Autonomy & Paternalism Andrew Latus Ethics/Humanities/Health Law Nov. 14, 2002.

15
Autonomy & Paternalism Andrew Latus Ethics/Humanities/Health Law Nov. 14, 2002

Transcript of Autonomy & Paternalism Andrew Latus Ethics/Humanities/Health Law Nov. 14, 2002.

Page 1: Autonomy & Paternalism Andrew Latus Ethics/Humanities/Health Law Nov. 14, 2002.

Autonomy & PaternalismAndrew Latus

Ethics/Humanities/Health Law

Nov. 14, 2002

Page 2: Autonomy & Paternalism Andrew Latus Ethics/Humanities/Health Law Nov. 14, 2002.

Objective

To connect some of the ideas about autonomy, beneficence, and consent that have been raised over the course of the term

Page 3: Autonomy & Paternalism Andrew Latus Ethics/Humanities/Health Law Nov. 14, 2002.

‘Therapeutic Privilege’

In 1961, a study revealed that 88% of doctors routinely would not tell terminally ill cancer patients that they had cancer.

Therapeutic Privilege: “When a doctor decides for a seemingly capable patient that it is in the patient’s best interests not to know certain information…” (Doing Right, 79)

Page 4: Autonomy & Paternalism Andrew Latus Ethics/Humanities/Health Law Nov. 14, 2002.

Paternalism

To treat someone paternalistically is to treat the person in a way that ignores or discounts his/her wishes but aims at promoting the person’s best interest.

Generally, paternalism in medicine is viewed as being a bad thing.

Question: What’s wrong with paternalism?

Page 5: Autonomy & Paternalism Andrew Latus Ethics/Humanities/Health Law Nov. 14, 2002.

The Trouble with Paternalism Cases of paternalism are cases in which the

principles of beneficence/non-maleficence win a fight with the principle of autonomy.

But respecting patient autonomy is widely seen as the most important element in the doctor-patient relationship.

Therefore, paternalism is a bad thing

or so the story goes…

Page 6: Autonomy & Paternalism Andrew Latus Ethics/Humanities/Health Law Nov. 14, 2002.

Justifiable Paternalism? In both medical and non-medical contexts, to say

someone is acting paternalistically is to generally to say something bad about that person’s actions.

But there are occasions when paternalistic behaviour is appropriate or even required

Parenting (‘Parentalism’) Incompetent Friends/Relatives

Page 7: Autonomy & Paternalism Andrew Latus Ethics/Humanities/Health Law Nov. 14, 2002.

Hard Cases Some of the most difficult cases concern circumstances

where we are confident that a competent friend or family member is going to make a bad decision

Here, we typically cannot control the person’s ultimate decision, but would think it wrong not to at least try to change the person’s mind.

‘I can’t let you… drop out of med school/go out with him/eat that week old pork chop.’

In these hard cases, some degree of paternalism seems appropriate.

Page 8: Autonomy & Paternalism Andrew Latus Ethics/Humanities/Health Law Nov. 14, 2002.

‘The Myth of Perfect Autonomy’

Why is it morally okay to attempt to override your friend’s/family member’s original intention in some cases?

Because, despite what philosophers might say about the importance of autonomy, we are rarely, if ever, wholly rational ‘self-rulers’

A General Rule of Thumb: The further a person is, in a particular situation, from being a rational self-ruler, the more paternalistic behaviour is morally appropriate.

Page 9: Autonomy & Paternalism Andrew Latus Ethics/Humanities/Health Law Nov. 14, 2002.

Autonomy & Paternalism Our typical ways of thinking about

capacity/competence treat it as an on-off notion.

We set a legal line as a cut-off for taking a person’s desires as authoritative.

This is a useful legal device, but it hides the morally important fact that capacity comes in degrees. Keeping this in mind is crucial if we want to understand the proper relationship between autonomy and paternalism.

Page 10: Autonomy & Paternalism Andrew Latus Ethics/Humanities/Health Law Nov. 14, 2002.

The Rule of Justified Paternalism**Stolen from Dr. Daryl Pullman

AUTONOMY

PATERNALISM

“The amount of paternalistic intervention justified or required, is inversely proportional to the amount of autonomy present”

Page 11: Autonomy & Paternalism Andrew Latus Ethics/Humanities/Health Law Nov. 14, 2002.

Autonomy & Patients The usual situations in which doctors encounter

patients are situations that threaten a patient’s ability to function as a rational self-ruler.

Lack of understanding Fear Sickness

What does this tell us about the place of paternalism in the doctor-patient relationship?

Page 12: Autonomy & Paternalism Andrew Latus Ethics/Humanities/Health Law Nov. 14, 2002.

The Doctor-Patient Relationship Which model of the doctor-patient

relationship is most appropriate?

1. Pure Paternalism

Model = Adult-Child (Hippocrates' view?) Doctor as expert Focus is on care, but not autonomy

Page 13: Autonomy & Paternalism Andrew Latus Ethics/Humanities/Health Law Nov. 14, 2002.

The Doctor-Patient Relationship 2. Technical

Model = Contractor-client Doctor presents options. Patient decides. Maximum autonomy for patient

Page 14: Autonomy & Paternalism Andrew Latus Ethics/Humanities/Health Law Nov. 14, 2002.

The Doctor-Patient Relationship

3. Friendship

Charles Fried - doctors are "limited, special-purpose friends"

The doctor takes on the interests of the patient Leaves room for both paternalism and autonomy and for

varying degrees of both in particular cases A friend will sometimes try to talk you into doing

something 'for your own good' even if that's not what you say you want.

Page 15: Autonomy & Paternalism Andrew Latus Ethics/Humanities/Health Law Nov. 14, 2002.

The Moral The huge stress placed on patient autonomy may go too far.

Autonomy is important, but paternalism has got too much bad press.

Legally, the stress on autonomy makes sense, but we should not let it oversimplify the moral situation.

Corollary: the balance between paternalism & autonomy may be better recognized in practice than in theory.