Afference copy as a quantitative neurophysiological model for consciousness

40
A®erence copy as a quantitative neurophysiological model for consciousness Hugo Cornelis and Allan D. Coop * Three Way Street, P. O. Box 5160, Braddon Australian Capital Territory 2612, Australia * [email protected] [Received 27 March 2014; Accepted 7 April 2014; Published 20 June 2014] Consciousness is a topic of considerable human curiosity with a long history of philosophical analysis and debate. We consider there is nothing particularly complicated about conscious- ness when viewed as a necessary process of the vertebrate nervous system. Here, we propose a physiological \explanatory gap" is created during each present moment by the temporal requirements of neuronal activity. The gap extends from the time exteroceptive and propri- oceptive stimuli activate the nervous system until they emerge into consciousness. During this \moment", it is impossible for an organism to have any conscious knowledge of the ongoing evolution of its environment. In our schematic model, a mechanism of \a®erence copy" is employed to bridge the explanatory gap with consciously experienced percepts. These percepts are fabricated from the conjunction of the cumulative memory of previous relevant experience and the given stimuli. They are structured to provide the best possible prediction of the expected content of subjective conscious experience likely to occur during the period of the gap. The model is based on the proposition that the neural circuitry necessary to support consciousness is a product of sub/preconscious re°exive learning and recall processes. Based on a review of various psychological and neurophysiological ¯ndings, we develop a framework which contextualizes the model and brie°y discuss further implications. Keywords: Consciousness; explanatory gap; a®erence copy; re°ex; inhibition; learning; mem- ory; prediction; qualia; review. 1. Introduction and Philosophical Context Although much is currently known about the vertebrate central nervous system (CNS), little is known about the emergence of consciousness. Guided by philosophical considerations, we review known psychoneurophysiological data to provide a plau- sible framework for conscious experience. This framework is developed from dem- onstrated neural properties that are widely considered fundamental to CNS operations, including: re°ex activity (Sechenov, 1863), its organization (Sherrington, 1906) and timing (Maniadakis & Trahanias, 2014); and the role of inhibitory pro- cesses (Lee & Maguire, 2014; Schel et al., 2014), learning (Pavlov, 1927; Thorndike, 1911) and memory (Brown et al., 2007; Hebb, 1949). In doing this, we ¯nd a possible explanation for the origin of qualia within the CNS. Journal of Integrative Neuroscience, Vol. 13, No. 2 (2014) 363402 ° c Imperial College Press DOI: 10.1142/S0219635214400020 363 J. Integr. Neurosci. 2014.13:363-402. Downloaded from www.worldscientific.com by Dr. Allan Coop on 07/12/14. For personal use only.

description

Consciousness is a topic of considerable human curiosity with a long history of philosophical analysis and debate. We consider there is nothing particularly complicated about conscious- ness when viewed as a necessary process of the vertebrate nervous system. Here, we propose a physiological "explanatory gap" is created during each present moment by the temporal requirements of neuronal activity. The gap extends from the time exteroceptive and proprioceptive stimuli activate the nervous system until they emerge into consciousness. During this "moment", it is impossible for an organism to have any conscious knowledge of the ongoing evolution of its environment. In our schematic model, a mechanism of "afference copy" is employed to bridge the explanatory gap with consciously experienced percepts. These percepts are fabricated from the conjunction of the cumulative memory of previous relevant experience and the given stimuli. They are structured to provide the best possible prediction of the expected content of subjective conscious experience likely to occur during the period of the gap. The model is based on the proposition that the neural circuitry necessary to support consciousness is a product of sub/preconscious reflexive learning and recall processes. Based on a review of various psychological and neurophysiological findings, we develop a framework which contextualizes the model and briefly discuss further implications.

Transcript of Afference copy as a quantitative neurophysiological model for consciousness

  • Aerence copy as a quantitative neurophysiologicalmodel for consciousness

    Hugo Cornelis and Allan D. Coop*

    Three Way Street, P. O. Box 5160, BraddonAustralian Capital Territory 2612, Australia*[email protected]

    [Received 27 March 2014; Accepted 7 April 2014; Published 20 June 2014]

    Consciousness is a topic of considerable human curiosity with a long history of philosophicalanalysis and debate. We consider there is nothing particularly complicated about conscious-ness when viewed as a necessary process of the vertebrate nervous system. Here, we propose aphysiological \explanatory gap" is created during each present moment by the temporalrequirements of neuronal activity. The gap extends from the time exteroceptive and propri-oceptive stimuli activate the nervous system until they emerge into consciousness. During this\moment", it is impossible for an organism to have any conscious knowledge of the ongoingevolution of its environment. In our schematic model, a mechanism of \aerence copy" isemployed to bridge the explanatory gap with consciously experienced percepts. These perceptsare fabricated from the conjunction of the cumulative memory of previous relevant experienceand the given stimuli. They are structured to provide the best possible prediction of theexpected content of subjective conscious experience likely to occur during the period of thegap. The model is based on the proposition that the neural circuitry necessary to supportconsciousness is a product of sub/preconscious reexive learning and recall processes. Based ona review of various psychological and neurophysiological ndings, we develop a frameworkwhich contextualizes the model and briey discuss further implications.

    Keywords: Consciousness; explanatory gap; aerence copy; reex; inhibition; learning; mem-ory; prediction; qualia; review.

    1. Introduction and Philosophical Context

    Although much is currently known about the vertebrate central nervous system

    (CNS), little is known about the emergence of consciousness. Guided by philosophical

    considerations, we review known psychoneurophysiological data to provide a plau-

    sible framework for conscious experience. This framework is developed from dem-

    onstrated neural properties that are widely considered fundamental to CNS

    operations, including: reex activity (Sechenov, 1863), its organization (Sherrington,

    1906) and timing (Maniadakis & Trahanias, 2014); and the role of inhibitory pro-

    cesses (Lee & Maguire, 2014; Schel et al., 2014), learning (Pavlov, 1927; Thorndike,

    1911) and memory (Brown et al., 2007; Hebb, 1949). In doing this, we nd a possible

    explanation for the origin of qualia within the CNS.

    Journal of Integrative Neuroscience, Vol. 13, No. 2 (2014) 363402c Imperial College PressDOI: 10.1142/S0219635214400020

    363

    J. In

    tegr

    . Neu

    rosc

    i. 20

    14.1

    3:36

    3-40

    2. D

    ownl

    oade

    d fro

    m w

    ww

    .wor

    ldsc

    ient

    ific.c

    omby

    Dr.

    Alla

    n Co

    op o

    n 07

    /12/

    14. F

    or p

    erso

    nal u

    se o

    nly.

  • Following satiation of biological imperatives such as survival and reproduction,

    probably no other issues have come to stimulate human curiosity more, in one way or

    another, than the descriptive, functional and explanatory mysteries surrounding the

    idea of consciousness. It is an idea with which all thinking persons can engage as it is

    central to the problem of how we understand the world including ourselves and our knowledge as part of the world, see Popper (1959). The challenge is to make

    sucient room in our models of cosmology and the general nature of reality to permit

    a consistent account of consciousness, and vice versa our notions of consciousnessmust accommodate an understanding of what it means for its content to be \reality

    as a whole" (Bohm, 1980). However, over 2000 years of curiosity (Koch, 2009) seems

    to have added little of substance to either discussion or knowledge.

    Three considerations provide a context for the framework we develop. The rst

    concerns Sherrington's (1940) contemplation of the planet, \furnace of molten rocks

    and metals, now yielding thoughts and values. Magic furnace. Beside its alchemy and

    transmutations the most impassioned dreams of Hermes Trismegistus and all his

    fellowship dwindle to paltry nothing". The second proposes that, \problems are

    solved not by giving new information, but by arranging what we have known since

    long". (Wittgenstein, 1953). The third states that, \At stake are central key concepts

    that directly involve fundamental convictions regarding the nature of man's inner

    being, physical reality, the meaning of existence and related matters of ultimate

    concern. . . . perspectives in this area profoundly shape human value systems and

    societal decision-making and hence human destiny". (Sperry, 1980).

    In short, (1) A remarkable structural evolution of matter has occurred, (2) we

    already know much of what is needed to solve the problem of consciousness and (3)

    we interpret and structure the world based on our understanding of how the brain

    works. Importantly, we consider many problems of consciousness would evaporate if

    it is accepted that construction of internal representations or replicas of the \outside"

    world is unnecessary (Velmans, 2009). For as O'Regan (1992) and many others have

    proposed it is continuously available \out there".

    Depending upon the gure of speech chosen, consciousness has been identied with:

    a state of being, a substance, a process, a place, an epiphenomenon, an emergent aspect

    of matter, or the only true reality (Miller, 1962); and described as a fascinating but

    elusive phenomenon for which it is impossible to specify what it is, what it does, or why

    it evolved; with little worth reading written about it (Sutherland, 1989).

    In the cognitive realm, nowhere has a dominant metaphor been more central and

    susceptible to \sporadic reformulation" in terms of the technology of the day than

    when theorizing about the brain (Daugman, 1993). For example, the following

    metaphors, ranging from cosmological to mathematical, have all been employed:

    embodied spirits and helmsmen (Arbib, 1972); hydraulics and mechanics (Vartanian,

    1973, 1953; Resniko, 1988); electricity (von Helmholtz, 1850a,b; Hebb, 1949;

    Hodgkin & Huxley, 1952) and optics (Pribram, 1969); networks of simple automata

    and societies of mind (Dennett, 1978; Minsky, 1988); determinism of the unconscious

    and automatic (Freud, 1904/1914); logical calculus of neurons (McCulloch & Pitts,

    364 H. CORNELIS & A. D. COOP

    J. In

    tegr

    . Neu

    rosc

    i. 20

    14.1

    3:36

    3-40

    2. D

    ownl

    oade

    d fro

    m w

    ww

    .wor

    ldsc

    ient

    ific.c

    omby

    Dr.

