Axtmann, philosophy, politics, carl schmitt,

download Axtmann, philosophy, politics, carl schmitt,

of 21

Transcript of Axtmann, philosophy, politics, carl schmitt,

  • 8/11/2019 Axtmann, philosophy, politics, carl schmitt,

    1/21

    Humanity or Enmity? Carl Schmitton International PoliticsRoland AxtmannDepartment of Politics and International Relations, School of Humanities, Swansea University,Wales, Singleton Park, Swansea SA2 8PP, UK.E-mail: [email protected]

    This article reviews Schmitts analysis of international politics from the period of

    the Weimar Republic to the early years of the German Federal Republic. Ithighlights the importance of Schmitts opposition to Woodrow Wilsons policiesand liberal universalism more generally for his understanding of and engagementwith international politics. Confronted with the decline of the state (the Ende derStaatlichkeit ), Schmitt develops a concept of the political that is not tied in with theexistence of the state. Schmitt embraces the fascist stato totalitario as a model for aqualitatively strong state and the distribution of the earth into hegemonicGrossra ume as the new nomos .International Politics (2007) 44, 531551. doi:10.1057/palgrave.ip.8800213

    Keywords: Carl Schmitt; humanity; enmity; the political; war; state; universalism

    Introduction: Carl Schmitt in his Time

    Still not a widely known figure in international relations theory, Carl Schmitthas come to be recognized as one of the most controversial as well as mostinfluential political thinkers of the 20th century. 1 Many political andintellectual critics and opponents of democracy in Germany took their

    arguments from Carl Schmitt. But as Jan-Werner Mu ller (2003) has recentlyshown, Schmitt has been a towering intellectual presence in post-war Europeanthought as well. Schmitts voluminous writings have produced thousands of items of interpretative literature, most of them in German, but also in Italian,Spanish and French with Anglo-American scholarship on Schmitt catchingup at great pace over the last two decades or so (Bendersky, 1983; Caldwell,1997; Dyzenhaus, 1997; McCormick, 1997; Cristi, 1998; Dyzenhaus, 1998;Mouffe, 1999; Scheuerman, 1999; Balakrishnan, 2000; Mu ller, 2003; Kennedy,2004).

    While there is no arguing about Schmitts centrality in conservative-nationalist and authoritarian-fascist thought past and present, the degree towhich his thinking has also influenced the democratic left, and the question asto the legitimacy of any incorporation of Schmitts thought into any left

    International Politics, 2007 , 44, (531551)r 2007 Palgrave Macmillan Ltd 1384-5748/07 $30.00

    www.palgrave-journals.com/ip

  • 8/11/2019 Axtmann, philosophy, politics, carl schmitt,

    2/21

    theory and politics, are highly controversial. Schmitt has rightly been perceivedto be one of the 20th century most profound critics of liberalism, and theliberal notions of democracy and of politics in particular. Since liberalism as anideology, theory and practice has been the be te noir of conservatism andsocialism alike since the 19th century and well into the second half of the 20thcentury, the endeavour of either side to draw on Schmitts arguments isunderstandable. A lively scholarly debate about the validity and merits of Schmitts critique of liberalism should therefore be no surprise. What hascaused disquiet, consternation and recrimination within the scholarly commu-nity is the fact that Schmitt developed his critique not from a position of dispassionate scholarly disengagement, as an intellectual endeavour of showingup the shortcomings of a particular theory, but as a committed politicalintellectual who did not only wish to critique liberalism but demolish thepolitical and social system to which it has given rise and bestowed legitimacy and who did not shy away to consort with the Nazis after 1933. It is thesituatedness of Schmitt the man and thinker in a concrete historical time andplace, the way in which he gave meaning to his world, the politicalconsequences that for him followed from his critique, and the anxious questionof those who find much to applaud in this critique as to whether it can beutilized for developing a non-authoritarian alternative to liberal society and

    democracy, that fan the heated debate. How best to deal with the ambiguouslegacy of this dangerous mind (Mu ller, 2003) exercises both politicallyengaged intellectuals and scholars.

    Born in 1888 and died in 1985, Schmitts life spanned four different politicalregimes in Germany, the Wilhelminian Reich, the Weimar Republic, NationalSocialism and the Federal Republic. In the Weimar Republic he moved within thehorizon of political Catholicism and supported the policies of Heinrich Bru ning,the leader of the Catholic Centre party. In the later years of the Weimar Republic,he argued for the parliamentary system to be replaced by a presidential system,

    advocating the use of presidential discretionary powers in cases of emergency toprotect the constitution against its critics. Once the Nazi had come to power, heaccommodated himself with the new regime quickly, publishing an infamousarticle in 1934 under the title The Fu hrer protects the Law (Fu hrer, 1934). 2 Hisfall from favour in 1936 brought to an end eventful 3 years in which Schmitt hadmoved into influential positions within higher education and the legal profession.Arrested in 1945 by the Allies but released without charge, he was not allowed toreturn to academia, but remained influential among the generation of legalscholars who had been socialized into the profession in the late 1920s and during

    the Nazi years as well as among a new post-war generation of law, political scienceand philosophy students, some of whom would achieve high positions within WestGerman society in the universities and in the legal profession, including judge inthe Constitutional Court (Laak, 2002).

    Roland AxtmannCarl Schmitt on International Politics

    532

    International Politics 2007 44

  • 8/11/2019 Axtmann, philosophy, politics, carl schmitt,

    3/21

    The title Schmitt gave to a collection of his essays in 1940 indicatesthe concrete historical situations to whose challenges he wanted to faceup, Positions and Concepts in the Struggle with Weimar, Geneva, and Versailles . Weimar stood for the new liberal-parliamentary regime whosefundamental problems of constitutional and political order, the problemsof sovereignty, legality and legitimacy had not been satisfactorily addressedand whose ambiguous embrace of liberalism had led to a misapprehensionof the true character of the political. Versailles signified the defeat in theFirst World War and the collapse of the Hohenzollern Empire, the ascriptionof war guilt to the German people and the imposition of reparation payments,the occupation of the Rhineland and revisionism. Geneva signified the riseof idealism in international politics and its concomitant moralization,the decisive ultimate step away from the ius publicum Europaeum thathad regulated the interaction of states for the last four hundred years or soto a new order whose contours were not yet clearly discernible. The emerg-ing new global constellation as a result of Germanys defeat in theSecond World War became a central concern in Schmitts writings after1945. If we wish to identify the focal point of reference for Schmitts thought,then it would be the experience and fate of the vanquished of 1918 and 1945(Willms, 1991).

    Just War or Just Peace: Schmitts Critical Engagement with WilsonianUniversalism

    My desire is y that America will come into the full light of the day when allknow that she puts human rights above all other rights and that her flag isthe flag not only of America but of humanity.

    Neutrality is no longer feasible or desirable where the peace of the world isinvolved and the freedom of its peoples, and the menace to that peace andfreedom lies in the existence of autocratic governments backed by organizedforce which is controlled wholly by their will, not by the will of their people.We are at the beginning of an age in which it will be insisted that the samestandards of conduct and of responsibility for wrong done shall be observedamong nations and their governments that are observed among theindividual citizens of civilized states.

