moral status (16). In one respect, the new

    concept o painism seems to be such a reductionistic and unicriterial approach to eth-ics. Yet, pain and suering are important actors in modern bioethics (20,21), both

    in theory and practice (22,23). The patient with pain becomes the person dened

    by pain, as James Giordano points out the complex situation o pain as a disease

    process versus pain as an illness phenomenon (23, p. 407). In general, it is not easy

    to bridge the dualism o pain as a disease with objective maniestation, and pain as a

    2011 by Taylor and Francis Group, LLC

  • 7/28/2019 b10403-14

    3/17

    PainismA New Ethics 185

    subjective illness phenomenon. Far more dicult is the attempt to integrate all kinds

    o problems in human and nonhuman ethics (abortion, euthanasia, war, biotechnol-

    ogy, environmental protection, etc.) into a uniying concept o painism, as Ryder

    does. In order to connect these domains, Ryder uses the termpain in a very broad

    meaning. Nevertheless, he is able to knowledge the dierences and diculties o

    (the term)pain. Thus, he interprets pain broadly to include all negative experiences,

    that is to say, all orms o suering, mental as well as physical. So, the words pain

    and suering are interchangeable (5, p. 26). Only under these conditions is it

    possible to include moral problems related to sentient animals and humans within an

    expanding circle o beings having a moral status.

    I believe that it is important to consider some general philosophical aspects and

    questions regarding Ryders proposal o painism. First, a crucial systematic question

    or ethics: is pain necessary or sucient to establish moral status? I compare the

    three approaches o Singer, Regan, and Ryder to provide some insight to questionsconcerning the role o pain and speciesism in modern ethics. This question is not

    crucial or a pure biomedical ethics, where pain oten is subordinate to the prin-

    ciple o nonmalecience (24) and to the question Why do no harm? (25). But it is

    equally important to note that pain is not an important actor in nonhuman ethics o

    biocentrism or ecocentrism. As Warren thinks, the human and animal privilege o

    sel-consciousness, sentience, or pain, biocentric ethicists like Paul Taylor (26) could

    ask: why should the non-sentience o organisms automatically mean that a moral

    agent cannot have moral obligations towards them (16, p. 433)? From an anthro-

    pocentric, biocentric, or ecocentric point o view, ethics sentience and pain are notnecessary or a moral status.

    In light o this, I will discuss examples or the application o Ryders painism in

    applied ethics, human ethics, biotechnology, and environmental ethics. In particular,

    I look at borderline cases in medicine that illuminate an old thinking pattern about

    humans in a vegetative state as being beyond pain and sensibility. My question is:

    what kind o role does pain play in ethical judgements about persons sometimes

    called human vegetables (42)?

    In short, my thesis is that Ryders rame o painism is too narrow or a general

    theory o ethics. To build his argument, I compare Ryders painism with the posi-tions o Singer and Regan, and then deliver examples, exegesis, and criticism in

    more detail. The general problem is that an ethics reliant solely upon pain may be

    insucient, or perhaps at the very least, unsatisying. The most dicult question or

    psychologists and biologists seems to be: what is pain? And or painists: how ar does

    pain extend within the expanding circle o sentient beings? In sum, I ask i painism,

    as an unicriterial approach, is a useul starting point or ethics.

    ryders PAInIsm: A mIddle wAy between the scyllA o

    utIlItArIAnIsm And the chArybdIs o rIghts theory?

    A crucial question or ethicists seems to be: is pain necessary or sucient to estab-

    lish moral status? In answering the question, Ryder steers between the Scylla o

    Singers utilitarianism and the Charybdis o Regans rights theory. In common with

    Singer, Ryders painism holds that pain is a basic criterion. Ryders painism also

    2011 by Taylor and Francis Group, LLC

  • 7/28/2019 b10403-14

    4/17

    186 Maldynia: Multidisciplinary Perspectives on the Illness of Chronic Pain

    shares Regans emphasis on the individual and rejection o utilitarian aggregation.

    Ryder tries to nd a position in between and to establish painism as new morality or

    guiding the treatment o both humans and animals. Thus, he rejects the utilitarian

    justication o pain by Singer, i the aggregated benets o all those aected by the

    action outweigh the pain (5, p. 48). According to Ryders pain-based undamental-

    ism, pain is the only evil and the moral objective is to reduce the pain o others

    (5, p. 27). An aggregation o pains across individuals does not make sense. For each

    individual, only that individuals pain is real. For painists, pain within the same indi-

    vidual is paramount; thus, the quantity o pain suered by the maximum suerer

    matters ar more than the quantity o individuals eected (5, p. 28). For Ryder, this

    is an implication rom his rule: speciesism is always wrong and the aggregation

    o pains and pleasures across individuals is meaningless (5, p. 29). Ryder sets an

    example. Killing 100 people painlessly becomes less wrong than torturing one o

    them to death. For Ryder, the key question is: how much pain was experienced bythe individual who suered most (5, p. 28)?

    Against Regans rights theory, Ryder sees no clear justication o an inherent

    value and a undamental right to be treated with respect. Moreover, he criticizes

    the problem oprecedence in conficts when Regan says that the only thing that can

    override one right is another right. For Ryder, there is a problem with the hierar-

    chy o rights: Without such rules, rights theory has a hollow centre. When aced

    with conficting rights, which right do we choose (5, p. 48)? But the main ailure in

    Regans rights theory, Ryder points out, is its oundation in mysterious reerences to

    telos (purpose) or to intrinsic values (5, p. 50).

    Is PAIn necessAry or suIcIent or morAl stAtus?