    Alla

    n Co

    op o

    n 07

    /12/

    14. F

    or p

    erso

    nal u

    se o

    nly.

  • 1943); the stochastic Boltzmann machine, spin-glass latices, Ising spins (Hopeld,

    1982; Hinton & Sejnowski, 1986; Gutfreund et al., 1988) and chaotic dynamics and

    attractors (Skarda & Freeman, 1987). Given such historical antecedents, it is

    probably shortsighted to regard the current metaphors of the brain as information

    processor and computer (Pylyshyn, 1986) or container of representations (Nadel &

    Piattelli-Palmarini, 2003) as entirely dierent kinds of breakthrough in the history

    of ideas.

    Ever since publication of the classic paper by Nagel (1974), \What is it like to be a

    bat?", the \intractable problem of consciousness" Churchland (1996), has been

    identied as, how is it that consciousness of subjective experience is possible? This is

    known as the \Hard Problem" (Chalmers, 1996), and concerns, \how and why

    consciousness arises from physical processes in the brain" (Chalmers, 1997).

    The \explanatory gap" is a philosophical term related to the \Hard Problem". It

    refers to the lack of an explanation of how physical properties give rise to the qualia of

    experience (Levine, 1983). We take a more pragmatic view of this problem than

    those who consider it represents the limits of current knowledge (Churchland, 1996),

    or of cognitive abilities (McGinn, 1989), or necessarily entails a metaphysical gap

    (Chalmers, 1996).

    Nevertheless, consciousness continues to be a prominent mystery for philosophy

    and science (Chalmers, 1996). Initially, the preserve of philosophy, more recently

    quantitive empirical studies have become both more accepted, and possible; with

    rapid advances over the last two decades (Price & Barrell, 2012), as ongoing devel-

    opment of experimental techniques and new observations drive theory and research

    (Blackmore, 2001).

    We are, of course, unhappy with much proposed for the \problem" of conscious-

    ness, whether hard or otherwise. The fact that philosophers are forced to deny its

    existence (Dennett, 1991), solve it by attribution of as yet unidentied irreducible

    properties (Chalmers, 1996), or claim it is beyond the limits of human knowledge

    (McGinn, 2004), seems somewhat unsatisfactory.

    Our starting position is therefore similar to that of Churchland (1996); to partition

    the mind-brain problem as Chalmers (1996) has done, \poses the danger of inventing

    an explanatory chasm where (all that really exists is) a broad eld of ignorance". The

    only conclusion from the fact that consciousness is mysterious, is that its mechanisms

    are not understood. From the vantage point of ignorance, it is dicult to tell which

    problems actually are harder and which will be solved rst. As Churchland (1996)

    suggests, \learn the science, do the science, (then) see what happens".

    The essence of the model presented here is a transguration of the philosophical

    explanatory gap into a neurophysiological context. This allows the introduction

    of a plausible \aerence copy" mechanism which bridges an otherwise inescapable

    physiological explanatory gap. In doing so, we address the confounding observations

    reported by Libet (2004, 1985), and more recently by Soon et al. (2008) and Bode

    et al. (2011). The issues involved concern the timecourse of sensory stimulation and

    voluntary motor acts and their emergence into consciousness.

    AFFERENCE COPY AS A QUANTITATIVE NEUROPHYSIOLOGICAL MODEL 365

    J. In

    tegr

    . Neu

    rosc

    i. 20

    14.1

    3:36

    3-40

    2. D

    ownl

    oade

    d fro

    m w

    ww

    .wor

    ldsc

    ient

    ific.c

    omby

    Dr.

    Alla

    n Co

    op o

    n 07

    /12/

    14. F

    or p

    erso

    nal u

    se o

    nly.

  • In proceeding, we aim to contribute to improved clarity of understanding by

    rening concepts which may not previously have been well articulated. To this end,

    we aim to explain, \How it is that subjectively we seem to exist in a seamlessly

    perpetual and detailed present moment".

    2. Considerations Developed About Consciousness in Dierent

    Temporal and Phylogenetic Domains

    In this section, we introduce biological considerations which assist in framing the

    model presented here. We begin by noting that Penrose & Hamero (2011) report the

    recognition of three general possibilities for the origin and place of consciousness in

    the universe: (1) It is a quality that has always been in the universe, (2) precursors

    have always been in the universe and biology evolved a mechanism to convert con-

    scious precursors to actual consciousness or (3) it is not an independent quality but

    has arisen as a natural evolutionary consequence of the biological adaptation of

    brains and nervous systems,

    Alternatively, the three major theories of consciousness taken most seriously by

    neuroscientists include the view that (Block, 2009): Consciousness (1) must be

    described in terms of higher order states, (2) is a property of a global workspace or

    (3) is a biological state of the brain.

    Solms (1997) has proposed the totality of human consciousness consists of three

    domains: (1) Primary external perceptions experienced as material reality; (2) pri-

    mary internal perceptions (aect) and (3) perceptions of activated traces of previous

    experiences (memory and cognition), the latter two being experienced as introspec-

    tive awareness (or psychic reality).

    Alternatively, Tulving (2002) has proposed three forms of consciousness:

    (1) Anoetic or \unthinking", which may be aectively intense, (2) noetic or cognitive

    activity linked to the physical instantiation of the objects of exteroceptive perception

    and (3) autonoetic or higher neocortical functions including, abstract perceptions

    and cognition, conscious (self) awareness and reection on episodic memory, pre-

    dictions of the future and fantasy or hallucination.

    Solms & Panksepp (2012) mapped the preceding scheme to phylogenetic evolution

    of: (1) Upper brainstem and septal areas (anoetic phenomenal experience), (2) lower

    subcortical ganglia and upper limbic structures of the cortical midline (noetic con-

    sciousness and learning) and (3) association cortex, providing the critical substrates

    for \reexive experiential blends that yield the stream of everyday awareness"

    (autonoetic consciousness).

    2.1. Consciousness a reduction to fragmentsIf self-awareness is taken as evidence for consciousness, then in evolutionary terms

    consciousness may have rst appeared about 5 million years ago and be at least as old

    as the placental divide in mammals (Wildman et al., 2007), with the foundations

    of consciousness and self-consciousness possibly formed as early as the amniote

    366 H. CORNELIS & A. D. COOP

    J. In

    tegr

    . Neu

    rosc

    i. 20

    14.1

    3:36

    3-40

    2. D

    ownl

    oade

    d fro

    m w

    ww

    .wor

    ldsc

    ient

    ific.c

    omby

    Dr.

    Alla

    n Co

    op o

    n 07

    /12/

    14. F

    or p

    erso

    nal u

    se o

    nly.

  • radiation (Warren et al., 2008). The core of human consciousness is thought to have

    originated in phylogenetically ancient structures activated by primitive emotions

    mediating arousal, in conjunction with limited connectivity with frontalparietal

    areas (Mashour & Alkire, 2013).

    It has been well demonstrated that the operations of the CNS add color, sound and

    a multiplicity of sensations to continual sampling of reality. This sampling is recorded

    with remarkable veracity from atomic and quantum domains (Kaupp, 2010; Smith,

    2002; Hecht et al., 1942). Such detail is likely captured at a resolution sucient for

    the existence of physical phenomena to be demonstrated, quantied, modeled and

    ultimately, understood.

    The cerebral cortex is currently considered to be the primary site containing the

    neural correlates of awareness (Mashour & Alkire, 2013). From a top-down perspec-

    tive, evidence for this includes the desynchronized nature of the electroencephalogram,

    activity in the thalamocortical systemandwidespreadbrain activity (Seth et al., 2005).

    The coupling of an internally based need system with an externally directed sit-

    uational awareness system is considered to provide a basis for the emergence of

    consciousness and has been shown to be closely related to the mental machinery seen

    in humans for generating arousal and awareness (Mashour & Alkire, 2013). The most

    basic emotions and arousal states are associated with internal feedback networks that

    guide an organism's behavior to the best possible outcomes. This functionality is

    considered to underly essentially all behavioral choices in the vertebrate brain

    (Mashour & Alkire, 2013).

    One feature of experience putatively identied by philosophers is an insubstantial

    component of consciousness called qualia. These have been dened as the internal

    and subjective components of sense perceptions, arising from stimulation of the

    senses by phenomena; they are recognizable qualitative characters of the given, which

    may be repeated in dierent experiences, and are thus a sort of universal (Jackson,

    1982). Qualia involve the subjective experience of the redness of red, the painfulness

    of pain and so on.

    At a psychological-level, Freud (1915) considered mental processes are in them-

    selves unconscious and that their perception by consciousness is similar to the per-

    ception of the external world by the sense-organs. Unconscious mental activity is

    therefore similar to all other natural processes (Solms, 1997), with most of mental life

    unconscious most of the time, only becoming conscious as sensory percepts, such as in

    words and images (Gray, 2002). Jackendor (1987) considers consciousness is not a

    particularly high-level process, as everyone has always wanted it to be, and that \it is

    not what makes us human".

    Besides subjectivity, in humans at least, conscious life has two other dominant

    features: unity and intentionality. The unitary nature of consciousness refers to the

    appearance of subjective brain experiences as unied, integrated and a constructed

    whole (Kandel, 2000b). Intentionality refers to the typical focus of consciousness

    being about objects or events (Edelman, 2003), with emotional (LeDoux, 2000) and

    semantic aspects (Chalmers, 1996), being central.

    AFFERENCE COPY AS A QUANTITATIVE NEUROPHYSIOLOGICAL MODEL 367

    J. In

    tegr

    . Neu

    rosc

    i. 20

    14.1

    3:36

    3-40

    2. D

    ownl

    oade

    d fro

    m w

    ww

    .wor

    ldsc

    ient

    ific.c

    omby

    Dr.