    The readers of this journal are likely to know whose words have just beenquoted. The first quotation is taken from President Woodrow Wilsons

    Address on Independence Day in 1914. The second quote is a passage fromWilsons Address of 2 April 1917 in which he recommended the declaration of a state of war between the United States and the Imperial German government.At stake in this war, Wilson proclaimed, was the ultimate peace of the world,

    Roland AxtmannCarl Schmitt on International Politics

    533

    International Politics 2007 44

  • 8/11/2019 Axtmann, philosophy, politics, carl schmitt,

    4/21

    a world that had to be made safe for democracy. Clearly, a principle was atstake as well, namely, that the right is more precious than peace (in Scott,1918, 65, 281, 284, 287).

    Wilson asserted in his Address on the Conditions of Peace on 8 January 1918that this final war for human liberty had its only justification in upholdingthe principle of justice to all peoples and nationalities, and their right to live onequal terms of liberty and safety with one another, whether they be strong orweak. Upon this principle, the structure of international justice was founded.According to Wilsons 14 Points, acting on this principle required theacceptance of the principle of national self-determination, and hence theterritorial reconfiguration of Europe (and the colonial world). It also requiredthat a general association of nations be formed under specific covenants forthe purpose of affording mutual guarantees of political independence andterritorial integrity to great and small states alike (in Scott, 1918, 354363).

    To the extent that Wilson endorsed the notion of human rights, he embracedthe idea of an abstract humanity. To the extent that he argued for a league of nations whose members would be states great or small, Wilson accepted,rhetorically, the reality of a pluriverse of sovereign and hence, in legal terms,equal states and thus the reality of a politically differentiated humanity. To theextent that Wilson adhered to the idea that the only justification for war is its

    service to mankind or humanity, to democracy and human rights, tofreedom and justice and self-government, Wilson, in effect, upheld the notionthat a distinction must be made between just and unjust wars (in Scott, 1918,40, 50, 288, 316). In such just wars, remaining neutral was not an option.While, after a century of bloody wars, one may feel almost intuitively inclined to applaud these principles and the sentiments they express, thisenthusiasm may be somewhat dampened once one realizes that Wilson spokeabout this service to mankind and humanity also in connection with thedeployment of American troops in Mexico during the civil war situation in 1914.

    Carl Schmitts reflections on international politics took shape in hisconfrontation with Wilsonian ideology and the reality of Germanys defeat inthe First World War. These writings on international politics entwined polemicalpolitical commentary published in newspapers with scholarly historical analysis,concept formation and theory building. In the following presentation of Schmitts thinking on international politics, his scholarly endeavours will bestressed. But the reader should be aware that Schmitt understood these scholarlywritings as contributions to political debate and mobilization. This becomesimmediately clear when we reconstruct Schmitts discontent with the notion of

    humanity and universalism, as it was, for example, deployed by Wilson, at thelevel of conceptual analysis. Humanity, Schmitt asserted, is not a politicalconcept (Concept, 1932, 55). Let us reconstruct Schmitts concept of thepolitical in order to understand this statement.

    Roland AxtmannCarl Schmitt on International Politics

    534

    International Politics 2007 44

  • 8/11/2019 Axtmann, philosophy, politics, carl schmitt,

    5/21

    In 1927, Schmitt published an essay with the title The concept of thepolitical. In 1932, he published a much revised version of that essay. Inresponse to political developments and criticisms of this essay in particular,the criticism of Leo Strauss Schmitt put out a third edition in 1933 anedition which, later on, he pretended did not exist. 3 The specific politicaldistinction to which political actions and motives can be reduced is thatbetween friend and enemy (Concept, 1932, 2526). This distinction denotesthe utmost degree of intensity of a union or separation, of an association ordissociation (Concept, 1932, 2526). The political can derive its energy fromthe most varied human endeavours, from the religious, economic, moral,ethical and other antitheses. Every antithesis transforms itself into a politicalone if it is sufficiently strong to group human beings effectively according tofriend and enemy (Concept, 1932, 37). The quality of the political resides inthe decision through which the other, the stranger or alien, is declared tonegate ones own existence and is thus defined as being in a particularlyintense way existentially different, and hence an enemy against whom battlemust be waged, which may rightly and justifiably lead to the enemysextermination. After all, the political receives its real meaning precisely becauseit refers to the real possibility of physical killing.

    In the West, so Schmitt asserts, the state had become the bearer of the

    monopoly of political decision, the decision on who should be consideredfriend, who enemy. The state as the decisive political entity possesses anenormous power: the possibility of waging war and thereby publicly disposingof the lives of men. The jus belli [in the sense of jus ad bellum , RA] containssuch a disposition. It implies a double possibility: the right to demand from itsown members the readiness to die and unhesitatingly to kill enemies (Concept,1932, 46). War follows from enmity. It is the existential negation of the enemy(Concept, 1932, 33). We shall see later how Schmitt defined the quality of theenemy in the context of the bracketing of war in the ius publicum Europaeum as

    a hostis iustus and why he felt that this understanding had been finallyabandoned in the early 20th century. For our current concern, which rehearsesSchmitts argument about humanity as a non-political concept, oneconsequence of his conceptualization of the political must be stressed.Manifestly, for Schmitt, a people which exists politically cannot renounce theright to determine by itself and at its own risk who is friend and who enemy. Itcannot hand over this decision to a third party, nor may it allow itself to bebound in its decisions by ethical considerations that may take the form of justwar arguments. For Schmitt, war can only have an existential meaning:

    If physical destruction of human life does not occur out of the existentialassertion of ones own form of existence against an equally existentialnegation of this form, then it can simply not be justified. No war can be

    Roland AxtmannCarl Schmitt on International Politics

    535

    International Politics 2007 44

  • 8/11/2019 Axtmann, philosophy, politics, carl schmitt,

    6/21

    justified by ethical and juristic norms. If there really are enemies in theexistential sense as meant here, then it makes sense, but only political sense,to repel them physically and fight them if necessary. (Concept, 1932, 49;altered translation of German original [Begriff] on p. 50])

    According to Schmitt, the notions that postulate a just war usually serve apolitical purpose; indeed, following Hobbes, Schmitt suggested that theconviction of each side to possess the truth, the good, and the just bring aboutthe worst enmities (Concept, 1932, 65). One must not forget, Schmitt urged,that there always are concrete human groupings which fight other humangroupings in the name of justice, humanity, order, or peace. When being

    reproached for immorality and cynicism, the spectator of political phenomenacan always recognize in such reproaches a political weapon used in actualcombat (Concept, 1932, 67). 4

    Humanity is best understood as a political weapon so at least Schmittargued. Of the Wilsonian rhetoric of humanity, Schmitt was witheringlyscathing:

    When a state fights its political enemies in the name of humanity, it is not awar for the sake of humanity, but a war wherein a particular state seeks tousurp a universal concept against its military opponent. At the expense of its

    opponent, it tries to identify itself with humanity in the same way as one canmisuse peace, justice, progress, and civilization in order to claim these asones own and deny the same to the enemy. The concept of humanity is anespecially useful ideological instrument of imperialist expansion, and in itsethical-humanitarian form it is a specific vehicle of economic imperialism.Here one is reminded of a somewhat modified expression of Proudhons,whoever invokes humanity wants to cheat. To confiscate the wordhumanity, to invoke and monopolize such a term probably has certainincalculable effects, such as denying the enemy the quality of being human

    and declaring him to be an outlaw of humanity, and a war can thereby bedriven to the most extreme inhumanity (Concept, 1932, 54).