    As mentioned, in a utilitarian approach to pain and pleasure, Benthams question

    Can they suer? is crucial. Pain and suering are the main antagonists o pleasure,

    and both are connected to the capacity or sentience. According to Warrens descrip-

    tion o Singers concept, this capacity is both necessary and sucient or having the

    same moral status applied to all sentient beings (16, p. 442). The argument is that only

    sentient beings can be cognitively aware o what happens to them, so that Althoughthe ability to experience pain is valuable to mobile organisms, serious pain is itsel a

    harm. Pain is an inherent evil to the being that experiences it, and pleasure an inher-

    ent good. Yet Warren objects to both strong sentience theory and a weaker version,

    because although sentience may be sucient or moral status o some organisms, it

    may not be necessary to instantiate moral regard or plants and nonsentient animals

    (as in biocentric or ecocentric approaches to ethics) (16, p. 443).

    In his Practical Ethics, Singers preerence utilitarianism describes three

    classes o living beings: sel-conscious beings like most adult humans, great apes,

    and perhaps other higher animals like whales, dogs, or cats; non-sel-conscious ani-mals like most birds or sh; and beings without any sentience like mollusks, micro-

    organisms, or plants. Singers concept guarantees primary moral status to persons

    with sel-consciousness; that is, they are guaranteed ull protection against being

    killed because o their uture options, interests, and preerences. This indicates that

    it is not necessary to have pain or moral status. In the second class, the case

    2011 by Taylor and Francis Group, LLC

  • 7/28/2019 b10403-14

    5/17

    PainismA New Ethics 187

    against killing is weaker (7, p. 132) because o the possibility that these animals

    could be killed painlessly such that the killing o non-sel-conscious animals may

    not be wrong, i they can be killed painlessly (7, p. 132). But this is only an argu-

    ment at the level o theoretical ethics, not o practice in animal arming or animal

    experimentation. The painless-replaceability argument indicates that moral statusor Singer allows painless killing i all interests are weighted and i the ethical cal-

    culation o interests leads to more pleasure in the world. Thus, sentience and pain

    are necessary to take these beings into account, but neither are sucient to protect

    them against being harmed or killed. The third class (beings without capacity or

    sentience and pain) o beings are, or Singer, morally irrelevant, and no necessity

    exists to take them into account.

    In summary, rom Singers point o view, either sentience or sel-consciousness

    is sucient to establish moral status. Thus, the capacity or pain is not necessary. A

    survey allows comparison o dierent positions and answers to the crucial question(see Table 13.1). Further embellishment o Ryders account will be provided later in

    this chapter.

    PAInIsm And sentIentIsm

    Ryder claims that Painism supersedes sentientism and explains why he rejects

    the earlier preerred term sentientism as a descriptor or his moral position (2,5,

    p. 34). The advantages o the new term are very dierent, in both principle, and on

    a pragmatic level. First is that sentientism might be deemed to reer to any sort oeeling or sensationor even to sentient beings incapable o experiencing pain at

    all (5, p. 34). He speculates that, or instance, lie-orms on other planets may have

    evolved systems in order to avoid danger without the subjective experience o pain.

    For Ryder, the subjective experience o pain is necessary and sucient regard-

    less as to who or what that experiences it; i one day painient machines may be

    produced, they, too, will become morally considerable (5, p. 34). Thus, or Ryder,

    the term individual includes all existing and uture systems that are capable o

    eeling pain. We must conclude that existing biological things, or instance, plants,

    or even uture iterations o machines or organic-synthetic chimerasi possess-ing the capacity or paincan be integrated in Ryders painism. Obviously, Ryder

    wants to avoid any kind o speciesism and a narrow concept o a moral circle, and

    thus preers the termpainism.

    The terms painism and painient seem to be more popular and easier to

    understand than sentientism, and pragmatically, these words useully ll some

    tAble 13.1

    I Pai na sfi ma sa?

    Pii I Pai na? I Pai sfi?Utilitarianism (Singer) No Yes

    Painism (Ryder) Yes Yes

    Rights Theory (Regan) No No

    2011 by Taylor and Francis Group, LLC

  • 7/28/2019 b10403-14

    6/17

    188 Maldynia: Multidisciplinary Perspectives on the Illness of Chronic Pain

    signicant gaps in the English language (5, p. 34). This is why Ryder rejects

    the termpathocentrism rom the Belgian Philosopher Johan Braeckman; its wider

    meaning inclusive o disease and emotion without any attendant pain becomes

    conusing. For Ryder, the capacity or pain is not only necessary but also sucient

    or conerring moral status.

    hurtIng And hArmIng

    Tom Regan attempts to elucidate the dierence between hurting and harming

    so as to allow ocus on the role o pain in his rights theory (27, p. 202). Regans

    assumption is that every subject o lie has dignity or an inherent value as an

    individual. Regan tells a ctional story about a scientist testing a new drug on chim-

    panzees, and argues against such research when anesthetics or other palliatives are

    not used to eliminate or reduce suering: to cause an animal to suer is to harmthat animalthat is to diminish that individual animals welare. But there may

    be an important dierence between harming and suering. An individuals wel-

    are can be diminished independently o causing him or her to suer, as when, or

    example, a young woman is reduced to a vegetable by painlessly administering a

    debilitating drug to her while she sleeps. According to Regan, harm has been done

    to her, although she did not suer. Not all harms hurt, in other words, just as not

    all hurts harm (27, p. 202). From his point o rights theory, this is a deprivation

    o individual reedom and lie, and it does not matter that this subject o lie has

    been killed humanely, without pain. This ction illustrates that pain is neithernecessary nor sucient or the moral status o individuals in Regans theory (see

    Table 13.1), rather, on the contrary, grounding ethics in pain (i.e. suering)as the

    only evil (5, p. 27) would be impossible or Regan.