    Alla

    n Co

    op o

    n 07

    /12/

    14. F

    or p

    erso

    nal u

    se o

    nly.

  • Ingvar (1985) considers conscious experience is based on three components:

    memory of the past, experience of \actual events in the now-situation" and concepts

    of the future or events which have not yet occurred. For him, the important question

    is, \to what extent do events in the brain, related to the past, the present and

    the future, take place at a conscious-(attentive) level or at a subconscious (pre- or

    subattentive-level) or at both levels simultaneously".

    In answering this question, Jackendor (1987) proposes that the character of the

    phenomenological mind is comprised of unconscious and conscious elements but

    that processing is always unconscious; in short, processes are never available to

    consciousness in perception, thought, learning or action.

    Many treatments of consciousness in the literature recognize, at least incipiently

    (Jackendor, 1987), that consciousness is projected from mental information struc-

    tures, where the stream of consciousness, made up of visual and verbal imagery, is

    usually sucient to be believed to constitute thought. But Jackendor (1987) con-

    siders this may not actually be the case. Rather, visual and verbal images emerge

    from intermediate structures, which are in turn generated from thought by manda-

    tory fast processing modules. Hence, the stream of consciousness is essentially

    nothing but evidence that thought is occurring in a subconscious domain, with both

    the process of thought and its contents inaccessible to awareness.

    Importantly, the fact that human cognitive processes are largely nonconscious has

    been periodically reported, although often ignored. von Helmholtz (1910) observed

    that we are not aware of the elements used to form a judgement we make\unconscious interferences" based on prior experience. Lashley (1956) further em-

    phasized, \No activity of mind is ever conscious . . .Experience clearly gives no clue as

    to the means by which it is organized". We are not conscious of the details that make-

    up a percept. Such details are inhibited from our conscious awareness. Instead, what

    is seen depends largely on what is already known (Snyder, 1998; Snyder & Barlow,

    1986; Gregory, 1970). Basically, every image is forced to t into a known percept

    (Snyder et al., 2004).

    This perspective on human perception is also strongly supported by reports of

    detail blindness (No, 2007); e.g., change (Simons & Rensink, 2005; O'Regan, 2003),inattentional (Mack & Rock, 1998) and repetition (Kanwisher, 1987) blindness; and

    the attentional blink (Chun & Potter, 1995; Raymond et al., 1992). Space precludes

    further review of this extensive literature, which we consider provides compelling

    support for our conjectures.

    Following a comprehensive review, Velmans (1991) concludes no human infor-

    mation processing is conscious in the sense that consciousness enters into or causally

    inuences the process. What enters awareness follows the processing to which that

    awareness relates.

    Similarly, Berlin (2011) concludes that complex cognition can proceed in the

    absence of consciousness, that the unconscious brain is active, purposeful and inde-

    pendent and can selectively access and activate implicit goals and motives. However,

    368 H. CORNELIS & A. D. COOP

    J. In

    tegr

    . Neu

    rosc

    i. 20

    14.1

    3:36

    3-40

    2. D

    ownl

    oade

    d fro

    m w

    ww

    .wor

    ldsc

    ient

    ific.c

    omby

    Dr.

    Alla

    n Co

    op o

    n 07

    /12/

    14. F

    or p

    erso

    nal u

    se o

    nly.

  • he notes that exactly how unconscious emotions and evaluations help shape the

    dynamics giving rise to conscious perception is still unknown.

    Gray (2004) has postulated three aspects of consciousness: (1) It contains a model

    of the relatively enduring features of the external world which is experienced as

    though it is the external world, (2) features that are particularly relevant to ongoing

    motor programs, or which depart from expectation, are monitored and emphasized,

    (3) The control variables and set-points of the brain's nonconscious servomechanisms

    are juxtaposed, combined and modied; in this way, error can be corrected.

    At the core of his model is a \comparator", which compares actual stimuli with

    expected stimuli a function performed by a behavioral inhibition system (Corr,2008). When there is no discrepancy, behavioral routines run uninterrupted and

    stimuli are not extracted for detailed processing by higher-level cognitive processes.

    When mismatch is detected between actual and expected states of the world, the

    alien features of the error-triggering environment are subjected to controlled, at-

    tentional, analysis and (often) emerge into conscious awareness.

    Perlovsky (2013) notes, brain imaging experiments have demonstrated that vague

    mental states and the entire dynamic logic process (taking approximately 500ms) are

    unconscious. Only nal near-logical sensory percepts become available to con-

    sciousness. Most brain operations (more than 99%) are inaccessible to subjective

    consciousness, while the mind operates by \jumps" among \islands" of conscious-

    logical states in an ocean of unconsciousness. In short, we are subjectively convinced

    of our consciousness. Further, in a recent review, Aru & Bachmann (2014) argue that

    attention and consciousness are independent from each other and phenomenal con-

    sciousness can emerge without attention.

    2.2. Timing of the phenomenology of consciousness

    Following Donders (1868), three fundamental response latencies or reaction times

    have been conrmed, \simple", \recognition" and \choice" (Baayen & Milin, 2010).

    For simple reexes in humans, the shortest reaction times are those of the uncon-

    scious blink reex with a mean latency of 10.8ms (Shahani, 1970); whereas, reex

    latencies formuscle in response to electrical stimulation range from 3151ms (hand) to

    5581ms (foot) (Tarkka, 1986). Similarly, response times of 810ms (auditory)

    (Kemp, 1973), 2040ms (visual) (Marshall et al., 1943) and 155ms (touch) (Robinson,

    1934), have been reported.

    Although, subjectively, recognition of familiar objects and scenes appears virtually

    instantaneous, this actually is not the case. For example, event related potentials in a

    visual recognition task show the visual processing required to identify an animal in a

    visual scene viewed for 20ms requires up to 150ms, with reaction times of 382567ms

    (median 445ms, Thorpe et al., 1996).

    We consider that on purely empirical grounds, these ndings argue directly

    against any immediacy whatsoever for the phenomenology of consciousness. In

    support of this position, in the following section (as one amongst several possible

    AFFERENCE COPY AS A QUANTITATIVE NEUROPHYSIOLOGICAL MODEL 369

    J. In

    tegr

    . Neu

    rosc

    i. 20

    14.1

    3:36

    3-40

    2. D

    ownl

    oade

    d fro

    m w

    ww

    .wor

    ldsc

    ient

    ific.c

    omby

    Dr.

    Alla

    n Co

    op o

    n 07

    /12/

    14. F

    or p

    erso

    nal u

    se o

    nly.

  • examples), we further briey explore vision in more detail. In particular, its temporal

    properties and implications.

    2.3. The problem of the rapid establishment of visual consciousness

    Principled estimates of the timing of visual activity can be made. For example, any

    activity requiring detail or color (e.g., driving or reading) must be located within the

    foveal area by a saccade. The fovea occupies less than 1% of retinal area but over 50%

    of the visual cortex (Krantz, 2012). It covers about two degrees of the visual eld or a

    disc about 4 cm in diameter at arm's length. In vertebrates, the fovea may be com-

    pared to the location where axons converge to form the head of the optic nerve. The

    resulting hole in the photoreceptor mosaic is up to six times the foveal area, which at

    35 forms a surprisingly large \blind spot", equivalent to a 610 cm diameter discat arm's length (O'Regan, 1992).

    Dierent saccades (Hopp & Fuchs, 2004), exhibit remarkably stereotyped

    amplitude, duration and peak velocity (Becker, 1989). Their dynamics are deter-

    mined by the point of origin within the visual eld and the trajectory of movement

    employed to locate a target. Typically, they last about 25190ms for movements of

    560, respectively (van Beers, 2008).Reactive targeting saccades exhibit latencies of about 180ms (Smit et al., 1987),

    but may be as fast as 100135ms (Fischer & Ramsperger, 1984; Fischer et al., 1993),

    whereas, memory-guided saccades may take well over 200ms (Hopp & Fuchs, 2004).

    The duration of the minimum ocular pause time in the absence of stimulus pro-

    cessing is about 200ms, with processing requiring an additional minimum 50100ms

    (Salthouse & Ellis, 1980). Although, for example, when reading, information may be

    extracted from foveal input within about 50ms (Rayner et al., 1981), with ocular

    pauses of 100200ms duration (van Diepen et al., 1995; Harris et al., 1988). Im-

    portantly, saccade optimization probably occurs during development rather than

    being innate (van Beers, 2008), as the dynamics of equivalent saccades vary across

    subjects (Boghen et al., 1974; Schmidt et al., 1979).

    The number of foveal xations (Nf ) required to cover the area of the binocular

    visual eld can be estimated from the number of square degrees (Guthrie, 1947), in

    the visual eld (Av) and fovea (Af ):

    Nf AvAf

    2 200 135

    2 2 2

    17; 1892:5465

    6; 750:

    If the optimal duration of a two-degree saccade is assumed to be 30ms (van Beers,

    2008) and the minimal ocular pause 100ms (well below the 250ms required for visual

    processing), the time required to scan the entire visual eld at foveal resolution with

    7.5 xations s1 is about 15min. A more physiologically realistic rate of three xa-tions s1 would require up to 37.5min.

    Given these gures, it is not surprising that an infant takes several months to

    develop, or more preciselylearn, accurate hand-eye coordination. However, what is

    370 H. CORNELIS & A. D. COOP

    J. In

    tegr

    . Neu

    rosc

    i. 20

    14.1

    3:36

    3-40

    2. D

    ownl

    oade

    d fro

    m w

    ww

    .wor

    ldsc

    ient

    ific.c

    omby

    Dr.

    Alla

    n Co

    op o

    n 07

    /12/

    14. F

    or p

    erso

    nal u

    se o

    nly.