    War in the name of humanity does no longer know of an enemy, but only of adisturber of the peace and hence an outlaw of humanity. War is not perceivedas war, but as executions, sanction, punitive expeditions, pacifications,protection of treaties, international police, and measures to ensure peaceremain (Concept, 1932, 79). Humanity, for Schmitt, was thus seen as anasymmetrical concept since it contains the possibility of the deepestinequality: since everyone belongs to humanity, any discrimination withinhumanity by denying the quality of being human to a disturber or destroyer of peace means turning the negatively valued person into an unperson whose lifeis no longer the highest value but becomes worthless and must be destroyed

    Roland AxtmannCarl Schmitt on International Politics

    536

    International Politics 2007 44

  • 8/11/2019 Axtmann, philosophy, politics, carl schmitt,

    7/21

    (Legal Revolution, 1987, 88). It is this asymmetry that makes bestiality theflip-side of humanity.

    The reason why humanity is not a political concept for Schmitt will nowbe clear. Conceptually, the political is defined by the distinction of friend andenemy; the political character of an association presupposes the real existenceof an enemy and hence, of necessity, the coexistence of another political entity.The political world is thus a pluriverse, not a universe: A world state whichembraces the entire globe and all of humanity cannot exist (Concept, 1932,53). The concept of humanity, furthermore, excludes the concept of the enemyyet, the enemy does not cease to be a human being. Without this specificdifferentiation, humanity cannot acquire political qualities. After all,humanity as such cannot wage war because it has no enemy (Concept,1932, 54).

    The political nature of Schmitts definition of the political is apparent: theother is liberalism. He charged liberalism with evading or ignoring state andpolitics in a very systematic fashion, endeavouring to tie the political to theethical and subjugating it to economics. For liberalism, to whom the individualmust remain terminus a quo and terminus ad quem , the demand by the politicalentity that in case of need the individual must sacrifice his (or her) life isunconscionable: the individual as such has no enemy with whom he (or she)

    must enter into a life-and-death combat if he (or she) does not want to do so.What we therefore find in liberal thought, Schmitt asserted, is an entire systemof demilitarized and depoliticalized concepts. For example, political combatand battle becomes competition in the domain of economics and discussion inthe intellectual realm. The liberal denial of the political manifests itself in theinternational realm in the ideological conception of humanity (Concept, 1932,7072). 5

    Ius Belli and the Juridification of International Politics

    Schmitt situated his critique of the idea of just war and its resurgence in theearly 20th century within both a historical and systematic context. Theresurgence of the just war notion signified for him the end of the period of theius publicum Europaeum . Since the 16th century, this new ius inter gentes hadgradually replaced the medieval ius gentium of Latin Christendom as a result of a spatial revolution that came about through the formation of sovereignterritorial states in Europe and the colonial conquests of the European powers

    (Nomos, 1950, Part III). From Hobbes to Kant, the theorists of this newEuropean public law conceived of states as moral persons who among eachother live in the state of nature with each of them possessing the ius belli andwithout an institutional common supreme authority, a common legislator or

    Roland AxtmannCarl Schmitt on International Politics

    537

    International Politics 2007 44

  • 8/11/2019 Axtmann, philosophy, politics, carl schmitt,

    8/21

    common judge, but as sovereign entities which face each others as equals. Thissovereign equality is the core of the fundamental rights that states possess, anequal right of all states to self-determination, a right to existence and thus botha right to self-defence against attackers and a right to territorial integrity aswell as a right of liberium commercium (Nomos, 1950, Part III, chapter 1;Repetitorium, 1948/50, 728730). This ius inter gentes recognizes that the iussupremae decisionis regarding war lies with the independent states. They decideby and for themselves whether to conduct war and whether to remain neutralas a third party in wars fought between other states. According to Schmitt,war in this legal order has its justice in the fact that the combatants are stateswhich exercise their rights as sovereign political entities. When they fight eachother, they view each other as just enemies ( iusti hostes ), not as perpetrators of crimes against humanity or outlaws who must be destroyed (Neutralisierun-gen, 1939, 324). Wars needed no longer to be justified through iusta causaarguments as part of the (medieval) just war tradition; but enemies had to betreated justly and as equals. Schmitt asserts that conceptualizing the friend enemy distinction without any recourse to ethical theories of just war was theprerequisite for the bracketing, and thus civilizing, of war.

    This ius publicum Europaeum was in the process of being dismantled, andwith it its civilizational advances (Nomos, 1950, Part IV). The rhetoric of

    humanity, particularly when deployed in connection with the notion of justwar, tends to define the other as an enemy of humankind and as such evil,against whom the use of violence is ultimately just. The moral evaluations of combatants result in distinguishing between violent actions that are deemed tobe criminal and inhumane in some instances, whereas in other instances theyare seen as expressions of legality and legitimate punishment meted out in aninternational police action. According to Schmitt, this discriminatory conceptof war leads, of necessity, to the destruction of the institution of neutrality. It isheld that a state cannot be friendly to a state which is condemned as a

    disturber of the peace and at the same time have friendly relations with thestate which pursues military sanctions against that disturber in the name of world peace and humanity (Wendung/Kriegsbegriff, 1937/38). The peace-restoring state then has a legitimate claim to demand an answer to thequestion: Are you with us or are you against us?. Because just wararguments delegitimize neutrality, they result, according to Schmitt, in totalwar (Vae Neutris, 1938; Neutralisierungen, 1939, 323331; Neutralita t, 1938;Totaler Feind, 1937).

    Furthermore, the juridification of international politics had a detrimental

    impact. The Wilsonian idea that, just as in the domestic arena the rule of lawhad overcome the state of nature, so a universally binding system of enforceable legal norms would regulate international conflicts and thus endthe international state of nature, was fundamentally flawed. The political world

    Roland AxtmannCarl Schmitt on International Politics

    538

    International Politics 2007 44

  • 8/11/2019 Axtmann, philosophy, politics, carl schmitt,

    9/21

    was a pluriverse of heterogeneous and antagonistic political entities which(potentially) posed existential challenges to each other. Existential life-and-death conflicts are not amenable to legal containment or at least so Schmittargued. Juridification of international politics is unlikely ultimately to lead outof the state of nature or to contain the political. The Covenant of the Leagueof Nations did not eliminate the possibilities for war; indeed, it did sanctioncertain types of wars, such as coalition wars, against those enemies whoattempt to bring about changes to the territorial status quo (Art. 10). TheKellogg-Briand Pact of 1928, too, renounced war as an instrument of nationalpolicy and commits the signatories to settle all international disputes bypeaceful means (USA/Imperialismus, 1932/33, 362365; Nomos, 1950, Part IV,chapter 4b). But war as an instrument of international politics against thosepowers that disturb the status quo was permitted. War cannot altogether beoutlawed. What is being outlawed are specific individuals, peoples, states,classes, religions etc., which, by being outlawed, are declared to be the enemy(Concept, 1932, 5051). The friendenemy distinction is thus not abolished,but the decision on the distinction has acquired a specific kind of legitimacy,grounded, as it apparently is, in international law.