    PAInthe only evIl?

    This brings us to address possible philosophical problems within Ryders concept

    o painism, and its connection to naturalism, Darwinism, neurocentrism, and inde-

    terminism. Ryder preers both a very broad concept o pain to include all kinds osuering and a very general concept o morality, which is only about the right

    and wrong treatment oothers (5, p. 4). This seems to be a morality without a

    ree moral agent who has responsibilities and duties, or instance, the duty to act

    morally. Here, he deaults to a reductive materialist stance in his claim that we are

    entirely the slaves o our brains and our ree will may be a product o unpre-

    dictable events at the quantum level (5, p. 51). Yet, he argues or a natural source o

    ethics: ethical standards are thus inspired by compassion, an innate compassion

    exists, and the history o ethics can be seen as an ever-expanding circle o compas-

    sion (5, pp. 15, 17, 62).For Ryder, to answer the question, why is pain bad? (5, p. 35), he states that pain is

    bad because it is badseemingly a circular answer. From this, he derives that a bad

    thing is that which causes pain, and so, morality derives rom this act (5, p. 36). I

    the moral premise o painism is based on acts or causes, it seems to be not ar rom a

    naturalistic allacy starting with natural or psychological acts (pain is bad) and then

    2011 by Taylor and Francis Group, LLC

  • 7/28/2019 b10403-14

    7/17

    PainismA New Ethics 189

    deriving value judgments or duties: or painists the primary duty is to alleviate pain,

    specically the pain o the greatest suerers (5, p. 37).

    There is a dierence between pain (at the physiological or psychological level) as

    a natural evil and pain as a moral evil. Toothache can be a physiological and psy-

    chological evil, but it is only a moral evil i the pain is induced by a moral agent, or

    instance, a torturer. Then we need another ethical criterion and a value judgement, or

    instance, that a person should be treated as an end in onesel (Kant). Ryder grounds

    his moral revolution in analogies between the crucial similarity o humans with

    other animals: rom this fows the conclusion that whatever is right or wrong in our

    treatment o other human beings is also right or wrong in our treatment o painient

    individuals o other species, however small they may be (5, p. 118). Despite the

    ambiguityor perhaps allacyo Ryders argument in structure, it is important to

    assess its content as relates to the value o pain in the moral consideration o both

    human and nonhuman others.

    PAIn In nonhumAn others: sPecIesIsm

    normAtIve And descrIPtIve dImensIons

    The term speciesism was introduced in the 1970s as a normative term in ethics and

    politics. For Ryder, this term is still very important to his concept o painism. A

    dierence in species is as morally irrelevant as are dierences in race, age or gen-

    der (5, p. 118). When introduced, the term speciesism also had a political unctionin the animal rights movement, to eliminate the unair conditions o animal mass

    arming and animal experiments in biological or medical research. Thus, it was cre-

    ated and mediated to prevent discrimination and to demand equal moral treatment

    and rights to humans and nonhumans. But the term has a theoretical background

    and a descriptive dimension as oten emphasized by Ryder, Singer, and others.

    Antispeciesism and painism belong to the moral implications o Darwinism

    and indicate that animals and humans are in the same moral category (5, p. 44).

    Darwinian evolution implies that the human species is but one o many species

    and that pain is the common enemy o all animal species (5, p. 45). In this con-text, species is used as a biological term with descriptive dimensions, and still we

    must consider that the term has been used to convey very dierent meanings in his-

    tory and contemporary biological contexts. For example, in pre-Darwinian times,

    species had sometimes been understood as an essentialistic logical, or ontological

    term. Ater Darwins Origin o Species, it became more o a classicatory unit or

    biological entities with special morphological, physiological, or genetic properties.

    There is a complex discussion in philosophy and evolutionary biology as to whether

    species reers to an individual or a set o organisms (28). Whatever species is, it is

    a theoretical concept in biology and not a normative term to engender judgementas oten used in applied ethics. As a descriptive term, it characterizes all kinds

    o organismshumans, animals, plants, and microorganisms. Thus, the biological

    term species is not restricted in its use.

    Does the reproach speciesism in modern ethics mean more than anthropo-

    centrism? It obviously does not, i speciesism is dened as in the Oxord English

    2011 by Taylor and Francis Group, LLC

  • 7/28/2019 b10403-14

    8/17

    190 Maldynia: Multidisciplinary Perspectives on the Illness of Chronic Pain

    Dictionary o 1985, as discrimination against or exploition o certain animal spe-

    cies by human beings, based on an assumption o mankinds superiority (5, p. 44).

    But rom the theoretical point o view, speciesism is not limited to homo sapiens

    sapiens but must be extended to all species o organisms that try to dominate others,

    or instance, when higher sentient animal species discriminate or exploit lower

    nonsentient animals or plants. In other words, i the principle regardless o spe-

    cies is introduced into ethics, it concerns all organisms, not only sentient animals

    as Ryder and others posit. From an evolutionary point o view, there is no reason to

    discriminate against any speciesthe continuity o the species does not allow us to

    draw discontinuous borders in organic nature. From this point o view, the border

    between painient and nonpainient individuals could be seen as arbitrary.

    sPecIes, IndIvIduAls, And PAInRyder asserts that Painism ocuses upon individuals and not on the conservation

    ospecies as a biological entity. He criticizes the anthropocentric and ethnocentric

    views o some environmentalists as irrational i they avor the extermination

    ospecies ooreign plants, which are not endemic in the ecosystem (5, p. 116).