  • surprising is adults subjectively experience a very rapidly established high resolu-

    tion global visual acuity in familiar environments. The question is, given that for

    any one viewpoint this should take almost 40min to establish, how is it so rapidly

    generated?

    A partial answer is provided by Hebb (1949) who suggests, \during the continu-

    ous, intensive and prolonged visual training of infancy and childhood, we learn to

    recognize the direction of line and the distance between points, separately for each

    grossly separate part of the visual eld". Further, \[I]t takes months for the rst

    direct apprehension of a gure such as a plain, well-marked triangle to be established.

    The normal human infant, apparently, reaches this stage quite early in life; but his

    further training continues every moment that his eyes are open, and must extend his

    capacity for prompt recognition of patterns falling outside the macula. . . . The sig-

    nicant fact is that characteristic normal generalization only shows up after a pro-

    longed and arduous training process."

    There is every reason to expect that similar extended training occurs with other

    senses. In summary, it would seem rapid establishment of consciously experienced

    perception may actually be enabled by prior learning; following sensory activation,

    percepts are evoked as required from the memory system.

    2.4. The subjective antedating of perception

    Two main types of organization of specic aerent systems have been reported for

    vertebrates (Voronin et al., 1968): (1) Individual sensory modalities in sh partition

    to dierent brain structures, whereas, (2) in mammals, all sensory modalities are

    collected in the forebrain. Those of amphibians and reptiles lie between these two

    bounds. Regardless of how basic human sensory modalities are classied, the dierent

    perceptual qualities they generate are the constituent elements of the envelope of

    consciousness and nothing else exists (Solms, 1997).

    A basic problem related to the conscious perception of stimuli and initiation of

    voluntary activity has been identied. Many studies conrm that, close to sensory

    threshold, a delay of up to about 500ms occurs before cerebral activities initiated by

    stimulus detection systems achieve the duration and intensity of stimulation or

    \neuronal adequacy" necessary to successfully elicit conscious awareness of the

    stimulus (Libet et al., 1964). (Although, stronger stimuli may reduce this delay to as

    little as 100ms.) The problem is that following neuronal adequacy, the subjective

    timing of the experience appears to occur without the actual delay required for

    neuronal adequacy to elicit conscious experience of the stimulus.

    One inference from such a result is that the experience of a skin-induced sensation

    is elicited at a cerebral-level with a much shorter delay than for cortically-induced

    sensation, an explanation discounted by Libet (1981).

    As a solution to this problem, Libet (2004) has proposed that following neuronal

    adequacy, subjective timing of the experience is automatically referred backwards to

    the moment when primary sensory cortex received the stimulus (2025ms after

    AFFERENCE COPY AS A QUANTITATIVE NEUROPHYSIOLOGICAL MODEL 371

    J. In

    tegr

    . Neu

    rosc

    i. 20

    14.1

    3:36

    3-40

    2. D

    ownl

    oade

    d fro

    m w

    ww

    .wor

    ldsc

    ient

    ific.c

    omby

    Dr.

    Alla

    n Co

    op o

    n 07

    /12/

    14. F

    or p

    erso

    nal u

    se o

    nly.

  • peripheral stimulation). The experience is thus \antedated" and subjectively appears

    to occur without the substantial delay required for conscious experience of the

    stimulus.

    Below, we provide a less paradoxical explanation. It forms the basis of the

    \aerence copy" model.

    2.5. Emotion

    For completeness, we now make a few comments about the role of emotion in neural

    function. (For more details, see for example, LeDoux (1996)). In a review, Vuilleu-

    mier & Huang (2009) report that interactions between brain systems involved in

    emotion and attention may contribute to regulating behavior and awareness by

    enhancing relevant sensory information. Emotional stimuli may also evoke uncon-

    scious reexive and involuntary processing under many conditions. Further, invol-

    untary monitoring of emotional stimuli and reexive boosting of perceptual processes

    may reect some \default" settings or intrinsic preparedness within neural pathways.

    They can also be adaptively shaped by various regulatory mechanisms that them-

    selves operate potentially with or without conscious control. Finally, we note Solms

    (1997) proposes that aect must be considered a sensory and perceptual modality.

    3. Biological Framework for a Model of Consciousness

    Based on the foregoing, and as outlined in more detail below; we present a model

    where unconscious precursors of the conscious experience of each given moment are

    molded within the memory system by integration with aerent stimuli (including

    emotional aects experienced as qualia).

    Our claim is that through the physiological mechanisms supporting this model,

    the repetitive nature of a purely reexive existence is transcended, content created

    and subjective experience expanded. Through these underlying mechanisms, the

    cumulative procession of known prior events and activities inform current experience

    and, via a surprisingly counter-intuitive mechanism, lay the basis for future behavior.

    Each successive moment is formed from, and experienced through, the cumulative

    record or memory of all relevant previous moments. In the deepest sense, each

    present moment is the last remaining moment; experienced not in its encapsulation of

    the past, but as an experience bounded prediction of the future.

    From this perspective, we consider there is sucient empirical data to formulate

    several broad conjectures from which a framework for consciousness might be

    developed:

    (1) With the exception of innate reexes (Zafeiriou, 2004), non-conscious activity in

    the CNS is generated, organized and controlled through elaboration of reex

    circuits assembled by associative learning.

    (2) Inhibitory processes are the preeminent mechanism whereby the CNS controls

    neural activity.

    372 H. CORNELIS & A. D. COOP

    J. In

    tegr

    . Neu

    rosc

    i. 20

    14.1

    3:36

    3-40

    2. D

    ownl

    oade

    d fro

    m w

    ww

    .wor

    ldsc

    ient

    ific.c

    omby

    Dr.

    Alla

    n Co

    op o

    n 07

    /12/

    14. F

    or p

    erso

    nal u

    se o

    nly.

  • (3) All CNS functions, from meaningful integration of sensory stimuli to con-

    sciousness and generation of motor plans, arise from ongoing (prenatally initi-

    ated) renement of learning.

    (4) Memory is a repository for learning and throughout life it is continually formed,

    and modulated, by accumulated moment-to-moment sampling of all available

    sensory modalities.

    (5) The physics of CNS function requires, and evolutionary pressures drive increased

    capacity for anticipatory prediction.

    We now briey explore evidence supporting these conjectures.

    3.1. From spinal cord reexes to reexive behavior

    The reexive nature of nervous systems is an evolutionary requirement imposed by

    the need for control of reliable response in ever-changing and dynamic environments.

    Thus, Sechenov (1863) was convinced that, \as far as the presence in man of three

    separate mechanisms directing the phenomena of conscious and unconscious life is

    concerned (viz. the mechanisms of the pure reex, and those of reex inhibition and

    augmentation). Let anyone who thinks this hypothesis is doubtful, even poorly

    demonstrated, or simply unacceptable, controvert it . . .If anyone nds a better

    explanation, I shall be the rst to welcome it".

    Since the early 19th century, it has been recognized that \just as the spinal reexes

    [bear] a `genetic' anity to the irritability of the simplest animals and of plants, so

    the operation of the highest nervous centers in humans [retain] the fundamental

    reex character of the lower" (Clarke & Jacyna, 1987). For example, Laycock (1845)

    concluded that, \the ganglia within the cranium being a continuation of the spinal

    cord, must necessarily be regulated as to their reaction on external agencies by laws

    identical with those governing the functions of the spinal ganglia and their analogues

    in the lower animals".

    Sechenov (1863) was the rst to propose that all aspects of cognition in humans

    are based on behavioral reexes or more generally that reex circuits provide the

    basis of all nervous function.

    During the 19th century, the reex concept became basic for attempts to explain

    the physiological functioning of the nervous system. By the end of the century the

    tendency was to include increasing parts of animal behavior under reexive move-

    ments; that is, movements elicited through stimulation originating from an organ-

    ism's external or internal milieu.

    Early in the 20th century the reex arc was established as the functional unit in

    CNS integration (Sherrington, 1906). Magnus (1924) demonstrated the reex nature

    of all the elementary motor activities, and it was believed stereotyped movements,

    such as those involved in walking, swimming and other locomotion, could be ana-

    lyzed and described in terms of reexes. Sequential patterns of eector activity were

    explained as arising from coordinated patterns of exteroreceptive and proprioceptive

    AFFERENCE COPY AS A QUANTITATIVE NEUROPHYSIOLOGICAL MODEL 373

    J. In

    tegr

    . Neu

    rosc

    i. 20

    14.1

    3:36

    3-40

    2. D

    ownl

    oade

    d fro

    m w

    ww

    .wor

    ldsc

    ient

    ific.c

    omby

    Dr.

    Alla

    n Co

    op o

    n 07

    /12/

    14. F

    or p

    erso

    nal u

    se o

    nly.

  • excitation of the CNS. Richet (1925) introduced \the conception of the psychic reex,

    in which the response following on a given stimulus is supposed to be determined by

    the association of this stimulus with the traces left in the hemispheres by past

    stimuli". In summary, the reex concept was used to explain the integrative functions

    of the brain previously considered to result from \psychic activities" (Jrgensen,1974).

    Subsequently, motor-related activity in the CNS was shown to not necessarily

    reect corresponding patterns of peripheral sensory activity. Thus, it was assumed

    animal locomotion and other types of movements are determined by central pattern

    generators, where the role of peripheral stimulation and sensory feedback is to

    activate and modulate these generators (Bullock, 1961).

    More recent interpretation suggests pattern generators may be intrinsic spinal

    processors comprised of hybrid feedforward/feedback systems which optimally

    compensate for both disturbances and sensor noise and can adapt central input to

    this optimized peripheral input (Kuo, 2002). This is not inconsistent with pattern

    generators being viewed as examples of sophisticated reex circuits.