    Indeed, juridification is not limited to the elaboration of norms and attemptsto ensure their validity. Juridification must also have an answer to the question,

    Quis judicabit? Who decides on whether a war is just or not; whether certaintypes of actions involving the use of violence or force are to be defined as waror are better understood as means to safeguard and secure international peace?If an international organization such as the League of Nations is designated tomonopolize this decision, surely, Schmitt suggested, we all realize that the greatpowers, while proclaiming respect for the law on all occasions, will no doubtdecide for themselves what is to be considered law in a concrete instance?Schmitt did not doubt that the great powers will either exercise hegemoniccontrol over the international system with its legal order or establish a parallel,

    particularistic system of international law. Schmitt was adamant thatexperience showed that every great power resisted the charge of any of itsactions being understood as an attack, a threat to or a disturbance of peace. Itwas likely that a great power would either insist that its actions were aninternal matter in which one rejected any attempts of outside intervention orthat its actions were the opposite of attacks and threat, namely the execution of international law to safeguard peace (Kernfrage, 1924, 67, 13).

    In the case of the League of Nations, Schmitt identified a specific problem(Kernfrage, 1924, 1926; Vo lkerbund, 1930/31; Nomos, 1950, Part IV, chapter

    3). With its legal foundation in the Peace Treaties of 1918, the League of Nations was charged to ensure the stability of the international order in linewith the provisions of those treaties (e.g., Art. 10 of the Covenant). The juridification of interstate relations partly due to the legal conclusion of

    Roland AxtmannCarl Schmitt on International Politics

    539

    International Politics 2007 44

  • 8/11/2019 Axtmann, philosophy, politics, carl schmitt,

    10/21

    warfare through formal peace treaties, partly as the result of an endeavour fora positivistic-legal definition of just war privileges the legally defined statusquo . The logical consequence for Schmitt was a situation where everyone whowishes to change the status quo possibly because this status quo is notperceived to constitute a just peace is considered as a disturber of the peaceand an enemy against whom any punitive action is not war but legal execution(Status quo , 1925, 5859). The revisionist twist in Schmitts argument of 1925was, of course, that he defined those powers which wished to uphold (orentrench) the status quo as it was defined in the Peace Treaties as threats topeace rather than Germany. Yet there is the more general point to whichSchmitt alerts us: law is a political tool and presupposes a situation of normalcy which is often, however, contested. The juridification of internationalrelations cannot eliminate or replace the political with its distinction of friendand enemy.

    The End of the State and the Grossraum: Towards a New Nomos of theEarth?

    If war is inevitable in human history and, hence, eternal peace is a pipe-dream how can it be limited? For Schmitt, this was the overriding problem

    of international politics as he claimed at least in the preface to the newedition of Der Begriff des Politischen in 1963 (Begriff, 1963, 19). The sovereignequality of states was essential in this regard since it ensured the relativizationof enmity and guarded against a discriminatory concept of war that woulddistinguish between just wars, and thus just enemies, and unjust wars, andthus unjust enemies who should better be called criminals. Clearly, thepolitical background for this argument is Versailles and war guilt, and later on,Nuremberg and Tokyo and the war crimes tribunals. And to the extent thatSchmitt argued that the principle of sovereign equality had been violated in the

    Versailles dictate, he could use a principle of the ius publicum Europaeum(as he understood it) to argue the case for a revision of a treaty through which,according to Schmitt, Germany had suffered a wrong.

    Yet, for Schmitt, the invocation of the sovereign equality of states as asolution to the problem of limiting war became increasingly unconvincing. Thiswas for the simple reason that Schmitt thought that the era of the state wascoming to an end. As we saw before, for Schmitt the state was the monopolistof political decision. The state as political entity was the highest entity becauseit prevented all antagonistic groupings from developing the most extreme

    enmity, that is, from confronting each other in a civil war (Staatsethik, 1930,155, 160). However, for Schmitt the state had become the captive of socialgroups, a fact well understood in the pluralist theories of the state which weredeveloped since the late 19th century mainly in England by Maitland, Cole,

    Roland AxtmannCarl Schmitt on International Politics

    540

    International Politics 2007 44

  • 8/11/2019 Axtmann, philosophy, politics, carl schmitt,

    11/21

    Laski and others (Concept, 1932, 3945). In those theories, the state wasperceived as one association among other associations, rather than as the oneassociation above all the other associations. Without a clear supremacy therewas also no hierarchy of duties and a concurrent plurality of loyalties forindividuals.

    The societalization of the state was the result of democratization. Thedistinctions between state and economy, state and civil society withered awaysince political will formation had been appropriated by political parties whoseinterests and motives were essentially derived from economic needs andconcerns. All areas of life had become politicized, a total state had emergedthat could no longer discriminate and concerned itself with all kinds of affairs.But this state, of which the German state was a prime example, was total in apurely quantitative sense, in the sense of pure volume. This type of state mustclearly be set apart from the qualitatively total state. For Schmitt, writing in1932, Mussolinis fascist stato totalitario was the shining example of thequalitatively total state. According to Schmitt, this state can still discernbetween friends and enemies and does not allow forces inimical to it, or thosethat limit or divide it, to develop within its interior. This state is total in thesense of intensity and political energy, not, as the quantitatively total state, inthe sense of incapacity to resist social groupings.

    The total state thus exists in two distinct forms, as total state out of weakness, a state that has lost its monopoly of decision under the onslaught of parties and organized interests. This is the state of bourgeois-capitalist liberalsociety. The other kind of total state, exemplified in fascist Italy, is the totalstate out of strength, a state in tune with the potentialities of modernity:

    Every state is anxious to acquire the power needed to exercise its politicaldomination y Every state expanded its power by technological means,more precisely, by the technomilitary instruments of power y old notionsconcerning state power and the possibility of resisting it fade away y Theproliferation of technical means also allows for the possibility of mass propaganda y No state can afford to yield these new technical means of mass control, mass suggestion and the formation of public opinion to anopponent. The formula total state accurately describes the contemporarystates undreamt-of new means of coercion and possibilities of the greatestintensity (Strong State, 1932, 216217).

    It needed the fascist victory in Italy to establish the qualitatively total state asboth reality and ideal or so, at least, Schmitt argued in 1932 (Strong State

    (1932); see also, Wendung/Staat (1931) and Weiterentwicklung/Staat (1933);for fascism, Wesen/Werden, 1929).According to Schmitt, liberal universalism complemented from without

    what democratization had accomplished from within, the wholesale attack on

    Roland AxtmannCarl Schmitt on International Politics

    541

    International Politics 2007 44

  • 8/11/2019 Axtmann, philosophy, politics, carl schmitt,

    12/21

    state sovereignty. The crisis of the German state, for Schmitt, wasfundamentally linked to its position under the Versailles Treaty. The treatyhad turned Germany into a debtor nation and an outlaw state. Itssovereignty had been limited and parts of it had become an object of international politics, demilitarized and subject to external intervention, suchas the Rhineland (Objekt, 1925; Politische Lage, 1930). The Inter-AlliedCommissions of Control (Arts. 203206) for demilitarization and theReparation Commission (Art. 233) exercised key sovereign rights; and inArt. 213, a permanent right of investigation into German affairs wasestablished for the Council of the League of Nations. National self-determination, the mantra of Wilsonian rhetoric, clearly was not meant toapply to Germany. Rather than the German people being (or remaining)subject of its own political existence as a state, it had been turned into the exactopposite, an object (Objekt, 1925, 27). Schmitt suggested that, in the light of Britains policies towards Egypt, the United States towards the Caribbean,and Frances in the Middle East, Germanys treatment should be considerednot just within the context of defeat in war, but as an element within thedeveloping system of liberal imperialism.