    From his point o view, this seems to be a kind o speciesism and anthropocentric

    discrimination. Thus, this critique does not ollow rom his construct o painism,

    because painism does not include non-painient plant lie (5, p. 46). This makes

    clear the tension between speciesism and painism in Ryders concept. As well,

    the concept produces other diculties. Ryder maintains that moral standardsshould apply equally to all painient individuals regardless o species (5, p. 119). I

    regardless o species means only regardless o the human species and not o all

    species (including sentient animals), then we must recognize an inconsistent use

    o the biological term species. I regardless o species reers only to the human

    species, it is used as a normative political term and not as a biological term. In this

    case, it does not aord any deeper meaning than the notion oanthropocentrism in

    animal ethics. Why should we only consider painient individuals o some species?

    Is that not another version ospeciesism being asked by a collective o higher pain-

    ient animals with nervous systems? Ryders painism may render the same questionas raised by Heta and Matti Hyriwho is like us? (30). We should classiy this

    position as a orm o neurocentric speciesism. Yet, i we accept that pain is the

    only evil, and thus is oundation o ethics, why do we not have a duty to protect all

    victims o natural predators that kill painient animals or ood? I pain is the only

    quality upon which to establish moral status, we should prevent these evils in any

    circumstance. I know, this is not the intention o painism. But such considerations

    demonstrate that painism as a modern ethics must also acknowledge some orm o

    natural order i it is to be meaningul.

    I pain is a natural phenomenon and an arbitrary product o natural selection thatconers advantages or some species o higher animals, then painism can be seen as

    a new kind o zoocentric speciesism, i not a new naturalism. But the problem or

    ethicists is not pain as a natural phenomenon; the crucial question is whether pain, as

    a unicriterial approach, is a necessary and sucient starting point or ethics.

    2011 by Taylor and Francis Group, LLC

  • 7/28/2019 b10403-14

    9/17

    PainismA New Ethics 191

    PAInIsmsome APPlIcAtIons And questIons

    painismand bioteChnology

    Fred Giord begins an address on biotechnology with a ctitious dialogue aboutFootball Birds or Egg Machines created by agricultural science. These entities

    lack any ability to move and have no sensory input to the brain (31). Giord stated:

    The main issue might seem to be the way the animals are treated but in act no

    harm comes to the animals or they have no conscious experience o pain or stress

    So just what could be wrong about it (31, p. 197)? How would Ryders painism

    decide this question?

    For Ryder, it is surely, morally desirable to alter nature in certain ways. There

    is no moral objection per se against genetic engineering and cloning o designer

    organisms under the ollowing conditions: that the process o production entails no

    suering, that the produced individuals do not suer increased pain or distress

    due to their altered natures, and that such organisms do not cause harm to others

    (5, p. 114). Rather, Ryder explicitly welcomes the potential o genetic engineering to

    reduce the capacity or pain, i, or example, it becomes possible to produce people

    and animals with reduced painience. What a revolution this will be! Ultimately there

    is the prospect o a painless uture! (5, p. 114). In this case, Ryder expresses his

    anthropological utopia, a vision o a painless uture, and he speculates about the

    trick o eliminating pain on the one hand, and maintaining the eeling o joy and

    compassion on the other hand, so as to enable, i not ortiy, moral concern or oth-

    ers. But, as Giordano (32) noted, while an emphasis upon the capacity to eel pain

    may be essential to any moral regard or ethic, it is also important to recognize that

    the elimination o pain, in part or in whole, raises additional philosophical, ethical,

    and practical issues and concerns. These include the extent o pain that should be

    eliminated; in whom; by what criteria; and how the lack o painience might aect

    or alter notions o existential gain and loss, nonharm, and, ultimately, the regard and

    treatment o others.

    painismand enVironmental ethiCsRyders work indicates a distance and dierence between modern environmental

    ethics and painism. Modern environmentalism began earlier than animal ethics, but

    as Ryder points out, its philosophical basis is oten thin and anthropocentric, driven

    oten by assuming a sel-interest human or mystical quality concerning lie in

    general, including nonpainient plant lie (5, p. 46).

    Painism is grounded in the pain o individuals; the classical approaches o animal

    liberation, humanism, and environmentalism are subordinate to painism in that

    they give rise to compassion (5, p. 46). In this case, Ryders painism is similar to

    Singers preerence utilitarianism, where the environment is only relevant i sen-tient beings are concerned: as Singer asks, is there value beyond sentient beings?

    Once we abandon the interests o sentient creatures as our source o value, where do

    we nd value (7, p. 277)? For Ryder, it is not the utilitarian aggregation and calcula-

    tion, but only the existence o a maximum suerer, whether the suerer is an animal

    2011 by Taylor and Francis Group, LLC

  • 7/28/2019 b10403-14

    10/17

    192 Maldynia: Multidisciplinary Perspectives on the Illness of Chronic Pain

    or a human being. For both Ryder and Singer, plants have no value, no interest, and

    no right to moral regard because they are not capable o sentience or eeling pain.

    Thus, Ryder and Singer would oppose those environmental ethicist like J. Baird

    Callicott, Paul Taylor, or Christopher Stone, who argue or rights or respect or

    plants. For instance, Christopher Stone (33) argues or guardianship, legal rights,

    moral worth, and dignity o nonsentient beings like plants. Is this tenable within the

    context o painism?