    The denition of a reex has been quite variable, ranging from the restrictive,

    \stimulus-evoked response that usually involves a single muscle or a limited group of

    muscles" (LeDoux et al., 2009), to the more general, \all neural processes (or neural

    responses) and following eector responses evoked by any currently acting stimulus",

    where a stimulus is a physical event (or a change in physical energy) which elicits the

    activity of sensory receptors or higher-levels of the aerent nervous system ( Zernicki,

    1968). In short, a reex is an automatic or involuntary and near instantaneous

    response to a stimulus. Importantly, it is possible to conclude a reex circuit may be

    activated by any sucient stimulus.

    As McCulloch (1947) has clearly stated, modes of functional organization of the

    cerebral cortex are reexive: \To that great extent to which its aerents inform it of

    the peripheral consequences of the action of its own eerent, any system is part of the

    path of a reex".

    Complex or chain reexes located in the CNS have been demonstrated to consist of

    a number of unitary processes, for which feedback control is essential ( Zernicki,

    1968). Further, Slonim (1968), notes that complex, obligate stereotypic behavior

    generated on the base of natural conditioned reexes in contrast to articial orfacultative trainingare components of specic adaptive behaviors required under

    dierent ecological conditions of existence.

    Both simpler innate and more complex behavior comprising chains of individual

    motor acts can generate and repeat themselves stereotypically and independently of

    the conditions of postnatal development. Thus, between the \instinct" and the

    \unconditional reex" there is a chain of stages dependent on either reex or the

    automatic nature of nervous system activation (Slonim, 1968).

    It is well-known in humans that, introspectively, some stimuli produce psychic

    responses which may be assumed present in higher animals (Doty, 1967; Thorpe,

    1966; Beritov, 1965). It has further been assumed that cerebral responses are

    374 H. CORNELIS & A. D. COOP

    J. In

    tegr

    . Neu

    rosc

    i. 20

    14.1

    3:36

    3-40

    2. D

    ownl

    oade

    d fro

    m w

    ww

    .wor

    ldsc

    ient

    ific.c

    omby

    Dr.

    Alla

    n Co

    op o

    n 07

    /12/

    14. F

    or p

    erso

    nal u

    se o

    nly.

  • manifestations of denite unitary central processes or neuropsychic processes, of

    which there are several kinds: eectively indierent or gnostic processes, or un-

    pleasant or pleasant processes that are negative or positive emotions, respectively.

    Psychic responses may additionally be divided into perceptions and images.

    Signicantly, Konorski (1967) hypothesized that both perception and image are

    manifestations of excitation of the same neurons, with the dierent psychic responses

    (perception vs. image) due to dierent ways of exciting these neurons; from the

    periphery and by association, respectively. There is a good reason to believe neu-

    ropsychic processes are located in the cerebrum, gnostic processes mainly in asso-

    ciative cortex, and negative and positive emotional processes in dierent places of the

    limbic system and hypothalamus ( Zernicki, 1968; Olds, 1956). Importantly, this

    seems to map well with the schemes of Tulving (2002) and Solms & Panksepp (2012)

    mentioned above.

    More recently, LeDoux et al. (2009) proposed that many behaviors fall into one of

    four categories: reex, reaction, action and habit; where habit formation (the most

    complex) and much of learning are dependent on conditioned reexes. For example,

    the brain of a student typist must coordinate sensory impulses from both eye and

    muscle to direct their ngers to particular keys. After sucient repetitions, the

    ngers automatically nd and strike the proper keys even when the eyes are shut.

    The student has \learned" to type; that is, typing has become a constellation of

    conditioned reexes (Lagasse, 2000).

    The simplest neuronal circuits are the monosynaptic reex arcs composed of one

    sensory neuron and one motoneuron, for example, the circuits subserving the patellar

    or achilles reex. Sherrington (1906) considered the whole nervous system to be based

    on this type of circuit, \even those of the cortex of the cerebrum itself". However, all

    but the simplest reex circuits are polysynaptic, where one or more interneurons are

    interposed between the aerent (sensory) and eerent (motor) neurons of the

    monosynaptic circuit.

    Once again, Sechenov (1863) has asked, \how is it possible, (in the case of the

    sensation of red), to speak of the paths of reexes?" Only to answer, \It is possible,

    because though we do not know what is going on in the excited nerves, muscles or

    brain centers, we cannot but see the laws of pure reex and cannot but consider them

    true . . .we can say that the nature of the given conscious act of man is the same as

    that of the reexes".

    An explicit example of the complex behavior generated by a relatively simple

    reex circuit is that found in the enteric nervous system. Associated with the gas-

    trointestinal tract, it is comprised of a similar number of neurons as the spinal cord

    (Furness & Costa, 1980). Within it, several types of neuromuscular activity are

    autonomously controlled by intrinsic sensory neurons (Bulbring et al., 1958). They

    include, stationary contractions associated with segmentation (Cannon, 1902), and

    two types of reex (Cannon, 1911); one a slowly advancing contraction, the other a

    \peristaltic rush" which propagates rapidly.

    AFFERENCE COPY AS A QUANTITATIVE NEUROPHYSIOLOGICAL MODEL 375

    J. In

    tegr

    . Neu

    rosc

    i. 20

    14.1

    3:36

    3-40

    2. D

    ownl

    oade

    d fro

    m w

    ww

    .wor

    ldsc

    ient

    ific.c

    omby

    Dr.

    Alla

    n Co

    op o

    n 07

    /12/

    14. F

    or p

    erso

    nal u

    se o

    nly.

  • Numerical simulations have shown the circuit underlying this reex is sucient to

    replicate both stationary and peristaltic activity, with the neuromuscular response

    determined by the state of intestinal contents (gas, liquid, solid), i.e., the details of

    the stimulus (Coop & Redman, 1992). These results suggest that more complex reex

    circuits within other neural systems can reliably generate a range of seemingly plastic

    behaviors in response to the specic details of circuit activation. Here, it is only

    necessary to mention the \absent minded" week end drive resulting in unexpected

    arrival at the workplace to recognize the ability of subconsciously active and entirely

    learned reex pathways to formulate, control and sustain extended patterns of

    complex behavior.

    On the basis of the long tradition briey reviewed here, we consider that a ma-

    jority of fundamental CNS operations are essentially reexive. Further, as reviewed

    above, it is their reexive nature which renders their activity unconscious. In this

    domain, equivalent stimuli reliably generate equivalent responses, modulated by

    circumstance, where subtle dierences in circuit activation may evoke either nely

    graded or signicantly dierent output.

    Phylogenetic elaboration of the CNS, particularly within associative cortex

    (Buckner & Krienen, 2013), results in both increased temporal separation between

    reex pathway activation and response, and increased complexity of learned reexive

    behavior; with (as we propose above) all such reexive activity constrained to the

    subconscious. Ultimately, as Velmans (2009) has put it, \an entity in the world is

    reexively experienced to be an entity in the world".

    In summary, Sherrington (1906) originally described the vertebrate nervous system

    as an orchestrated constellation of increasingly elaborated reex pathways culmi-

    nating in a head ganglion or brain. From this perspective, the known record of

    vertebrate evolutionary history (see e.g., Butler (2009)), and development of the

    associative circuits of the hominid nervous system (Buckner & Krienen, 2013), it is

    likely appropriate inhibitory processes andmodulation of intrinsic and learned reexes

    is fundamental to CNS function, and thus, ultimately, behavior and consciousness.

    3.2. Inhibition and disinhibition of reexive behavior

    Typically, a personmight be considered capable of expressing a near innite repertoire

    of behaviors. However, it is clear that in the normal course of events, they are never all

    expressed simultaneously. Rather, sequences of behavioral patterns, each appropriate

    to the given circumstances, are expressed as ongoing behavioral ows generated in

    response to perceived environmental concerns. The emergence of a particular behavior

    from a repertoire of possible behaviors is controlled by the (psychological) repression

    or (physiological) central inhibition of alternative behaviors (Beritov, 1968). This is

    the basic factor providing for the integrity of behavioral reactions. Further, Beritov

    (1968), reports central inhibition caused by stimulation of sensory nerves embraces

    the entire neuroaxis and follows adequate stimulation of all sensory modalities. In

    humans, general central inhibition also occurs during deliberate cognitive activities,

    376 H. CORNELIS & A. D. COOP

    J. In

    tegr

    . Neu

    rosc

    i. 20

    14.1

    3:36

    3-40

    2. D

    ownl

    oade

    d fro

    m w

    ww

    .wor

    ldsc

    ient

    ific.c

    omby

    Dr.

    Alla

    n Co

    op o

    n 07

    /12/

    14. F

    or p

    erso

    nal u

    se o

    nly.

  • such as arithmetic and suppression of conditioned and unconditioned reex activity.

    We take this to mean that tonic inhibition at the physiological-level is responsible for

    repression in the cognitive and behavioral domains.

    As Smith (1992) has concluded, \Inhibition . . . became the controlling mechanism

    that made possible those very functions, thought and deliberative action, that gave

    humanity dignity and independence from nature. The possibility of inhibition was

    the possibility that past associations rather than immediate sensations would

    sometimes initiate movements. It was the possibility that sensation might combine

    and recombine as intelligence and thought. Without inhibition, sensation merely

    exhausted itself in movement".

    Gray (2002) considers that the inhibitory function of consciousness solves a major

    evolutionary problem: How to ensure that automatic responses are appropriately

    activated; and how controlled processes are invoked only at critical junctures when a

    denite choice must be made between cautious risk-assessment and prepotent

    responses. At these moments, after ne-grained analysis aorded by control pro-

    cessing, appropriate adjustments can be made to the automatic system, such that

    when the same (or similar) stimuli are encountered in the future, automatic-reexive

    behavior will be more appropriate. In this way, controlled/conscious eects come to

    determine automatic/nonconscious eects, albeit with a time lag.