    Schmitt analysed the US-American foreign policy as paradigmatic. TheMonroe Doctrine of 1823 possessed a genuine political character (Kernfrage,

    1926, 121126; USA/Imperialismus, 1932/33, 351355; Grossraum/Universa-lismus, 1939; Grossraumordnung, 1941; Nomos, 1950, Part IV, chapter 5). Itgrew out of a concern in both the United States and Britain that the Europeancontinental monarchical powers of the Holy Alliance would attempt to restoreSpains former colonies in Latin America, many of which had become newlyindependent states. The Doctrine rested on the political idea that the OldWorld and New World had different systems and had to remain distinctspheres. While recognizing existing colonies and dependencies in the WesternHemisphere, it declared that the United States would resist any future

    colonization in this sphere and would view any attempt by a European powerto oppress or control any state in the Western Hemisphere as a hostile act. Inreturn for the non-intervention of non-American powers in this space, theUnited States itself would abstain from any intervention outside this space.

    For Schmitt, the Monroe Doctrine, in perceiving the world as being dividedbetween continents and hemispheres, each with its own political order, for thefirst time expressed the idea of the Grossraum , a large territorial expanse inwhich alien powers had no right to intervene. This idea appealed to Schmitt,and he compared it favourably to the British Empire, a hotchpotch of

    heterogeneous possessions strewn over the surface of the world and without acoherent principle of political legitimacy (Balakrishnan, 2000, 238). ThisDoctrine legitimized the hegemonic control of the United States over theAmerican subcontinent. The Roosevelt Corollary of 1904 then claimed

    Roland AxtmannCarl Schmitt on International Politics

    542

    International Politics 2007 44

  • 8/11/2019 Axtmann, philosophy, politics, carl schmitt,

    13/21

    hemispheric police power by stating that, in cases of flagrant and chronicwrongdoing by a state within the space of the Western Hemisphere, the UnitedStates could intervene in the internal affairs of that state. This was a positionalready clearly articulated in the Platt Amendment of 1901 according to whichCuba had granted the United States the right to intervene to safeguard theindependence of Cuba and to keep in power a government that was capable of protecting life, property and personal freedoms and upholding public order aswell as ensuring that foreign financial demands would be met. Cuba was justone of a number of countries with which the United States concluded suchintervention treaties. The principle of non-intervention and hence thesovereignty of those states was, as a result, dislodged; the sovereign decisionas to whether there were grounds for intervention rested with the United States(Kernfrage, 1926, 122124).

    As a consequence of Woodrow Wilsons policy the spatialized system of non-intervention, that had been given justification in the Monroe Doctrine,was transformed into a universal, as it were, uprooted or de-localized,system of interventions [ raumlos allgemeines Einmischungssystem ]. Theideology of liberal democracy and the related ideas of free world trade anda free world market now replaced the geopolitical principle of the MonroeDoctrine, The Monroe Doctrine as a genuine doctrine of space is the explicit

    opposite to a space-neglecting transformation of the earth into an abstractworld and capital market (Grossraum/Universalismus, 1939, 336). Bydeclaring the compatibility of the Monroe Doctrine with the Covenant of the League of Nations (Art. 21), the universalist objectives of the United Statesbecame enshrined in international law. The League handed over de factopolitical sovereignty in the Americas to the United States, while allowing theUnited States an active role in shaping European politics, since the dependenceof the Latin American member states on the United States allowed it toexercise indirect influence without itself being a member of the League.

    When President Coolidge said in 1928, the year of the Kellogg-Briand-Pact,that an act of war in any part of the world is an act that injures the interests of my country, the universalistic interventionist orientation of the United Stateswas made quite explicit. The Stimson Doctrine of 1932 articulated the principleof non-recognition by the United States of international territorial changeseffected by force. Intend on continuing with the open door policy in China,the United States informed the Japanese after their military occupation of Manchuria, that it would not recognize any treaty or agreement y which mayimpair the treaty rights of the United States or its citizens in China, including

    those which relate to the sovereignty, the independence, or the territorial andadministrative integrity of the Republic of China, or the international policy toChina, commonly known as the open door policy. The door had now beenopened for US-American interventions around the globe.

    Roland AxtmannCarl Schmitt on International Politics

    543

    International Politics 2007 44

  • 8/11/2019 Axtmann, philosophy, politics, carl schmitt,

    14/21

    For Schmitt, writing in 1942, the reasons behind this development wereclear, the interests of world capitalism. These interests

    compel to pursue a policy of ever present, ubiquitous intervention and non-recognition, which presumes that Washington is entitled to approve ordisapprove of changes in any part of the world. The traditional distinctionbetween trade and politics as much trade as possible, as little politics aspossible has become inherently untrue because in the long run there canbe no world trade without world politics (Beschleuniger, 1942, 434).

    What had come to an end was a particular spatial order of the world, aparticular nomos of the earth. What we were witnessing, according toSchmitt, was a new spatial revolution.

    The nomos of the earth its appropriation, distribution and utilization sincethe age of discovery and European colonization was structured aroundglobal lines (Globale Linie, 1943; Nomos, 1950, Part II, chapter 1). The rayawas a distributional line that divided the newly discovered world on the basis of Pope Alexander Inter caetera divinae of 1494 between the Spanish andPortuguese. The amity line on the basis of the Peace of Cateau-Cambre sis of 1559 was an agonal line that divided the earth in a space in which the ius publicumEuropaeum obtained and intercourse between the European states was rule-

    governed and a space beyond the line where international law was suspendedand a kind of state of nature obtained. The Monroe Doctrine established a lineof self-isolation in the notion of the Western Hemisphere. The endeavours toground the spatial order of the earth took place just at the time when theformation of the state in Europe had ushered in a spatial revolution in Europe.

    For Schmitt, it was historically significant that this emerging Europeanworld order immediately broke up into land and sea (Land/Meer, 1981). Theland was divided into closed territories of sovereign states, whereas the searemained free of state or territorial sovereignty. This was the basic spatial

    premise out of which grew the ius publicum Europaeum . It meant that twodistinct types of war could be distinguished. On the one hand, land warbetween states was conducted by, and between, regular armies with a cleardistinction between combatants and non-combatants as well as with theprotection of private property. Out of these land wars arose the bracketing of war on the basis of a clear friendenemy distinction. War at sea, on the otherhand, did not recognize the distinction between combatants and civilpopulation. It knew the total enemy: the subjects of an enemy state as wellas everyone who engages in trade with the enemy and strengthens its economy

    are considered as enemies whose life, liberty and property are not protected(Souvera nita t/Meer, 1941, 407).The nomos of the earth since the 16th century was thus global but knew the

    dichotomy of land and sea. It was believed initially to have its legitimacy in the

    Roland AxtmannCarl Schmitt on International Politics

    544

    International Politics 2007 44

  • 8/11/2019 Axtmann, philosophy, politics, carl schmitt,

    15/21

    distinction between Christian and non-Christian peoples. Since the 18thcentury its legitimacy was grounded in the distinction between civilized anduncivilized peoples. While this distinction lost much of its force in the course of the 19th century despite the civilizational and racial (racist) notions of theWhite mans burden the idea of stages of civilizational development stillinformed the mandate system of the League of Nations (Art. 22).