    painismand plants

    Mary Anne Warren summarizes the skeptics position concerning plants in modern

    ethics: As ar as we can tell these organisms have neither sense organs nor nervous

    systems; and their behaviour rarely seems indicative o a capacity or pleasure or

    pain. Thus, while it is impossible to be absolutely certain that these organisms arenot sentient, it is a good bet that they are not (15). Here, Warren adressed Tompkins

    and Birds (34) Secret Lie o Plantsindeed a dubious concept rom a modern

    scientic point o view. But serious scientists organized the rst symposium on

    Plant Neurobiology in Florence in 2005, and the acknowledged plant physiologist

    Trewavas tried to deend plant intelligence (35,36) in a discussion about cell-to-cell

    communication by means o phytohormones as neurotransmitter-like substances, the

    role o electric membrane potentials, and ion channels, unctioning like brain pro-

    teins to orm plant synapses: actin-based domains or cell-to-cell communica-

    tion (37,38). I mention these theories and acts in order to point out the hypotheticalboundary o sentience o Ryders and Singers ethical position. I science would

    someday nd something like sentience orpain, it could initiate problems with plant

    experiments or vegetarianism. An ethical approach like Ryders cannot accommo-

    date environmental value and protection, but Singers can i it serves utility but is

    still neurocentric. I do not expect that plants can eel pain, but the hypothetical ques-

    tion clearly indicates that ethical theories like Ryders or Singers are ounded in

    zoocentrism and neurocentrism. In short, no nervous system, no sentience, no pain,

    no interests, no moral value, no rights.

    However, this kind o neurocentric approach may exclude not only plants romany moral status, but also humans beyond the boundary o sentience (e.g., patients

    in apersistent vegetative state sometimes called human vegetables) (see below). It is

    curious that the approach to environmental ethics advocated by Christopher Stone

    was just the other way around. I it is possible that human vegetables have rights,

    Stone concludes analogously that it is also possible or plants to have some type

    o moral status. He considers the case that legal guardianship is possible or both

    human vegetables and real vegetables (33). This consideration is not provided in

    Ryders painism; thereore, it becomes important to address painism in the context

    o euthanasia and concepts o negative states and human vegetables.

    painismand euthanasia

    Ryders treatment o euthanasia illuminates new aspects o painism and the role

    o pain in ethics. Ryder provides cases o brain-dead persons being used as organ

    2011 by Taylor and Francis Group, LLC

  • 7/28/2019 b10403-14

    11/17

    PainismA New Ethics 193

    donors, in which organs were removed without the use o anesthesia. This is dubi-

    ous because even a brain-dead person could have intact neural pathways that are

    activated by extreme stimulation. Such cases illustrate the call or the precaution-

    ary principle that, wherever painience is uncertain in a living animal it should be

    assumed to exist (5, p. 70).

    Yet, painism justies euthanasia, or nonhumans and those human cases where

    unconsciousness seems to be irreversible in accordance with some o the prior work

    o Callahan, such that Wherever death is perceived to be the greater good or lesser

    evil or the patient (except where there is evidence o specic opposition to eutha-

    nasia by that individual patient) then it should be allowed to proceed. Concerning

    passive euthanasia, Ryder maintains that I withholding anything causes pain or

    distress then it ought not to be done. The argument that suering does not matter

    because this patient is dying anyway is entirely irrational and deeply immoral (5).

    For Ryder, anesthesia, analgesia, and euthanasia should be developed, and discrimi-

    nation o age is irrational and wrong (5, p. 72).

    brain, pain, persistent VegetatiVe state, and extreme Cases

    This leads to other aspects and problems o painism as relates to extreme cases in

    human ethics. For example, what about persons near or beyond the boundary o sen-

    tience, such as in a persistent vegetative state (PVS)? Does pain play a role in this ethi-

    cal issue? According to Ryder, we must expect that even rudimentary pain guaranteesa moral status, but the question remains: what is the consequence? From the classical

    rame o the our principles (24), there oten is no clear answer possible because o

    the complexity o the situation. Sometimes it seems that principles o autonomy and

    justice dominate benecence and nonmalecence. With respect to extreme cases (like

    brain death or PVS), ethicists must consider whether burdens o treatment outweigh

    benets and that the principle o nonmalecience does not imply the maintenance

    o biological lie, nor does it require the initiation or continuation o treatment with-

    out regard to the patients pain, suering, and discomort (24, p. 135).

    In general, it is accepted that PVS is a orm o deep unconsciousness causedby ailed operations in the cortex responsible or activities that we recognize as

    specically human (39, p. 197). Nevertheless, the brain stem is still unctioning and

    controlling involuntary unctions. The crucial question in this context is whether

    PVS patients have pain. It is not easy to address, because it depends on the way in

    which we view pain (40). I we distinguish pain as a physical sensation, the response

    o the PVS patient to noxious stimuli would indicate that there is a physical response

    to pain or discomort but that the aective level o human suering is not present.

    Experience with such patients shows no behavioural indication o such suering

    (39, p. 205). Yet, Caplan admits that we have no way o knowing what is going on inthe mind o the unconscious person. I we could indeed establish that there is pain,

    and that there is, in act, considerable pain, then our answers might be quite dierent.

    That question, however, remains to be answered, although present consensus argues

    against the existence o such pain, mental or physical (39, p. 206). Even the issue o

    physical pain sometimes seems to be presented inconsistently.

    2011 by Taylor and Francis Group, LLC

  • 7/28/2019 b10403-14

    12/17

    194 Maldynia: Multidisciplinary Perspectives on the Illness of Chronic Pain

    In the PVS case o Nancy Cruzan, the State Supreme Court described her medi-

    cal condition as oblivious to her environment except or refex responses to sound

    and perhaps painul stimuli, suggesting that her highest cognitive brain unction

    is exhibited by her grimacing perhaps in recognition o ordinarily painul stimuli,

    indicating the experience o pain and apparent response to sound (39, p. 52). In this

    case, the Supreme Court considered best interest standards and declared that the

    burden o a prolonged lie measured by the experience o pain and suering mark-

    edly outweighed its satisactions; thereore, treatment could be terminated under a

    limited-objective standard (39, p. 48). This indicates the complexity o the situation

    but clearly stresses the burden o a prolonged lie rom the experience o pain and

    suering as an important actor in balancing dierent principles in ethical judge-

    ments about PVS.