    We have previously concluded that, in the electrophysiological domain, ring of

    hippocampal pyramidal and cerebellar Purkinje neurons (Coop & Reeke, 2004; Coop

    & Redman, 1998), may more immediately be controlled through disinhibition and

    eective connectivity, than alterations in aerent stimulation frequency.

    It has recently been reported frontal cortex mediates unconsciously triggered in-

    hibitory control (van Gaal et al., 2008), and a role for inhibition in the control of

    cortical activity is further supported by disinhibition being a signicant control

    mechanism in the spinal cord (Sechenov, 1863), striatum (Chevalier & Deniau, 1990)

    and somatosensory cortex (Xing & Gerstein, 1996a,b,c), including olfactory bulb

    (Cazako et al., 2014). More generally, there is persuasive evidence the cortex may be

    under widespread and strong inhibition (Calford & Tweedale, 1991; Dykes et al.,

    1984), while pathological alterations to inhibition may lead to the excitatory dys-

    functions of epilepsy (Avoli, 2004) and schizophrenia (Lewis et al., 2005). A recent

    review of the functional signicance of intrinsic oscillatory brain properties con-

    cluded, \it is by selection, via inhibition that the most elaborate neuronal patterns

    are generated in the CNS" (Llinas, 2014).

    3.3. Learning and habituation

    In a recent review, Schacter et al. (2011) consider human learning to be acquisition of

    knowledge or skills through experience, study, or by being taught. However, learning

    is not usually immediate, but rather typically is an incremental process building

    upon, and shaped by, what is already known; to produce relatively permanent

    changes in the behavior of an organism.

    AFFERENCE COPY AS A QUANTITATIVE NEUROPHYSIOLOGICAL MODEL 377

    J. In

    tegr

    . Neu

    rosc

    i. 20

    14.1

    3:36

    3-40

    2. D

    ownl

    oade

    d fro

    m w

    ww

    .wor

    ldsc

    ient

    ific.c

    omby

    Dr.

    Alla

    n Co

    op o

    n 07

    /12/

    14. F

    or p

    erso

    nal u

    se o

    nly.

  • Two types of learnings have been distinguished (Kandel et al., 2000a). The sim-

    plest is non-associative. Two forms are common, habituation (Sokolov, 1963) and

    sensitization (Shettleworth, 2010). Two forms of associative learning have also been

    identied, classical (Pavlov, 1927) and operant (Thorndike, 1911) conditioning.

    As suggested by Sechenov (1863), learning may contribute to understanding,

    knowledge and as we have seen, even qualia (where qualia have been proposed to

    originate in local cortical network activity (Orpwood, 2013)), \the successive reexes

    acquired by learning lead to a perfect notion of the object, to knowledge in its ele-

    mentary form. Indeed, the scientic knowledge of external objects is simply an in-

    nitely broad notion of each of them, i.e., the sum of all possible sensations evoked in

    us by these objects under all conceivable conditions . . .I shall merely point out that

    sensations from all spheres of the senses can be diversely combined, but always by

    means of consecutive reexes. These combinations give rise to countless notions that

    arise in childhood, notions providing, so to speak, material for the entire subsequent

    psychical life".

    In other words, when objects in the environment occur frequently enough, with

    repeated regularities, they can be incrementally added to the memory of similar

    previous encounters. Slight variations over time elaborate the memory system far

    beyond that of any single sensory experience, and as Sechenov suggests, this con-

    tinually enriches records of sensory experience and thus conscious phenomena.

    It is notable that at the electrophysiological level, very young animals may only

    receive and integrate relatively small amounts of information per unit time in circuits

    which function more slowly than those of adults (Scherrer, 1968). Associated learning

    may occur consciously or unconsciously. For example, the eects of internal stimuli

    have been shown to be active as early as the embryonic stage, particularly in studies

    of conditions under which the onset and patterning of electrical activity takes place in

    the higher parts of the embryonic brain.

    Even at this early stage, central inhibition displays its controlling inuence on

    coordinating reex activity (Biryukov, 1968), and there is evidence for prenatal

    habituation in humans as early as the 32nd week of gestation (Sandman et al., 1997),

    indicating the nervous system is developed for learning and memory formation prior

    to birth.

    3.4. The unity of fragments of memory

    The recollection of past experience is considered to be a reconstructive process. It can

    be broken down into a number of constituent processes, with memories recreated

    from their component parts, although little is known about the neural correlates

    (Hassabis & Maguire, 2009). As such, human memory has been considered comprised

    of a variety of testable components forming a \memory system"a containing past

    aWe recognize the nomenclature generally accepted in memory research, where \memory system" refers to the

    multistore memory model (LaRocque et al., 2014). However, for convenience we use this phrase to refer to the morestate-based or unitary memory model described by Brown et al. (2007).

    378 H. CORNELIS & A. D. COOP

    J. In

    tegr

    . Neu

    rosc

    i. 20

    14.1

    3:36

    3-40

    2. D

    ownl

    oade

    d fro

    m w

    ww

    .wor

    ldsc

    ient

    ific.c

    omby

    Dr.

    Alla

    n Co

    op o

    n 07

    /12/

    14. F

    or p

    erso

    nal u

    se o

    nly.

  • experience (Atkinson & Shiffrin, 1968). This multi-store modal memory model pro-

    poses sensory memory containing short-term records of sensory stimulation (250

    500ms duration). Those stimuli which are attended enter short-term memory (up to

    18 s duration), and if suciently rehearsed are transferred to long-term memory (in

    principle unlimited).

    Each of these memory domains has subsequently been further decomposed. For

    example, short-term memory is associated with a working memory (Baddeley &

    Hitch, 1974), while long-term memory may be divided into either explicit memory

    which is partitioned into episodic (Tulving, 1972), procedural (Milner, 1962) and

    semantic (Tulving, 1972) components; or declarative memory, comprising implicit or

    procedural memory (Schacter, 1987) or emotional memory (LeDoux, 2000).

    One signicant problem with this multi-store approach is that dierent principles

    are assumed to apply over dierent time scales. This runs counter to the generally

    held expectation that scientic principles should hold over a wide range of temporal,

    spatial, or physical scales (Barenblatt, 1996). As a consequence, Brown et al. (2007)

    have proposed memory is unitary over all time scales, from milliseconds to years.

    Here, the basic idea is that items are more distinctive, and hence both more

    memorable and easier to identify, to the extent they are located in sparsely-populated

    regions of psychological space. This implies forgetting is a consequence of reduced

    local distinctiveness, not trace decay. Importantly, the same mechanisms are used for

    retrieval over all time scales. There is considerable empirical support for this model as

    it resolves many observations not easily accounted for by the more widely accepted

    multi-store memory model.

    This so-called temporal ratio model is concordant with the synaptic trace theory of

    memory rst proposed by Hebb (1949). He posits the brain retains information

    through learning-induced changes in the synaptic connections between neurons.

    Once consolidated, a memory is then embedded and embodied through its xed

    trace. Thus, learning occurs through general mechanisms of experience-dependent

    synaptic plasticity, e.g. Hubel et al. (1977), which ultimately lead through a cascade

    of intracellular molecular mechanisms to the formation of long-term memory. Sub-

    sequently, it has been shown memories can temporarily be rendered labile and sen-

    sitive to modication. Once an existing memory has been destabilized, it is possible to

    enhance and even incorporate new content (for review, see Flavell et al. (2014)).

    For over a century, psychologists have focused their studies on memory of the past.

    However, a signicant function of memory is its role in allowing individuals to imagine

    possible future events (Schacter et al., 2007), to guide behavior in the future based on

    analogies, through memory resulting from both real and imagined experience (Bar,

    2009b). Schacter & Addis (2009) consider that predicting the future and remembering

    the past may be more closely related than everyday experience suggests. It has re-

    cently been shown that similarities in cognitive processes underlying past and future

    events are complemented by analogous similarities in brain activity. For example, the

    same \core network" of brain regions is recruited when people remember the past and

    imagine the future (Buckner et al., 2008; Schacter et al., 2008, 2007).

    AFFERENCE COPY AS A QUANTITATIVE NEUROPHYSIOLOGICAL MODEL 379

    J. In

    tegr

    . Neu

    rosc

    i. 20

    14.1

    3:36

    3-40

    2. D

    ownl

    oade

    d fro

    m w

    ww

    .wor

    ldsc

    ient

    ific.c

    omby

    Dr.

    Alla

    n Co

    op o

    n 07

    /12/

    14. F

    or p

    erso

    nal u

    se o

    nly.

  • In this view, past and future events draw on similar information stored in memory

    and rely on similar underlying processes: in an active creative extrapolation, memory

    supports the construction of future events by extracting and recombining stored

    information into a simulation of a novel event. Schacter et al. (2008) further suggest

    that simulation of future events requires a system that can exibly recombine details

    from past events. Thus, memory can be thought of as a tool used by the prospective

    brain to generate simulations of possible future events. Schacter et al. (2007) consider

    such a hypothesis requires a shift of conceptual emphasis with regard to the role of

    memory in cerebral activity.

    3.5. Prediction as reconstruction of the future

    Prediction is pervasive throughout much of brain function and is almost continually

    operative at conscious and reex-levels, as success in a goal-oriented, moving system

    is enhanced by such innate functionality (Llinas, 2001). For the nervous system to

    predict, it must at least perform a rapid comparison of the sensory-referred properties

    of the external world with a separate internal sensorimotor representation of those

    properties (Llinas & Roy, 2009).

    If it is to synchronize with the external events of each given moment the brain

    must leave itself enough time to implement movement decisions. It cannot be stuck

    doing something when required to perform another task. The consequent mode of

    operation derives from a \look-ahead function", proposed to be an inherent property

    of neural circuits (Llinas, 2001).