    For Schmitt, the nomos of the ius publicum Europaeum had come to an end.The technological revolution of the means of transport and communicationhad shrunk the earth (Raumrevolution, 1940, 388). The conquest of air spacehas ushered in a new view of the earth, which overcomes the distinctionbetween land and sea and necessitates a new concept of space. Warfare in theair, and from the air, leads to a complete re-evaluation of land war and war atsea. It is in its very nature that warfare from the air can no longer distinguishbetween combatant and non-combatant (and may even find it difficult toseparate friend from enemy) and hence accelerates the trend towards totalwar, which is in any case propelled forward by the development of weapons of mass destruction. Ever more states, in the past the subjects of the ius publicumEuropaeum , lose their sovereignty as they become domestically captives of organized social interests and externally find themselves in manifold relation-ships of political and economic dependency (Kernfrage, 1926, 7879). For

    Schmitt, US-American and British endeavours of world control and worlddomination, the welding together of global capitalism and global intervention,aims for global unity. The Soviet Unions design for world revolution is but analternative form of planetary imperialism, not its potential nemesis. In eithercase, its legitimacy is seen to be grounded in the idea of humanity(Strukturwandel, 1943, 670).

    The situation that has arisen is characterized by a diremption of international law into two poles, a universalistic-imperialist, space-transcend-ing global law on the one side, and a pathetically state-fixated law of a space-

    constricting nature bound to small territorial spaces, on the other side. Seenfrom one pole, humanitarian interventions are considered legal in interna-tional law, but from the other pole, even the most minute intervention isconsidered a breach of international law (Raum/Grossraum, 1940, 251). Thepluriverse world of the modern territorial state, however, is irretrievably lost.A balkanized continental Europe, divided into micro-states or states withoutsovereignty cannot counter-balance the universalistic-imperialist powers(Raumrevolution, 1940, 390). If there was to be not just one master of theuniverse, then more was required than a revolt of the masters of the past, that

    is, the states. Genuine large territorial spaces [ Grossra ume ] alone would becapable of confronting the global powers. What was required, in a sense, wasthe embrace around the world of the idea of the Monroe Doctrine, the creationof large spatial expanses dominated by a regional hegemon which uphold the

    Roland AxtmannCarl Schmitt on International Politics

    545

    International Politics 2007 44

  • 8/11/2019 Axtmann, philosophy, politics, carl schmitt,

    16/21

    notion of non-intervention into its territory. Such Grossra ume , whosehistorical, economic and cultural substance frequently, though notexclusively of a vo lkisch nature amounts to a veritable degree of homogeneity, are truly in accordance with the new spatial dimensions andthe economic structure of the current age and are thus the carriers of realsovereignty (Kernfrage, 1926, 79; Probleme/Rheingebiet, 1928, 264; Raumre-volution, 1940, 390; Grossraumordnung, 1941; Strukturwandel, 1943).

    In his writings about Grossraum during the Second World War, Schmitt putforward the idea that there was, of necessity, a leading, hegemonic power, aReich , whose political idea radiated throughout the Grossraum and whichwould have the task to repel any intervention into that territorial space byoutside powers (Grossraumordnung, 1941, Sections V and VI). But on theterritory of the Grossraum , one would still find peoples organized in states butalso peoples which did not any longer have the organizational capacity forbuilding a state. However, the Reich ultimately dissolves the sovereignty of the states in concentrating the ius ad bellum in its hands and by enforcinghomogeneity as the prerequisite for a substantively grounded genuineGrossraum . The idea of an equality of sovereign states has been left behindand the argument has moved on to the idea of a pluriverse of sovereignGrossra ume and their equality as a prerequisite of stable peace (Ordnung, 1962,

    607).After the Second World War, Schmitt held fast to the idea of Grossra ume ,

    but in his publications did no longer pursue the idea of a necessary hegemon inthe form of a Reich . He queried the notion that technical and economicdevelopments would ultimately result in world unity. Neither did he accept,writing in 1951, that the bipolar division of the world in the cold war (but alsomanifested in a series of hot wars) would either continue to exist interminablyor result in an ultimate unity as one side defeats the other. Rather, he saw thevery real possibility of the emergence of an international balance of several

    Grossra ume (Einheit, 1951). Yet, in what the homogeneity of these Grossra umeshould be grounded, he would not spell out in his published work. 6

    Conclusion

    War and justice; peace and humanity: how to understand these concepts, theirrelationships and the reality they conceive has been at the centre of Schmittscritical engagement with liberal universalism. The invocation of humanity,

    Schmitt argues, is an ideological cover for power politics, while humanitycannot be a political concept in Schmitts definition of the political: the usesto which the concept is put are deeply political. Crusades in the name of humanity still remain wars, even if one prefers to speak of humanitarian

    Roland AxtmannCarl Schmitt on International Politics

    546

    International Politics 2007 44

  • 8/11/2019 Axtmann, philosophy, politics, carl schmitt,

    17/21

    interventions. To speak of justice, humanity and the shared interests of humankind opens up the possibility for an ethical discourse, which allows forthe moral damnation of the enemy as evil and, in extremis, its annihilation.The enemy becomes foe. In the mortal struggle between good and evil, therecan be no neutral third. A just war is a total war, everyone is party, no onebystander; and the just cause justifies use of whatever means must bedeployed to eradicate evil.

    If one wishes to accept Schmitts theses and the arguments he offers insupport, then one should be clear as to what it is one adopts, namely, aparticular kind of critique of the ideology of humanity and related concepts.However, one does not gain an armoury of arguments for peace. Rather, one isfortified for conducting war for the right reasons (as spelled out by Schmitt).After all, 9/11 and all that was a supremely Schmittian political moment, aclear distinction between friend and enemy and the actualized possibility of thephysical killing of the other. The ensuing total struggle against terroristsand partisans (or insurgents) abroad and the identification of the enemy athome (homeland security) epitomize the political. Arguing from aSchmittian position against the NATO intervention in the Kosovo, forexample, make it well-nigh impossible to argue against the war in Afghanistanor in Iraq. 7

    We encounter a similar dilemma with regard to Schmitts idea of theGrossraum . One may buy into the argument living, after all, one maybelieve, in the age of globalization about the end of the modern state andthe need for spatially larger territorial political entities, based on expansivesocial, economic and technological interdependencies and driven by a politicalwill. But the Schmittian concept of the Grossraum carries clear qualitativeconnotations; the Grossraum is grounded in homogeneity a unity in diversity,constructed, controlled and maintained by a hegemon. Hence, it needshierarchy and dominance within as well as military vigilance, the willingness to

    use violence, vis-a -vis the outside world. It thus needs the political will to definethe other. The new right in Europe has shown much willingness to elaboratethe logic of a Schmittian Grossraum (Holmes, 2000; Mu ller, 2003). It is quiteclear that a Schmittian Grossraum is not a zone of peace. Hitler, so Schmittthought, had got this right, too.

    Notes

    1 For a discussion of Carl Schmitt with reference to international relations, see, inter alia ,Scheuerman (1999, chapters 6 and 9) and Pichler (1998). For two early discussions of Schmitts

    writings on international politics, see Preuss (1935) and Herz (1939). Stirk (1999, 2003) putsSchmitts contributions to international law in the context of the intellectual debate and politicsof the Nazi era. For recent discussions of Schmitts opus magnum on international law andinternational politics, The Nomos of the Earth , see, for example, Antaki (2004), Koskenniemi

    Roland AxtmannCarl Schmitt on International Politics

    547

    International Politics 2007 44

  • 8/11/2019 Axtmann, philosophy, politics, carl schmitt,

    18/21

    (2004), Marramao (2000) and Scheuerman (2004). An interesting German study of Schmittswritings on Grossraum is Blindow (1999). See also: Kerve gan, 1999.