    From the viewpoint o Ryders painism, two statements are relevant. The rst

    concerns the approach to euthanasia and brain death. Wherever painience is uncer-tain (as in the case o brain death), the precautionary principle conrms a duty

    not only to administer enough analgetics to remove all pain but also to administer

    all appropriate psychoactive drugsnot only to alleviate pain but to induce eupho-

    ria (5, p. 51). Is it ethically allowable to actively induce the dying process o a PVS

    patient whose lie could be extended several decades? This question leads back to the

    roots o Ryders painism and his engagement or the treatment o animals. As Ryder

    emphasizes, nonhuman euthanasia is accepted and justied in the West. In human

    cases like severe dementia, severe head injury, and whenever unconsciousness is

    expertly deemed to be irreversible, the moral case is similar (5). But what about thecases o dementia, PVS, brain death, and so orth? I the patient, signicant others,

    and kin would suer greater distress i euthanasia occurs than the distress they

    are already suering, then euthanasia is unethical, but i not, euthanasia should

    proceed. This statement sounds like a utilitarian weighting o interests on the basis

    o pain. However, i the patient has issued inormed directives regarding termination

    o lie support, then euthanasia is permissible. Ryder asked, Where is the ethical

    diculty (5, p. 71)? I hold that one diculty is the conusion o heterogeneous

    principles. In these cases, Ryder introduces the criterion respect or autonomy to

    solve ethical problems, but neither a utilitarian weighting o pain nor the principle oautonomy is justiable in a pure painism that is grounded solely on the presence o

    pain in human and nonhuman beings.

    who Is the mAxImum suerer?

    With respect to the important role o individual pain, we have to remember Ryders

    other basic statement: the moral objective is to reduce pains o others. But who are

    these others? Ryder rejects any aggregation o pains and pleasures across individu-

    als as is possible in utilitarianism (5, p. 27), claiming that The moral priority is totry to reduce the pain o the maximum suerer in each case and not to maximize

    the pleasure o all aected individuals. The number o individuals is irrelevant, but

    the aggregation o pain and pleasure in the same individual is meaningul. According

    to this rule, killing 100 people painlessly becomes less wrong than torturing one

    o them to death. This sentence indicates that there is no right to lie, protection

    2011 by Taylor and Francis Group, LLC

  • 7/28/2019 b10403-14

    13/17

    PainismA New Ethics 195

    o lie, or sanctity o lie in painism, per se. In this case, the question seems to

    be only: how much pain was experienced by the individual who suered most (5,

    p. 28)? This is a narrow monocriterial approach and leads to the question, who is the

    maximum suerer? For instance, rom the viewpoint o painism, i we know that a

    particular PVS patient (e.g., with no pain) has a dog who loves her, and who would

    pine i the PVS patient died, then it would be justied to keep the PVS patient alive

    to protect this animal as the potential maximum suerer, given Ryders rule that we

    try to act, thereore, as though human interests count or no more than nonhuman

    interests (5, p. 29). But here we see an apparent imbalance that touches moral senti-

    ments. Obviously, some clarication is needed i we are to take painism as a valid

    ethical construct.

    ConCerningthe VegetatiVe language about

    human beingsbeyond sentienCeand pain

    The ctitious case shows that animals count in painism, but nonpainient beings like

    plants do not. In this context, I would like to add an observation about the dierent

    language used to dene people in these borderline cases. Obviously, we use a spe-

    cial language to characterize natural beings that lack the capability or pain. This

    language is o bioethical relevance. For instance, the lie o humans in a persistent

    vegetative state has been compared with a vegetables lie, and in cases o brain death

    or dementia, oten we nd the statement that they vegetate. This kind o language

    includes descriptive and normative judgements. As mentioned, or Singer or Ryder,there exists no inherent or intrinsic value beyond the border o sentience (e.g., as in the

    case o plants). The moral status o plants seems to be similar to the situation o the

    PVS patients: I they have no experiences at all, and can never have any again, their

    lives have no intrinsic value. Their lies journey has come to an end. They are bio-

    logically alive, but not biographically (7, p. 191). In ordinary language, these persons

    sometimes are called human vegetables, and even the scientic term vegetative state

    contains an allusion to the plant metaphor. In Internet dialogues about the Schiavo

    case, the ollowing sentences appeared (March 20, 2005): (A) I would think the most

    oensive comparison would be comparing Terri to a piece o broccoli (B) A veg-etable, which she is, and courts and doctors have determined she is. I call this kind o

    language about human beings beyond sentience or pain vegetative language and here

    eel it is important to add a ew remarks rom historical and ethical points o view.

    A common assumption in this kind o vegetative language is that it reers to a

    state beyond sentience and pain. Since the end o the 1960s, discussions about brain

    death included the term human vegetable, and this has been criticized (41). The

    origins o this vegetative language derive rom the Aristotelian and scholastic term

    anima vegetativa, the vegetative soul, which is responsible or nutrition, growing,

    and propagation o organisms (42). According to Aristotle, all human beings possessa vegetative soul, but their telos is to live a rational lie. The telos o animals is to

    realize the capacities o a sensitive soul, including pleasure and pain. This tradition

    in metaphysics infuenced the introduction o the term vegetative nervous system in

    the early nineteenth century by the German physician Reil, which was then replaced

    in the English language by the term autonomous nervous system. Nevertheless,

    2011 by Taylor and Francis Group, LLC

  • 7/28/2019 b10403-14

    14/17

    196 Maldynia: Multidisciplinary Perspectives on the Illness of Chronic Pain

    Jennet and Plum still avored the new termpersistent vegetative state in their 1972

    paper, which has led to several misunderstandings. They wrote: the word vegetative

    itsel is not obscure: vegetate is dened in the Oxord English Dictionary (29, p. 76)

    as: to live a merely physical lie. But Jennett and Plum emphasized the point o

    being devoid o intellectual activity or social intercourse. As urther explanation,

    they added: It suggests even to the laymana limited and primitive responsiveness toexternal stimuli; to the doctor it is also a reminder that there is relative preservation

    o autonomic regulation o internal milieu (43, p. 736). This is a version o special

    language about a status beyond pain, but it suggests to both the layman and the physi-

    cian that there is no pain to consider.