    Pellionisz & Llinas (1979) provide a model of such a function based on the Taylor

    expansion. It yields predictions of the frequency-time function of cortical input and is

    an emergent property of inherently parallel distributed neural circuits. It relies on

    relationships between neuronal ring rates and events in the external world. If some

    neurons respond quickly, some do so at intermediate velocities, and some measure

    events in real time, the output of such a circuit will be a reconstruction or prediction

    of an event ahead of its time of completion. It is widely believed, in the absence of any

    other possible sources, such functionality is memory-based (Bar, 2009a).

    The signicance of such a mechanism is found mainly by its incorporation into

    larger, cognitive states or entities. In other words, the extent to which sensory cues

    aect brain function is determined by their impact upon pre-existing functional

    dispositions of the brain (Llinas, 1987, 1974). Llinas (2001) considers this indicates a

    far deeper issue than might initially appear. In fact, the predictive abilities of the

    brain may be profoundly more fundamental than suggested by a purely look-ahead

    model.

    We extend this approach to provide a signicantly more comprehensive predictive

    functionality which lies at the heart of the aerence copy model. It is distinguished by

    originating entirely within the memory system, an absence of immediately direct

    comparison between sensory-referred properties of the external world and internal

    sensorimotor correlates, and provision of a basis for conscious temporal detachment.

    380 H. CORNELIS & A. D. COOP

    J. In

    tegr

    . Neu

    rosc

    i. 20

    14.1

    3:36

    3-40

    2. D

    ownl

    oade

    d fro

    m w

    ww

    .wor

    ldsc

    ient

    ific.c

    omby

    Dr.

    Alla

    n Co

    op o

    n 07

    /12/

    14. F

    or p

    erso

    nal u

    se o

    nly.

  • In fact, we claim that through infant learning, physiological processes of aerence

    copy are evoked as sets of embedded reex functions. They lead to the creation of

    temporal experience and consciousness through their ability to fabricate the phe-

    nomena of the present moment. The correlate is development of an awareness which

    enables distinction of the past from the future and thereby create the subjective

    temporal experience and phenomenology of each given moment.

    3.6. Estimates of memory capacity and rate of formation

    Unquantied beliefs concerning the characteristics of the human brain have long

    been considered to make it an outlier in evolutionary terms and are frequently

    employed to justify its remarkable cognitive abilities. However, the human brain has

    been found to contain just the number of neurons and non-neuronal cells expected for

    a primate brain of its size; with the same distribution of neurons between its cerebral

    cortex and cerebellum as in other species, along with appropriately scaled energy

    costs (Herculano-Houzel, 2011, 2012).

    In concordance with our identication of a putative aerence copy system, in this

    section we take the opportunity to provide some estimates of what might be referred

    to as the content acquisition and content storage domains of the human CNS. These

    may be distinguished from the content manipulation domain.

    With regard to content manipulation, there is a considerable literature reporting

    estimates of the transmission rate of information by neurons within the CNS. These

    estimates are typically based on an assumption of either a rate or temporal code.

    Theoretically, for a rate code with strictly periodic neuronal ring, the information

    per spike is calculated from log2N=N , where N gives the number of spikes persecond. This gives values of 3:3 101 and 6:6 102 bits spike1 for ring rates of10 and 100 spikes s1, respectively. Alternatively, for a temporal code, where thevariability of spike timing is taken into account, the calculation of information

    transmission becomes considerably more complicated (e.g., see Stein (1967)). In

    short, for example, information per spike increases to 34 bits spike1 (Softky,1995), with a theoretical maximum of about 9 bits spike1 (MacKay & McCulloch,1952).

    However, here we are initially interested in the content storage domain of the

    memory system, in particular, an estimate of its \storage capacity". Such an estimate

    then allows a \mean acquisition rate" to be determined for the content acquisition

    domain. In doing this we are estimating a possible rate at which experience may be

    recorded prior to transformation to states of the nervous system within the content

    manipulation and storage domains.

    One way to quantify these domains is in computational terms. For example, a

    synapse can be represented as a single binary bit. Based on this assumption we can

    employ the following data to make an \order of magnitude" estimate of storage

    capacity. The aim is to give some sense of the putative capacity of human memory

    in computational terms. We note, better estimates will be considerably complicated

    AFFERENCE COPY AS A QUANTITATIVE NEUROPHYSIOLOGICAL MODEL 381

    J. In

    tegr

    . Neu

    rosc

    i. 20

    14.1

    3:36

    3-40

    2. D

    ownl

    oade

    d fro

    m w

    ww

    .wor

    ldsc

    ient

    ific.c

    omby

    Dr.

    Alla

    n Co

    op o

    n 07

    /12/

    14. F

    or p

    erso

    nal u

    se o

    nly.

  • by, for example, neuronal loss due to ageing in the frontal lobes (up to 20%

    (Masliah et al., 1993; Gibson, 1983)), and likely continual addition of neurons in,

    at least, the hippocampus (Altman, 1963), olfactory bulb (Altman, 1969) and

    striatum (Ernst et al., 2014).

    The human brain has been reported to contain 86:1 109 8:1 109 neurons,of which 19%, or approximately 16:4 109 are cortically located (Azevedo et al.,2009). The number of synapses in the neocortex has been reported at 1:5 1014(Pakkenberg et al., 2003). Assuming non-cortical neurons exhibit a similar average

    number of synapses as cortical neurons, and all synapses may be modied by expe-

    rience; the total estimated number of synapses in the brain may be as large as

    7:89 1014.At one bit per synapse, this number of synapses corresponds to a storage capacity

    of about 90Tb. Assuming a human lifespan of 70 years, with the knowledge there are

    approximately 3:2 1010 ms in a year, it can be estimated there are on average about358 \naive" synapses available each millisecond to record the state of the nervous

    system. From a computational perspective, this corresponds to storage of

    44 bytesms1 or 43Kb s1, 2.5Mbminute1, 150Mbhour1 or 3.5Gb day1. Thisdaily value is comparable with high denition movies which consume approximately

    2Gbhour1. Interestingly, by this analysis, a 90min movie has a similar storagerequirement to our estimate of the average daily human storage capacity.

    These gures may signicantly increase if it is accepted that new memories cannot

    be formed during sleep, which is considered to be reserved for the stabilization,

    enhancement and integration of memories (Walker et al., 2005). If it is assumed on

    average a person spends approximately 8 h sleeping each day, then memory storage

    capacity may increase up to about 470 synapses per millisecond, corresponding to

    storage throughout waking life of 57.3Kb s1 or approximately 200Mbhour1.From a computational perspective, such calculations provide an indication of the

    general volumes of \data storage" or average sustainable daily rate of lifetime

    memory formation and provide a starting point for the development of more practical

    hypotheses. Although the putative per millisecond synaptic sampling rate seems

    trivial, as our calculations show, the cumulative capacity is substantial. As Sechenov

    (1863) has proposed, \By means of absolutely involuntary learning . . . in all spheres

    of the senses the child acquires a multitude of more or less complete ideas of objects,

    i.e., elementary concrete knowledge".

    4. The Explanatory Gap

    The \explanatory gap" is a philosophical term referring to the lack of an explanation

    of how physical properties give rise to the qualia of experience (Levine, 1983). We

    appreciate such a \literary" denition is a necessary step in problem identication,

    but consider it a misplaced expectation that any deep resolution is possible while

    explication languishes in such purely metaphorical or narrative domains. Any solu-

    tion is likely only available following location of the \gap" within an appropriate

    382 H. CORNELIS & A. D. COOP

    J. In

    tegr

    . Neu

    rosc

    i. 20

    14.1

    3:36

    3-40

    2. D

    ownl

    oade

    d fro

    m w

    ww

    .wor

    ldsc

    ient

    ific.c

    omby

    Dr.

    Alla

    n Co

    op o

    n 07

    /12/

    14. F

    or p

    erso

    nal u

    se o

    nly.

  • neuropsychophysiological context. More specically, we consider the problem of the

    explanatory gap becomes tractable when translated from a philosophical to an em-

    pirical context.

    Quantication is fundamental to the scientic method and by making this con-

    ceptual transformation, the philosophical idea of the explanatory gap can be placed

    rmly into the core of the scientic tradition. However, we recognize that with

    quantication comes reduction, itself a characteristic of the scientic method. In doing

    so we acknowledge the metaphorical nature of much written about consciousness. As

    suggested in the Introduction, because of the highly multidimensional, intangible and

    generally elusive nature of consciousness many of its various aspects are only available

    through metaphorical language and description. It is these aspects which are greatly

    reduced by transference from the philosophical to the physiological domain.

    To make this transfer we propose, at its most general, that the physiological

    explanatory gap is dened as the gap between the occurrence of a stimulus at ex-

    ternally or internally directed sensory receptors and the initiation of a response,

    motor or otherwise. It is this gap which must be \explained" by the nervous system

    and to which, in its own way, aspects of the philosophical formulation actually refer.

    Most importantly, during this period it is not possible for a nervous system to

    know anything about changes in the external environment. For this reason, a sig-

    nicant evolutionary advantage likely accrues to an organism capable of correctly

    predicting evolution of the environment during this period. More specically, in the

    case of placental mammals, the foregoing denition might be recast as, \the temporal

    duration from the time of interaction of a sucient sensory stimulus with a receptor

    until the time at which a percept of that event is subjectively recognized within

    conscious experience".

    This transformation recasts the problem of the explanatory gap by removing it

    from a philosophical domain of narrative contemplation to the domain of empirical

    quantication. There it can be rigorously studied as an incontrovertible feature of the

    vertebrate CNS.

    As we show below, this is an illuminating example of how narrative language used

    to speculate about the brain can be recast in empirical terms to more decisively

    explore CNS activity and, in this case, \bridge" the explanatory gap.

    5. Eerence Copy as Motor Predictor Model

    Modern eerence copy models (Fig. 1(a)) derive from a proposal which originally

    posited direct sensation of the motor command: \The impulse to move, which we

    initiate through the innervation of our motor nerves, is immediately perceptible".