    2 References in the text to Schmitts writings are made in the form of abbreviated titles that arelisted in Part 1 of the bibliography with full bibliographical data.

    3 The first version of Der Begriff des Politischen has recently been reprinted in (Schmitt) Frieden(pp. 194239). For an excellent discussion of the substantial changes that Schmitt made to thistext in 1932, and those he made to the 1932 edition a year later, as well as the reasons for thesechanges, see Meier (1995). Unless otherwise noted, in this article, reference is made to the 1932edition (either in the German original or the English translation).

    4 Not much comfort here for just war philosophers. But if one wishes to find an intellectuallineage for George W. Bush and his war on terror, we should look primarily to Carl Schmitt and not to Leo Strauss.

    5 Schmitts concept of the political is not limited in its application to international politics. This

    becomes obvious when we observe what he has to say about democracy. Every actual democracy,he asserts, rests on the principle that not only are equals equal but unequals will not be treatedequally. Democracy requires, therefore, first homogeneity and second if the need arises elimination or eradication of heterogeneity. (Crisis, 1926, 9) And for Schmitt, homogeneityrefers above all to national homogeneity. The extermination and annihilation of the internalenemy in the interest of homogeneity and order is as important as combating the external enemy;indeed, without homogeneity the political unit will lose the capacity to make a sovereign decisionon who its enemies are and whether an existential threat obtains that needs to be fought.

    6 Over the last 20 years or so, Carl Schmitt has increasingly been discussed as a political theologian.Heinrich Meier (1995, 2004) has been the most vociferous and thoughtful advocate for a readingof Schmitts texts as political theology (but see, e.g., the critical assessment of Manemann, 2002).

    It would be a worthwhile endeavour to review Schmitts analyses of international politics on thebasis of the political theology hypothesis. In a letter to A lvaro dOrs in September 1951, Schmittrefers to his lecture on the Unity of the World and remarks: Anything but the Christian unity of the world would be the work of the Anti-Christ. As his references to the Anti-Christ and the Kat-echon, which one finds scattered throughout his work, indicate, Schmitt writes within the horizonof (an idiosyncratic) Christian eschatology (Briefwechsel, 2004, 119123).

    7 For a flavour of the debate on military intervention, and Kosovo and Iraq in particular, thatrefers to Schmitts position, see, for example, Ananiadis (2002); Chandler (2002); Rasch (2000);Stirk (2004); and Zolo (2002). See Habermas (2004) for a pronounced anti-Schmittian argument.

    References

    I. Books and Articles by Carl Schmitt :

    Articles. (1999) Four Articles, Edited, translated and with a Preface by Simona Draghici, Corvallis,OR: Plutarch Press.

    Begriff. (1963) Der Begriff des Politischen , (1932) Sixth edition of the text of 1932 with a prefaceand three corollaries, Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Beschleuniger. (1942) Beschleuniger wider Willen oder: Problematik der westlichen Hemispha re,in SGN, pp. 431440.

    Briefwechsel. (2004) Carl Schmitt und A lvaro dOrs , Briefwechsel, edited by M. Herrero, Berlin:Duncker & Humblot, 2004.

    Concept. (1932) The Concept of the Political , Translated and with an Introduction by GeorgeSchwab, Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 1996.

    Roland AxtmannCarl Schmitt on International Politics

    548

    International Politics 2007 44

  • 8/11/2019 Axtmann, philosophy, politics, carl schmitt,

    19/21

    Crisis. (1926) The Crisis of Parliamentary Democracy . E. Kennedy, (trans.) Cambridge, MA: MITPress, 1992.

    Einheit. (1951) Die Einheit der Welt, in Frieden, pp. 841871.Frieden. (2005) Frieden oder Pazifismus? Arbeiten zum Vo lkerrecht und zur internationalen Politik,

    19241978 , Edited and with a preface and notes by Gu nter Maschke, Berlin: Duncker &Humblot, 2005.

    Fu hrer. (1934) Der Fu hrer schu tzt das Recht, in PuB, pp. 227232.Globale Linie. (1943) Die letzte globale Linie, in SGN, pp. 441452.Grossraumordnung. (1941) Vo lkerrechtliche Grossraumordnung mit Interventionsverbot fu r

    raumfremde Ma chte. Ein Beitrag zum Reichsbegriff im Vo lkerrecht, in SGN, 4th edn., pp.269371.

    Grossraum/Universalismus. (1939) Grossraum gegen Universalismus, in PuB, pp. 335343.Holmes, D.R. (2000) Integral Europe. Fast-Capitalism, Multiculturalism, Neofascism , Princeton:

    Princeton University Press.Kernfrage. (1924) Die Kernfrage des Vo lkerbundes, in Frieden, pp. 125.Kernfrage. (1926) Die Kernfrage des Vo lkerbundes, in Frieden, pp. 73193.Land/Meer. (1981) Land und Meer. Eine weltgeschichtliche Betrachtung , Hohenheim: Edition

    Maschke (English edition: Land and Sea . Translated and with a foreword by Simona Draghici,Corvallis, OR: Plutarch Press, 1997).

    Legal Revolution. (1987) The Legal World Revolution, Telos 72: 7390.Neutralita t. (1938) Vo lkerrechtliche Neutralita t und vo lkische Totalita t, in Frieden, pp. 617628

    (English text in Articles , pp. 3745.).Neutralisierungen. (1939) Neutralita t und Neutralisierungen, in PuB, pp. 309334.Nomos. (1950) Der Nomos der Erde im Vo lkerrecht des Jus Publicum Europaeum , 4th edn., Berlin:

    Duncker & Humblot, 1997 (English edition: Nomos of the Earth in the International Law of JusPublicum Europaeum , New York: Telos Press, 2003).

    Objekt. (1925) Die Rheinlande als Objekt internationaler Politik, in Frieden, pp. 2650.Ordnung. (1962) Die Ordnung der Welt nach dem Zweiten Weltkrieg, in SGN, pp. 592618.Politische Lage. (1930) Die politische Lage der entmilitarisierten Rheinlande, in Frieden, pp.

    274280.Probleme/Rheingebiet. (1928) Vo lkerrechtliche Probleme im Rheingebiet, in Frieden, pp.

    255273.PuB. (1940) Positionen und Begriffe im Kampf mit Weimar Genf Versailles, 19231939 , 3rd

    edn., Berlin: Duncker & Humblot, 1988.Raum/Grossraum. (1940) Raum und Grossraum im Vo lkerrecht, in SGN, pp. 234268.

    Raumrevolution. (1940) Die Raumrevolution. Durch den totalen Krieg zu einem totalen Frieden,in SGN, pp. 388394.

    Repetitorium. (1948/50) Vo lkerrecht [Ein juristische Repetitorium], in Frieden, pp. 701840.SGN. Staat, Grossraum, Nomos. Arbeiten aus den Jahren 19161969 , Edited and with a preface and

    notes by Gu nter Maschke, Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.Souvera nita t/Meer. (1941) Staatliche Souvera nita t und freies Meer. U ber den Gegensatz von Land

    und See im Vo lkerrecht der Neuzeit, in SGN, pp. 401430.Staatsethik. (1930) Staatsethik und pluralistischer Staat, in PuB, pp. 151165 (English text: Ethic

    of State and Pluralistic State in C. Mouffe (ed.), The Challenge of Carl Schmitt , London: Verso,1999).