    From a philosophical point o view, these vegetative terms and statements can

    allow one to recognize an ontological paradigm or the moral status o real vegeta-

    bles and human vegetables. In this context, only the ethical role o pain is important.

    Whatever is possible or impossible concerning the state o pain and suering o PVSpatients, it seems to be incorrect to describe the state o these patients by vegetative

    terminology. They are not plants, they do not live the lie o plants; rom a biologi-

    cal point o view, plants are completely dierent organisms than animals. Further, it

    remains an open question whether PVS patients have a biography, because it is pos-

    sible that some o these patients live in a border region with rudimentary cognition

    and pain (44).

    Thus, experts should be cautious when using this vegetative language in state-

    ments about people in borderline situations (e.g., PVS, brain death, dementia, or

    within the dying process), because this language can easily lead to a total misun-derstanding o the complex medical and ethical situation. The animal ethicist Tom

    Regan used this vegetative terminology merely as a ctitious analogy and metaphor

    to illustrate his view about hurting and harming a person who is killed in his or her

    sleep without pain. The environmentalist Christopher Stone used this vegetative lan-

    guage as a strategic analogy to deend rights or trees, corresponding to the rights or

    human vegetables as represented by their guardians. But or Peter Singer, it is more

    than a metaphor or strategy i he compares plants with humans who are beyond the

    border o pain. Here it is an essential ontological analogy, indicating a substantial

    parallelism o the moral status o plants and those patients in situations beyond sen-tience and pain. This is a kind o neurocentrism and zoocentrism, which now ollows

    the traditional speciesism in anthropology (45).

    conclusIon

    Richard Ryders painism is one o the more interesting concepts in modern bio-

    ethics, and indeed Ryder was an important thinker in the last 30 years. His term

    speciesism was inspiring or animal ethics. For Ryder, pain is necessary and su-

    cient to establish moral status. This monocriterial basis o ethics leads to sev-eral tensions with Ryders speciesism and allows only a narrow ramework or the

    solution o the dicult problems in modern environmental and biomedical ethics.

    Ryders painism provides no starting point or the principle o autonomy and or

    the protection o lie. Ryder emphasizes the aggregation o pain only within each

    individual, but rejects any aggregation o pain between individuals as utilitarianism

    2011 by Taylor and Francis Group, LLC

  • 7/28/2019 b10403-14

    15/17

    PainismA New Ethics 197

    does. This position leads to the question: who is the maximum suerer? When

    considering biotechnology, euthanasia, or PVS, principles other than pain are likely

    to be necessary to understand the complex situations and engage descriptive and

    normative judgments.

    Acknowledgments

    I would like to thank Virginia A. Sharpe, Heike Baranzke, and James Giordano or

    their helpul comments on earlier versions o this chapter.

    reerences

    1. Ryder, R. 1972. Experiments on animals. In:Animals, men and morals. An enquiry into

    maltreatment o non-humans, eds. S. Godlovitch, R. Godlovitch, and J. Harris, 4182.New York: Taplinger.

    2. Ryder, R.D. 1993. Sentientism. In: The Great Ape Project. Equality beyond humanity,

    eds. P. Cavalieri and P. Singer, 220222. London: Fourth Estate.

    3. Ryder, R.D. 1998. Painism. In: Encyclopedia o applied ethics, Vol. 3 (JR), ed. R.

    Chadwick, 415418. San Diego, CA: Academic Press.

    4. Ryder, R.D. 1999. Painism: Some moral rules or the civilized experimentator.

    Cambridge Quarterly o Healthcare Ethics 8: 3542.

    5. Ryder, R.D. 2001. Painism. A modern morality. London: Centaur Press.

    6. Singer, P. 1975/1990.Animal liberation (2nd ed.). New York: Review/Random House.

    7. Singer, P. 2005. Practical ethics (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.8. Regan, T. 1984. The case or animal rights. Berkeley: University o Caliornia Press.

    9. Ingensiep, H.W. 1996. Tierseele und tierethische Argumentationen in der deutschen

    philosophischen Literatur des 18. Jahrhunderts (The animal soul and arguments in ani-

    mal ethics in the German philosophical literature o the 18th century). International

    Journal o History and Ethics o Natural Sciences, Technology and Medicine. N.S. 4(2):

    103118.

    10. Morris, D.B. 1994. Geschichte des Schmerzes. Aus dem Amerikanischen von Ursula

    Gre. Frankurt am Main: Insel Verlag.

    11. Thomas, K. 1983.Man and the natural world. A history o the modern sensibility. New

    York: Pantheon Books.

    12. Bentham, J. 1948.A ragment on government with and introduction to the principles o

    morals and legislation (1789/1823), ed. W. Harrison. Oxord: Basil Blackwell.

    13. Primatt, H. 1992. The duty o mercy (1776/1834), ed. R.D. Ryder. Fontwell, West Sussex:

    The Kinship Library, Centaur Press.

    14. Mill, J.S. 1863/1895. The works o John Stuart Mill. III Utilitarianism (12th ed.).

    London: The New Universal Library, Routledge.