    (von Helmholtz, 1878/1971). This idea was later integrated into motor physiology

    through \corollary discharge" (von Holst, 1954; Sperry, 1950).

    As reviewed by Mulliken & Andersen (2009), because sensory information is

    substantially delayed, it has been proposed the brain makes use of an internal for-

    ward model which relies on eerence or eerent copy. This is an internal copy of an

    AFFERENCE COPY AS A QUANTITATIVE NEUROPHYSIOLOGICAL MODEL 383

    J. In

    tegr

    . Neu

    rosc

    i. 20

    14.1

    3:36

    3-40

    2. D

    ownl

    oade

    d fro

    m w

    ww

    .wor

    ldsc

    ient

    ific.c

    omby

    Dr.

    Alla

    n Co

    op o

    n 07

    /12/

    14. F

    or p

    erso

    nal u

    se o

    nly.

  • outowing, movement-producing signal generated by the motor system. It is pro-

    posed to allow integration of sensory and motor feedback signals to estimate current

    and upcoming positions and motions of a limb during movement (Blakemore et al.,

    2000). Upon eective execution, the actual proprioceptive feedback of a motor action

    eectively balances the predicted sensory feedback. Thereby, the eerence copy is an

    early-warning signal sent by motor production areas to the corresponding somato-

    sensory areas specialized in the proprioception of motor execution. It also allows

    perceptual structures to distinguish between self and externally mediated signals.

    6. Aerence Copy as Sensory Predictor Model

    An explanatory gap exists for the time it takes a sensory stimulus to evoke fabri-

    cation of a current percept and for the percept to emerge into consciousness. Our

    claim is, this physiological explanatory gap is bridged by conscious experience, which

    originates through aerence copy as a construct evoked from within the memory

    system.

    The special character of this consciously experienced percept is that it is not

    actually just a record of sensory activation entering the nervous system. Rather, it is

    a memory-based prediction (activated by stimulus presence) of the state of the

    internal and external environment of the nervous system expected at the time

    (a) (b)

    Fig. 1. A. Eerence Copy: Model proposes that upon motor preparation and intention, copies ofeerent motor information are fed back and used centrally in an emulation algorithm, which calculatesthe anticipated somatosensory changes expected as a consequence of the planned motor execution.Subsequently, peripheral changes at the level of the muscles, the joints and the skin generate actualproprioceptive feedback, which will eectively balance the predicted sensory feedback in somatosensorycortex (at the level of a so-called \comparator"). B. Aerence copy: A model complementary to eerencecopy proposes that upon sensory stimulation, receptor stimuli are fed forward and maintained sub-consciously in the memory system while they are integrated with the relevant memories they evoke.Once integration is complete, a prediction of the percept expected on the basis of the received sensorystimulus emerges as an \aerence copy" into the explanatory gap created by the time taken for inte-gration to occur. If the aerence copy eectively matches the environment, predicted experience andactual experience match suciently that no further action is required. Otherwise, surprise is experiencedand attention may be redirected. Panel A adapted from (Bazan, 2012).

    384 H. CORNELIS & A. D. COOP

    J. In

    tegr

    . Neu

    rosc

    i. 20

    14.1

    3:36

    3-40

    2. D

    ownl

    oade

    d fro

    m w

    ww

    .wor

    ldsc

    ient

    ific.c

    omby

    Dr.

    Alla

    n Co

    op o

    n 07

    /12/

    14. F

    or p

    erso

    nal u

    se o

    nly.

  • integration of the given sensory input is complete. It is in this sense that aerence

    copy is a predictor of sensory experience. This process is illustrated and explained in

    more detail in Fig. 2.

    Aerence copy can be conceptualized as complementary to the eerence copy

    system (Fig. 1(b)), but applied to inowing sensory activation rather than the out-

    owing, movement-producing activity of the motor system. It is the physiological

    mechanism which enables and completes the cyclic ow of experience and behavior

    through the cognitive domain of the nervous system and the physical world within

    which it is embedded.

    Following, for example, Dehaene & Naccache (2001) and Gray (2004), it is clear

    the neural activity driving aerence copy is widely distributed, although the details

    of precise location and mechanism are as yet unclear. Nevertheless, in the normal

    course of events, the construct fabricated by aerence copy processes would be based

    on, and exist in, the \past" due to the temporal delay introduced by the neural

    activity enabling its conscious appearance. This situation is only compounded by the

    fact that each successive moment is also a past moment prior to being experienced as

    the present.

    The aerence copy model is proposed as a solution as to how it is that subjective

    experience appears to exist in the present moment when the time required for sen-

    sations to consciously appear necessarily require sensory events evoking a conscious

    percept to occur in the past.

    The model resolves this apparent conict in the following way. At any one mo-

    ment, entry of sensory input into consciousness is delayed while its eects are inte-

    grated into ongoing neural activity to fabricate withinb the memory system a

    comprehensive percept of the contents expected or predicted for a given moment.

    Importantly, we further claim that the ability to do this is learned, as is the

    content of the behavioral repertoire it ultimately subserves, with the complexity of

    the processes involved being a major reason for the extended developmental period

    seen in humans. As they are learned, the processes subserving aerence copy, simi-

    larly to other learning, become a \reexive" mechanism residing in the subconscious.

    It is in this way the explanatory gap is bridged and conscious experience gener-

    ated. The content of consciousness is this memory-based prediction of the composi-

    tion of the next actual future moment, subjectively experienced as the present

    moment. It is a reexive mechanism learned during development to accommodate

    ongoing function in the ubiquitous presence of the explanatory gap.

    Ultimately, ongoing neural activity is modulated as required by sensory content

    and the associations it evokes from within the memory system. What is commonly

    referred to and experienced as subjective phenomenal consciousness is this

    bIt does not make sense to say \from" memory as this implies memory is consulted by some lookup procedure. This

    creates a signicant problem as retrieved content must be collected and displayed somewhere. Attempts to resolve

    this additional complexity has spurred previous solutions resulting in homunculi and the mechanics of the Cartesian

    Theatre. Importantly, following Nikoli (2014), we consider \monitor-and-act" is a more complete descriptor thanthe notion of representation as the former incorporates both \memory storage" and \processing".

    AFFERENCE COPY AS A QUANTITATIVE NEUROPHYSIOLOGICAL MODEL 385

    J. In

    tegr

    . Neu

    rosc

    i. 20

    14.1

    3:36

    3-40

    2. D

    ownl

    oade

    d fro

    m w

    ww

    .wor

    ldsc

    ient

    ific.c

    omby

    Dr.

    Alla

    n Co

    op o

    n 07

    /12/

    14. F

    or p

    erso

    nal u

    se o

    nly.

  • Fig. 2. Framework for consciousness: The schema is given for a single external stimulus. Model fea-tures are given at the top (A. Explanatory gap, C. Predicted percept) and subjective time (Past mo-ment, Present moment, Future moment) indicated at the bottom of each panel for three consecutive550ms moments (separated by dark vertical bars). Upper horizontal dotted line distinguishes twodomains within each panel. An upper physical domain contains a stimulus originating externally to thenervous system. A lower cognitive domain (within the nervous system) is further subdivided into two\internal" domains; a sub/pre-conscious domain (top) containing the memory system (comprisingsensory, short and long-term memory); and a conscious domain (bottom). Stimulus evoked sensoryarousal activates the memory system () to evoke relevant memories of previous stimulus experiencewhich together are integrated (! ) to generate an appropriately fabricated percept then released tothe conscious domain () as the best prediction of immediate future experience. Panel 1: An Explana-tory gap 1A exists in the past moment (1B) for the time it takes (! ) a stimulus to evoke acomprehensive prediction within the memory system of future stimulus-modulated experience. Oncefabricated, the Predicted percept (1C) emerges into the conscious domain (indicated by vertical stripesprojecting from the sub/preconscious domain into the conscious domain and perception) as a subjectiveconscious experience in the Present moment (1D). The large upper arrow head indicates appropriateongoing subconscious elaboration of memory by incorporation of correctly predicted perceptual com-ponents. The large lower arrow indicates the ongoing evolution of predicted perceptual experiencewithin the conscious domain. Panel 2: Illustrates temporal evolution of the relationships given in Panel 1into the next moments. During the Explanatory gap (2A), integration of a new sensory stimulus nowoccurs within memory system while the predicted percept generated during the explanatory gap of the(just passed) moment (1B) has now emerged as an appropriate stimulus modulated percept into theconscious domain of the present moment (illustrated in 1D, but for clarity not shown in 2B). Thisprocess continues as the Predicted percept (2C) being generated during the current Explanatory gap(2A) will be consciously experienced in the subsequent Future moment (2D). It is in this way ongoingperceptual experience is continuously generated through aerence copy to bridge the sliding window ofthe explanatory gap. Consciously experienced subjective phenomenology is a product of a previouslyconstructed prediction of the experiential contents expected to occur during the present moment.

    386 H. CORNELIS & A. D. COOP

    J. In

    tegr

    . Neu

    rosc

    i. 20

    14.1

    3:36

    3-40

    2. D

    ownl

    oade

    d fro

    m w

    ww

    .wor

    ldsc

    ient

    ific.c

    omby

    Dr.

    Alla

    n Co

    op o

    n 07

    /12/

    14. F

    or p

    erso

    nal u

    se o

    nly.

  • physiological process of creating a prediction of the experience of the present moment

    based on prior experience of the given situation or environment.

    When this functionality is paired with the ability of the CNS and itsmemory system

    to discriminate and cumulatively \record" in the domain of single photons (Gregory,

    1966) and atoms (Green, 1976); the elements available for fabrication create eectively

    \seamless" and entirely \resolvable" percepts. Naturally, environmental needs and

    requirements create