    Status quo. (1925) Der Status quo und der Friede, in Frieden, pp. 5172.

    Strong state. (1932) Strong State and Sound Economy: An Address to Business Leaders, inR. Cristi (ed.) Carl Schmitt and Authoritarian Liberalism , Cardiff: University of Wales Press,1998, pp. 212232 (German original text with the title: Starker Staat und gesunde Wirtschaft inSGN, pp. 7191).

    Roland AxtmannCarl Schmitt on International Politics

    549

    International Politics 2007 44

  • 8/11/2019 Axtmann, philosophy, politics, carl schmitt,

    20/21

    Strukturwandel. (1943) Strukturwandel des International Rechts, in Frieden, pp. 652700.Totaler Feind. (1937) Totaler Feind, totaler Krieg, totaler Staat, in Frieden, pp. 481507 (English

    text: Total Enemy, Total War and Total State in Articles, pp. 2836.).USA/Imperialismus. (1932/33) USA und die vo lkerrechtlichen Formen des modernen Imper-

    ialismus, in Frieden, pp. 349377.Vae Neutris. (1938) Das neue Vae Neutris!, in Frieden, pp. 612616.Vo lkerbund. (1930/31) Der Vo lkerbund, in Frieden, pp. 333348.Weiterentwicklung/Staat. (1933) Weiterentwicklung des totalen Staates in Deutschland, in PuB,

    pp. 211216 (English text: Further Development of the Total State in Germany, in Articles, pp.1927).

    Wendung/Kriegsbegriff. (1937/38) Die Wendung zum diskriminierenden Kriegsbegriff, inFrieden, pp. 518597 (English edition: War/Non-War? A Dilemma, ed. and translated bySimona Draghici, Corvallis, OR: Plutarch Press, 2004).

    Wendung/Staat. (1931) Die Wendung zum totalen Staat, in PuB, pp. 166178 (English text: TheWay to the Total State, in Articles, pp. 118).

    Wesen/Werden. (1929) Wesen und Werden des faschistischen Staates, in PuB, pp. 124130.

    II. Secondary Literature

    Ananiadis, G. (2002) Carl Schmitt on Kosovo, or, Taking War Seriously, in D.I. Bjelic andO. Savic (eds.) Balkan as Metaphor. Between Globalization and Fragmentation , Cambridge, MA:The MIT Press, pp. 117161.

    Antaki, M. (2004) Carl Schmitts Nomos of the Earth , Osgoode Hall Law Journal 42(2): 317334.Balakrishnan, G. (2000) The Enemy. An Intellectual Portrait of Carl Schmitt , London: Verso.

    Bendersky, J. (1983) Carl Schmitt: Theorist for the Reich , Princeton: Princeton University Press.Blindow, F. (1999) Carl Schmitts Reichsgru ndung: Strategie fu r einen europa ischen Grossraum ,

    Berlin: Akademie Verlag.Caldwell, P.C. (1997) Popular Sovereignty and the Crisis of German Constitutional Law. The Theory

    and Practice of Weimar Constitutionalism , Durham and London: Duke University Press.Chandler, D. (2002) From Kosovo to Kabul: Human Rights and International Intervention , London:

    Pluto Press.Cristi, R. (1998) Carl Schmitt and Authoritarian Liberalism , Cardiff: University of Wales Press.Dyzenhaus, D. (1997) Legality and Legitimacy: Carl Schmitt, Hans Kelsen and Hermann Heller in

    Weimar , Oxford: Clarendon Press.Dyzenhaus, D. (ed.) (1998) Law as Politics. Carl Schmitts Critique of Liberalism , Durham and

    London: Duke University Press.Habermas, J. (2004) Hat die Konstitutionalisierung des Vo lkerrechts noch eine Chance?, in

    J. Habermas (id.) Der gespaltene Westen , Frankfurt a. M.: Suhrkamp Verlag, pp. 113193.Herz, J.H. (1939) The National Socialist Doctrine of International Law and the Problem of

    International Organization, Political Science Quarterly 54(4): 536554.Kerve gan, J.-F. (1999) Carl Schmitt and World Unity, in C. Mouffe (ed.) The Challenge of Carl

    Schmitt , London: Verso, pp. 5473.Kennedy, E. (2004) Constitutional Failure. Carl Schmitt in Weimar , Durham and London: Duke

    University Press.Koskenniemi, M. (2004) International Law as Political Theology: How to Read Nomos der Erde ?

    Constellations 11(4): 492511.

    Laak, Dirk van (2002) Gespra che in der Sicherheit des Schweigens. Carl Schmitt in der politischenGeistesgeschichte der fru hen Bundesrepublik , Berlin: Akademie Verlag.

    Manemann, J. (2002) Carl Schmitt und die Politische Theologie. Politischer Anti-Monotheismus ,Mu nster: Aschendorff Verlag.

    Roland AxtmannCarl Schmitt on International Politics

    550

    International Politics 2007 44

  • 8/11/2019 Axtmann, philosophy, politics, carl schmitt,

    21/21

    Marramao, G. (2000) The Exile of the Nomos : For a Critical Profile of Carl Schmitt, Cardozo LawReview 21: 15671586.

    McCormick, J.P. (1997) Carl Schmitts Critique of Liberalism. Against Politics as Technology ,Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Meier, H. (1995) Carl Schmitt and Leo Strauss. The Hidden Dialogue , Chicago and London:University of Chicago Press.

    Meier, H. (2004) Die Lehre Carl Schmitts. Vier Kapitel zur Unterscheidung Politischer Theologie und Politischer Philosophie , 2nd edn., Stuttgart: Metzler.

    Mouffe, C. (ed.) (1999) The Challenge of Carl Schmitt , London: Verso.Mu ller, J.-W. (2003) A Dangerous Mind. Carl Schmitt in Post-War European Thought , New Haven

    and London: Yale University Press.Pichler, H.-K. (1998) The Godfathers of Truth: Max Weber and Carl Schmitt in Morgenthaus

    Theory of Power Politics, Review of International Studies 24(2): 185200.Preuss, L. (1935) National Socialist Conceptions of International Law, American Political Science

    Review 29(4): 594609.Rasch, W. (2000) A Just War? Or Just A War?: Habermas, and the Cosmopolitan Orthodoxy,

    Cardozo Law Review 21: 16651684.Scheuerman, W.E. (1999) Carl Schmitt. The End of Law , Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield

    Publishers.Scheuerman, W.E. (2004) International Law as Historical Myth, Constellations 11(4): 537550.Scott, J.B. (ed.) (1918) President Wilsons Foreign Policy. Messages, Addresses, Papers , New York:

    Oxford University Press.Stirk, P. (1999) Carl Schmitts Vo lkerrechtliche Grossraumordnung , History of Political Thought

    20(2): 357374.Stirk, P. (2003) Carl Schmitts Enemy and the Rhetoric of Anti-Interventionism, European Legacy

    8(1): 2136.Stirk, P. (2004) Carl Schmitt, the Law of Occupation, and the Iraq War, Constellations 11(4):

    527536.Willms, B. (1991) Politics as Politics: Carl Schmitts Concept of the Political and the Tradition of

    European Political Thought, History of European Ideas 13(4): 371383.Zolo, D. (2002) Invoking Humanity. War, Law and Global Order , London: Continuum.

    Roland AxtmannCarl Schmitt on International Politics

    551

    International Politics 2007 44