    15. Warren, M.A. 1997. Moral status: Obligations to persons and other living things.

    Oxord: Oxord University Press.

    16. Warren, M.A. 2003. Moral status. In:A companion to applied ethics, eds. R.G. Frey and

    C.H. Wellman, 439450. Malden, MA: Blackwell.

    17. Ingensiep, H.W. 1997. Personalismus, Sentientismus, BiozentrismGrenzprobleme

    der nicht-menschlichen Bioethik. (Personism, sentientism, biocentrismboundary

    problems in non-human bioethics). Theory in Bioscience 116: 169191.

    18. Baranzke, H. 2004. Does beast suering count or Kant: A contextual examination o

    Section 17 oThe Doctrine o Virtue.Essays in Philosophy. A Biannual Journal. 5(2):

    116.

    2011 by Taylor and Francis Group, LLC

  • 7/28/2019 b10403-14

    16/17

    198 Maldynia: Multidisciplinary Perspectives on the Illness of Chronic Pain

    19. Singer, P. 1981. The expanding circle. Ethics and sociobiology. Oxord: Clarendon

    Press.

    20. Cassel, E.J. 2004. Pain and suering. In:Encyclopedia o Bioethics, Vol. 4 (3rd ed.). ed.

    S.G. Post, 19611969. New York: MacMillan Reerence, Thomason Gale.

    21. McCloskey, H.J. 2001. Pain and suering. In: Encyclopedia o Ethics (2nd ed.). eds.L.C. Becker and C.B. Becker, 12691271. New York: Routledge.

    22. Giordano, J. 2006. Moral agency in pain medicine: Philosophy, practice and virtue. Pain

    Physician 9: 4146.

    23. Giordano, J. 2004. Pain research: Can paradigmatic expansion bridge the demands o

    medicine, scientic philosophy and ethics? Pain Physician 7: 407410.

    24. Beauchamp, T.L., and J.F. Childress. 2001. Principles o biomedical ethics (5th ed.).

    Oxord: Oxord University Press.

    25. Sharpe, V.A. 1997. Why do no harm? Theoretical Medicine 18: 197215.

    26. Taylor, P.W. 1986. Respect or nature. A theory o environmental ethics. New Jersey:

    Princeton University Press.

    27. Regan, T. 1993, Ill-gotten gains. In: The Great Ape Project. Equality beyond humanity,

    eds. P. Cavalieri and P. Singer, 194205. London: Fourth Estate.

    28. Wilkins, J.S. 2009. Species. A history o the idea. Berkeley: University o Caliornia

    Press.

    29. Oxord English Dictionary, the Compact Edition, Vol II PZ. 1971. Oxord: Oxord

    University Press.

    30. Hyri, H., and M. Hyri. 1993. Whos like us? In: The Great Ape Project. Equality

    beyond humanity, eds. P. Cavalieri and P. Singer, 173182. London: Fourth Estate.

    31. Giord, F. 2002. Biotechnology. In: Lie science ethics, ed. G. Comstock, 191224.

    Ames, IA: Iowa State Press.

    32. Giordano, J. 2010. From a neurophilosophy o pain to a neuroethics o pain care.In: Scientifc and philosophical perspectives in neuroethics, eds. J. Giordano and B.

    Gordijn, 172189. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    33. Stone, C. 1985. Should trees have standing? Revisited: How ar will law and morals

    reach? A pluralist perspective. Southern Caliornia Law Review 1154.

    34. Tompkins, P., and C. Bird. 1974. The secret lie o plants. London: Allen Lane.

    35. Trewavas, A. 2003. Aspects o plant intelligence.Ann Bot92: 120.

    36. Trewavas, A. 2004. Aspects o plant intelligence: An answer to Firn. Ann Bot 93:

    353357.

    37. Baluska, F., Volkmann, D., and D. Menzel. 2005. Plant synapses: Actin-based domains

    or cell-to-cell communication. Trend Plant Sci 10: 106111.38. Baluska, F., Mancuso, S., and D. Volkmann. 2006. Communication in plants: Neuronal

    aspects o plant lie. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.

    39. Caplan, A.L., McCartney, J. J., and D.S. Sisti. 2006. The case o Terri Schiavo. Amherst,

    NY: Prometheus Books.

    40. Giordano, J. 2009. Pain: Mind, meaning and medicine. Glen Falls, PA: PPM Press.

    41. Jonas, H. 1974. Against the stream: Comments on the denition and redenition o

    death. In: Philosophical essays, ed. H. Jonas, 132140. New Jersey: Prentice Hall.

    42. Ingensiep, H.W. 2006. Leben zwischen Vegetativ und Vegetieren. Zur historischen

    und ethischen Bedeutung der vegetativen Terminologie in der Wissenschats- und

    Alltagssprache. (Lie between vegetative and vegetate. Concerning the histori-

    cal and ethical meaning o the vegetative terminology in scientic and ordinary lan-

    guage). International Journal o History and Ethics o Natural Sciences, Technology

    and Medicine 14(2): 6576.

    43. Jennett, B., and F. Plum. 1972. Persistent vegetative state ater brain damages. The

    Lancet(April 1): 734737.

    2011 by Taylor and Francis Group, LLC

  • 7/28/2019 b10403-14

    17/17

    PainismA New Ethics 199

    44. Gupta, A., and J. Giordano. 2007. On the nature, assessment, and treatment o etal

    pain: Neurobiological bases, pragmatic issues and ethical concerns. Pain Physician 10:

    525532.

    45. Ingensiep, H.W. 2009. Speciesismos. In:Handbuch antrhopologie der menschzwischen

    natur, kultur und tecknik, eds. E. Bohlken and C. Thies, 418422. Stuttgart: Metzler.